‘ g 5,; _ " ; f-mmLmCSOMNmaximum ~ 1 : *IHE mtmmflctwmmvsmm ........ ~ ; Humogmo mmmsm‘reumvmsm 9- J j SOSEPHIWWM {BENDERSIKYF-é'7‘???235';_.~;'}7_i‘."37_il?'-3-??113ff5’717’77 ~i.g1a_,~y;;:;1 f;9z§,;ii13f1g§gggij;°“ff}f]3f;gf “-7“: LI BRAR Y Michigan State University I p‘ 1-, .53 "mm ...1., LL; “ink ABSTRACT THE POLITICS OF AN INTELLECTUAL: THE POLITICAL ACTIVITY AND IDEAS OF CARL SCHMITT, 1910-1945 BY Joseph William Bendersky Among the host of outstanding twentieth-century (hrmmlintellectuals Carl Schmitt certainly holds a place ofexecute these laws in accordance with the changing demands of the situation.65 Schmitt concedes that some limitations on the auflxmity of the military commander continue to exist. TheIMlitary commander cannot suspend the principles of um Rechtsstaat.66 He can, for example, after suspending conmfitutional laws, still find his limitations in the independence of the judicial powers. By suspending the mnmtitution the military commander might expedite a legal case, but he cannot punish. For he is not author— ized to interfere with the legal decisions of the state, amican only demand or inhibit the execution of its decisions.67 It remains unclear in Schmitt's analysis Mmther these limitations on the military commander are almapossible under a dictatorship. 651bid., pp. 160—161. 66Ibid., p. 149. 67Schmitt, "Einwirkungen," pp. 796—797. 41 The non—ethical application of state power in time of war had most certainly had its impact on the formerly neo—Kantian Schmitt. Still clinging to the principles of the Rechsstaat, he shows a new awareness of the reality of power, realizing that the war had created a tremendous centralization of power in the executive. The Rechtsstaat now appears reduced to a legal or constitutional state, since Schmitt no longer refers to the ethical purpose of the state as expounded in his pre-war book Der Wert. Concrete danger, or the term he later utilizes most fre— rather than ethical purpose dictates the actions of the state.68 He concerns quently, the "concrete situation,‘ himself mainly with the manner in which one applies state power to meet these concrete dangers and necessities, and he attempts to provide some historical and legal per- spective for these issues. It is in this respect that these first articles on dictatorship serve as transitional works for Schmitt. Many of the central ideas embodied in these articles, including the state of exception, and the distinction between laws and measures, later arise as integral parts of his political and legal theories. Even the renowned and highly controversial theory of dictatorship so closely associated with the name Carl Schmitt, emanates in part 68$chmitt, "Diktatur," pp. 147, 159. ‘V‘ _ n. u 42 frmnthese two works. The distinction between a Com— IMssarial Dictatorship and a Sovereign Dictatorship is notclearly developed by him before 1921, but this dis- thmtion does bear a striking resemblance to his wartime categories of the powers of a military commander under nurtial law and those of a dictator. Carl Schmitt's attraction to these wartime problems foretells the tenor oflfls future work and activity. Many of his more influ- mmial publications in the Weimar Republic deal essen- tiaUy with the extent to which laws, and even the con- stiunion itself, could be suspended in order to meet an enmflng danger and to reestablish a normal state of affairs. a... 4m ._. ‘ n W "M “H CHAPTER II THE YEARS OF INSECURITY, 1919-1922: THE DEVELOPMENT OF CARL SCHMITT'S POLITICAL CONSCIOUSNESS Germany's demoralizing defeat and the proclamation of the republic, followed by years of domestic upheavals and civil war, were agonizing times for Carl Schmitt. As a nationalist he found it difficult to reconcile himself to a defeat aggravated by such a humiliating and oppressive peace. Domestic events evoked equal reactions of dismay and incertitude from Schmitt. The Wilhelmian state, in whose bureaucracy he served and to which he owed his loyalty, capitulated to republican, democratic and even socialist revolutionary forces. An unstable republic with doubtful legitimacy and authority replaced the most powerful state in German history. The continued existence of the republic remained uncertain and its future political direction left Schmitt in bewilderment. Unlike its pre- decessor, to which Schmitt once attributed an ethical pur— Pose, the early republic lacked clearly established centers and patterns of authority. Complicating the confusion and more disturbing to the conservative and Catholic Schmitt was the example of a successful Bolshevik revolution in Russia, which 43 'u .... .n w. . 1 w 44 encouraged threatening attempts at socialist and conmunist revolutions throughout Germany. Most of Schmitt's military duties kept him in Munich, where he personally experienced the short-lived Bavarian Soviet Republic and its brutal repression in 1919. Along with a majority of the Bavarian middle classes, Schmitt reacted very strongly against the excesses and violence of this abortive Soviet experiment. When finally released from the military on July 1, 1919, Schmitt could not return to Strassburg to continue his academic career. What previously appeared as a highly promising career for him as a professor of law or as a civil servant in the Prussian bureaucracy suddenly became questionable. He had lost his academic position as Dozent at the University of Strassburg when it closed on November 11, 1918; subsequently it was restored as a French institution after the Versailles Treaty.l His per— sonal fate depended upon the changing course of events and in these early years his own future remained as doubtful as that of the republic. This perplexing turn of events and shocking personal experience forced Schmitt to reeval- uate his entire political and intellectual outlook. Fortunately Moritz Julius Bonn assisted Schmitt in acquiring a lectureship at the Munich Handelshochschule lBA, R—6l, Bd. 64, "Lebenslauf." 45 in September of 1919. This marked the beginning of a very close friendship which, in spite of their often opposing political viewpoints, endured until the end of the Weimar Republic.2 Schmitt retained his academic position in Munich until October 1921, at which time the University of Greifswald offered him a professorship of public law.3 During the period of uncertainty surrounding the establishment of the republic, the civil war, and Schmitt's search for a permanent academic position, he conceived of two of his more renowned books, Politische 4 And each book bears a direct Romantik and D_i_e Diktatur. relationship to the political and social upheavals of the period, as well as to Schmitt's self-evaluation of his own political position. The title of the first book, Politische Romantik, indicates the new dominant trend in Schmitt's interests—-politics. It is also of significance that he conceived and wrote this book amid the instability and chaos of Germany in 1919. For this year brought about a major turning point in Schmitt's thinking. The war and the German revolution had impressed upon him the necessity of politics. Many of his more important 2BA, Nachlass Moritz Julius Bonn, Nos. 48—50, 56; and Moritz Julius Bonn, So Macht Man Geschichte: Bilanz Eines Lebens (Muenchen, 1953), pp. 330—332. 3BA, R—21, Bd. 144, Mappe 39. 4References are to the 1925 edition of Politische 3933535, and the 1921 edition of Die Diktatur. «v n, 46 publications thereafter would concern politics in con— trast to his pre—war writings, where for the most part he totally neglected politics. A highly interpretive historical and philosophical work, Politische Romantik contains an unusual critical analysis of the political nature of Romanticism. Schmitt noted that many scholars have viewed the romantic move— ment as revolutionary, while others have presented it as conservative or reactionary. Both interpretations Schmitt regards as incorrect, because Romanticism constitutes for him neither a politically revolutionary nor a conservative or reactionary movement.5 In fact, "politics is as foreign to him (i.e., to a political romantic) as is morality or logic."6 "Where political activity begins political Romanticism ends."7 A romantic cannot maintain or advocate a continuous or definite political position, whether revolutionary or conservative, since he lacks the ability to decide for himself what appears to be right.8 The desire to be productive without becoming active is the essence of the political romantic.9 But 5Politische Romantik, p. 14. 6Ibid., p. 205. 71bid., p. 224. 8Ibid., p. 207. 9Ibid., p. 223. 47 Schmitt draws a clear distinction between this type of political romantic and a romantic politician. He con— ceives of the latter as, "a person, who although he is not essentially a romantic, can still be motivated through romanticized ideas."lo The immortal type of romantic politician Schmitt sees in Don Quixote, a man capable of distinguishing between what appeared to him as right and wrong, and thus able to reach political deci- sions. Karl Ludwig Sand's assassination of Kotzebue in 1819, Schmitt cites as an actual example of a romanticized, yet politically motivated act.11 The very nature of the political romantic, as interpreted by Schmitt, precludes such political activity, since he defines Romanticism as "subjective occasionalism." Everything exists merely as an occasion (Anlass) or opportunity for the productivity of the romantic.12 God, who formerly provided a universal absolute and objective standard, no longer stands in the center, but is super— seded by the individual subject, who treats the world only as an occasion for his own intellectual performance 13 and artistic productivity. There exists no absolute Rm lOIbid., p. 205. llIbid., pp. 205—207. lzIbid., p. 23. 13Ibid., pp. 107, 110—111, 138. m {EH rife! if as Hit 491 48 vmnnge point or frame of reference, other than himself, miwhich the romantic can base his decisions. Society and Instory, cosmos and humanity serve only as potential mmasions for the productivity of this genial "Ich." The dfiect itself, whether political or not, provides only a nahneless, functionless concrete point around which the nmmntic game of imagination is suspended.14 With the loss of God as an absolute new frames of reference, or what Schmitt called "new worlds," continually appear; but these are only "occasional worlds" utilized by um romantic as vehicles for his own romantic productivity. Consequently, Romanticism reveals a remarkable capability of associating itself with the most varying political con- dfljons and contradictory philosophical viewpoints. While Um revolution triumphed Romanticism appeared revolutionary, at Um end of the revolutionary period it became conserva— UNe,and after 1815 even closely associated with a very remnfionary restoration.15 Schmitt presents Adam Mueller aS'Um clearest representative of such political roman- . . 1 t1Cl$m 6 Mueller's treatment of the world as a mere Subjective occasion for his own romantic productivity Sdmutt infers from the fact that in Goettingen Mueller \— 14 _ Ibid. 15 Ibid., pp. 160-161. 16Ibid., p. 182. ml .3 s an); Sim 1M] =1 u; in 49 became an Anglophile, in the feudal milieu of Berlin extremely feudal, and in the clerical circles of Vienna very clerical. Unlike Sand or Don Quixote, "the most important sources of political vitality, the belief in right and indignation over wrong, did not exist for him."17 Mueller's romanticism prevented him from making moral and political distinctions, and he always stood in the service of some other unromantic energy, whether con— servative or revolutionary. This harsh criticism of Mueller was one indication of Schmitt's intellectual self-evaluation in response to the changing political conditions around him. Before starting to write this study Schmitt had idealized Adam Mueller and the romantics. Now he condemned Mueller as an Opportunist devoid of all moral values. That change of attitude on the part of Schmitt was due more to the chaotic circumstances of 1919 than to any scholarly analeis of Mueller. At this time Schmitt found himself in a Similar situation to that of the early romantics, and as a result he wrote Politische Romantik in an effort to define his own intellectual position. Some scholars, including Meinecke, who considered the book as one of the most Significant publications on Romanticism in decades, K— 17Ibid., p. 177. u 44‘ .mi 35355 ‘11 50 underestimated Schmitt's personal relationship to his own thesis.18 At the end of the First World War Schmitt wit- mmsed a rapid and unexpected change from a conservative, auflxmitarian regime to a revolutionary situation, and fhmlly the rise of a new political order. Nonetheless, 1m refused to follow the example of the political nmmntics and treat the world as merely a changing sub— jedfiye occasion for his own intellectual productivity. As alflstoricist Schmitt believed in the uniqueness of lustorical events, but he still held firm to the opinion thm:one must maintain some basis on which to make polit— nml and moral distinctions. An intellectual must be capMHe of separating himself from purely aesthetic and amjstic productivity and be prepared to make definite mflitical decisions.19 Schmitt felt that he must try to awfid the moral remissness inherent in the subjective occasionalism of the political romantics. He could not wand by without making political and moral distinctions rfifirding recent developments in post-war Germany. This book contained nothing specific about what antude Schmitt actually held towards the new republic. M 18 _ . . - Friedrich Meinecke, "Politische BQTEEEiE von' Dr. Carl Schmitt—Dorotié (1919)@ WI Band cxxr (1920), pp. 292-296. 19Schmitt interview, July 13: 1973- 51 We receive instead only the general impression of an individual in the midst of a personal intellectual crisis, making a firm commitment to become political. The war, the Russian and German Revolutions, and more directly the events he personally witnessed during the Bavarian Soviet Republic, had convinced him that politics cannot be neglected. But he realized that political decisions must be based on some firm intellectual foundation. With Adam Mueller in mind Schmitt rejected the idea of placing himself at the disposal of the new political trends cur— rently dominant, and he decided to draw his own political distinctions according to what he considered right and wrong. Carl Schmitt had disassociated himself from polit— ical Romanticism, as he had interpreted it. The topic of Schmitt's as Diktatur, published in 1921, reveals more exactly the nature of his growing political concern in the years after 1919. He saw the domestic political stabilization of Germany and a return to normalcy as the first priority. The political and social upheavals of the early republic allowed no oppor— tunity for internal stabilization; and not only the republic but Germany as a state often reached the verge of political disintegration. After the formation of the republic, there came the repression of the Independent Socialists and Spartacists by the Free Corps in 1919, the Kapp Putsch and general strike of 1920, and leftist me till stud file 321 :3 6 ie fact 52 attempts at revolution in the Ruhr, combined with a variety of other domestic disorders. These events in many cases involved nothing less than civil war, which alarmed Schmitt considerably. But although he desired the restoration of order, peace and stability Schmitt neither advocated a restoration of the old Reich, nor the destruction of the Weimar Republic and its constitution in favor of a dictatorship. % Diktatur clearly shows that at this time Schmitt had accepted the Weimar Republic and its constitution as the legally constituted authority in Germany. Nowhere in this study does Schmitt even suggest the restoration of the old Reich or the establishment of a German dictatorship. Schmitt believed that a new political and legal order had come into existence once the German people had accepted the Weimar constitution. He reconciled himself to that fact and transferred his loyalty to the new regime. This set a pattern for much of his future political behavior; he would always obey the legally constituted authority. The only political thesis contained in Di_e Diktatur rele— vant to Germany in 1921, pertains to securing the Weimar Republic through the use of its constitutional emergency powers. Schmitt's actual political position notwithstand— ing, critics have often misinterpreted this book due to its title, Schmitt's later political activity and 32E ill 2:15 bill In 53 writings, and the rise of the Nazi dictatorship. Most critics of this book in fact usually refer to the second 1928 edition, which includes a corollary on the Dictator- ship of the Reichspresident under Article 48 of the Weimar Constitution. When Schmitt published the first edition of his work he was still a young, and relatively unknown professor. The book, of course, did add to his recog- nition within the academic and legal professions, and the intellectual community in general, but it had no political influence at the time. D_ig Diktatur falls into the category of a his— torical and theoretical study of the nature of dictator- ship from ancient Rome to the establishment of the Weimar Republic, rather than of rightwing political propaganda. The origins of this book can be detected in two separate yet related areas of Schmitt's own experience. His war— time interests in the Belagerungszustand as represented in his two articles on martial law and dictatorship pro— vided the basic theoretical groundwork for this study. Many of the fundamental ideas in these articles appeared in a revised form as part of his theoryof dictatorship. His early distinction between martial law and dictator— ship he transformed into the distinction between a Com— missarial and a Sovereign Dictator. And the distinction between laws and measures acquired even more importance When Schmitt applied these concepts to the power of the .190 3270 it zeal 54 Reichspresident under Article 48 of the Weimar constitu- tion. The second and more immediate origin of Schmitt's theory stemmed from the unexpected Russian and German Revolutions, and the ensuing civil war in Germany. Schmitt's interest in the legality and legitimacy of a newly created political order had already been aroused by the successful revolution in Russia and the alleged establishment of a Soviet dictatorship of the proletar- 20 The German revolution and the creation of the iat. Weimar Republic had a similar effect, but added a new dimension to the problem as a result of the upheavals and civil war which plagued the early republic. Schmitt devotes almost the entire book to tracing the concept and nature of dictatorship historically. He points out for instance that the humanistic writers of the Renaissance held a similar view of dictatorship to that of the ancient Romans. A dictator was appointed by the Roman Consul at a time of danger either to conduct a 20The Russian Revolution also inspired a rejuven— ated interest among other scholars regarding Marxism and the dictatorship of the proletariat. See Hans Kelsen, Sozialismus un_d Staat: Eine Untersuchung _Dgr Politischen Theorie _D_e_s_ Marxismus (rev. 2nd ed.; Leipzig, 1923) , pp. 65—80, 150-152, 158-165, 172—175. Kelsen first pub— lished this work as an article in Archiv fuer die in? .‘ME 55 . 21 . . war or to suppress a domestic revolt. "The dictator is not a tyrant and the dictatorship is not an absolute form of rule, but rather an exclusively republican and consti- "22 He could not tutional method of preserving freedom. change existing laws, abolish the constitution and system of government, or make new laws. This historical practice represents only one form of dictatorship, however, which Schmitt defines as a Conmissarial Dictatorship. The Commissarial Dictator is always the action commissar of the pouvoir constitué.23 He derives his authority from a constitutional organ and he retains his title only within the existing constitution.24 His appointment lasts for the duration of the crisis and during that time he may, if he deems it necessary, temporarily suspend cer- tain laws and even the constitution in order to bring about a normal state of affairs. Once the danger subsides the authorizing pouvoir constitué relieves the Commis- sarial Dictator of his commission and reinstates the ori— ginal constitution and legal order.25 21Die Diktatur, p. 1. 22Ibid., pp. 6-7. 23 Ibid., p. 146. 24Ibid., p. 145. 251bid., p. 136. EVE 56 Schmitt contrasts this type of Commissarial Dictatorship with a Sovereign Dictatorship. Quite dis- similar to the Commissarial Dictator, the Sovereign Dictator sees in the total existing order the condition, which he wishes to eliminate through his actions. He does not merely suspend an existing constitution . . but attempts to create a condition in which he can establish a constitution, which he views as the true constitution. He appeals not to an exisging, but rather to a newly arising constitution . 2 A Sovereign Dictator receives his authority from the “formless pouvoir constituant," the people, and it is to the people to whom he appeals. Because these politically formless people from whom authority emanates cannot organize themselves a Sovereign Dictator must first create the external con- ditions which permit the realization of a viable consti— tutional or governmental authority. Theoretically the sovereignty of the dictator lasts only as a "transition" (Uebergang) , until he fulfills the purpose of establishing a new constitutional state of affairs. The limited tran- sitional nature of a SOVereign Dictatorship actually dis— tinguishes it completely from an absolute monarchy or a sovereign aristocracy.27 The early regimes of Caesar and Sulla in ancient Rome, as well as the dictatorships during the French Revolution, Schmitt cites as examples of 261bid., p. 137. 27Ibid., p. 146. m .‘n «It. 3334 .. .La -... .‘V I'M 57 Sovereign forms of Dictatorship. In the twentieth cen— tury the Leninist dictatorship in Russia and the National Assembly during the German revolution serve as signifi— cant examples. The existing constitutional and political order in each case was eliminated in favor of a newly arising order. Two major problems concerning Schmitt's theory of Commissarial and Sovereign Dictators are quite evident. If the Commissarial Dictator refuses to relinquish his office after‘completing the task for which he is appointed, and since he wields extensive power, he could quite possibly become a Sovereign Dictator and eliminate the very constitutional or political order he supposedly protects. Related to this problem is that of the Sovereign Dictator whose authority and recognition may rest only with the dictator himself without appealing to the people. Instead of, serving as a transitional figure the Sovereign Dictator takes on the character of an absolute dictator, perpetuating himself as the sole center of authority and power. Caesar, Sulla, and Lenin eventually all pursued this course with rather marked success. Consciously aware of these possibilities, Carl Schmitt feared that the recent Russian example would encourage the Germans to follow suit. The extreme left continued to call for revolution in Germany and Ebert, a 351 58 Smflal Democrat, held the office of president. These con- dfljons disturbed Schmitt even more in light of the Inmeasing domestic disorders and civil war, which forced hmquent reliance upon the presidential emergency powers aMflmrized under Article 48 of the Weimar constitution. in foresaw the possibility of the destruction of the Wammr state and its constitution through the misuse of Article 48 by the extreme left. The Reichspresident under Article 48 could, when mflflic order and security are endangered, take the neces— sary measures (Massnahmen) to reestablish a normal state ofaffairs. Schmitt referred to these powers as those of acmmmissarial Dictator and he supported the necessary appfication of these powers during the unstable and vola— tihayears of the young republic. But he feared that if a machspresident were to assume unlimited powers in a crisis situation he might attempt to destroy the existing commfitutional and political order. A leftist president couhieven strive to institute a dictatorship of the pnfletariat. Therefore, Schmitt cautioned that, if this unlimited authority is not to signify a dis— integration of the total existing Rechtszustand and the transferring of sovereignty to the Reichspresident, these measures (Massnahmen) must always be merely of a factual nature, and as such could be neither acts of legislation nor the administration of justice.28 28116161., pp- 201—202. 59 The radical right could also accomplish the destruction of the Weimar state and constitution through Article 48. Countless rightist, anti—republican movements and activities dominate this period, but these generally occurred outside of the existing constitutional structure without reliance on Article 48. In 1921, Germany had a Social Democratic president and Schmitt's real concern about the possible abuse of Article 48 remained the Com- munists. His frightful personal experience with the Bavarian Soviet Republic left him a horrifying image of Communism. Without specifically identifying either the German extreme left or the radical right in Di_e Diktatur, Schmitt emphasized the socialist theory of the dictator- ship of the proletariat and Lenin's Soviet Dictatorship.29 As the threat of Comnunist revolution abated, Schmitt cautioned less about the possible abuse of the presidential emergency powers, and henceforth argued against placing narrow restrictions on the powers of the president. It should be noted that he began lending his strong support to the presidency while Friedrich Ebert still occupied that office. Ebert had gradually proven his non- revolutionary nature to Schmitt. Whether motivated by fear of the radical right or left, however, Carl Schmitt's interest in the continued 291bid., pp. v—viii, 204—205. 3:1 ’ Leif/5:5 -. .fl 60 existence of the Weimar constitution and state is quite evident. In relating his theory of dictatorship to the German situation Schmitt was upholding the letter and the spirit of the Weimar constitution. With the Weimar constitution in mind Schmitt attempted to reconcile his own profession of law with the actual political world. The first obstacle he encountered came in the form of Hans Kelsen's pure theory of law (reine Rechtslehre) . Law should be based upon a system of norms, Kelsen insisted, and be kept isolated from socio— logical and political considerations which taint its purity.30 Schmitt's awareness of the interrelationship of law and politics, however, led him to conclude that Kelsen's position was untenable. He challenged Kelsen's Normativism with his own theory of Decisionism, which pertained more directly to the exceptional case rather than the norm. Schmitt first presented his concept of Decisionism in two articles in 1922, and he published these in a book entitled Politische Theologie later that same year.31 Taken by itself Politische Theologie is a 30Hans Kelsen, Der Soziologische Und Der Juristische Staatsbegriff: Kritische Untersuchung Des Verhaeltnisses Von Staat Und Recht (Tuebingen, 1922) , “— PP- 2-3, 75-81, 53. 31 Carl Schmitt, "Die Staatsphilosophie der Souveraenitaetsbegriffs und Politische Theologie," Hauptprobleme der Soziologie: Erinnerungsgabe fuer Max 61 mmmwhat confusing work, lacking a precisely organized amidetailed system of thought. But the individual com— pmmmts of Schmitt's Decisionism are essentially clear. Among the more important decisionist ideas of Sctht are his concepts of sovereignty and the state of mmeption (Ausnahmezustand); two ideas which underlie his fuhne approach to real and theoretical political prob- lems. Schmitt always maintained that, "the exception is nwreinteresting than the normal situation. The normal simmtion proves nothing, the exception proves everything; it not only confirms the rule, but the rule lives only frmnthe exception."32 When referring to the anmmmzustand Schmitt envisioned a situation of a defi— Iute and critical political nature. It can at best be dmflgnated as a case of extreme emergency (N23), endan— gmflng the very existence of the state.33 Not every mdraordinary authorization, every police emergency, or emenfimcy degree, however, properly signifies an Aumuflmezustand. These often involve, on the contrary, a state of emergency (Notstand), quite dissimilar to an Aummhmezustand. Such a state of emergency could require Wehnr(Muenchen, 1922) Bd. II; Politische Theologie: ~—______—_—___ 32Politische Theologie, p. 22. 33Ibid., p. 12 5121‘ ...‘1( 62 the suspension of the entire existing legal order. If this condition arose the state would continue functioning while the existing legal order becomes insignificant};4 An Ausnahmezustand on the other hand always describes a situation other than simply anarchy and chaos, and a situation which remains susceptible to legal recognition. The state can suspend legal norms in the event of an Ausnahmezustand and the decision of the sovereign could even become absolute and destroy existing norms. But a minimum of the existing legal and political order must always remain.35 By its very definition as an exceptional case the Ausnahmezustand excludes the possibility of binding it to a norm. Politically speaking, Schmitt believed it totally impossible to predict in advance in what form or situation an Ausnahmezustand would occur, and likewise impractical to prescribe beforehand in any detail the legally permis— sible procedures to deal with unique any varying excep— tional cases.36 A constitution, from Schmitt's point of view, could at best state precisely who assumes authority in a state of exception and only in general terms 34Ibid., p. 18. 351bid., p. 19. 36Ibid. , p. 12. E ~'Li 63 describe his powers}.7 Article 48 of the Weimar consti- tution, for example, empowers the Reichspresident to deal with an Ausnahmezustand, but always under the control of 38 The numerous disorders of the early the Reichstag. republic and the frequent application of Article 48 to a multitude of diverse situations greatly influenced Schmitt's theoretical formulations on this point. And in turn these theoretical foundations provide the justifica— tion for his future opposition to the Ausfuehrungsgesetz, which aimed at defining precisely the authority of the Reichspresident under Article 48. A second reason for Schmitt's critique of Nor- mativism and of Kelsen's pure theory of law, is the realistic question of who retains the actual power in such a critical period. He rejects the idea of the applica- bility of norms to an exceptional case, because one must first establish a normal situation before the normative legal order could have any meaning. "All law is situation law," and the person or group which holds sovereignty (i.e., real power and authority) in effect decides whether there exists an exceptional case or a normal state of affairs, and exercises a monopoly over the final deci— sion establishing and guaranteeing the situation. This 37Ibid. 38Ibid., p. 17. 64 act of sovereign decisionism emphatically illustrates the political authority of the state, proving that the state does not need law, in this case norms, in order to estab— lish law.39 Thus Schmitt opens his Politische Theologie with the now famous phrase, "Sovereign is he who decides in a state of exception." Schmitt considers the relationship between the highest legal and the highest actual power as the funda- mental problem of the concept of sovereignty.41 It is this point of contention more than any other aspect which stands at the heart of the conflict between Kelsen's Normativism and the Decisionism of Carl Schmitt. Through his efforts at separating sociology and politics from the legal concept of the state Kelsen, according to Schmitt's critique, presents the state as something purely legal.4'2 Kelsen's legal state, therefore, would be identical with only its constitutional laws, that is with its basic and unifying norms.43 A system of norms would determine 39Ibid. , p. 20. 4oIbid., p. 11. 41Ibid., p. 27. 421bid., pp. 27—28. 43Ibid., pp. 28-29. w- .M: (".3 65 mwereignty for Kelsen rather than a person or a smficlogical—psychological power complex.44 Kelsen's purely legalistic approach to the state amito the question of sovereignty Schmitt found completely mmcceptable. He was too keenly aware of the realities of power politics to isolate himself solely within the con- fines of the legal discipline, while ignoring the actual polfljcal functions of the state. Schmitt perceived of the state as something more than simply the sum of its constitutional laws and, in times of crisis, he was will— ing Unforego a part of the Weimar constitution in order hapreserve the Weimar state and the constitution as a Mwle. His own theory of Decisionism showed that in a state of exception, when sovereignty emerges as the dmflding factor, norms become inoperative. The decision ofaisovereign in a state of exception could actually be boniout of nothing without regard to norms.45 Of primary importance during a state of exception is not the appli— cafility of norms, but the problem of, "Who decides?"46 Thenmin thrust of Schmitt's decisionist arguments fol— lowed this course of reasoning. He refused to eschew the political and sociological realities governing the issues 44Ibid., p. 28. 45Ibid., p. 42. 461bid., p. 46. 66 of authority and power, particularly when dealing with the state and the concept of sovereignty. Imp m1. CHAPTER III THE POLITICAL IDEAS OF CARL SCHMITT, 1922—1928 Shortly after the publication of Politische Theologie Carl Schmitt accepted a professorship at the University of Bonn, where between 1922 and 1928 the pre- cocious young scholar from Plettenberg rose to national prominence in the academic and legal professions. Finding Bonn a particularly fertile atmosphere in which to pursue his interest in political studies, he wrote several of his more influential works on the harsh realities of political life while at this provincial Rhine university. In a letter to Moritz Julius Bonn, Schmitt described his satisfaction with his new position: "Bonn is now magnifi— cent. Everything, lectures, practice sessions, etc. have the best results."1 A scholar with Schmitt's proclivity towards politics had good reason to be pleased with his new academic duties. For most of the courses Schmitt taught at Bonn were not in jurisprudence but in political science. Aside from an occasional course by Erich lCarl Schmitt to Moritz Julius Bonn, June 16, 1922, BA, Bonn Nachlass, No. 49. 67 i2: 68 Kaufmann, Schmitt held a place of distinction as the only professor in the law faculty to teach courses on poli— tics.2 In doing so he actually pioneered in the develop- ment of political science in Germany. Political science was a highly controversial dis— cipline in the Weimar Republic and had not yet achieved the status of an independent field of study. Before World War I political science in Germany merely served as an auxiliary discipline to public law. There were pre-war political treatises by Treitschke and others, but they never reached the level of a precise science. Important political subjects such as public opinion, the nature of political parties, and interest groups were either totally ignored or handled on the periphery of legal studies.3 Attempts by reputable jurists like Georg Jellinek and Fritz Stier-Somlo to advance political science further failed to acquire widespread acceptance in the profes— sion.4 Robert Michels, a close friend of Max Weber who wrote an enlightening study of political parties, never received an academic appointment in Germany because of 2 . . . . Verzeichnis der Vorlesungen a_n der Rheinischen Friedrich—Wilhelm—Universitaet fl Bonn, 1922—1928, Bonn University Archives. 3Peter Gay, Weimar Culture: The Outsider as Insider (New York, 1968), pp- 37‘39- 4Fritz Stier-Somlo, Politik (Leipzig, 1911). Georg Jellinek, Allgemeine Staatslehre (Berlin, 1900) . J, ‘115 t] (it .4 69 his socialist associations. The Hochschule fuer Politik, opened in 1920 to educate Germans in political affairs, remained an exception among academic institutions. Most law faculties maintained a skeptical attitude toward political science and for the duration of the Weimar Republic jurists debated the actual relationship between law and politics without arriving at any consensus.5 Although Carl Schmitt had not yet developed a discernible political theory during his early years at Bonn, his political sympathies were quite evident from the manner in which he approached theoretical and actual political problems. His anti—liberalism, preference for authority, and stress on order and stability predisposed him to a critical attitude toward the instability of the Weimar system. Not surprisingly the European crisis of liberal—democracy and parliamentary government attracted his attention. The intellectual critique of liberalism and rational politics itself, which began before World War I, now pervaded twentieth-century political thought. Polit— ical publicists exposed the discrepancy between the liberal ideology and the actual process of party politics. While Marxists continued to criticize parliament as an 5Ulrich Scheuner, "Die Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer in der Zeit der Weimarer Republik," Archiv des oeffentlichen Rechts, Bd. 97, Heft 3 (Septemm, 1972), pp. 359-361. same: 15 Gaet is peop 44 Me 4 self- someig is irra 44min Alfredo ire powe isadersh golitica 70 instrument of class rule, theorists like Robert Michels and Gaetano Mosca argued that instead of representing the people, ruling elites controlled parliaments in their own interest. These theorists Viewed political parties as self-perpetuating oligarchies unhampered by popular sovereignty. At the same time an increasing emphasis on the irrational element in political behavior further undermined the foundations of liberalism. The works of Vilfredo Pareto, Georges Sorel, and Max Weber elucidated the power of myth and the attraction of charismatic leadership as opposed to individuals making rational political decisions. Complicating the issue was the inability of liberal institutions to handle the influx of the masses into the political process. As a result, when the Germans started their first real experiment with a republican form of government, liberalism was already on the defensive throughout Europe. To many Germans the deficiencies of their own parliamentary system confirmed the decline of liberalism. Contrary to the liberal ideal of peaceful compromise the Reichstag served as the battleground for uncompromising interest groups and political factions. No single party ever acquired the support of a majority of the population. Coalition governments were hindered by the fact that Weimar political parties represented specific and antagonistic social classes, economic interest groups, and 4, 1M 4.. 71 irreconcilable ideologies. Although the Social Democratic Party accepted the Republic it remained essentially a class party and its socialist ideology separated it from the bulk of the middle classes. The SPD considered the Republic as simply one stage in the progression toward a socialist state. On the other hand, Germany's middle classes had originally acquiesced in the establishment of the Republic only because they saw it as a bulwark against Bolshevism and as a means to a more lenient peace. A small minority of middle class liberals did support the German Democratic Party in its cooperation with the Republic, but the hostility between liberals and socialists prevented any lasting coalitions between the DDP and the SPD. Most middle-class liberals followed Gustav Stresemann's German People's Party, which likewise found cooperation with the SPD difficult. Stresemann's party was far too nationalistic and too closely connected with industrial interests to satisfy the socialists. And further to the right the German Nationalist People's Party represented the interests of agrarians and large- scale capitalism. Ideologically the DNVP was anti— republican and reactionary, with strong monarchist ten— dencies. The two extremist parties, the National Socialists and the Communists, were avowed enemies of the Republic and refused to cooperate with any government. Only the Catholic Center Party offered a possibility for 72 umpromise. While favoring progressive social legislation amicontinually criticizing liberal capitalism, the Center Pargrwas totally committed to private property and to mahflnining the stability of the Republic. Impeded by these irreconcilable antagonisms the Wannr Republic was never to experience any period of laying governmental stability. The unstable Weimar panUament would witness twenty—one different coalition mnmrnments in its short history. At times only the efflnts of dedicated leaders in the executive branch like Eben:and Stresemann, kept the government functioning at all. Under these conditions numerous political tracts appeared in Germany dealing with the crisis of parlia— mannry government, and in 1923 Schmitt joined the public admck on liberalism. His main argument was that the nmdeniinstitution of parliamentarism had lost its intel- lectual basis.6 In this regard, Schmitt's objective was Emply to analyze the contemporary situation in Germany; rm did not attempt to undermine the Republic through his hnfillectual critique. Schmitt believed that the way for reflnmlproposals could only be opened after the problem was fiflly understood.7 One would accomplish nothing by 6Carl Schmitt, Die geistesgeschichtliche Lage des lmutigen Parlamentarismus (2nd ed.; Berlin, 1926), PP. 30, 62. 7Ibid., p. 30. 1.. . »__ia= .’d=."i."—’ __ . 1 . 33—15:. .»__._ .r,_. .. ("1' .7; IECE . L .M 4 , .7. .191 iii. Em .W\u..rui\\.nw\im .msym\m>mm (hm :M... 73 ignoring the impact of political factors such as the irrational power of myth or the role of interest groups. Schmitt's critique of liberalism, especially his recognition of the irrational in politics, is often mis— interpreted. A legend has been perpetuated that his Decisionism was actually an irrational political philos— ophy similar to certain ideas of Georges Sorel, Ernst Juenger, Oswald Spengler, and Martin Heidegger.8 Accord— ing to this legend Schmitt opted for "action instead of deliberation, for decision instead of evaluation."9 Although Schmitt did state, "dictatorship is the opposite of discussion," he never advocated any romantic or irra— tional doctrine of Decisionism.lo His Decisionism was a realistic theory based on the necessities of a concrete situation. The decision of a sovereign is a measure necessary to re-establish a normal state of affairs during a time of crisis. It is applicable only to the 8Christian Graf von Krockow, Die Entscheidung: Martin Heidegger (Stuttgart, 1958) . Heinrich Wohlgemuth, Qa_s Wesen des Politischen Er der heutigen neoromantischen Staatslehre——Eine methodischer Beitrag zu seiner 1933-1944 (New York, 1963) . Iggers, German Conception, PP. 25-26, 243, 245. Hugo Fiala (Karl Loewith) , "Politischer Dezisionismus," Internationale Zeitschrift fuer Theorie des Rechts, Jhg. 9, Heft 2, pp. 108—111. 9Neuman, Behemoth, p. 45. lOCari Schmitt, Pol. Theo., p. 80. the 1:91 74 ameptional situation and includes no advocacy of irra— tional political thought or activity. Neither was Schmitt's Decisionism undemocratic. Ebr he viewed democracy as a series of identities between nfler and ruled, governing and governed, the people and thehtrepresentatives. A democracy could be militaristic mrpacifistic, progressive or reactionary, absolute or hberal. Thus democracy and liberal parliamentarism are 1km always synonymous, though in their 19th—century mxuggles against monarchy and aristocracy a common pur— posexnuted them.11 The central criterion of democracy remains the identity of law with the will of the people.12 Majority rule is not necessarily identical with the will oftflm people. Throughout history democratic minorities or elites have felt that they embodied the true will of the people, and that they must first suspend democracy in order to develop true democracy. Bolshevik rule in Soviet Russia presents a perfect example of such misuse of democratic principles. Whoever controls the means of mmmr, propaganda, and persuasion develops the will of He people to correspond to his own will. The Soviet regime illustrates that "dictatorship is not the opposite of democracy," but rather the opposite of parliamentary llCarl Schmitt, Die geistes., pp. 32, 41. 12Ibid., pp. 34—35. Hi pm: 41 75 13 government. In fact parliamentary government often represents anti-democratic tendencies. On the European continent constitutional parlia- mentarism had its classical age in the bourgeois kingdom of Louis Philippe and its classic mani— festation in Guizot. The old monarchy and aristoc— racy were vanquished and the approaching democracy appeared as a chaotic current, against which a dam must be built. Between monarchy and democracy rose the correct middle of the bourgeois—kingdom of con— stitutional parliamentarism.l4 Schmitt perceived the essential element of this liberal system as public discussion. The free expression ofcontrasting opinions would result in rational and cor— rect decisions. Ideally discussion replaces force and {nogress would follow the victory of right over power.15 hireality, however, political parties and parliamentary life bear no resemblance to this liberal ideal. The adsting institution of parliament had degenerated into "a poor facade for the rule by parties and vested economic hmerests."l6 Instead of public discussion, small party cmmuttees or party coalitions convene secretly. Within 'Umse secret committees not the will of the people but interest groups decide the political fate of Germany. Public discussion has become an empty and idle formality l3Ibid., pp. 37—38. 14Ibid., p. 63. 15Ibia., p. 61. 16 Ibid., p. 29. following 7411mm :4' meani Enters Liberalis a: insm acts as e ".".e peep} sciousnes :ie 11an 76 following the decision making process. Consequently, parliament has "lost its hitherto existing foundation and meaning. "17 In opposition to liberal parliamentarism stands a dictatorship in the form of radical Marxism. Like liberalism it also rests upon a rational metaphysics. As an instrument of the world spirit the Marxist dictatorship acts as a rational educating—dictatorship, instructing the people of their true will. Possessing a higher con— sciousness than the masses the educating dictators "compel the unfree to freedom."18 These two rationalist systems, liberal and Marxist alike, now face a challenge by the irrational theory of 19 direct action. The challenge is theoretically repre— sented in Sorel's concept of myth and Bergson's élan vital. Myth based on intuition and not rational discussion or rational dictatorships would provide the masses with the courage and motivation for direct action and martyrdom. What men value arises not out of reasoning, but from instinct and intuition.20 l71bia., pp. 62—63. lsIbid., pp. 64, 69—70. lgIbid., p. 76. 20Ibid., pp. 80, 84—85. ten My A ‘H A“ 77 Contemporary models of political myth existed in Bolshevik Russia and Fascist Italy. Although the basis of a rational Marxist dictatorship is challenged by the theory of myth, Schmitt believed that myth still played a significant role in Soviet Russia. Originally rationalist western Marxists developed the idea of the bourgeoisie as the ultimate enemy. The idea moved east where it combined with a traditional Russian hatred of the complicated, artistic and intellectual civilization of western Europe. Together the Russians and proletarians viewed the bourgeoisie as the incarnation of a deadly mechanism threatening their way of life. Russian nationalism united with the proletarian instincts of class struggle to form a new myth. But the national myth is always stronger than the class myth. Where the national and class myths con- flict the former always emerges victorious, as demonstrated by Mussolini's Fascist movement.21 The Italian model contains ominous signs for western European governments. A new national enthusiasm based upon myth reigns in Italy, where there previously existed a constitutional and parliamentary government in the liberal Anglo—Saxon tradition. Therefore, Schmitt Claimed, "the great psychological and historical signifi— canoe Of the theories of myth cannot be denied," and the k 21. Ibid., pp. 87—89. :48 the p Che u be 54 78 rationalism of parliamentary thought has lost its dominant position. With this Italian example in mind he took little comfort in the argument made by liberals that no acceptable substitute for parliamentary government had yet been dis— covered. That argument would surely prove futile when the political power of myth confronted parliamentarism. The phrase "Parliamentarismus, fig sonst?" would not alone - - . . . . 22 be suffiCient to reVitalize the age of discu581on. Schmitt could provide no solution to the crisis nor any alternative to parliamentary government. Nowhere in this work did he even suggest dictatorship or mythically based direct action as a substitute for the Weimar system. His critique of liberalism may have contributed to the despair and pessimism regarding the future of the Repub- lic, but by pointing out the inconsistencies between the liberal ideology and the actual practices of government - . . 2 he did not cause the crisis of parliamentarism. 3 k.— 22 . Ibid., pp. 87, 89-90. 23Both Fijalkowski and Sontheimer contend that SChmitt's critique of parliamentary government emanated erm his anti—liberalism, rather than from a logical anal— y51s 0f the failings of the parliamentary system. But even One of Schmitt's harshest critics, K. D. Bracher, C9ncedes the existence of an actual crisis in German par- llamentary government. Recently Helmut Rumpf has acknowl- ed99d a certain value in the realistic attitude of . SCmutt-'8 critique of parliamentarism as it existed in the Weimar Republic. See: Juergen Fijalkowski, gig Wendung 23%. op. cit., pp. 5, 36, 63-65, 142. Kurt Sontheimer, Antidem_okratisches Denken in der Weimarer W: Die politischen Ideen des defifschen WEE ;. .406" 1 t w 44 . 54‘. ‘ will 79 By rejecting liberalism Schmitt was not repudi- ating western values, civilization and culture. In con- trast to certain misinterpretations of his work Schmitt's political philosophy did not result from the anarchy of values which plagued many of his contemporaries. Earlier Schmitt had attributed the failings of the political romantics to the loss of universal values and he was highly critical of intellectuals who fell into this cate- gory.24 Any attempts to compare his political philosophy with the thoughts of Nietzsche are completely misleading, especially since Schmitt's fervent Catholicism clashed with Nietzsche's anti—christian prejudice.25 From Schmitt's point of view Nietzsche "was a very sick man," and his philosophy held no attraction for the Weimar M Meg 1918 und 1933 (Munich, 1964), pp. 94-95, 96—98. Karl Dietrich Bracher, Die Aufloesung der Weimarer W (5th ed.; Berlin, 1971), pp. 2—7-28_—, 34—‘3‘5. Rumpf. o_p. cit., pp. 42—43. 4 Carl Schmitt, Pol. Romantik, p. 138. _ 25Hans Kohn wrote that Schmitt's political philosophy expresses a, "hatred of western civilization, Of liberalism, of humanitarianism." Georg Iggers on the other hand views Schmitt's Decisionism as the result of the European anarchy of values, and Peter Pattloch even places Schmitt's ideas into a Nietzschean framework. See: Hans Kohn, The Mind 9_f_ Germany: The Education of a Nation (New York, 1960W. 327. Iggers, 9p. cit., m3T 544-245- Peter Pattloch, Recht Als Einheit von Ordnung und Ortung: E % zum Rechtsbegriff fl Carl Schmitts "Nomos der Er£ (Aschaffenburg, 1961), p. 9. 21 jurist. mom: ‘this '01 and that and admiJ versalisx institut: :91er w politicai person a: We! of Its powel the churt the p0111 mst a1s« tha poli' Politics ethos of Pohtisc? 80 26 . . . yuist. Unlike Nietzsche and many of Schmitt's own con— taqmraries, the Catholic jurist firmly believed that, "fins world has its hierarchy of values and its humanity," amithat, "in it lives the political idea of Catholicism ."27 The Roman Catholic church as a historic complex amiadministrative apparatus continues to embody the uni— versalism of the Roman Empire.28 But as a juridical institution the Catholic church represents more than merely worldly jurisprudence, and only maintains its political power and authority by representing a concrete person and idea, i.e., Christ himself.29 The political Power of Catholicism is not a physical or military power. Its power rests solely on the belief in the authority of the church as the representative of Christ on earth. Like the political power of Catholicism all political power nmst also involve more than mere physical force. "To Hm political belongs the idea, because there is no DOlitics without authority and no authority without an "30 ethos of belief. Thus, in order to have such authority M 26 Schmitt interview, July 13, 1973. ._ 27Carl Schmitt, Roemischer Egthgliglgflgi BBQ Bfljfifighg Form (Munich, 1925), PP~ 29'30' 28 Ibid., p. 8. 29Ibid., pp. 25-26, 29—30. 3OIbid., pp. 25, 29—30. my 901 sochasG freedom a in the £0 with this Liberal o tion and i and socio is: and p oppositioo tatholici: for beyom an alliam ‘oial cap: altar coul factory a1 rEjection approach ' War sim in the ab‘ Profound 1 81 every political system must represent a person or an idea, such as God, or the people, or abstract ideas such as freedom and equality. In the twentieth century a mechanistic metaphysics in the form of liberal capitalism and socialism competes with this idea of representative political authority. Liberal capitalism and socialism deal solely with produc- tion and consumption ignoring the moral, psychological, and sociological nature of men. Such economic functional— ism and power techniques for controlling men stand in opposition to the political idea of Catholicism.31 For Catholicism recognizes the significance of ideas which go far beyond the basic material needs of men. Consequently, an alliance between the Catholic church and modern indus- trial capitalism is impossible. The union of throne and altar could not be replaced by the union of office- factory and altar.32 If Schmitt's anti-liberalism emanated from his rejection of a purely mechanical, functional, and economic approach to politics, his anti-socialism had deeper roots. Ever since his horrifying experience with the communists in the aborted Bavarian Soviet Republic he possessed a Profound hatred of Bolshevism as the potential 3lIbid., pp. 18—20. 321bid., p. 33. — ehihilator of was expressed this sen 'fortunately,‘ he civilization and hi fact that the Unive Hessian outpost . . tatholicism he dec] there both the cl cities and the Russ soil these two barb hmpean traditions inthis struggle be church must stand, European civilizati Although Ca tines the Catholic “trepudiated both iliavor of what he thrent in western hilly consider suc mites and Christia iatSchmiee suffer v . 33Carl Schn ""191. are 21291 34 Carl Schm 82 annihilator of western civilization. Schmitt clearly expressed this sentiment in a letter to M. J. Bonn: “fortunately," he said, "the sun of our thousand—year civilization and humanity still shines here, despite the fact that the University of Bonn was considered as a Russian outpost . . . ."33 In his work on political Catholicism he declared that compared to western European culture both the class—conscious proletariat of the great cities and the Russians are barbarians. United on Russian soil these two barbarian groups are challenging western European traditions and values. He went on to say that in this struggle between East and West the Catholic church must stand, "on the side of ideas and western European civilization . ."34 Although Carl Schmitt never stated what universal values the Catholic church represented, it is clear that he repudiated both relativism and materialistic ideologies in favor of what he considered as the absolute values inherent in western culture and Christianity. One could hardly consider such a traditional defense of western Values and Christianity as nihilistic or as an indication that Schmitt suffered frOm a personal crisis of values. 33Carl Schmitt to Moritz Julius Bonn, June 16, 1922, BA, Bonn Nachlass, No. 49. 3 4Carl Schmitt, Rom. Kath., pp. 51-53. That Schm. hflrolicism was ur heritage and faitl tire pragmatic P0“ tie Catholic Cents root only saw th socialism and libe teeter was the ess tea. Only the abi right and the left urued functioning of the Center Part survival of the R81 order and stabilit, Taken toge and his statements prise no systemati lavueness of many ‘ugs about his act ilournent Weimar 3' rilationship betwe if parliamentarism illegad that Schmi if parliamentarisn ‘ior being a coalj 83 That Schmitt ascribed such noble attributes to Catholicism was understandable in light of his Catholic heritage and faith. Equally significant, however, was the pragmatic political perspective from which he viewed the Catholic Center Party. In practical political matters he not only saw the Center Party as standing between socialism and liberalism, but he also believed that the Center was the essential pillar of the Weimar party sys— tem. Only the ability of the Center Party to unite the right and the left, he believed, could assure the con— tinued functioning of the system. For him the politics of the Center Party were of crucial importance in the survival of the Republic and the preservation of political order and stability. Taken together Schmitt's critique of liberalism and his statements concerning political Catholicism com— prise no systematic or precise political theory. The vagueness of many of his ideas often led to misunderstand— ings about his actual intentions. Richard Thoma, another prominent Weimar jurist, for example, misinterpreted the relationship between Schmitt's Catholicism, his critique Of parliamentarism, and his work on dictatorship. Thoma alleged that Schmitt presented Europe with the alternative Of parliamentarism or dictatorship, with Schmitt's solu- tion being a coalition of a national dictator and the Catholic church. 35 ndclarify his id 1926 on 'The Antit lassDenocracy,“ w duction to his ear true his interest receded into the b nth the political Schmitt st of parliamentarism constitutions, inc tune to embody th representatives , rt independent pol iShrticle 21 of t he representative Subject to their 0 Instructions. “38 \__.______ 3SRichard lished der Diktat svualpolitik, Bd. 36Carl Sch I“ hid noderner h due, 1926), pp. r5 ' . .ielstesgeschic 37%!” r fl 3a"Die Wei in, ed, Guenh 84 35 Catholic church. To counteract such misunderstandings and clarify his ideas Schmitt published an article in 1926 on "The Antithesis of Parliamentarism and Modern hhss Democracy," which thereafter would serve as an intro— mxmion to his earlier work on parliamentarism.36 By this time his interest in political Catholicism had already receded into the background and his preoccupation was Wiflithe political problems of the Weimar Republic. Schmitt still asserted that the essential element ofgmrliamentarism was public discussion. Parliamentary constitutions, including the Weimar constitution, con- tnnm to embody the liberal ideal of individually elected representatives, who through rational discussion arrive 37 atihdependent political decisions. A case in point is Article 21 of the Weimar constitution: "The deputies arertpresentatives of the entire people. They are only sMfiect to their own consciences and are not bound by nmtructions."38 In reality, Schmitt notes, strict party 35Richard Thoma, "Zur Ideologie des Parlamentaris- mm und der Diktatur," Archiv fuer Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, Bd. 53 (1925), PP- 215, 217. 36Carl Schmitt, "Der Gegensatz von Parlamentaris— musrmd moderner Massendemokratie," Hochland, Jhg. 23 LLme, 1926), pp. 257—270. Citations are to Schmitt's @fi geistesgeschichtliche Lage, 1926 edition. 37 Ibid., pp. 7, 9-10, 13. 38"Die Weimarer Verfassung," in Staatsverfas~ flgflgg, ed., Guenther Franz, (Munich, 1950), p, 184. fi discipline, comprov parliament. Elect. of pairing rational asses are won thrr appeal to special . hooves not discus vith which to gove. hrfrorn being a d irstrtution for ma of interest groups udlascisrn is not :entary government :vrhnore to its 0 than mass democr Democracy no modern form of definition of demc harm of the 96 Weeeneity. Whi] dtriiocracy does not hides the basis fr ml: or national. 91event of homoge‘ “We itself able \W 39 Carl Sc 85 discipline, compromises, and coalitions prevail within panUament. Elections follow a similar pattern. Instead ofnmking rational choices between candidates the voting nesses are won through propaganda apparatuses, which appeal to special interests and emotions. The objective bemmws not discussion but the procurement of a majority widiwhich to govern in the interest of one's own party. Far from being a democratic institution parliament is an nmtitution for manipulating the masses for the benefit ofinterest groups. Thus, the dual threat of Bolshevism andEascism is not the only cause of the crisis in parlia— mentary government. Parliamentary government contributes rmmh more to its own demise by its inability to adjust to modern mass democracy.39 Democracy also faces a crisis because there exists no modern form of a democratic state. To his earlier defhfition of democracy as an identity between rulers and Um will of the people, Schmitt now added the concept of mmmgeneity. While liberalism accepts all men as equals dammracy does not. Homogeneity rather than equality pro— \ndes the basis for democracy. Often religion, citizen— shqm or nationality COnstitute the necessary cohesive element of homogeneity. When necessary a democracy must Prove itself able to "exclude or destroy the heterogeneous." 39Carl Schmitt, Die geist., pp. 11, 21. fi In various historic different categorie hunter-revolution; ‘he equality of the rotheequal.“ For upossible to deter vdthhonogeneity a unity of establish: ‘hevill of the per stems from its faii critic state based Schmitt's r accepted. But eve ceded that democra dd he agreed with Unlike Schmitt, ho tutdon where “nego halal interest g 'deuotiations“ or if the functioning ditched firmly cc Although 5 iii lost its intei \w- eow” . 41Moritz "’5' “A: Bier: Ila 86 hivarious historical periods the heterogeneous fell into different categories of barbarians, atheists, aristocrats, tomnfir-revolutionaries, etc. "In democracy there is only tmaequality of the equal and the will of those who belong to am equal." For without this homogeneity it would be hmmssible to determine the will of the people. Even wiflihomogeneity a state must still overcome the diffi— culty of establishing an identity between the ruler and Hm will of the people. The crisis in the modern state stems from its failure to transform itself into a demo— cratic state based on homogeneity and identity.40 Schmitt's definition of democracy was never widely accepted. But even his liberal associate M. J. Bonn con— ceded that democracy is not identical with parliamentarism, andrm agreed with Schmitt‘s concept of homogeneity. mflike Schmitt, however, Bonn saw parliament as an insti— tution where "negotiations" or "compromises" between special interest groups take place. For Bonn such 'megotiations" or "bargainings" were a necessary element of Um functioning of parliamentary government, and he remained firmly committed to that form of government.41 Although Schmitt believed that parliamentarism hadlost its intellectual foundations he could find no 4OIbid., pp. 14, 16, 22. 41Moritz Julius Bonn to Carl Schmitt, June 11, 1926, BA, Bonn Nachlass, No. 50. neeptable replac levas concerned rentvas the less ship, or untried i exists today, apolitical syste functions tolerab 43 the fear less.ll ressvould not su because politics ’ authority without tardy, YE son panel a purely technical means 01 the ideologically deheimar state. future stability c that he had, "an r hired the German : By expres: iharbinger of do \N 42Carl Sc “Ellis 4 4Carl Sc 4 SCarl Sc dun \ we N0 87 acceptable replacement for that institution. So far as he was concerned the contemporary functioning of parlia— ment was the lesser evil compared to Bolshevism, dictator— ship, or untried methods of government.42 "Parliamentar— ism exists today," he said, "as a method of government and a political system. Like everything that exists and functions tolerably, it is useful, nothing more and nothing "43 less. He feared, however, that mere functional useful— ness would not suffice to sustain parliament forever, because politics involves authority and there is no 44 authority without a representative idea. "Parlamen— tarismus, was sonst? would prescribe an idealess status gig and a purely technical means of governing. This technical means of governing would have no defense against the ideologically oriented radical movements endangering the Weimar state. Describing his real concern for the future stability of the Weimar state Schmitt confessed that he had, "an almost continual fear for the manner in which the German right and left pursue their politics.”S By expressing this fear Schmitt was not acting as a harbinger of doom, who projects an intellectual crisis 42Carl Schmitt, Die geist., pp. 6—7. 43Ibid. 44tCarl Schmitt, Rom. Kath., p. 25. 45Carl Schmitt to M. J. Bonn, June 17, 1926, BA, Bonn Nachlass, No. 50. udtbeoretical di vrrst fears about ineffectiveness o vere well-founded . intervals of stab' inrldhar I and 1 aborted revolutio the country since Reichspresident r the emergency pow hirer constituti discussion, but t disorder. Befoe mold utilize Artz‘ occasions. 47 The const: Ertillent reliance Shiite found par leeluring and pub l a the Weimar consti 88 and theoretical dispute into a political situation. His worst fears about extremist political groups and the ineffectiveness of the Reichstag to cope with this threat were well-founded. Germany had experienced very few intervals of stability and tranquility between the end of World War I and 1925. Strikes, riots, civil war and aborted revolutions from the radical right and left plagued the country since the Weimar Assembly. At times the Reichspresident ruled the nation solely on the basis of the emergency powers authorized under Article 48 of the Weimar constitution. Not parliamentary compromises and discussion, but the frequent use of Article 48 assured the survival of the Republic in its early stages of domestic disorder.46 Before the end of the Republic the government would utilize Article 48 on more than 250 different occasions.47 The constitutional complications involved in the frequent reliance upon presidential emergency powers Schmitt found particularly interesting. In 1924 he began lecturing and publishing specifically on the problems of the Weimar constitution, always granting special attention “Frederick Watkins, The Failure 93 Constitutional Emergency Powers under the German Republic (Cambridge, Mass., 1939), pp. 9, 133. 47Clinton Rossiter, Constitutional Dictatorship: Crisis Government in the Modern Democracies (Princeton, 1948)! p. 33. — tolrticle 48.48 play a central :0 politics. Schmit tidy and power of domestic peace an miybe achieved ' He did not view t ahogator of the dilated his theor Social Democrat F Soimitt perceived who in an Ausnahm heileimar consti The grave dential emergency "diva: legal and 1 imists the contre iidiom of the pre 49 . iii oiling to ti 89 48 to Article 48. Henceforth, the Reichspresident would play a central role in Schmitt's approach to Weimar politics. Schmitt's goal was always to insure the integ— rity and power of the Weimar state. This presupposed domestic peace and tranquility, which he believed could only be achieved in times of turmoil by a strong president. He did not View the Reichspresident as an Ersatzkaiser or abrogator of the constitution. In fact when Schmitt for— mulated his theory of presidential emergency powers the Social Democrat Friedrich Ebert held that office. Instead Schmitt perceived the president as a commissarial dictator, who in an Ausnahmezustand, would act as the defender of the Weimar constitution and state. The grave danger of abuse inherent in the presi— dential emergency powers created a heated controversy in Weimar legal and political circles. Amongst Weimar jurists the controversy surrounded the correct interpre— tation of the precise wording and intention of Article 48.49 Owing to the frequent use of Article 48 and the 48Vorlesungsverzeichnis, Univ. of Bonn. 49Article 48 states: "If a state does not fulfill the duties imposed by the Reichsconstitution or the law of the Reich, the Reichspresident can hold it to the perform— ance of these duties with the aid of armed force. The Reichspresident can, when public order and Security is considerably disturbed or endangered, take the necessary measures in order to restore public security and order; in necessary cases intervene with the aid of armed force. To this goal he is allowed to temporarily suspend msettled mature . that this became ‘ oonierence of the lawyers, held in . Pounded i: none than 97 memb: only half that nun this first confern jurists. Particij huiasky of Munici teller of Leipzig habinqen.51 0n the is conference took 0 overwhelming opin that the limits 0 fire enumerated i \—._._..____ ill or a part of 114.115, 117, 11 All measc article must be i the Reichspreside if the Reichstag determined by a 1 ofitted). “Die v 50"Verhan Staatsrechtslehrn Venoeffentlichunn Staatsrechtslehn 1Scheun 90 numettled nature of paragraph five, it is not surprising Hut flfls became the major issue of debate at the first mnfierence of the Association of German Constitutional Lawyers, held in Jena on April 14 and 15, 1924.50 Founded in 1922, the Association never acquired nmre than 97 members at its peak and normally attracted mfly half that number to its conferences. Nonetheless, Hus first conference included most of Germany's renowned jurists. Participating were Stier—Somlo of Cologne, Nmflasky of Munich, Thoma and Anschuetz of Heidelberg, Heller of Leipzig, Jellinek of Kiel, and Bilfinger of Tuebingen.51 On the issue of presidential emergency powers the conference took on the form of a general debate. The overwhelming opinion of the participating jurists was that the limits of the Reichspresident's emergency powers were enumerated in paragraph two of Article 48. These all or a part of the stipulated basic rights in articles 114, 115, 117, 118, 123, 124, and 153. All measures taken under paragraphs 1 or 2 of this article must be immediately reported to the Reichstag by the Reichspresident. These measures are to be suspended if the Reichstag so demands . . . . The details will be determined by a federal law" (paragraph four has been mfitted). "Die Weimarer Verfassung," pp. 188—189. 50"Verhandlungen der Tagung der deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer zu Jena am 14. und 15. April 1924," Veroeffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer, Heft 1, (Berlin, 1924). 51Scheuner, 92° cit., pp. 351, 354—355. jurists argued the tie seven articles enumerated in this federal law detail nonresident in c interpretations. oiacompletion 1a inparagraph five, Erwin Jacc lecturing on the d the Jena conferenc from the one held Schmitt held that Mars in times of Save of a completi concurred with thi received the enornn hri. As a basis 5iloificant ambigu first sentence of \~_________ 52 " Verhan 53Cc‘arl Sc eds Reichspraesid Verhandlungen , " edition of Schmit iindented as an ap 91 jurists argued that the Reichspresident could suspend only the seven articles of the constitution specifically enumerated in this paragraph. They urged passage of a federal law detailing precisely the emergency powers of the president in order to prevent future abuses or mis— interpretations. For these jurists the immediate passage of a completion law (Ausfuehrungsgesetz) , as stipulated in paragraph five, was seen as an urgent necessity.52 Erwin Jacobi and Carl Schmitt, the two members lecturing on the dictatorial powers of the president at the Jena conference, presented a divergent interpretation from the one held by a majority of their colleagues.53 Schmitt held that the Reichspresident assumes extensive powers in times of disorder and opposed the immediate pas— sage of a completion law detailing his powers. Jacobi concurred with this interpretation but his lecture never received the enormous attention later granted Schmitt's work. As a basis for his argument Schmitt pointed out a significant ambiguity in the wording of Article 48. The first sentence of paragraph two states that the president 52"Verhandlungen," op. cit., pp. l38-l39. 53Carl Schmitt and Erwin Jacobi, "Die Diktatur des Reichspraesidenten nach Art. 48 der Reichsverfassung," "Verhandlungen," pp. 63-136. Citations are to the 1928 edition of Schmitt's Die Diktatur, where his lecture appeared as an appendix. can take 'necessa security and orde articles he may 5 noted that in tin necessitate the s stitutional artic tense two could n1 he heichspreside: me for taking a1 tine am additiona humerated rights hhepmmrs of special authority authority of the hhse"necessary This uniq direct outcome of could predict the oonsequently be a hnecessary to a enumerate precise aaasures.55 Unde atemporary soven \_.________._ S4Ibid. I 55 Carl S 92 can take "necessary measures" to reestablish public security and order, whereas sentence two lists seven articles he may suspend to achieve this goal. Schmitt noted that in times of crisis "necessary measures" might necessitate the suspension of other, nonenumerated con— stitutional articles. Therefore, he concluded that sen- tence two could not serve as a limitation on sentence one. The Reichspresident has a general authority under sentence one for taking all "necessary measures" and at the same time an additional special authority to suspend certain enumerated rights under sentence two. But the limitations on the powers of the Reichspresident pertain only to this special authority. Any attempt to enumerate the general authority of the Reichspresident would be contrary to the 54 phrase "necessary measures. " This unique interpretation of Article 48 was a direct outcome of Schmitt's Decisionism. Since no one could predict the exact nature of a crisis beforehand and consequently be able to determine the measures that would be necessary to alleviate the crisis, it is impossible to enumerate precisely what would constitute future necessary 55 measures. Under Article 48 the Reichspresident acts as a temporary sovereign during a crisis. He decides when an 54Ibid., pp. 225, 229. 55Carl Schmitt, Pol. Theo., p. 12. nonnahmezustand e: neet this crisis. mahsolute seven to the constituti. The Const touted the Reich: htiole 48, but ti oomissarial dict. Assembly had been thepeople to est. hen the Assembly oonstitution its ; constitutional an: hirer of the Reici bound to this new constitution unde 'either a soverei Excludes the othe iiStance, be tran constitution itse iIticle 48.58 56Carl Sc 57Ibid. , 58 Ibid. , 93 Ausnahmezustand exists and what measures are necessary to meet this crisis. The Reichspresident by no means becomes an absolute sovereign dictator, because he is always bound to the constitution and the consent of the Reichstag. The Constitutional Assembly realized that it granted the Reichspresident unusual authority under Article 48, but this authority was intended as that of a commissarial dictator and not a sovereign one.56 This Assembly had been a sovereign dictatorship authorized by the people to establish a new legal and political order. When the Assembly completed its work and produced a new constitution its sovereignty ended. The newly created constitutional and political order actually limits the power of the Reichspresident. As a commissarial dictator bound to this new order he could not legally destroy its constitution under Article 48. A country can have, "either a sovereign dictatorship or a constitution, one excludes the other."57 The Republic could not, for instance, be transformed into a monarchy nor could the constitution itself be altered in any manner under Article 48.58 56Carl Schmitt, Die Dik., p. 233. 57Ibid., p. 238. 581b1d., pp. 242, 254. A Reichsp non-enchanted co tone 'necessary that he receives infringements are tons, who seek to hytemporarily sun tion.59 Yet, even tourist a basic 1 him the Reichspn institutions ment: theheichstag, and It was Sc] the Reichspresiden tinged through a asimple completil deposition to the Lav detailing the President stemmed he Constitutiona liters because th Siteration existed 94 A Reichspresident may infringe upon any individual non-enumerated constitutional articles if he deems these to be "necessary measures" to meet a crisis, providing that he receives the consent of the Reichstag. Such infringements are typical methods of commissarial dicta- tors, who seek to save the constitutional order as a whole by temporarily suspending individual parts of a constitu— tion.59 Yet, even in an Ausnahmezustand there continues to exist a basic constitutional and organizational minimum which the Reichspresident cannot suspend. These are the institutions mentioned in Article 48: the Reichspresident, the Reichstag, and the government.60 It was Schmitt's contention that the authority of the Reichspresident as stated in Article 48 could only be changed through a constitutional amendment and not through a simple completion law relative to paragraph five.61 His opposition to the immediate passage of such a completion law detailing the precise emergency powers of the Reichs— president stemmed from very practical considerations. The Constitutional Assembly granted these exceptional powers because they realized that an abnormal and critical situation existed in Germany. From this Schmitt inferred 591bid. 6oIbid., pp. 244-246. 6lIbid., p. 257. fl that the Assembly paragraph five 1111 Germany in 1924 h nomad state of a viile Germany sti bility would only yer the existing proposed law hind republic, but the thevay for revol Carl Schm leagues at the Je jurists never ter limits and correc “hority of Weima define the limits President and dem hrists like the ihhained highly c hihiasky, a staun hter oppose Schn [Hills the Reich, \w one. 62 95 that the Assembly intended to delay the fulfillment of paragraph five until Germany returned to normality. And Germany in 1924 hardly reflected the restoration of a normal state of affairs.62 To tamper with the constitution while Germany still struggled through a period of insta— bility would only intensify the crisis and possibly endan— ger the existing constitution itself. Not only would the proposed law hinder the president's defense of the republic, but the amending of the constitution would open the way for revolutionary and reactionary amendments. Carl Schmitt failed to persuade many of his col— leagues at the Jena conference or thereafter. Weimar jurists never terminated their debate over the actual limits and correct interpretation of Article 48. A majority of Weimar jurists persisted in their efforts to define the limits of the emergency powers of the Reichs— president and demanded the passage of a completion law. Jurists like the Munich law professor Hans Nawiasky, remained highly critical of Schmitt's interpretation. Nawiasky, a staunch defender of parliamentarism, would later oppose Schmitt in the famous 1932 trial Prussia versus the Reich, where the central issue concerned the 621bid., pp. 258-259. Wei powers winery's polita' linitations of Ar dedomestic stat dude in mind pron the issue at the idiot convened in proposal for pass at the conference but later maneuve horn succeeded in hill into the Rei ever passed the E they power of th The inter deciding factor 1 lrudiments were u he jurists, of sThaitt' s cautio heidelberg law p 63For an rarliamentarism Parties see: gig hhiebingen, 1925) 96 63 For those with emergency powers of the Reichspresident. Nawiasky's political convictions the incertitude as to the limitations of Article 48 greatly aggravated the danger to the domestic stability of Germany.64 With this incerti— tude in mind prominent German lawyers once again debated the issue at the thirty—third German Jurist Conference, which convened in Heidelberg during September 1924. A proposal for passage of a completion law was introduced at the conference and such a bill actually was written. But later maneuvers in the political arena by chancellor Marx succeeded in preventing the introduction of this bill into the Reichstag.65 In the final analysis no bill ever passed the Reichstag limiting or defining the emer— gency power of the Reichspresident under Article 48. The interpretation of Carl Schmitt was never the deciding factor in this controversy, though later his arguments were utilized in defense of presidential power. Some jurists, of course, did recognize the wisdom of Schmitt's caution. Even Richard Thoma, a well known Heidelberg law professor who favored passage of a 63 . . . . For an indication of Hans NaWiasky's defense of parliamentarism and his attack on the critics of political parties see: Die Stellung der Regierung _ifl Modernen Staat (Tuebingen, 1925) . 64Hans Nawiasky, “Das Durchfuehrungsgesetz zum Artikel 48 der Reichsverfassung," Das Recht, Jhg. 28, Heft 20, (Sept. 20, 1924), pp- 454—468. 65 . Scheuner, o_p. Cit., p. 372. mletiom law. In are stable times inquest that imrn heighten demands further aggravate political and psyn tbefate of all r orders and upheav. hheGermans to st hicbspresident, . his ability to de Schmitt c Strong president . iehmew, however, alone could offer ind despite his a Modern democra hlnewill of the lion in direct (1 legal Society in the methods of 97 completion law, recommended postponing the issue until more stable times. He justified postponement with Schmitt's argument that immediate attempts to pass such a law would heighten demands for general constitutional revision and further aggravate a volatile situation.66 But concrete political and psychological factors actually determined the fate of all reform proposals for Article 48. The dis- orders and upheavals of the early Republic predisposed the Germans to strong centralized leadership by the Reichspresident, and they were quite reluctant to limit his ability to deal with future crises. Schmitt continually extolled the virtues of a strong president as a bulwark against domestic disorder. He knew, however, that in the long run a strong president alone could offer no solution to the parliamentary crisis. And despite his emphasis on the necessity of establishing a modern democratic state form, with an identity between the will of the people and their rulers, he saw no solu— tion in direct democracy. In a lecture before the Berlin Legal Society in December 1926 he stated that even though, "the methods of direct democracy have often been 66Richard Thoma, "Die Regelung der Diktaturgewalt," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 29, Heft l7/l8r (1924), PP. 654-664. monarended as a thiscorrection in He acknow oonstitution cont democracy through dunlV_°1__k3£“t$_Ch_e provisions provid denocracy. By a decide a dispute Reichstag and the could exercise th legislation for t People really leg or decide a case “— 67cm 16 entitled, Volkser 13 huslgung deg her ummittelbarer \ titatnons are to 68Article shall he brought the Reichspreside A law who if at least one-‘ l0arefen:endurn 1 so petition. An initi ii the qualified h111 must accomp Shall lay the hi the before the Place if the req hichstag . . . r 98 recommended as a means to correcting parliamentarism . . this correction would quickly lead to a collision."67 He acknowledged that Article 73 of the Weimar constitution contained two possibilities for direct democracy through initiative (Volksbegehren) and referen— 68 dum (Volksentscheid) . Yet, Schmitt denied that these provisions provide any permanent foundation for direct democracy. By a referendum the people could themselves decide a dispute within the Reichstag, or between the Reichstag and the government. Similarly, the people could exercise their right of initiative and propose legislation for the Reichstag. In neither case do the people really legislate. They merely propose legislation or decide a case of conflict. Only in very extraordinary 67This lecture was expanded into a short book 2u_r Auslegung (leg Weimarefierfassung 113d zu_i*—I7ehre _v_on 5131; unmittelbaren Demokratie (Berlin, 1927) , (and all citations are to this book), p. 51. 68Article 73 states: "A law passed by the Reichstag shall be brought to a referendum before its promulgation if the Reichspresident so decides within a month. A law whose promulgation is deferred at the demand of at least one-third of the Reichstag shall be submitted to a referendum if one-twentieth of the qualified voters SO petition. An initiative shall be resorted to if one—tenth Of the qualified voters so request. A fully elaborated bill must accompany such a request. The Reich government shall lay the bill together with a statement of its atti— tude before the Reichstag. The popular vote does not take Place if the requested bill is passed unchanged by the Reichstag . . .," "Die Weimarer Verfassung," p. 191. circumstances do hr instance, Whi aocepted unchang‘ rented to the per hold combine an process, which Sr legislation by ti fnrough this proc nary legislative cases the people legislative authc irregular nature transforming it 1' thehheichstag. '1 crate and the Com the princely pro; hive thinker. He privilege or prop future manipulati hirthermore, he ( he entire proce: race on this pro V 69Carl S soy—d.” 99 circumstances do the people themselves actually legislate. For instance, when an initiative of the people is not accepted unchanged by the Reichstag it must then be pre- sented to the people for a referendum. This situation would combine an initiative and a referendum into one process, which Schmitt defines as "the procedure for legislation by the people," (Volksgesetzgebungsverfahren) .69 Through this procedure the people legislate and the ordi- nary legislative institutions are pushed aside. In such cases the people themselves become the direct bearers of 70 It was Schmitt's belief that the legislative authority. irregular nature of this popular legislative act precluded transforming it into an extra-legislative organ next to the Reichstag. The joint referendum by the Social Demo— crats and the Communists in 1926 for the expropriation of the princely properties had obviously alarmed the conserva— tive thinker. He held no particular admiration for royal privilege or property, but he was disturbed by possible future manipulation of Article 73 by extremist groups. Furthermore, he doubted both the very democratic basis of the entire process and the feasibility of frequent reli— ance on this procedure. Km 69Carl Schmitt, Volksentscheid, pp. 10, 14. 7°1bid., pp. 22, 33. Schmitt natural restrain hole cannot mee sion decide upon nnlated and word initiative of tho power of formula ence on the resu.‘ allegedly stems, dependent upon t] Given the questia "fl greatly fron dpnrticular tree hi the minority v the outcome. 71 Thus, th: Salution to the t hrsen the probln this constitution he father of en. tlilieyuhlic nigh hi endanger the he legislative \_——_ 7lIbid. . __.._. 72 100 Schmitt emphasized that modern mass society places natural restraints on direct democracy. The people as a whole cannot meet together in an assembly, and by discus— sion decide upon an initiative. Such initiatives are for— mulated and worded by a minority and then presented as an initiative of the entire people. Those who control the power of formulating an initiative have a deciding influ— ence on the results. The people, from whom the initiative allegedly stems, merely answer yes or no, with the results dependent upon the precise wording of the initiative. Given the question peace or war the answer would certainly vary greatly from a question with more precise details of a particular treaty. In addition, propaganda and agitation by the minority controlled press would greatly influence the outcome . 71 Thus, this form of direct democracy offers no solution to the crisis of parliamentarism and could even worsen the problem if extremists were allowed to manipulate this constitutional clause. Schmitt cited the fears of the father of the Weimar constitution, Hugo Preuss, that the Republic might become dependent upon direct democracy 72 and endanger the young parliamentary system in Germany. The legislative initiative of the people, therefore, 711bid., pp. 31—38. 721b1d., p. 51. should not be co equal to the leg always decisioni intended meaning oases.73 By intro ideas on contemp himself as one o is achieved this theUmiversity 0 Born career came fr0h the provinc hierarchical ce sented for the f basic political scholarship his 101 should not be considered as an extra organ of government equal to the legislative power of the Reichstag. It is always decisionist in character and retains its true and intended meaning only when exercised in exceptional 73 cases. By introducing an unending series of controversial ideas on contemporary political issues Schmitt established himself as one of Weimar's most influential publicists. He achieved this national reputation while a professor at the University of Bonn. The crowning achievements of his Bonn career came in 1928 just as he was about to depart from the provincial Rhine university for the intellectual and political center of Berlin. In two books, EEE Begriff dgg Politischen and the Verfassungslehre, Schmitt pre— sented for the first time a specific description of his basic political philosophy and a systematic elucidation oflfls constitutional theory.74 Although in terms of scholarship his work on constitutional law far surpasses his political treatise, the latter has attracted much more attention and criticism.75 The contentious nature of Der 73Ibid., pp. 47-48. 74Carl Schmitt, Der Begriff des Politischen (Berlin, 1963), and Verfassungslehre (Berlin, 1970). 75 See: Mathias Schmitz, Die Freund-Feind—Theorie —-——.—§_—_ ———————— __—______——_—______‘___ politik, Bd. 67, (1932): Pp. 732—749. Hasso Hofmann, M arises d: political. Fori to which politic. the distinction i The dist the most extreme nassociation 0 not necessarily the foreigner, a nature he is in something other flict with him i Comeit has mean hinot as a net lv . .nsed Wlth ec Ono Whom, genera 102 Begriff arises directly out of Schmitt's definition of the political. For him, "the specific political distinction Uswhich political actions and motives can be reduced, is Um distinction between friend and enemy."76 The distinction between friend and enemy involves thermmt extreme intensity of a binding or separation, of mnassociation or disassociation. A political enemy is notrmcessarily morally evil. "He is merely the other, the foreigner, and it is sufficient that according to his nature he is in a special intensive sense existentially something other and foreign, so that in extreme cases con— flict with him is possible . . . ."77 The friend—enemy concept has meaning only within this existential framework and not as a metaphor or symbol. It should not be con- fused with economics, morals, or private feelings. Com— petitors, general opponents, and private enemies consti- tute no political enemy, because, "the enemy is only the 78 public enemy," i.e., hostis and not inimicus. Moreover, "Feindschaft——Grundbegriff des Politischen?" Zeitschrift fuer Politik, Jhg. 12, Heft 1 (February, 1965), pp. 17-39. mnien Freund, L'essence d3 politique (Paris, 1965). A complete misinterpretation of Schmitt's ideas is included hiCharles Frye, "Carl Schmitt's Concept of the Political," 333 Journal of Politics, XXVIII (November, 1966), pp. 818— 830. —_ 76Carl Schmitt, Der Begriff, p. 26. 77Ibid., p. 27. 78Ibid., p. 29. Hostis refers here to the public Political enemy and inimicus to the unpolitical private his political en hatred of one'5 i The polin ni'cself. It rs from various are: economics, nation potentially polii ing bindings and neutral or polit: since each remain intense degree 01 occur in any para political distinr AM mills in serious Significant. Th6 103 this political enmity contains no obligation of personal hatred of one's public enemy. The political has no precise and immutable nature in itself. It receives its substance, power and motivation from various areas of human life, such as religion, economics, nationalism, etc. All of these areas are potentially political and at different times produce vary— ing bindings and separations. None of these areas are neutral or politically free spheres as liberals contend, since each remains at least potentially political. If an intense degree of association or disassociation should occur in any particular area the result would be the political distinction of friend and enemy. This only occurs in serious cases where the degree of intensity is significant. The decisive factor is whether or not the motives of men, be they economic, religious, ideological, or other, are strong enough to transform this potentiality into a real situation of political conflict.79 One can comprehend this infamous criterion of friend and enemy only in the context of Schmitt's concept of the state as the political status of an organized enemy. Whenever Schmitt utilizes the term enemy he means hostis. For the historical background to these terms see: George Schwab, "Enemy oder Foe: Der Konflikt der modernen Politik," Epirrhosis: Festgabe fuer Carl Schmitt (Berlin, 1968). 79Ibid., pp. 20, 24, 36, 38. people in a tern political and t] the state.80 Pr may have both aspects. The m is war. Intern; of an armed strr tically through the concept itse he political 1i real possibility enemy distinctic nation as the na 82 other nation . is the essential friend from the between Scfii't—t if the revoluti ti0n" like Erns fulfilling exis mgStom of St l-Yn 1929)“? 104 people in a territorial unit. The state is something political and the political is something always related to the state.80 Political distinctions between friend and enemy have both their domestic and their international aspects. The most extreme realization of political enmity is war. Internationally war manifests itself in the form of an armed struggle between organized states and domes— tically through civil war within an organized state. But the concept itself is neither aggressive nor militaristic. The political lies not in the conflict itself but in the real possibility of conflict and the necessary friend— 81 enemy distinction. Likewise, this concept designates no nation as the natural or perpetual friend or enemy of any other nation.82 On the international scene the state acts as the essential political unit which distinguishes the friend from the enemy, and at the same time maintains the means with which to carry out a struggle against the enemy. As the deciding political unit the state assumes 80lbid., p. 21. 81Ibid., pp. 33, 37. Thus, there is no connection between Schmitt's concept of the political and the ideas of the revolutionary conservatives of the "Front Genera— tion" like Ernst Juenger, who saw in the struggle itself a fulfilling existential experience. See Ernst Juenger Eh_e Storm of Steel, trans. , Basil Creighton (Garden City, ——. N.Y., 192977 82 Ibid., p. 35. an enormous com through its power and ultimate arl land the finai and be killed. 83 The inte its ability to a Consequently, t] determine the do uals or groups n peace and exist Staatsfeind. 84 lTOups may exis‘ to the state. : relevancy for p; the role of Sta trol over the d flict achieves Policy antagoni 83w. “SPEE- SChnitt is no the state in 9 Wish the frie " . . in no w Wery man who determined and central system 0r corporation 105 muenormous concentration of power in itself. The state, through its power to conduct wars, becomes the unequaled andufltimate arbiter over the lives of men. A state can demand the final sacrifice, that its citizens both kill and be killed.83 The international status of a state depends upon its ability to assure domestic order, peace, and stability. Consequently, the state in cases of necessity must also determine the domestic enemy or Staatsfeind. Any individ— uals or groups which seriously threaten the domestic peace and existence of the state fall into the category of 84 Within the state competing parties and Staatsfeind. groups may exist so long as they present no serious danger to the state. Schmitt's concept of the political has relevancy for party politics only when a party assumes the role of Staatsfeind. If the state loses complete con— trol over the domestic situation, and domestic group con- flict achieves a stronger intensity than the foreign policy antagonisms against another state, the result is 83Ibid., pp. 45—46. 84Ibid., pp. 39, 46-47. It should be noted that Schmitt is not advocating here totalitarian control by Um state in granting it this sovereign role to distin— ‘guish the friend from the enemy. This sovereign role, . . in no way means that every detail of the life of every man who belongs to the political unit must be determined and commanded by the political, or that a central system should destroy every other organization or corporation." P. 39. civil war and ti enmy. But undo its own enemy or: ular group as a A world would disappear between friend i politics. As 11 of sovereign sti enemy will rema: Perhaps clearer insight the rest of his the political an each of his futu political appro which played su hitings. Only foreign enemies Stability. In lliming for the "is to survive lvth the domest llrthemore, on 106 civil war and the domestic distinction between friend and enemy. But under such conditions each group determines its own enemy rather than the state identifying any partic— ular group as a Staatsfeind. A world in which the possibility of such conflicts would disappear would be a world without the distinction between friend and enemy, and by definition a world without politics. As long as the world is organized into a system of sovereign states the distinction between friend and enemy will remain. Perhaps no other work by Schmitt exhibits a clearer insight into his basic outlook on politics. For the rest of his life he would adhere to his definition of the political and use it as the point of departure for each of his future political works. Central to his entire political approach is the state, the organizational unit which played such an important part even in his earliest writings. Only the state can protect its citizens from foreign enemies and maintain domestic order, peace and stability. In this respect Re}: Begriff contained a warning for the Weimar Republic. If the Weimar Republic was to survive as a sovereign state it must distinguish both the domestic and the foreign friend from the enemy. Furthermore, one cannot separate politics from other 85Ibid., p. 32. areas of life an potentially poli religion, culturr unrealistic. Th derives its subs serious crisis t various areas of rants, or the st aignty. Needless point of Schmitt presented in sys this work appear highly respected 30th Schmitt an he as an indep choline of publ' the traditional tional law with fliture studies hour of a more 86Rudol “Mich, 1928). 107 aremsof life and society, since these areas are all potentially political. Attempts by liberals to separate religion, culture, economics, and law from politics are muealistic. The political per se has no essence and derives its substance only from other areas. In times of serious crisis the Weimar state must either intervene in various areas of life and society when necessity so war- rants, or the state will abrogate its position of sover- eignty. Needless to say, the state was also the focal pohn:of Schmitt's constitutional theory, which he first presented in systematic form in his Verfassungslehre. nus work appeared in 1928 almost simultaneously with Verfassung End Verfassungsrecht, a book written by the himfly respected Berlin law professor Rudolf Smend.86 BoUoSchmitt and Smend sought to establish constitutional law as an independent branch of study within the dis- flpline of public law. But more important they challenged the traditional, purely legalistic approach to constitu- Uonal law with two theories which presented politics as maintegral part of constitutional law and government. Schmitt and Smend not only laid a solid foundation for future studies but also provided convincing arguments in favor of a more politically oriented handling of 86Rudolf Smend, Verfassung und Verfassungsrecht (Munich, 1928). mtemporary con their books maria leimar jurists c lonetlaeless, tha ieiear jurists. In promc tend found a cc lelsen and the m retain the separ had already cont M and ti changed. It was constitution as its basic norms tressed Schmitt. ' constitution as Specific type 0 does not have a l constitution, ' lecial type of 108 contemporary constitutional problems. For this reason their books mark a turning point in the dispute among Weimar jurists over the relationship of law and politics.87 Nonetheless, that controversy would never be resolved by Weimar jurists. In promoting their respective theories Schmitt and Smend found a common opponent in the normativeness of Hans Kelsen and the more traditional jurists who wanted to retain the separation between law and politics. Schmitt had already confronted Kelsen in his work on Politische 'Nmologie and their fundamental differences had not changed. It was Kelsen's definition of a state and a constitution as something purely legal (i.e., the sum of its basic norms and constitutional laws), which most dis- tressed Schmitt. As a Decisionist Schmitt perceived a state and a constitution as much more than a system of norms or a collection of individual laws. He defined a constitution as the entire concrete condition of a specific type of political unit and order. The state does not have a constitution, but rather, "the state is a constitution," in that the constitution denotes a . 88 specral type of rule and form of the state. One cannot 87Scheuner, op. cit., p. 352. 88Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, pp. 3, ll—l6. separate politi< itself is actua Althougl cal of Kelsen’ s Schmitt's Decis role in Smend' 5 state and its o e‘nich other asp into a meaningf constitution is developments. 89 ill state as co “titration, sc Stability and 0 Schmitt concrete pol it i bility of the p W to p . “1th 1n Ge 1 he Weimar Cons bl a C°nstitutp eighty has \ B9 SNEnc 109 separate politics from a state or constitution, which itself is actually a political unit and form. Although no Decisionist, Smend was equally criti- cal of Kelsen's concept of the state. Just as with Schmitt's Decisionism the state also played a central role in Smend's "Integration Theory." Smend viewed the state and its constitution as the institutions through which other aspects of life and society are integrated into a meaningful whole. Therefore, the state like its constitution is inseparably connected with political developments.89 But whereas Smend saw the constitution and state as constantly developing through the process of integration, Schmitt displayed a greater tendency toward stability and order. Schmitt always concerned himself with the existing concrete political and legal situation and with the sta— bility of the political order; which in this case was the Weimar Republic. It is evident from Schmitt's Verfassungslehre that he accepted the Weimar constitution and state as the legitimate and legally constituted authority in Germany. He perceived the establishment of the Weimar constitution as an act of sovereign Decisionism by a constitution-granting power. Since 1789 this sovereignty has rested with the people, and as the 89Smend, Q. cit., p. 78. constitutions“ oidP°1itical 1 es definitely 5 people, and at l and against the hole change th‘ sovereign DeciSS oileinar. Nonethel nev state when 1 instead they mea stitution to rep state essentiall this Schmitt 110 nstitution-granting power they decide the type and form a political unit and order. The Weimar constitution s definitely a "decision for democracy," by the German ople, and at the same time a "decision for the Republic 1 against the monarchy."90 Until the German people as a ale change the existing order through an act of vereign Decisionism Schmitt would submit to the authority Weimar. Nonetheless, the German people did not create a w state when they established the Weimar constitution. stead they merely introduced a liberal—democratic con— itution to replace the monarchy and left the German ate essentially in the same form as the Second Reich.9l this Schmitt meant that the Weimar state as a sover~ gn territorial political unit, with which the German a hple identify, had not changed appreciably from the old ch of 1871. It now functions as a liberal—democratic te, but still as a sovereign German nation—state. And ugh Schmitt claimed that a state and constitution are , when he refers to the political aspects of a con- tution he often means the power of the state as a itical unit, its government, bureaucracy, and army. 90 Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, pp. 20-24, 77, 91 Ibid., p. 97. inns, bl’ ”mitt su'tution he was But beca lore of politica o “to argued t according to Sch tutional laws ma stitution as a w nder Article 73 since this artic paper and not cc sharp distinctic lava and the cor. Siltlily details a 111 s, by submitting to the authority of the Weimar con- itution he was upholding the power of the German state. But because a constitution denotes the type and of political and legal order within the state, itt argued that the "constitution is inviolable." ording to Schmitt's interpretation individual consti~ ional laws may be altered under Article 76 but the con— dtution as a whole cannot.92 Neither can referendums er Article 73 sanction a violation of the constitution, ace this article merely grants the people legislative ver and not constitutional—giving powers.93 He draws a arp distinction here between individual constitutional m and the constitution itself. Constitutional laws are rmly details and subject to amendment; however, the con— .tution determines the specific form of a political unit iorder. Consequently, the original essence of a con— tution could only be changed by an act of sovereign usionism by all the German people, as was the case when 921bid., pp. 25—26. Article 76 states: "The con- itution may be amended by means of legislation. Acts the Reichstag regarding the amending of the constitu- on are effective, however, only if two—thirds of the pal members are present and at least two-thirds of the asent members agree. Acts of the Reichsrat regarding andments to the constitution also require a majority two—thirds of the votes cast. If on the initiative of apeople a constitutional amendment is adopted through a krendum, the consent of a majority of those entitled vote is required . . .," "Die Weimarer Verfassung,“ 192. 931bid., p. 98. they first estab topic a constitu complete alterat ould not pass a could transform anarchy. Any 1 Pepublic into an constitutional r Schmitt stated c anarchical prim destruction of t defense of the e 39m“ Signific tonstitlltlon. The issu controVersy 0Ve1 lent, became par Period! 1929493 Sllrn‘attl SVe & d s leerle“Cing one .udes. Under ti 112 first established the constitution. Following this a constitutional change is quite different from the ete alteration or destruction of a constitution. One not pass a law under Article 76, for example, that transform Weimar Germany into a Soviet Republic or a hy. Any law that attempts to change the Weimar Lie into any other form of government besides a Ftutional republic and democracy is unconstitutional. ft stated categorically that, "the restoration of :hical principles could only be achieved through the uction of the constitution."94 In pursuit of this se of the existing order he kept a consistent stand at significant and wide ranging amendments to the itution. The issues of constitutional change, like the >versy over the emergency powers of the Reichspresi— became particularly significant during the crisis L 1929-1933. At the time of the publication of :t's Verfassungslehre in 1928, Weimar Germany was .encing one of its most stable and prosperous inter— Under the leadership of Hindenburg, who offered dogical security to many Germans, the government ed to muddle through with one coalition after another; e government was at least functioning. Along with 94Ibid., p. 104. pip relative 5t It appeared that sufficient time eternal differe nation of Carl disrupt the cont Eerenained pess only because he :ensions and irr be shown by his Scimitt's main i toning and to e 113 elative stability went a growing economic prosperity. eared that the Republic might survive if allotted ient time to consolidate its power and solve its al differences. Despite the traditional character- n of Carl Schmitt, he never made any attempts to t the continuation of this brief period of stability. ained pessimistic about the future of the Republic ecause he recognized the extent of its internal ms and irreconcilable political factions. As will wn by his actual political activity before 1929, t's main interest was to keep the government func- g and to enhance the power of the German state. CHAPTER IV THE POLITICS OF A CONSERVATIVE INTELLECTUAL, 1922-1928 Throughout the short life of the Weimar Republic nmitt never isolated himself within the ivory tower :tualism of a university professor. He often left wersity lecture halls for the political arena he 3 fascinating. Indeed, the political arena pro- uch of the inspiration for his work, and his public ty increased in direct proportion to his involvement tical controversies. Yet, he at no time became a ian in the strict sense of the word; rather he the role of the political intellectual and publicist. tuous of party politics he refused to take active party affairs or submit to party discipline and nda. Schmitt preserved this independence while ally expressing his opinions on political issues ntaining a strong belief in the necessity of al involvement. It was his desire to avoid the al romanticism of Adam Mueller, by making political tions without opportunistically placing himself 31y in the service of just any political faction. 114 To account for everyday pc concepts we hisovn ori Quite natur himself to authority c lectually s cation of t the letter " . to 1 ‘ie desert itinitt alp Franz Blei, Second edip 115 To a certain degree intellectual pride and vanity for Schmitt's aloofness from the vulgarity of y political organizing and activity. Ideas and s were his main concerns, and he was well aware of originality and brilliance in handling such ideas. aturally Schmitt rejected any thought of submitting fto the limitations of a party line, or to the .ty of party leaders he might consider less intel— .ly sophisticated than himself. We receive an indi- of this intellectual vanity from several sources. atter to M. J. Bonn, Schmitt described his desire to find an oasis of possible discussion, here in 1 And :ert of barbarous stupidity in which we live." :also betrayed a similar attitude when he asked dei, "who in Germany could write the forward to the edition of my Politische Romantik? You cannot do it you are too lazy, and all the others cannot they are too stupid."2 But this intellectual vanity never blurred 's insight into the realities of power politics. :epts were always bound to a concrete situation, addressed himself directly to the specific political lCarl Schmitt to M. J. Bonn, June 17, 1926, BA, Bonn, No. 50. 7 'Franz Blei, "Der Fall Carl Schmitt: Von einem, :annte," Der Christliche Standestaat (December 25, 1218. id 19931 Pmble not foalet that lifterent sense land} Undoubt intellectual frc professor of put branded inescap his profession a of actual conten :‘nese challenges Owing to conservative ant 116 al problems of Weimar. As Schmitt phrased it: "Do get that I am a jurist, and an 'intellectual' in a nt sense from, for example, Bert Brecht or Thomas Undoubtedly, Schmitt was a different type of ctual from artists and literary figures. As a or of public law the issues he confronted often d inescapable political choices. Unlike the arts, fession required a precise and realistic evaluation a1 contemporary problems; he never avoided facing hallenges. Owing to his reputation as a politically involved ative and nationalist Weimar intellectual, many 3 mistakenly associate Carl Schmitt with the con— ve revolutionary movement.4 However, the term vative revolutionary" is only one sub-group of the non historians call German nee-conservatism, which 5 thinkers ranging from moderates like Max Weber ecke to Ernst Niekisch, the originator of Bolshevism. What they all had in common was the looking nature of their conservatism; and they 3Car1 Schmitt to author, March 2, 1974. 4Kohn, Egg Mind, pp, giE., pp. 336—340. Mohler, ervative, op. cit., pp. 76, 83. George Mosse, is of German Ideology: Intellectual Origins of d Reich (New York, 1964), pp. 283—285. Kurt—— er, "Der Tatkreis,“ Vierteljahreshefte fuer hichte, Bd. VII (1959), as Cited in Egn_Weimar 1930—1933, ed., Gotthard Jasper (Cologne, 200—201, 210—211. Mp united in naavaaualisti< pep sought to the nonarchYI " of the 01d Reis conservatives < leinar Republi‘ Many mt tive thinkerS, as the "elders republicans by accepted the Ru sust function. enbraced the R lives their 1 sovenent withi 117 united in their opposition to the mechanized and idualistic bourgeois world. In one manner or another sought to rejuvenate conservatism after the fall of onarchy, without pursuing a reactionary restoration e old Reich. But here the unity ends. For neo- rvatives differed greatly in their response to the r Republic. Many members of the older generation of conserva- thinkers, like Weber and Meinecke, often referred to e "elders," became Vernunftrepublikanern, i.e., licans by reason rather than sentiment. These elders ted the Republic as the political order in which they function. Although they never enthusiastically med the Republic they never worked for its overthrow. 5 their intention to develop a conservative political ent within a republican framework. They rejected the :mism of many of their fellow conservatives who urged ional revolution from the right, or who actively pted to undermine the Republic. The national or conservative revolutionaries were elves a very diverse grouping of intellectuals and ical publicists, united only in their anti- licanism and in fostering a vague doctrine of a nal revolution. Generally Moeller van den Bruck's The Third Reich, served as an ideological focal with which these various individuals and groups could identifY- or conservatiVE Reich, which WC alien and conse coherent or agl this new consez lone, like OSWE socialism uniti and capitalism; sued to retair Christianity. :onservative re :ion or a natic values. Moreon “Eleni a distir nonalisn, a te 118 dd identify. These thinkers believed that the national conservative revolution would usher in a new Third ch, which would represent the ideals of German nation— sm and conservatism. But they failed to develop any erent or agreed upon View as to the actual nature of s new conservative Reich, and the means to achieve it. e, like Oswald Spengler, advocated a form of Prussian ialism uniting all Germans at the expense of liberalism capitalism; while others, such as Wilhelm Stapel, ed to retain a link between their movement and istianity. There was no agreement as to whether this servative revolution would consist of an actual revolu— n or a nationalistic revival of traditional German ues. MoreOVer, the conservative revolutionaries dis— yed a distinct inclination toward extremism and irra— nalism, a tendency most noticeable in their uncompro- ing disdain for the Republic. In contrast to the ars or Vernunftrepublikanern, who came to terms with Republic, the conservative revolutionaries saw in nar the manifestation of all that they detested, and (looked forward to its demise. Along with their Lllingness to make the best of the Republic the con— ative revolutionaries demonstrated an explicit and sponsible disregard for its security and future. On this very significant issue of the Republic ,Schmitt most clearly separated himself from the consen :ltely future approac he elc' :evolut lealisn ioninat philosc :ionaq the est \ 119 :rvatives of the national revolution. Though defi- y a conservative with many reservations about the e of Weimar, Schmitt was a Vernunftrepublikaner, who mched the Republic with a similar attitude to that of elders. Before 1933 he made no mention of a national .ution nor even hinted at a future Third Reich. .sm, and not irrationalism or hopes for a revolution, ated Schmitt's thinking. His entire political sophy opposed the disruptive consequences of revolu— ry change and he always supported the maintenance of stablished order. Carl Schmitt never involved him- with attempts to undermine the Weimar system; instead cepted it as the existing political situation of the n people. He voiced severe criticisms of the system effort to arrive at viable solutions to the problems imar; and there was much to criticize. Still, even is criticism we notice the attitude of the nftrepublikaner. For Schmitt consistently argued st solutions which concerned tampering with the ing system, since he feared such tampering might extremist groups and parties an opportunity to it the situation. Only by age could one categorize Schmitt as a : of the war generation from which many conservative itionaries emanated. This particular group of con- :ive revolutionaries became known as the "front general ‘renche enerie ntlool and the solutit itse ghilos< activis u con; 120 ion." Four years of tragic struggle in the 5 provided them with a cohesive bond of common nces, which preconditioned their future political . Their most influential experience had been war y came to accept war, revolution, and action as ns in themselves.5 War and struggle became an end If. This war experience was the guiding political phy of thinkers like Ernst Juenger, and political ts like Franz Seldte, leader of the Stahlhelm. hough he is often placed in the same category as 'end Ernst Juenger, the war experience itself had arable influence on Carl Schmitt. Never having at the front Schmitt remained isolated from the experiences of war so vital for figures like : and Seldte. Schmitt did not consider struggle, action as ends in themselves. He conceived of war armed conflict between organized political units :eme cases. The struggle itself had absolutely no I; he based his friend-enemy distinction solely on entiality of the conflict. War was a fact of a1 life, and certainly nothing to be desired or d. Of significance to Schmitt was not the indi— taking part in the conflict, but war as an aspect 5Klemperer, New Conservatism, 92. cit., p. 47. In 121 itics between sovereign states.6 It was, in fact, rpose of the state to assure peace and order and to te the chances of struggle. With the front generation and other conservative tionary groups, Schmitt shared some of the intel- l aspects of the "ideas of 1914," which were anti— , anti—bourgeois, and anti-liberal. These intel— l affinities, however, were also held by many con— ives who, like Meinecke, became Vernunftrepublikanern. f these attitudes remained with Schmitt throughout fe, without interfering with his sharp sense of m and his ability to adapt to newly developing ions. Like conservatives since the French Revolu— Schmitt retained a pessimistic view of human nature paid special attention to the irrational and ious nature of life. In an age of mass politics he ized the psychological and political significance ational behavior, though he never promoted irra- Lsm as a political doctrine. Now a widely accepted : among political scientists, the recognition of rational element in politics was never an insight I only to conservative revolutionaries. Furthermore, Carl Schmitt had no direct contact nservative revolutionary circles before he moved to 6Carl Schmitt Der Begriff, op. cit., pp. 33—35. 3erlin stage. tionari as the became lectual Seinric Lectua] Eugen I such tl :lonari 122 the Weimar Republic reached its final crisis me of the more important conservative revolu— were associated with several organizations such itisches Kolleg and the Juniklub, which later Herrenklub. This group consisted of intel— ike Moeller van den Bruck, Martin Spahn, on Gleichen, and Wilhelm Stapel. The intel— ho rallied around the newspaper gig Tat of erichs and Hans Zehrer formed another center of ht. What interest these conservative revolu— had in Schmitt, they developed only after 1928. Schmitt was never a member or close associate Drganizations. While Schmitt continually lectures at the republican oriented Hochschule EEK in Berlin, he was neglected by the conserva— Lutionary circles of the Politisches Kolleg. lO mention of Carl Schmitt in the files of the as Kolleg before 1928 and then only concerning rns. And Schmitt's name does not appear on any 'viving membership and contributor lists of . . 7 ve revolutionary organizations. Before 1928 hese include: Gewissen (1920-1924), ger Ring ), Herrenklub (Berlin and local groups), vativen Vereinigung Eng Einzelverbindungen, litisches Kolleg (1922—1923). See: Hans Joachim tt, Arthur Moeller van den Bruck BBQ ger aere Nationalismus ififdéifWeimarer Republik 1, 1962), appendix. Politisches Kolleg , BA, ., 15, 21, 28, 34, 35, 46, 63, 64. Neither is Schuit :onser period conser lot th erecut ical a iniire ublished nothing in any of the journals of a ive revolutionary nature. Later during the crisis 30-1933 he published a few articles in various 've journals like ger Ring and Deutsches Volkstum. articles dealt with the immediate crisis and the of state power to preserve the existing polit— egal order. e argument is often made that Schmitt's real on the conservative revolutionary movement was through his writings and ideas, that he placed of thinkers like Spengler on a scholarly 1.8 This contention assumes that Schmitt's a attuned to the ideological tenets and goals of :vative revolution, an assumption which his Litical ideas and behavior tend to negate. ;chmitt's works contain no direct reference to of Spengler, Moeller van den Bruck, or other .ve revolutionaries, and he lent no credence to ,5. After 1928, of course, some of Schmitt's t utilized by conservative revolutionaries, but were sometimes utilized by the left as well. name listed among the one thousand members of klub as cited in Deutscher Herrenklub (n.d.), curt von Schleicher, BA, Militaerarchiv, Freiburg, iohler, Die Konservative, op. cit., p. 76. Mind, gp. cit., pp. 336-337. Mosse, The Crisis, p. 283. issues bath 5: social: a hats] :epts, sharplj il equ viewed lespin lchnit 124 itt was one Weimar critic among many and the confronted were issues of common discussion on s of the political and ideological spectrum. The political and legal theoretician, Herman Heller, ritic of Schmitt, also dealt with similar con— ough from a very different perspective.9 He isagreed with Schmitt's theories while assuming y anti-liberal position, and like Schmitt, he mogeneity as one of the essentials of democracy. he mutual enmity betWeen the left and Carl his ideas concerning liberalism, dictatorship, ritique of parliamentary government and political ere used by Karl Mannheim, Robert Michels, Otto 11 er, and other leftist thinkers. Naturally, Hermann Heller, Europa und der Fascismus (Berlin, sf und Voelkerrechts (Berlin, 1927). oHermann Heller, “Politische Demokratie und omogenitaet," Probleme der Demokratie (Berlin, 38, 40-41, and forward by Arnold Wolfers to 1Karl Mannheim, "Competition as a Cultural n," (1928), and "The Democratization of Culture," {gm Karl Mannheim, ed., Kurt Wolff (New York, . 248, 291. Robert Michels, Zur Soziologie des egg in der modernen DemokratiE?_Untersuchungen Oligarchischen Tendenzen deg Gruppenlebens , 1924, New York, 1970), ed., Werner Conze, pp. 59, 410. Otto Kirchheimer, "The Socialist and Theory of the State," (1928), Politics, Egg 1 Change: Selected Essays of Otto Kirchheimer, eric Burin, Kurt Shell (New York, 1969), pp. 6, 8. Schni' iiuitl or' the est op select iecrsi tionar Lie er patdin L. ............... 125 's appeal to the left was minimal and generally to his critique of liberalism. Towards the end Republic the left viewed him as one of their great— onents. Likewise, the radical right was also very ve in its use of his ideas, and he exercised no a influence on the thoughts of conservative revolu- as. They accepted his critique of liberalism and asses of pluralistic party politics, while disre— his commitment to the stability of the Republic. During his Bonn years Carl Schmitt's political :ion was mostly with Catholic groups and the Center He became one of the most prominent spokesmen for rl Catholicism in the Weimar Republic.12 Aside ral journals, most of his articles were published latholic press, particularly in Hochland, and the pr organs of the Center Party, Germania and the fle_Volkszeitung. In the Nazi era Hochland became he resistance journals. Only in 1932, after broke with the Center Party, did Hochland begin icism of the Catholic jurist.l3 For most of the 12Hermann Hefele, "Zum Problem einer Politik aus olischen Glauben," Abendland, Jhg. 2, Heft 7 1927). P. 195. 13See: Konrad Ackermann, Der Widerstand der rift Hochland gegen den NationalSOZialismus 1965), pp. 124, 183 Erich Brock, "Der Begriff :ischen——Eine Auseinandersetzung mit Carl Schmitt," , Jhg. 29, Heft 11 (1932): pP- 394-404. trenti public holes Center as he :ions 126 his ideas appeared acceptable enough to warrant ion in these journals and papers. Refusing to accept party membership Schmitt, none- associated quite closely with the politics of the arty for several reasons. A devout Catholic, he to a family tradition which represented genera- support for the Catholic political cause. As of the Catholic clergy his great uncles took an art in the Kulturkampf against Bismarck, and his arried on this tradition by his membership in the ’arty. Considering this heritage it is quite under— .e that Schmitt should have numerous personal and working acquaintances within the party.14 illy Schmitt perceived the Center Party as the the entire Weimar system, without which no coalie rld be formed. He viewed the Center Party as the ‘ stabilizing force in Weimar politics, and the committed to the existing constitutional order. Schmitt also developed friendships with Catholic ‘tuals outside of the party. In addition to the .an Hans Barion, Schmitt influenced the writings Hugo Ball and Waldemar Gurian. Upon first read— dtt's early Weimar works, Hugo Ball was exceed— pressed. Ball wrote to his wife that Schmitt l . . . 4Carl Schmitt, First InterView. — m. its-a 7:; S. . betweer Jewish became 127 15 Schmitt tholic thinker is a new type of Kant." admirer personally in the summer of 1924 and. er they corresponded until 1925. At the height of usiasm for the Bonn professor, Ball published an e article in Hochland, honoring Schmitt as the of Catholicism and European civilization. Far more important, however, was the friendship Schmitt and Waldemar Gurian. A Russian emigre of escent, Gurian had converted to Catholicism, and ne of the most significant Catholic publicists of er half of the Weimar Republic. Before turning to ce writing Gurian worked on the editorial staff of nische Volkszeitung. Schmitt and Gurian estab— heir relationship in 1924 and it lasted until urian attended Schmitt's seminars at the University and the two families frequently socialized to— Forced to emigrate after the Nazi seizure of irian launched a series of vehement attacks in .gn press against his former mentor Carl Schmitt. lent the final years of his life as a professor SHugo Ball to wife, November 23, 1923 and 1923; Ball to Carl Schmitt, November 19, 1924, , 1925, January 27, 1925, February 11, 1925; Ball rchtwanger, March 25, 1925; in Hugo Ball Briefe (Einsiedeln, 1957), pp. 164, 171, 191, 194, 208, 313. Hugo Ball, "Carl Schmitts Politische Theologie," Bd. 2 (April—September, 1924), pp. 263—286. l‘ t 128 lniversity of Notre Dame.17 Like Hugo Ball, Gurian acially enchanted with Schmitt's political :ism and his anti-liberalism, as expressed in 325 Katholizismus E29 Politische Form. As a fanati— i—Bolshevik, Gurian was attracted by Schmitt's stand against Bolshevism, and much of the termin- nployed by the young Gurian was taken directly from hmitt. 18 Schmitt also had some personal contact with h Bruening, and in 1930 Schmitt fully supported the 5 of the Catholic chancellor. At a 1928 conference alic intellectuals and other leaders, hosted by the ester Kreis in Boppard, Schmitt and Bruening par— 19 ad together in the discussions. Schmitt claims :er Bruening wanted to place his name on the ballot l7Heinz Huerten, Waldemar Gurian: Ein Zeuge der .serer Welt in der ersten Haelfte des 29. erts (Mainz, 1972), pp. 12—13, and Deutsche Briefe: t der katholischen Emigration, Bd. II, ed., erten (Mainz, 1969), p. xxxv. 8See also: Waldemar Gurian, "Carl Schmitts ngslehre," Germania (April 18, 1929). LgGottfried Treviranus, Das Ende von Weimar: Bruening und seine Zeit (Vienna, 1968), pp. 129 t he refused in order to maintain his independence rty control.20 One cannot strictly speaking consider Schmitt as a the Center Party, since he never actively took part :y politics. He supported the Center Party because it as the only true constitutional party. His :al relationship with the party was restricted to support of the Centrist position on several crucial al and constitutional issues. Usually Schmitt ed this support in articles released in the Che Volkszeitung, and in Gutachten regarding con- onal questions. Very often his articles concerned currently before the Reichstag, or of immediate importance. With each issue he attempted to pre— mself as a neutral commentator standing above the ts of struggling political parties. Although his a1 opinions normally coincided with the position of ter he did manage to maintain his independence. Late twenties he disassociated himself from the s of the Center Party, when he believed it was r opportunist and when it differed with his inter— n of the constitution. 20Second Schmitt Interview. Bruening and Schmitt :ontact after 1945. See: letter, Bruening to December, 1955, Carl Schmitt——Personal Papers. () 130 Having a congenial personality and searching mind t enjoyed contact with individuals of different cal and ideological orientations. M. J. Bonn, for e, was an outspoken defender of the Republic and l democracy. Bonn had been a member of the German elegation at Versailles and afterwards served as a of the gold delegation at the League of Nations. i-liberalism of Schmitt and his frequent criticisms ailles and the League did not interfere with the e friendship between the liberal and the conserva— ofessor.21 Bonn brought Schmitt into contact with the demo— ally oriented Hochschule fuer Politik in Berlin. Schmitt occasionally delivered lectures and came )ntact with other defenders of the Republic such as : Heuss. At one time the Hochschule considered 22 : for a permanent academic appointment. And by no means reflecting the general political views institution, or figures like Heuss, Schmitt con— to lecture there until 1933. In spite of the diversity of his intellectual tances, Schmitt feared the diversity of political 21 . Bonn, S9 Macht, op. c1t., pp. 330-332. Nachlass 35., 49, 50. 22Theodor Heuss, Erinnerungen, 1905-1933 Jen, 1963), pp. 300—304. Wolfers, Probleme, KIEBDA 131 ns dominating German politics. He saw the essential m of Weimar in the fact that its constitution was a mise. The Germans had failed to make a definite on between contradictory political, social, and ic philosophies. Instead they attempted a compromise ht and left, conservatism and socialism, within a l-democratic framework.23 Fortunately, a second ise, one between church and state, satisfied the ic Center Party and as a result it became the center entire system. Doubting the willingness of other to accept the Weimar compromises, Schmitt con- the Center the only real constitutional party, a, in his view, it was the only party firmly com— to the existing constitutional order.24 The other aspects of the constitutional compromise Led very few and this compromise could not be l over into the political arena. In effect, Weimar pluralistic party state, in which several antagon— uarties faced each other. These parties represented t interest and ideological groups, without the 23Carl Schmitt to Erich Kaufmann, 1921, "Schmitt, . Prof., "Sicherheitsdienst des RFSS SD Hauptamt E fuer Zeitgeschichte, Munich, AKZ 4062/68 Fa 503, p. 186. Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, op. cit., 5. 3 24 . . Carl Schmitt First InterView. Carl Schmitt's to a proposed Italian edition of his works .shed manuscript, August 1971). K~V~ill 132 ibility of compromise.25 The promising note of a blican majority which existed in the Weimar Assembly kly disappeared. The Weimar coalition of SPD, DDP, Center lost the majority in 1920, never to regain it. eforth, incompatible parties had to be brought ther in order to form any majority government. Only Catholic Center Party offered the opportunity for the ssary political compromises and all coalitions nded upon its cooperation.26 As the only party which across social and economic classes, which at the same was bound to the constitutional compromise of church state, the Center Party, according to Schmitt's esti— on, was the pivotal party in the Weimar system. The er presented the best chance of achieving the sta- ty Schmitt so cherished. It was in this atmosphere that Schmitt began lg a public stand on political issues. His first Lc declaration on a pending political issue serves as :cellent example of his basic approach to the Weimar :itution and politics.27 Reichspresident Ebert had 25Bracher, Die Aufloesung, gp. cit., pp. 20—24. 261bid., pp. 67, 75—82. 27Carl Schmitt, "Nochmalige Reichstagsaufloesung," ische Volkszeitung No. 836 (October 26, 1924), ssungsrechtliche Aufsaetze aus den Jahren 1924-1954 In, 1958), pp. 13-28, and "EIHHSIngeit' und :her Anlass' bei der Reichstagsaufloesung nach Art. 133 olved the Reichstag on October 20, 1924, owing to the ility of chancellor Marx to form a government that had confidence of a majority of the deputies. The elec— s of the previous spring had shown a marked trend he right. Although the Center Party remained stable major partner in the coalition, the SPD, lost 71 seats. extensive gains made by the Nationalists and Communists ented the formation of a governing coalition. Here a clear instance of the pluralistic party politics itt criticized throughout the Weimar period. He ced that two of the most serious constitutional and tical problems of Weimar were involved, the dissolving :he Reichstag and the building of a viable majority ernment. Under normal circumstances the constitution was e clear about the proper procedure for dissolving the 28 hstag. But Schmitt held that the current problem who decides, in a doubtful case, what constitutes "the reason" (gleiche Anlass), as stipulated in Article 9 . . . . He also argued that interpreting this article too 3r Reichsverfassung," Archiv des oeffentlichen Rechts, 3 (1925), PP. 162-174. 28 . . . Article 25 states: "The ReichspreSident can rlve the Reichstag only once for the same reason the Anlass). The new elections will begin at the t sixty days after the dissolution." Die Weimarer ssung, p. 185. 29 Carl Schmitt, "Nochmalige," op. cit., p. 13. -a, 134 iterally could paralyze the entire governing process and ndermine the constitution itself. By this Schmitt meant hat the failure to form a majority government was not ubject to the phrase "only once for the same reason," or the entire constitutional workings of the government apended upon the formation of a viable governing 30 fjority. Thus, the Reichstag could once again be dis— Flved, without violating the true nature of Article 25, F the event that a viable majority was still lacking Eter the election.31 Terms like "only once" and "the me reason" were relative rather than absolute concepts. iese terms should be bound to the concrete political rse at issue.32 Otherwise, Article 25, literally inter— eted and applied to this problem, would make the con- itution nothing but a pure formalistic document with prelationship to the actual existing political situa- on. It could also become the tool of anti- nstitutional and disruptive political groups seeking to ralyze the government by, on the one hand, preventing a formation of a majority government, and on the other, eventing new elections which might return such a govern— ! majority. If this occurred, either an intolerable x“ 3oIbid., pp. 16—17. 31Ibid., pp. 25-26. 32 Ibid., pp. 21, 23. 135 ration would endure for four years, or a fictitious new son for dissolution would have to be invented.33 Rather than intending any violation of the consti- ion Schmitt wanted to assure that the essential opera— is of government would continue unhampered by the dire sequences of a too literal interpretation of the consti— hon. The constitution for Schmitt was more than a ection of individual laws; it must be considered as a e. Individual laws must never be allowed to serve as :etext for anti—constitutional elements to impede the :tioning of government and endanger the entire consti- .ona1 order. If Schmitt favored any cause in this roversy it was that of chancellor Marx and the parties- he Weimar coalition. The groups most likely to bene— from the literal interpretation that Schmitt opposed the extremists, the Communists, Nationalists, and s. In 1927 Schmitt specifically warned against the ible use of a vote of no confidence under Article 54, n obstructionist tactic by the Communists and German 34 During the presidential system of late analists. ar the formalistic interpretation of constitution, as as the misuse of Articles 25 and 54, became points rntention between various political factions and 3 . 3Ib1d., p. 26. 34Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, QB: cit., p. 345. 136 the government itself. When Schmitt first pro— ris interpretation Ebert was still Reichspresident, a one Who would decide in doubtful cases. The continued functioning of the government and pger presented by extremists and pluralistic party its remained a constant concern for Schmitt. This temost in his mind when, upon the death of Reichs- ent Ebert in 1925, Schmitt publicly voiced his pon the election of a new president.35 Schmitt's resis was that party loyalties and discipline should ‘ermine the selection of the new Reichspresident. he Weimar constitution all of the German people dly elect the Reichspresident, and this method acts unter weight to the system of proportional repre— on and party lists. The Reichspresident should e trust of most of the German people and avoid g the tool of party programs and interest groups. alls under the control of one party the potentially is abuse of presidential power is extraordinary. ring party united with the office of Reichspresident the possibility of a constitutional dictatorship. respect Schmitt noted that ". . . no constitution can so easily legalize a Staatsstreich as the 35Carl Schmitt, "Reichspresident und Weimarer ng," Koelnische Volkszeitung, No. 198 (March 15, . 1. Heine plura pro-t rat'ne when const this 137 ar constitution."36 Theoretically, a two—thirds vote 1e Reichstag guards against this possibility, but the alism of Weimar parties prevents the cooperation of :hirds of the deputies. Schmitt also presented some er ominous questions about the fate of a democracy a democratic majority is lacking and when anti- iitutional parties paralyze parliament. To prevent the office of president requires an individual to e as a pouvoir neutre who, standing above parties and .al interests, will assure the smooth functioning of state. Ebert had followed such a policy of the xal force;" there was a danger his successor may 7 Therefore, careful attention must be paid to the hality of the new Reichspresident, rather than to olitical party. Schmitt's own choice was not clear. That he pub— d in a Centrist newspaper, stressed the immense rs involved, and advocated a constitutionally bound 31 force, however, presents several indications of :eference. The extremist parties offered the est danger and were totally unacceptable to Schmitt. Icial Democrats he denounced by name as advocating 1y a party candidate and making the election an 36Ibid. 37Ibid. 138 e of party prestige and loyalty. Neither was Schmitt orting the candidacy of Hindenburg, since when Schmitt ished this article Hindenburg was not included in the n candidates presenting themselves in the March 29, tion.38 Because of his close affiliation with the olic position, and his belief in the Center as the true constitutional party, Schmitt probably favored cellor Marx. There is no evidence regarding Schmitt's es in the runoff election of April 26, between Marx Hindenburg. But it is doubtful that Schmitt would abandoned the Center in favor of Hindenburg, a can- te of the rightist parties which were very antagonistic he existing constitutional and political order. Schmitt's desire to maintain the status quo of Neimar legal order was also clear from his stand st the further democratization and socialization of epublic. One of the most emotional controversies of involved the debate over the properties of the former . . 39 . . ties and princes. This issue demonstrated one of tt's elusive qualities, and illustrated his ability vor a legal over a political decision and to favor a a1 interpretation of the constitution in certain 9Cuno Horkenbach, ed., Das Deutsche Reich von bis Heute (Berlin, 1930), pp. 225, 228. 139 ances. Schmitt had already advocated a legal decision he matter in 1922.40 In a Gutachten he now opposed two 5 introduced by the Communists and the Democratic y regarding the expropriation of the princely prop— 41 es. Both bills he considered as unconstitutional and revolutionary nature, and also as violating Articles 105, and 109.42 By making laws so specific as to r only to the princely properties in question, legis- rs would interfere with a judge's right independently nterpret the law, thereby subjugating the judges to legislature.43 And in directing these laws against specific German citizens, legislators deny these viduals equality before the law. Schmitt compared a proposed laws with the anti—jesuit and anti—socialist of the former Reich.44 Such laws were nothing less 40Carl Schmitt, "Die Auseinandersetzung zwischen ause Wittelbach und dem Freistaat Bayern," Koelnische zeitun , No. 436 (June 6, 1922). 41Carl Schmitt, Unabhaengigkeit der Richter, hheit vor dem Gesetz und Gewaehrleistung des teigentums nach der Weimarer Verfassung: Ein Rechts- hten zu den Gesetzentwuerfen ueber die Vermoegen— inandEfsetzung mit den frueher regierenden tenhaeusern (Berlin, 1926). 42Article 102: "The Judges are independent and ct only to the law." Article 105: "Exceptional courts Orbidden." Article 109: "All Germans are equal before aw.“ Die Weimarer Verfassung, pp. 197—198. 43Carl Schmitt, Unabhaengigkeit, 92° cit., pp. 9—10. 44Ibid'l p. 20. —&-’i r- '* 7 140 he type of political measures possible only during volutionary months of 1918-1919, when a sovereign orship ruled Germany. Since that time the German have established a constitutional state and no tutional party can now propose revolutionary 45 es. Over fifteen million Germans disagreed with t's constitutional interpretation and voted in favor ropriation in the June 20, 1926, referendum. r revolutionary or constitutional in character the returns fell five million short of the necessary for a constitutional amendment. The defeat of the as hardly a positive sign for the conservative t, who viewed it as a dangerous precedent. He had cial sympathy for the privileged remnants of the nian Reich. One year before this he had defended, ther Gutachten, democratic and equal voting rights the new constitution against the privileges of the :lass voting system of the Second Reich.46 Of , the preservation of the German state structure old Reich, as adopted by the Weimar Republic, was 45Ibid-, pp. 26—27. 46Carl Schmitt, "Gutachten zu der Frage der mg der Wahlordnung fuer das Saargebiet vom 29. IV. lf die Gemeinde Saarlouis-Roden," unpublished manu— (Bonn, July 22, 1925), BA, Nachlass Richard Bd. 47. _- wfi. . 141 >f his first priorities. But the princely houses and -repub1ican politics had absolutely no role in this me. The real fear of Carl Schmitt was that such :endums sponsored by extremist parties would open the i gates to further revolutionary and socializing ires. Examples of Schmitt's sincere interest in maintain— iomestic peace and tranquility, and of his tolerance 1e Republic, are also evident in his resistance to titutional changes proposed by the right. From 1926 929 there were several proposals for constitutional sion, strongly supported by the German Nationalists, German People's Party, and right-wing groups around nberg and veterans' organizations like Seldte's helm. These proposals included the establishment of 0nd Chamber of parliament, indirectly elected, to ce the Reichstag and act as an Upper House. A ed demand involved amending Article 54 of the consti- n in order to allow the government more power and endence from the Reichstag.47 Both proposals were ded to weaken the popular and democratic aspects of onstitution. One of the greatest opponents of these rvative and reactionary reforms was the Center Party. 47BA, Reichskanzlei, 1919—1933, R—43—I, hsverfassung, (1919-1926)," 1864, "Reichsverfassung, -1933),“ 1865. 142 although he made no immediate comment on these pro- 15 in the public press, Schmitt consistently agreed lthe Center Party's opposition. His constitutional ings at this time display a categorical repudiation he idea of a Second Chamber and he never supported hwnts to Article 54. Though a devastating critic of parliamentary tnment and of pluralistic party politics, which ered the functioning of the government, Schmitt still ed the constitutionality of a Second Chamber. Since msidered the basis of democracy as homogeneity and ity, he held that "the political consequences of a racy must contradict the Two Chamber System."48 An endent Second Chamber would endanger the unity of the n and present a duality in the legislature which sedly represents the will of the people.49 The con- of a Second Chamber either recognizes certain note— y characteristics of certain individuals within the n, such as education, age, or property, thus violating emocratic concept of equality of all citizens, or it mot recognize these special traits and thereby rates the need for a Second Chamber.5O 48Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, 9p. cit., p. 294. 49Ibid. 50Ibid., pp. 294—295. 143 Rightist movements to strengthen the power of the nent by amendments to Article 54 likewise received port from Schmitt.51 Through these amendments st groups, especially the German Nationalist Party, to make the government less responsive to the will Reichstag. This was one stage in their overall 0 institute their reactionary, anti—constitutional ,ti-republican programs by constitutional means. mg central government in Schmitt's estimation was .necessary element in the politics of a state. He ;ed the fact that the government was so dependent he changing and unstable groupings within the tag. Nonetheless, he felt that the executive .already had sufficient and extensive constitutional to cope with the situation. Schmitt was always cal of constitutional revisions which were intended troy the republican nature of the constitution.52 luctance to alter the constitution continued even the crisis period 1930-1933. Instead he urged that ichspresident exercise the enormous constitutionally l powers at his disposal. 51Article 54 states: "The Reichschancellor and inisters require the confidence of the Reichstag ir administration. Each of them must resign, if :hstag withdraws its confidence through a formal ion." Die Weimarer Verfassung, p. 189. 52Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, op. cit., 114, 196-197, 303, 356—359. 144 One of the crucial constitutional provisions of presidential power was Article 48. Where the right per— ceived this article as a potential instrument for under— mining the Republic, Schmitt hailed it as a method of preserving the existing constitution and state. Weimar democrats and leftists agreed with neither of these inter- pretations and persisted in their efforts to propose strict limitations on the Reichspresident, by precisely enumerating his powers under Article 48. The question had been an issue at the first meeting of the Association of German Jurists and the German Jurist conference in 1924. An overwhelming majority of jurists, excluding Schmitt and Jacobi, urged passage of a completion law, and bills were actually drafted.53 Passage of a completion law once again became a public issue in 1926. The Democratic faction of the Reichstag initiated a demand for the regulation of Article 54 48 through a federal law. Democrats claimed that there had been extensive abuse of these powers during the period of inflation and that now the enemies of the Weimar consti- :ution intended to use Article 48 to introduce their flotatorship plans. In the end this law suffered the ame unfortunate fate of earlier proposals. But before M.— 53Scheuner, op. cit., pp. 371—372. 54BA, R—43—I, "Art. 48 der Reichsverfassung, 924—1930)," 1870. 145 subsiding the controversy elicited a similar response from both Carl Schmitt and Hindenburg. In an article of October 30 in the Koelnische Volkszeitung, Schmitt reiterated the viewpoint he pre— sented at the Jurist conference two years earlier.55 It was impossible to enumerate what "necessary measures" a Reichspresident may utilize in an Ausnahmezustand. Such regulations are based on norms which, in a state of exception, become inoperative. It is equally impossible to predetermine the type and extent of a danger to public order and security and the measures needed to meet the situation. The experiences of the first seven years of :he Republic had demonstrated the variety of occasions mich might arise and none could have precisely been fore- men. Also, any alteration of the powers of the Reichs— mesident already mentioned in the constitution require a mnstitutional amendment and not simply a federal law. bnsidering the party splintering in the Reichstag, the ecessary two-thirds majority for a constitutional amend— ent was out of the question. Although Schmitt had no direct contact with either indenburg or the government at this point in his career, he 1926 controversy over the completion law was an 55Carl Schmitt, "Das Ausfuehrungsgesetz zu Art. 48 er Reichsverfassung; (sog. Diktaturgesetz)," Koelnische blkszeitung, No. 805 (October 30, 1925). 146 explicit example of the influence of Schmitt's ideas. fifile the issue was still pending Hindenburg explained us opposition to the legislation in a detailed letter to :hancellor Marx.56 Because Hindenburg was incapable of mnstructing such a detailed legal interpretation the bcument was probably prepared by his legal advisor Otto missner, a state secretary in the Office of the President. In the Bruening era Meissner took a special interest in he works of Carl Schmitt, and the advice of the state ecretary proved instrumental in convincing Hindenburg of he legality of the presidential system. Of importance ere was that the legal ideas, arguments, and often the ording, were taken directly from Carl Schmitt's work. chmitt and Jacobi were the only major jurists to take a idely known stand against the completion law and limi— ations on the power of the Reichspresident. Though no ention of Schmitt's name was made, the entire document as based on the interpretation he presented before the ssociation of German Jurists in 1924. Hindenburg stated that, because of the multi— licity of possible threatening dangers to state security, xperience has shown the necessity of allowing the eichspresident a free hand in executing measures 56Letter, Reichspresident von Hindenburg to eichschancellor Marx, November 22, 1926, BA, R—43—I, 870. 1.: (1.1.3:: ._,_,~. 147 according to the demands of each individual case. “A rigid formalistic definition regarding the exercise or even the limitation of his rights, would signify a weakening of his authority and a serious danger to state 57 security." Furthermore, the Reichspresident can in an Ausnahmezustand suspend more than merely the enumerated articles in Article 48, paragraph two. ". . . . He can institute in other respects all necessary measures to achieve the goal of the restoration of public security and order, and to this goal he can temporarily suspend and "58 The alter also legal and constitutional regulations. limitations on his power are restricted to the organiza— tional and structural regulations of the constitution. "He can neither suspend, limit, nor change the institution of the Reichspresident, the Reichsgovernment, or the institution of the Reichstag (also the Reichsrat)."59 Hindenburg also emphasized that the proposed law was of a constitutional amending character and required a two— thirds vote of the Reichstag.60 57Ibid., p. 2. 58Ibid., p. 9. 59Ibid. 60 Ibid., pp. 11—12. For the source of these argu— ments see: Carl Schmitt, "Die Diktatur," "Verhandlungen," 93. c1t., pp. 74—77, 88-90, 93—95, and Carl Schmitt "Das Ausfuehrungsgesetz," op. cit. and cont Schnitt' pretatic powers, over the the Reic llSt the interpre crisis 0 148 Hindenburg's argument was decisionist in nature [contained precisely the essential elements of Carl mitt's interpretation of Article 48. No other inter— tation granted the Reichspresident such extensive ers, while, at the same time, restricting his power m the organizational minimum of the constitution, i.e., i Reichspresident, government, and Reichstag. This was it the beginning of the government's reliance on the erpretations of Carl Schmitt which, during the final sis of 1930—1933, would become so important. The Reichspresident was the key to Schmitt's con— .tutional theory. The Weimar constitution and state was :existing political system of the German peOple. mitt‘s goal was not the restoration of the old Reich, destruction of the Weimar system, or the institution a visionary Reich in the future. As a Vernunftre- likaner Schmitt was conservative, cautious, and roached the Republic in a highly realistic manner. He ed Weimar controversies in terms of guaranteeing stic peace and stability, and assuring the smooth tioning of the institutions of government. For this on he wanted to prevent the government from being lyzed by either extremist political groups, or by a functional and formalistic interpretation of the con— ution. To achieve the desired stability in a country nated by pluralistic party interests the leich: state hound detail 149 chspresident must exert himself in the interest of the te and the nation as a whole. He should neither be nd to one party nor be inhibited by laws further ailing his constitutional powers. Only after the reintroduction of domestic unity tranquility could Germany achieve another of Schmitt's orities. Like all German conservatives, Schmitt was a ionalist, and he desired that Germany resume its Vious status as an independent and sovereign nation hin the European state system. He refused to accept shackles of the oppressive Versailles Diktat. From a isionist point of View sovereignty precluded restricting foreign or domestic affairs of a state by international missions or a League of Nations. Always consciously re of the realities of power politics, Schmitt detected self—interest of certain great powers hidden behind prOClamations of maintaining peace, the status quo, awing war, and seeking international arbitration in licts between sovereign states. These were merely des concealing the true national interests of the orious powers in their attempts to preserve the spoils ar. Perhaps over zealous in his campaign against the ty of Versailles and the League of Nations, Schmitt never bellicose nor a proponent of revenge. Concurrently with his analysis of the Weimar con— ution Schmitt turned his attention to international 150 d politics. Around 1924 he began teaching courses ernational affairs at the University of Bonn and ng his polemics on the subject into the political through public lectures and numerous publications.61 for the most part, not a theorist, but a political ist and analyst of international relations, comment- the foreign policy problems of Weimar Germany. in a demilitarized and occupied Rhineland, Schmitt bstantial reason to criticize the peace settlement e German post-war predicament. And, like his com— ies on domestic politics, he expressed many of his on foreign affairs through the Catholic press and in es before Catholic and Center Party organizations. One of Schmitt's first public stances on foreign cs came in a lecture before a conference of the 62 The immediate and Center Party in April of 1925. for Schmitt, as a Rhinelander and nationalist, was itiation of discussions leading to the Locarno Since 1924 members of the League had debated the on of guarantees for the security of Europe, and in 7y of 1925 Stresemann offered to respect Germany's r frontiers as defined by the Treaty of Versailles. believed that the Rhineland was becoming a pawn in 61 . . . Vorlesungsverzeichnis, Univ. of Bonn. 62 . . Carl Schmitt, Die Rheinlande als Objekt :ionaler Politik (Cologne, 1925). 151 ational bargaining and that even the existing status emilitarized Rhineland infringed upon German sover— Schmitt told his audience that a new form of 'alism had developed out of the Treaty of Versailles interfered with state sovereignty and authority.63 imperialism embodied new methods of rule and exploi— , such as protectorates, mandates, and intervention Les which avoided open political annexation. England ruled Egypt, albeit Egypt was recognized as a sover— state. The United States exercised control in sup- .y independent states of Latin America, like Cuba, and Panama. The former German colonies were not :d or taken over as colonies, but ruled as mandates :name of the League. Terms such as independence, etermination, and sovereignty lost their traditional gs as a result of this new form of hidden imperial- The controlled states no longer retained the ability ide their own political fate in a decisive case of ct. As Schmitt so often noted, sovereignty lies im who decides in a state of exception. Therefore, olled state was hardly sovereign if a foreign power ervene in its affairs. Whether this intervention assure security and order, to protect foreign 152 sts and private property, as designated by inter— al treaties, the outcome was still an infringement te sovereignty.64 If Germany had not yet lost its ignty it was because the opponents of the Treaty of lles had reserved for Germans the right to make cal decisions. Foreign intervention and control also disrupted stterns of state authority and loyalty, so necessary a functioning of any state. Attempts at transfering :y from the state to the League would prove futile. [uently, respect for state power and law were under- without any replacement for this state authority. rid this breakdown in state authority Germans must .all attempts to turn the Rhineland, through the s of modern imperialism, into an object of inter— al politics. International commissions must not be d to infringe upon German sovereignty.65 While the big four met at Locarno in October, 1925 er to conclude the treaty negotiations, Schmitt pub— an attack in Hochland on the proposed provisions.66 eaty was intended to insure the status quo and thus 64Ibid., pp. 11—12, 14—15. 65Ibid., pp. 20, 26, 30. 66Carl Schmitt, "Der Status quo und der Friede," d, Jhg. 23, Heft 1 (October, 1925). Citations are itionen und Begriffe im Kampf mit Weimar——Genf—— lles, 19§§:i9§§“Tfiafibfing“I§ZoTT‘ppi"35:427“““ 153 eace of Europe; and the continued demilitarization e Rhineland remained a cornerstone of the treaty. 'ng the entire treaty as an illusion, Schmitt refused cept these suppositions. The legalization of the s gug through treaties would never guarantee peace. no, like Versailles, with its provisions for inter— on and a demilitarized Rhineland, was merely a system urdening Germany and restricting its power.67 ally the status qug in the Rhineland served various ests. The English desired peace on the continent to any disturbance of their world wide economic tests. For France the status qug signified its polit- and military hegemony on the continent; in essence, lomination of an armed nation of forty million over an ed population of sixty million, and the rule of a ating country over an industrially expanding people. ermans submitted to the status qug to prevent the duction of new burdening obligations on their mic life.68 So abnormal and unsatisfactory was the existing tion, that, instead of insuring peace, guaranteeing tatus quo would eventually end in new conflicts. itly the status quo merely legalized an unbearable 67Ibid., p. 36. 681bid., pp. 38—40. 154 ation between war and peace, in which the politically ng powers temporarily dominated the politically weak.69 1 Germany received its rightful place among the family uropean nations, free from infringements on its sover— y, this abnormal condition would continue. By Germany's return to its rightful place in ean politics Schmitt did not mean entry into the e of Nations. In fact, Germany's entrance into the e provided the subject for Schmitt's first major work ternational relations. In Dig Kernfrage deg erbundes he analyzed the structure of the League, ting out several internal problems, and cautioning ist accepting it as a political panacea.70 He argued it was not actually a League of Nations, i.e., a Is of peoples, but rather a league of sovereign states rovernments. Although the humanitarian and nonpolit— aspects of the League were promising, nothing had .y changed in the traditional concepts of international ics, particularly where the interests of the great 5 were concerned.71 The League itself had no sover- y, because it lacked the power to decide independently 3 various members. 69Ibid.: pp. 41—42. 70Car1 Schmitt, Die Kernfrage des Voelkerbundes in, 1926). 7lIbid., pp. 9—10. 155 He questioned whether the League was a League ), or an alliance (Buendnis), or an administrative ure (Buero).72 Each case presented a problem for y. A League must be based upon homogeneity and tees, and the related matter of sovereignty.73 In egard the decisive criteria remained who decides guarantee must be enforced, and were the members neous enough to allow the intervention of the League ir affairs. If, on the other hand, the unifying of its members was only an alliance of similar sts aimed at restraining Germany, then the League >thing less than an instrument of the victors to :t and legalize their spoils.74 The real danger for 1y was not that changes in the status qug by force >rohibited, but that the existing situation would be .zed forever as the unalterable status qua guaranteed a League. The separation of millions of Germans from national state and the divided German boundaries not even be subject to a peaceful solution.75 Article 19 of the League charter allowed for peace— ange, decisions about justifiable changes did not 721bid., p. 15. 73Ibid., p. 21. 74Ibid., p. 37. 751bid., p. 38. 156 upon the correctness of a proposed change. The tical interests of the stronger powers in the League ally determined the merits of any change.76 The same true if one considered the League as a practical iistrative apparatus. Members would utilize this rument when and only so long as it suited their rests. Without a sovereign League power political con— :ations would always prevail over principles such as a, legitimacy, and right. Since the League's :eignty was in doubt, Schmitt urged a clarification of 1ctual nature and intentions of the League before any entered. Otherwise Germany's membership could :e the perpetuation of its own defeat and the surrender 78 :5 arms and rights. Later, in a critique of ecke's Idee der Staatsraeson, Schmitt noted that, of :e, everyone desires right, morality, ethics, and h The problem lay with "who decides?" what consti— h in a specific concrete case, peace or the dis— ,ng of the peace. 76Ibid., p. 51. 77Ibid., p. 79. 781bid., p. 82. 79Carl Schmitt, "Zu Friedrick Meineckes 'Idee der sraeson," Archiv fuer SgglglfliEEEEEEEEEE 3E9 lpolitik, BET—56 (1926). p- 231- 157 With such realism guiding him in matters of foreign flicy Schmitt relentlessly opposed the League and the msailles Treaty. He best described his attitude in a everly timed article on Machiavellianism, wherein he mned the German people of the unavoidable struggles of mer politics.80 Schmitt released this article in the .dst of a raging controversy over the fulfillment of mmany's treaty obligations, and most notably the dis- mament clauses. Stresemann had reported to the German minet on June 20, 1927, concerning the meeting of the ague council and his discussions with Briand over dis- ntling German eastern fortifications. When Schmitt blished this article Stresemann was already scheduled to esent the government's foreign policy declaration to the ichstag on June 23. During this speech Stresemann nounced that Germany would fulfill its disarmament ligations in accordance with Versailles. At the same me, however, Stresemann secretly allowed the violation several disarmament clauses.81 The title of Schmitt's article referred to the ne 22nd, anniversary of the National Assembly vote to tify the Treaty of Versailles. Though mentioning \_—-—— 80Carl Schmitt, "Machiavelli-—Zum 22. Juni 1927," fiEEEEEE Volkszeitung, No. 448 (June 21, 1927). 81Horkenbach, Deutsche Reich, 92. cit-r PP- 240‘ 1- Hans Gatzke, Stresemann and the Rearmament 9f 925E321 ew York, 1969), pp.—9"2-95. 104- 158 :her the treaty nor the policies of Stresemann, Schmitt arly made his point. Machiavelli's importance lay not us success or failure as a theoretician or statesman, in his recognition that political leaders must make -sions on the basis of concrete political circumstances the proper method of handling these circumstances. ility and immorality are aspects of private life and tho place in politics. In political life they are :ractions serving only the purpose of propaganda. .tics is an indestructible part of human nature and prality, in Schmitt's words, is simply a scarecrow in gruesome necessity of political self-preservation. dtt concluded that morality might have a place in .tics and that "my views would be wicked if men were h but men are not good." In other words, Germany's brs should conduct foreign policy according to polit- .necessity and self—interest without regard to the :ates of formal treaty obligations. Well into the Nazi period Schmitt continued lec- ng and publishing on the weakness of the League and ' . 82 inability to assure peace in Europe. Long before 82See: Carl Schmitt, "Der Voelkerbund und Europa," land, Jhg. 25 (January, 1928), pp. 345—354, Der _ kerbund und das politische Problem der FriedenSSicherung _______ ___ ___ _ -PZi9r 1930), "Die politische Lage der entmilitaeriSier Rheinlande," Abendland Jhg. 5 (July, 1930), pp. 307— "Sprengung der Locarno—Gemeinschaft durch Einschaltung SOWjetes," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 41, Heft 6 6), pp. 337—341. 159 inflicts of the thirties exposed the inefficacy of eague, he recognized that nothing had changed in the tional functioning of international politics. It was a system of individual, conflicting sovereign s. As Germany's foreign policy problems receded into packground after 1928, Schmitt began concentrating his its mostly on German domestic strife and politics. sonn jurist was about to become more directly involved plitics than he had ever anticipated. Before finally lrawing from the captivation of his involvement, this llectual would commit the sin of political romanticism. CHAPTER V THE INTELLECTUAL ENTERS THE CENTER OF POLITICS, 1928-1931 By 1928 Carl Schmitt had achieved a reputation as illiant and prolific Weimar jurist and political pub— st. Such growing national attention elevated him e the status of the average German professor. Hence, eft Bonn in 1928 to accept the Hugo Preuss chair of at the Berlin Handelshochschule.l No doubt it was Preuss chair and the attraction of Berlin, rather than business school itself, that held the most enticement him. Berlin, the political and intellectual center of any, offered a more prestigious setting, befitting a lar of national repute and recognition. His selection the Preuss chair depended upon the recommendation of friend Moritz Julius Bonn, then the director of the elshochschule. A man of liberal political viewpoints, was a loyal supporter of the Republic until its end. :hmitt had been considered an enemy of the Republic Juld hardly have been selected to occupy a position held by the father of the Weimar constitution. 1 39. BA, R—61, Bd. 64, "Lebenslauf;" R—21, Bd. 144, 160 161 During his Bonn days Schmitt never eschewed Weimar ical controversies. Continually making public state— and lectures Schmitt explained his own position in ost explicit manner. But Bonn was not Berlin. The university town left Schmitt without direct access e center of Weimar politics and its decision makers. after taking up residence in Berlin did Schmitt enter nnermost circles and cliques of Weimar political :rship. In Berlin he established close personal and family rct with Johannes Popitz, a state secretary in the rn Finance Ministry. Popitz had acquired a reputation lingenious expert in financial affairs and his .ons commanded a good deal of respect within the lucracy. An irreproachable civil servant with sharp ical instincts, he viewed his own official and polit- behavior in terms of responsibility and impartiality. ics for Popitz was a matter of solving specific ems through practical alternatives and decisions. bureaucratic pragmatism allowed him to serve a variety litical leaders. Papen appointed him as a Reich ssar for Prussia and as a cabinet minister in 1932; serving as Prussian Finance Minister and State allor under Hermann Goering, Popitz became a central 3 in the conservative resistance and in the plot to sinate Hitler. Sharing similar ideas on the problem 162 Weimar pluralism and the necessity of a strong, erly state, Popitz and Schmitt worked closely together ing the waning years of the Republic. It was actually 5 association with Popitz that allowed Schmitt to move 0nd university life and into influential government :cles. Of historical significance was Schmitt's relation— ip to the intimate confidant of Hindenburg, General :t von Schleicher. Given their diverse backgrounds, the iversity professor and the military officer showed narkable similarities in their political outlooks and jectives. Of course, while Schmitt was at his best in a world of ideas and theory, Schleicher's forte was litical intrigue. Schleicher excelled at behind the anes maneuverings that included the appointment and sposition of Chancellors and their cabinets. But, no :ter how damaging these machinations might have been to a reputation, he was motivated by a sincere concern for afuture of Germany and the Reichswehr, rather than by e personal ambition. His long-range goal was the ablishment of a strong, stable Germany, in which, urally, the interests of the Reichswehr would be 2Hildemarie Dieckmann, Johannes Popitz: Entwicklung Wirksamkeit in der Zeit der Weimarer Republik (Berlin- lem, 1960), p. 137. Lutz-Arwed Bentin, Johannes Popitz Carl Schmitt: Zur wirtschaftlichen Theorie des totalen —__——___ —_—_________—_____._.__———.~_ 163 ecured. Like Schmitt, he had abandoned any hopes for a estoration of the old order and came to terms with the epublic out of practical considerations.3 The professor nd the General each saw political stability as the first riority, even if it was to be achieved within a republican ramework. The most striking parallel between the attitude f Schmitt and that of Schleicher was their common oppo— ition to constitutional revision during a time of intense risis. In his early overtures to Bruening in 1929 chleicher did, contrary to Schmitt's interpretation, pro— wse amending the constitution on the basis of Article 48. his occurred, however, before the upsurge of the NSDAP nd before the real gravity of the situation was clear. hereafter, Schleicher discarded this plan and, with chmitt, looked to a government that would stand above arties and deal with the extreme right and left, without mending or abrogating the constitution. They both saw uch a solution in a presidential government. And it was n the issue of the presidential system that the ideas of chmitt and the politics of Schleicher converged, closing he gap between the realm of theory and the world of alitics. \——_——.—_——_. Be, 1959), pp. 167—172. Andreas Dorpalen, Hindenburg and 1g Weimar Republic (Princeton, 1964), pp. 123—124, 170— 71. 164 Schmitt made Schleicher's acquaintance through the eral's aides Colonel Erich Marcks and Colonel Eugen Ott, officers in a position to influence Schleicher's deci- ns. As director of the press office of the War Ministry, after August 1932 as Reich press chief, Marcks partic- rly exercised a considerable degree of personal influence his superior. In his capacity as Schleicher's public ations officer Marcks was also privy to the inner work— is and plans of the cabinet. The activities of Colonel h were likewise of a highly political nature. In addi- >n to heading the armed forces section of the War listry, Ott acted as Schleicher's Reichstag observer las the liaison in the General's attempted negotiations :h Hitler. Ott was frequently called upon to advise idenburg and the cabinet on political questions that olved the army. Because Ott and Marcks had been so sely connected with the intrigues of Schleicher, the is relieved both officers of their Berlin posts in 4. The Nazis sent Ott to Tokyo as military attache transferred Marcks back to a regular army unit. After 1929 Schmitt became the adviser to the leicher clique in constitutional affairs; he maintained closest contact with Marcks and Ott. Through these nections Schmitt's ideas were filtered into the decision ing circles and in this manner he was kept informed of intentions of the government. It is doubtful that 165 hmitt would ever have played the important role he did the end of the Weimar Republic without the personal and litical contacts he acquired in Berlin. Perhaps the working of fate brought Carl Schmitt, a theorist of the Ausnahmezustand, to Berlin just as the imar Republic was once again to experience a period of stained crisis. Neither Schmitt's writings on the state exception and the dictatorial powers of the president ier Article 48, nor his advice to political leaders were sponsible for the crisis which led to the end of the public. Werner Conze was correct in stating that oppos— g theoretical positions, such as the Decisionism of Carl nmitt and the necessity of a democratic party state vocated by Richard Thoma, do not provide the key to erstanding the collapse of Weimar. Instead the problem t be investigated in light of the concrete situation sting at the end of the Weimar Republic, in order to ermine why a multiparty parliamentary system failed to ction in Germany in 1929-1930.4 The fundamental weakness of the Weimar party state ch led to the paralysis of the parliamentary system er 1929 had existed since the inception of the Republic. ultiplicity of antagonistic political groups and parties 4 Werner Conze, "Die Krise des Parteienstaates in tschland 1929/30," Historische Zeitschrift, Bd. 178, t l (1954). p. 50. ' ‘ "’ _________ 166 idered the formation of stable and enduring governing iorities and coalitions. Parties were based not upon litical platforms, but upon incompatible ideologies and oresented distinct social and economic classes. These :eressenparteien proved unable to make the compromises :essary for cooperation with their opponents. Thus, the Llure of the republican forces and the parties within a Reichstag to integrate their programs and policies :h one another actually decided the fate of Weimar. The last attempt at a workable compromise between ase antagonistic parties came in the form of the Great alition of 1928. But the new cabinet, headed by the :ial Democrat Hermann Mueller, did not receive its cliamentary majority from the republican parties alone was forced to rely upon the support of the German ple's Party. Still, the divisions between the German ted to allow for lasting cooperation. Beginning in 9 the economic crisis strained the tenuous basis of the lition and led to its eventual disintegration. At a e when cooperation was most necessary, the disinte- tiOn of the coalition left Weimar Germany without a ble governing majority, as class and party interest dominated over the common and national interest. The first years Carl Schmitt spent in Berlin were i l Fple's Party and the Social Democrats were too deeply s plagued by the paralysis of the government, economic 167 Epression, and movements for reform and revolution from he right and left, with three unsuccessful attempts at wercoming the parliamentary stalemate through a presi- mntial government. In these crisis years Schmitt enjoyed us greatest public acclaim through his writings, and his reatest political influence on decision makers. He chieved this influence and popularity by attempting to rovide theoretical and practical solutions to the polit- cal problems then besieging Germany. Aside from counsel- ing the Schleicher clique he published numerous books and rticles on topics of pressing political importance and fctured on these problems to several academic and business rganizations. From the earliest stages of the crisis Schmitt alt the Weimar constitution and state faced an internal anger. He identified two major elements of such danger s the "inner political neutrality of the state" and :cessive pluralism. These ideas were based upon what he nsidered an outdated liberal political philosophy, and re antithetical to the type of strong state Schmitt pre- rred. They also directly related to the two problems in facing Germany, parliamentary paralysis and economic ression. He attacked the doctrine of pluralism in a lecture a conference of the Kant Gesellschaft in Halle on 168 2, 1929.5 The advocates of pluralism, Schmitt ed, removed the state from its status as the highest ical and social unit, relegating it to a position st other social groups and associations, such as ious and economic organizations. A "plurality of hies" resulted in making the state dependent upon a ariety of these diverse groups and their special 6 Schmitt did not deny that a sts and compromises. l plurality of interests and associations existed. ued only that it must exist within the organized 'cal unit of the state, and the state must stand above individual interests and represent the whole nation. :ate decides a case of unavoidable conflict between :ent loyalties and conflicting groups. An individual Find no greater field of freedom than that guaranteed trong state. e political unit (i.e., the state) is the highest it, not because it dictates omnipotently or levels 1 other units, but because it decides and therefore thin itself can hinder all other adverse associ— ions . . . . Where it exists, the social conflicts individuals and social groups can be decided, so at an order, i.e., a normal situation, remains. ‘alistic party states the unity of the state con— only so long as two or several parties come to 5Carl Schmitt, "Staatsethik und pluralistischer Positionen und Begriffe, op. cit., PP. 133—145. 6Ibid., pp. 134—135. 7Ibid., p. 141. 169 rms and recognize common premises. Then the state is sed upon a constitution, commonly recognized and spected by all parties. Under such conditions the thority of the constitution can serve as the foundation r a very effective political unit. Unfortunately the condition of the Weimar Republic longer reflected this pattern. Not only did several rties refuse to recognize the authority of the consti— tion and the Republic, but those that did were so vided they could find no common premise on which to operate. From Schmitt's point of View the real casualty s the state and its constitution. To counteract this end he began addressing himself to the question of who, ting on behalf of the whole nation, could stand above ese diverse interests and serve as the defender of the ate and constitution. Given the conditions of Weimar believed that only a neutral force with extensive power, resenting all the German people, could play the role of defender of the constitution. Always having stressed need for a strong president, Schmitt now turned to the 'chspresident as the only viable institution to fulfill 's purpose. Schmitt first introduced this solution to 170 the woes of Weimar in a 1929 article entitled "Der Hueter der Verfassung." In a related article Schmitt had denied that the German supreme court, the Reichsgericht, could serve as the protector of the constitution as it had proclaimed in a decision of October 15, 1927.10 On the contrary, the protector of the constitution must be of a highly polit- ical nature and endowed with extensive political power. The supreme court was incapable of both defending the con~ stitution as a whole and of wielding sufficient political power. Its decisions were limited to violations of indi— vidual constitutional laws and, even in this respect, its decisions were always too late. So long as it remained purely judicial rather than political it must decide after a violation has occurred.12 Also, he recognized that the court would be powerless against a constitutional amending 13 law under Article 76. And he feared that an extremist arty might use this article legally to abuse or even 9Carl Schmitt, "Der Hueter der Verfassung," rchiv des oeffentlichen Rechts, Neue Folge, XVI (March, 929), pp. 161—237. loCarl Schmitt, "Das Reichsgericht als Hueter der erfassung," (1929), Verfassungsrechtliche Aufsaetze, P- cit., p. 70. llIbid., pp. 69-70. 12Carl Schmitt, Der Hueter der Verfassung Tuebingen, 1931), pp. 32—33. 13Ibid., p. 16. 171 stroy the existing constitution. Thus, Schmitt approached e defense of the constitution as a realistic political oblem and not as a judicial one. The judiciary so long it stayed above politics was quite limited in its de- nse of the constitution. Laws may be passed in defense the constitution and judicial decisions rendered, but thout political authority the judiciary would still main powerless, for "one law cannot be the defender of 14 A true defender of the constitution .other law." quires the political authority to distinguish the iend from the enemy and the real power to enforce that cision. If the judiciary received such political thority it would result in the politicalization of stice.15 Consequently, Schmitt doubted that the judiciary uld overcome a crisis which was so political in nature. litically, contemporary Germany was an unstable, ralistic coalition-party—state rather than a parlia— tary party-state.l6 Political parties under a parlia- tary party—state are free associations, without firmly trolled or tightly disciplined organizations. Such ties act as a means of forming government policy. A 14Ibid., p. 40. 15Carl Schmitt, "Reichsgericht," op. cit., p. 98. 16 Carl Schmitt, Der Hueter, op. cit., pp. 88-89. 172 rliament becomes the arena in which numerous socio— Jnomic, cultural, and confessional opponents, along with tying interests and opinions, are transformed into a ified political will.17 Through the free negotiations representatives different party interests are trans- rmed into an over—party will. To its misfortune Weimar ver approximated this type of party—state. Weimar rties were thoroughly organized structures with influ— tial bureaucracies, standing armies of functionaries, i entire systems of help and support organizations, to ich an ideological, social, and economic clientele was iesively bound.l8 A proportional representation system elections and the list system further aggravated the ablem. Voters no longer voted for an individual repre- itative. Instead they confronted a party list contain— ; a series of names selected in secret, uncontrolled :ty committees. This resulted in a statistical grouping 1 distribution of the voting masses according to a lority of party lists. Because parties were organized m firmly bound political and social power blocks actions constituted an appeal to the standing party w and, in effect, a plebiscite.19 17Ibid. l8Ibid., p. 83. 19Ibid., pp. 86-87. The problem of political par— 8 and the list system was a generally recognized one, -_2 -'r*- " _'-" u—a’ugn—r—‘Ax-ét‘x- ifi~_.—:‘n;~.— >7 -_--. .. 1,. 173 No longer the arena of compromise and unity par- liament had become the arena for the division of the nation into a plurality of social groups. This pluralism led either to the inability to form majorities, or to a con— dition in which the present majority used all legal pos- sibilities of its term in office to secure its possession of power, and to limit the opportunity of its opponents to 20 do the same. The plurality of loyalties and the uncom- promising organizations endangered the unity of the state and destroyed respect for the constitution, since each group had its own concept of the constitution. Maintaining the legal reins of power every incumbent majority or coali— tion declared its own actions as legal, designating any threats to, and criticism of, its own position as illegal and contrary to the spirit of the constitution.21 Whereas particularly in the latter stages of the Republic. Even two jurists so diametrically opposed to Carl Schmitt as Fritz Hartung and Hans Kelsen saw these as two of the most crucial problems paralyzing the parliamentary system. See: Fritz Hartung, Jurist unter vier Reichen (Cologne, 1971), pp. 90-91. Hans Kelsen, "Die Krise des parlamentar— ischen Systems," February 4, 1931, speech before the Februar—Klub in Cologne. The Februar—Klub was a non— partisan political organization dedicated to constitu— tional reform and a strengthening of the power of the Reichsgovernment over the Reichstag. Nachlass Friedrich spaeter Vorsitzender des Februar—Klubs, BA, Kleinen Erwerbungen, No. 484, Bd. 2, (1930-1931). 20Carl Schmitt, Der Hueter, op. cit., p. 89. ZlIbid., p. 90. 174 a the nineteenth century the danger to the constitution ame from the executive, with the legislative branch erving as the defender of the constitution, the current 22 For the anger resided in the legislative branch. luralistic social and economic power blocks in parlia— ent had led to the paralysis of the government and pres- ntly threatened the political unity of the nation. A strong political power standing above these iffering positions was not the alternative. Rather than cting as the defender of the constitution this "Higher hird" would actually be the sovereign ruler of the tate.23 The solution lay, therefore, in a "Neutral hird," a pouvoir neutre standing, not above, but next 3 other constitutional powers. This neutral third must amain neutral and independent of party interests and apresent the entire nation. The democratic sections of ie Weimar constitution provided for such a neutral third 1 the form of the Reichspresident. Directly elected by re German people, his term lasted for seven years, aking him independent of changing parliamentary majorities rd coalitions. He maintained special political powers rainst the parliament through his ability to dissolve m Reichstag, call new elections, and present national 221bid., pp. 24-25. 23Ibid., p. 132. 175 eferendums. All of these provisions granted him the ower to appeal directly to the people as a whole without eliance on the parties. The Reichspresident also retained xtensive political authority to deal with a crisis under rticle 48. In this manner the Reichspresident had the ower to represent the political will of the German people nd, thereby, acted as the defender of the constitution and 24 he unity of Germany. Ebert and Hindenburg, each in is own way, had played the role of the neutral third and he defender of the constitution quite successfully.25 Soon Schmitt‘s thesis became a significant legal rgument and catchword for the presidential system. incerely believing in the necessity of a neutral force chmitt by no means used his legal arguments to cover ttempts to establish Hindenburg as the figurehead of a avernment ruled by rightist parties. As throughout most E his life Schmitt now concerned himself with maintaining :der and stability in a time of crisis. He did not itend the presidential system as a method of destroying re constitution and the Republic. The role of the intellectual in politics Schmitt .80 compared to the neutrality of the Reichspresident. rintellectual was neither to be the servant of one 24Ibid., pp. 158-159. 25ibid., p. 139. 176 tical party or ideology, nor to remain aloof from tics. Neutrality meant not passivity and inactivity independence from party control.26 The intelligentsia be able to maintain its respect as a free, objective, unorganized intellectual force. Rather than promoting osition and goals of a particular party the intel— tsia should provide the leading spirit for the nation. by preserving this independence could the intelli— ia stimulate public opinion and national feeling, lements Schmitt considered essential to the continued ence of the Weimar Republic. On this point Schmitt d the increasing difficulty for political thinkers to ad their intellectual independence. He even doubted a political intelligentsia independent of organized Les still existed in Weimar Germany. Warning that an >endent intelligentsia and a constitutional structure end in hand, he stated that, "the fate of the German .ligentsia and education will also be the fate of the r constitution."27 Schmitt followed his own advice on the independence e intellectual in politics. Though previously favor— he position of the Center Party he still managed to participation in party politics, and in this way he 26Carl Schmitt, "Hugo Preuss in der Deutschen slehre," Die Neue Rundschau, XXXXI, Ed. I (1930), p. 27Ibid., p. 303. 177 ined independent from all parties until the Nazi one- y state stifled all opposing factions. So as not to ect his political obligation and to avoid playing the of the aloof, passive intellectual, he offered his ices to the German state. Subsequently he assisted president, army, and bureaucracy, the forces he per— lly perceived as standing above party politics. ually his activity went far beyond maintaining intel- ual objectivity and stimulating public opinion, ough certainly it did fall within the scope of enhanc» national feeling. Since Schmitt's arrival in Berlin he was in c0n— with Schleicher circles. Around 1929 when Schleicher n having more and more influence with the government Hindenburg, the ideas of Schmitt were filtered into the ers of policy making. Because Schmitt never person— met Hindenburg the intermediaries of the Schleicher :ie kept Schmitt informed of the inner workings and itions of the government, and at the same time they >duced Schmitt's ideas to Hindenburg.28 Most important ' these ideas was the Reichspresident as the defender e constitution and the execution of Article 48 to the problems then besieging the Republic. 28Schmitt Interview, July 13, 1973. 178 "Der Hueter der Verfassung" first appeared as an cle in March 1929. Aside from circulating this arti- among his close friends in the Schleicher clique itt sent copies directly to certain government offices, e his work was greeted with enthusiasm. Otto Meissner, e secretary in the Office of the Reichspresident, 9: I have taken special interest and notice of your arguments and the characterization of the Reichs— president as the neutral and mediating force. . . . I am also convinced that every successor to the first two Reichspresidents will View this activity as one of his most important tasks and that gradually a practice will arise, which realizes your tenet of the neutral and mediating force.29 equal enthusiasm Erich Zweigert, state secretary in Reich ministry of the interior, hailed Schmitt's work clear—sighted and courageous," stating, ". . . it d give me excellent support in the impending discus— s with the lawyers from the judiciary over the future 30 1e supreme court . . . ." The government was starting to take note of the ible value of Schmitt's ideas. Henceforth, the serv— and ideas of Carl Schmitt would be utilized by the in government for the duration of the Republic. .tt's most influential role in this regard had to do 29State secretary Otto Meissner to Carl Schmitt, 8, 1929, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 30State secretary Erich Zweigert to Carl Schmitt, 4, 1929, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 179 th the Schleicher plan for a presidential system. The eas of Schmitt and the plans of Schleicher would go hand hand as both attempted to discover a solution to the litical and economic crisis then facing Germany. Schmitt ovided a convenient legal and theoretical foundation for e plans of Schleicher. But Schmitt's writings after 29 should not, for this reason, be construed as mere opaganda or polemics written only to justify the actions the government, or more precisely the presidential sys— m. These were scholarly works, of a highly political ture, directed at the existing situation of late Weimar. om his early years Schmitt had always asserted that litical theories and analyses should not be based upon stract constructions but upon a concrete situation. In ct, the components of Schmitt's presidential system, st notably the idea of the Reichspresident as the ivoir neutre, were already clearly formulated by imitt in 1927, before he moved to Berlin and involved melf with the Schleicher circle.3l During the winter of 1929 Schleicher began pro— ing his plan for composing a cabinet which, standing rve narrow party interests and representing the national erest, would have the confidence of the Reichspresident the army, and in this manner he hoped to overcome the 31Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre, op. cit., 350—353. 180 :isis. If the Reichstag refused to go along the ichspresident would dissolve the Reichstag and rule der Article 48. Schleicher had already advocated a .milar alternative in 1927. For this reason the origin fthe presidential system is often solely attributed to :hleicher.32 Yet the legal components of Schleicher's esidential system were quite similar to the presi- ntial system developed since 1927 by Carl Schmitt. Most kely Schleicher decided to use Schmitt's arguments as e legal foundation for his own political intentions. is interesting to note that Schleicher first renewed s efforts for a presidential solution after coming into ntact with Schmitt and after the release of "Der Hueter r Verfassung." Schleicher's original plan, however, :luded changing parts of the constitution in order to establish a workable political order in Germany, a sition not advocated by Schmitt in his writings. Schleicher's first problem was to select a suitable ncellor for his plans and for this purpose he began rting the conservative Catholic Heinrich Bruening of Center Party. After Easter of 1929 Schleicher first 32 3—1945 (New York, 1964), pp. 436—437. Dorpalen, ienburg and the Weimar Republic, pp. 127, 170. Walter '~__—_ _— 181 )posed his plan to Bruening directly. According to ileicher, the Reichspresident wanted to reestablish a :kable political order before his death. Since the ichspresident had sworn an oath to uphold the consti- :ion he refused to support any unconstitutional schemes. arefore, Schleicher proposed dissolving the Reichstag and .ing with Article 48 until affairs were brought in ler. Bruening stated that governing areas of economic [social life in this manner might be possible, but that :icle 48 could not be used to change the constitution. deicher countered this by informing Bruening that he lassembled in the War Ministry Gutachten from crown ists which proved that Article 48 could be used for nding the constitution. Several days later Bruening eived these Gutachten through state secretaries Joel Zweigert. These Gutachten, indeed, Showed the pos— le use of Article 48 for overcoming the crisis, but nothing to do with the reform and constitutional erations that Schleicher had read into them.33 No doubt among these Gutachten Carl Schmitt's eter der Verfassung" held a prime position. The leicher circles, as well as state secretary Zweigert, (I) already in possession of Schmitt's work. Schmitt self claimed that one of the Gutachten in question 33Heinrich Bruening, Memoiren, 1918—1934 ittgart, 1970), pp. 145—147. 182 elonged to him and that he was also working closely with weigert.34 Moreover, these Gutachten contained a cate- orical rejection of the idea of constitutional reform nder Article 48. Similarly Schmitt repeatedly renounced he possibility of constitutional change through Article 48. nd in 1929 Schmitt again commenced speaking out against onstitutional reform during this period of crisis. Schleicher's possible misuse of Schmitt's ideas Dints out the dangers facing the intellectual in politics. he creations of an intellectual are never taken over pre- isely by politicians, rather they are used for a polit— :al purpose, often in a distorted form as justifications 3r political acts. Very often these ideas are intention— Lly misinterpreted or altered to fit a particular set of )litical circumstances or ends. Once the intellectual Laces his ideas and talents at the service of politicians rch ideaS'become the tools of these politicians, to be sed or disregarded, depending upon the changing needs of reir own position. This is the price the intellectual rst pay when he enters the world of politics, abandoning e purity of the ivory tower. Carl Schmitt was more than .lling to take such chances, for he enjoyed his new posi— .on as an adviser to the decision makers, and all the estige, excitement, and enhanced celebrity which 34Schmitt interview, July 13, 1973. 183 accompanied it. Schmitt sincerely thought that his ideas were influencing events and, in many respects, perhaps they were quite influential. But his ideas were by no means the governing force behind the activities of the govern— ment or the politicians he served. Throughout 1929 Schleicher continued to promote the presidential system as a solution to Germany's ills. Meanwhile the political and economic situation worsened intil the paralysis of a pluralistic party-state Schmitt iad warned against became a reality. Unable to agree on increases in the unemployment insurance and budgetary natters the parties of the Great Coalition reached a stalemate of noncooperation. On March 27, 1930 the meller cabinet resigned. The following day saw the first stage of success of Schleicher's plan when Hindenburg rppointed Heinrich Bruening chancellor. Bruening's eventual goal was to free Germany of he oppressive burden of reparations. To accomplish this e believed that he must first put Germany's finances in mder. Bruening intended to reserve the Great Coalition nd work with the Reichstag while relying, especially in inancial matters, on the increased power of the govern— ent. When the Reichstag on July 16, rejected his finan— ial programs Bruening abandoned his reliance on the eichstag and commenced issuing his programs as emergency ecrees authorized under Article 48. The Reichstag then 184 nvoked its constitutional right under that same provision nd voted to repeal these decrees. Instead of resigning ruening dissolved the Reichstag and called for new elec— ions for September 14. This was the actual beginning E the presidential system and represented a further iccess for Schleicher's plan. Immediately after Bruening entered office Schmitt ad begun publicly supporting the sweeping and drastic :onomic measures the new chancellor was about to intro— ace. Speaking on April 8, 1930 before the fiftieth Con— srence of the German Chamber of Industry and Commerce :hmitt urged strong action on the part of the state to ercome the growing economic crisis.35 Before this flience, which included numerous members of the govern- mt and the Reichstag, Schmitt attacked the liberal inciples of the inner political neutrality and absolute m—intervention of the state in the economy. He empha- zed that these outdated nineteenth century concepts pre— nted a real danger considering the current condition of rmany.36 The state of the twentieth century was an onomic state and to a great extent the domestic and reign policy of a country was political economics. The 35Carl Schmitt, "Neutralitaet gegenueber der rtschaft?" Germania, No. 166 (April 9, 1930). 36Carl Schmitt, "Das Problem der innerpolitischen utralitaet des Staates," (1930), Verfassungsrechtliche fsaetze, op. cit., p. 41. 185 alyzing effects of the unstable coalition-party—state sting in Germany hindered the formation of political isions which were not based upon the narrow economic erests of the parties forming a coalition at any one ticular time. Resulting decisions were rarely impar- l and often did not take in account the interest of nation as a whole.37 The depoliticalization of the state‘s economic icies offered no solution. Politics was an unavoidable sequence of anything of public interest or of concern the state. Schmitt reminded his audience that "the ght from politics is the flight from the state."38 ther did the solution lie with the total control of the nomy by the state, as exemplified by the Soviet system Russia and the Fascist stato corporativo in Italy. a systems were directed by a rigidly centralized one— :y state which Schmitt rejected.39 Germany required :her total state control of the entire economy nor a :ening of the state power over the economy. What any needed was decisive political decisions on the .of the state concerning the economy. In this manner 37Ibid-, pp. 54—55. 38Ibid., pp. 56-57. 39ibid., p. 44. 186 :he state could best represent the interests of the entire . 4 nation. 0 Schmitt believed that this did not require changes in or abandonment of the existing constitution. He cau— :ioned against such plans noting that “all constitutional 41 possibilities by no means have been exhausted." The mal problem facing the German people was not constitu— jonal reform but unity. They could save themselves as a political unit or exist as a reparations state controlled w foreign powers.42 In taking this stance Schmitt was, i course, supporting Bruening's plan to use the consti- mtional emergency powers to put Germany's economy in mder and to relieve the country of its burdens as a eparations state. Around this same time Schmitt informed is acquaintance Ernst Niekisch of his desire to play a ore active political role and to advise Bruening on con— titutional matters. He even attempted fruitlessly to nlist Niekisch's support for Bruening.43 While Schmitt ublicly displayed this support the Bruening government tom its inception was beginning to utilize the constitu- ional interpretations of Carl Schmitt. 4OIbid., p. 57. 4lIbid., p. 58. 421bid. 3Ernst Niekisch, Gewagtes Lebens: Begegnungen und flgpfligpo (Cologne, 1958), p. 242. 187 Several immediate problems faced the Bruening government's application of Article 48 to solve the eco- nomic crisis. The first problem involved a possible rejection by the Reichstag of the government emergency decrees. Since a rejection of these decrees by the Reichstag would interfere with Bruening's plans he hoped to dissolve the Reichstag and, in the interim before the new elections, reinstitute these decrees. This would avoid at least temporarily any interference on the part of the Reichstag with Bruening's manipulation of Article 48. But this procedure created a second problem for Bruening. There was some doubt as to whether the Bruening government after having already received a vote of no confidence from the Reichstag could, in the interim between elections, iremain in power and continue issuing emergency decrees Jpreviously rejected by the Reichstag. Attempting to ans— iwer these questions in Bruening's favor, Herbert Dorn, ministerial director of the Reich finance ministry, pro— vided the government with a Gutachten on April 3, concern- ing the interrelationship of Article 48 and the dissolving 44 Of the Reichstag. According to Dorn the opposition of the Reichstag could only constitutionally be counteracted 44Gutachten Dorn EB Punkt l der heutigen Minister— besprechung. (3.4.1930) Zur Frage der Anwendung des Artikels 48 der Reichsverfassung und der Aufloesung des Reichstags. BA, R-43—I, Bd. 1870, "Art. 48 der Reichs— Verfassung (1924-1930)," pp. 107-110. 188 if the Reichstag was dissolved. In such an event Dorn stated, \ Walter Jellinek and Karl Schmitt are of the opinion that a government which receives a vote of no con— fidence can countersign the dissolving order of the Reichspresident and remain in office as the managing government until after new elections . . . and that some sort of legally constituted limitation on its functions for the period after the vote of no con- fidence is not provided for.45 That interpretation would leave the Bruening government free to implement its programs under Article 48 during the interim. And not surprisingly the position taken by the Bruening government when its emergency decrees were suspended by the Reichstag on July 18, 1930 exactly paralleled the interpretation of Jellinek and Schmitt. When a Social Democratic motion for suspending the emer— ‘gency decrees passed the Reichstag with 236 votes to 221, ‘Bruening immediately dissolved the Reichstag. Not only ldid the Bruening government refuse to resign, but on l July 26, it instituted five new emergency decrees on economic and financial matters.46 No longer in session the Reichstag had no opportunity to vote to suspend these new decrees. The government, however, realized that it probably would face the suspension of these measures after the new elections in the fall. It began immediately 45Ibid-, pp. 108—109. 46Horkenbach, Deutsche Reich, op. cit., pp. 315—316. 189 preparing its legal and political case for the use of Article 48 to overcome the economic crisis. Two days after the issuance of these new decrees Carl Schmitt provided the Bruening government with a Gutachten justifying the constitutional power of the Reichspresident to issue such financial decrees under 47 With this action Schmitt made his services Article 48. available to the Bruening government, setting a precedent for his future cooperation with the policies of the suc- ceeding two Reichschancellors. In making his talents available to the government Schmitt did not opportunis— tically change his own opinions. He remained generally consistent with prior positions he had held on the actual power of the Reichspresident under Article 48. But now Schmitt was willing to accept a greater exercise of presidential power concerning emergency decrees. Schmitt observed that constitutional developments over the previous ten years had produced several changes regarding the Ausnahmezustand and emergency decrees, which now must be considered as integral parts of the existing constitutional order. These changes developed out of the practices of the government, decisions of the supreme 47Carl Schmitt, Verfassungsrechtliches Gutachten Grund des Art. gofAbs. 2 RE. finanzgesetzvertretende Verordnungen op erlassen, July 28, 1930, BA, R-43—I, Bd. 1870. 190 court, and legal literature. Two of the most significant developments were the authority of the Reichspresident to issue decrees as substitutes for laws ("gesetzvertretende Verordnungen"), and the further expansion of his powers to deal with special financial and economic states of excep— tion.48 The authority of the Reichspresident under Article 48, Schmitt believed, also applied to the current situation because an extensive threat to public order and security could arise from economic and financial crises.49 A Reichspresident could exercise his exceptional powers in financial matters so long as he observed the constitu— 50 To support this tional limitations on these powers. contention Schmitt cited several examples from the eco— nomic crises of 1923—1924, as precedents in the use of Article 48 to overcome such problems. As a consequence of the practice of the last ten Years emergency decrees of the Reichspresident now went beyond the status of merely being measures (Massnahmen). ThOUgh still not formal laws as would be passed by the legislature, presidential decrees did carry the authority 481bid., pp. 1—3. 491bid., p. 3. 50 Ibid., pp. 6-7. 51Ibid., p. 4. 191 of law. Accordingly, the present economic and financial programs did not require formal laws and could be ful— filled by decree—substituting-laws (gesetzvertretende 52 Schmitt Verordnungen), issued by the Reichspresident. stated that he personally still adhered to the distinction between measures (Massnahmen) and laws (Gesetze), but that developments in constitutional practice had blurred this distinction.53 By conceding this point Schmitt was not accepting the Reichspresident as an unlimited legislative authority usurping the constitutional power delegated to the Reichstag. "It is self—evident," Schmitt explained, "that a limitless, uncontrolled competency of the Reichpresident is not being advocated here . . .," and, "that the actual limits of the exceptional powers of the Reichspresident and the actual security against the misuse of his power lies in the control authority oi the Reichstag . . . ."54 A majority vote in the Reichstag could immediately suspend any emergency decree. Schmitt went on to say that in the event these decrees were issued while the Reichstag was not assembled the government was constitutionally obligated to present these decrees to the newly assembled or elected 521bid., pp. 6—13. 53Ibid., p. 11. 54Ibid., p. 22. 192 Reichstag for ratification.55 If the re-assembled or newly elected Reichstag was incapable of gathering a majority the decrees would stand as issued. For a Reichstag incapable of conducting policy because it lacked a workable majority should not be allowed to incapacitate a viable government.56 The government and the central bureaucracy received this Gutachten with open arms and grasped on to its argu— ments as one of the strongest legal defenses of their pro- grams. Bruening received this Gutachten from state secre— tary Dorn on July 30. In a letter to the chancellor Dorn stated, the conclusion to which this work comes is much more satisfactory since Prof. Schmitt is one of the few constitutionalists who, up to now, basically refused to recognize a decreeing power of the Reichspresident on the basis of Article 48. In case hesitations from other sides should be forthcoming, this Gutachten would, for that reason, be an essential foundation for our position.57 This modification in Schmitt's position obviously held more value for the government than for Schmitt himself. What Schmitt desired was not theoretical consistency forever but accurately to analyze the concrete situation and propose necessary solutions. Nonetheless, the objec— tive of both Schmitt and the government regarding the 551bid., p. 23. 56Ibid., pp. 23—24. 57State secretary Dorn to Reichschancellor, July 30, 1930, BA, R—43—I, Bd. 1870, p. 285. 193 decreeing power of the Reichspresident coincided. They were both intent upon allowing the Reichspresident exten- sive power so that, through the chancellor, his cabinet and the bureaucracy, the stalemate in the Reichstag could be overcome and the necessary programs instituted to meet the crisis. During the summer and fall of 1930 Schmitt's Gutachten attracted a good deal of attention within the government and bureaucracy. It became the subject of phone conversations and correspondence between various ministries including the finance ministry, the Chancellery and the ministry of the interior.58 On October 7, another constitutionalist, Professor Richard Thoma, presented the government with a Gutachten dealing precisely with the financial and economic emer- gency decrees issued by the Reichspresident on July 26.59 Thoma accepted the constitutionality of the decrees in general, while interpreting several individual parts as unconstitutional. Concurring with Schmitt, he also held 58Ministerial director von Hagenow to state secre— tary Zweigert, August 2, 1930. Zweigert to von Hagenow, August 2, 1930. Zweigert to State secretary Puender, October 10, 1930. BA, R-43—I, Bd. 1870, PP. 311-312, 322. 59Richard Thoma, Rechtsgutachten ueber goo . Verfassungsmaessigkeit der Verordnung goo Reichspraesidenten Egg behebung financiellEET wirtschaftlicher poo sozialer NOtstaende vom 26. Juli 1930, Reichsgesetzblatt Teil I.S. fill. Auf ErEUEhEH des Reichsministerium goo Innern, OctobEf—7, 1930, BAT‘R—43—I, 1870. See also: Richard Thoma, "Die Notstandsverordnung des Reichspraesidenten vom 26 Juli 1930," Zeitschrift fuer oeffentliches Recht, Bd. XI (1931), pp. 12—33. 194 that these decrees must be immediately suspended upon request of the Reichstag as required by paragraph three of Article 48.60 As expected Schmitt was far more con- scious of the realistic political situation in the Reichstag than Thoma, who appeared more interested in the purely legal aspects of the case. Schmitt clearly fore— saw a situation in which the Reichstag would either be unwilling to challenge these emergency decrees, or be unable to overcome its paralytic pluralism and form the necessary majority to suspend these decrees. Not even a realist like Carl Schmitt could have foreseen the catastrophic results of the election of September 1930. The election proved to be a great victory for the radicals and for all practical purposes signaled the end of a viable parliamentary form of government in Germany. Most shocking was the ominous forward surge of the National Socialists from 12 seats in 1928 to 107 in the new election. At the same time the Communist Party showed significant gains, rising from 54 to 77 seats. Although the Social Democrats remained the strongest party in the Reichstag, reduced by only 10 seats to 143, the second and third strongest parties now consisted of the two most fanatical and radically anti-republican 60State secretary Zweigert's summary of Schmitt and Thoma Gutachten, November 10, 1930, BA, R—43-I, Bd. 1870, pp. 380-383. 195 61 Bruening's parties, the Nazis and the Communists. plan for returning a submissive Reichstag, and his desire to acquire the support of the German Nationalists for his programs, were shattered as the Nationalist parties lost many of their seats to the Nazis. Under these circum— stances no stable majority coalition could be formed except for a government of the right with the National Socialists included in the government. A resurrection of the Great Coalition was unlikely and offered no alter— native since the member parties now controlled only 47.3 percent of the seats. Unwilling to take the Nazis into the government Bruening was forced to assemble a minority cabinet based on the Center Party and several small right— wing groups, which received the toleration of the Social Democrats.62 All hopes for the Reichstag reasserting itself and irejecting the emergency decrees of Bruening's presidential ‘government were overshadowed by the now threatening danger of the National Socialists. Along with many of his con— ytemporaries Carl Schmitt had underestimated the potential of the Hitler movement. Shortly after World War I he had encountered the National Socialists during his Munich 61Horkenbach, Deutsche Reich, op. cit., p. 401. 62Alfred Milatz, "Das Ende der Parteien im Spiegel der Wahlen 1930 bis 1933," pop Ende opp Parteien 1933, ed., Erich Matthias and Rudolf Morsey (Duesseldorf, 1960), pp. 756-758. 196 days. Then he considered them as an insignificant fanati— 63 As the Nazis cal group whom he could not take seriously. started to gain extensive support throughout Germany in the late twenties Schmitt viewed them as an anti—constitutional party which, like the Communists, should not be given the opportunity to destroy the Republic. He argued that the state could not remain neutral where its own existence was concerned and that anti—constitutional parties should be denied an equal chance to acquire power, particularly when their actual goal included the destruction of the very legal order granting them that opportunity. Schmitt called such absolute neutrality an absurdity which no constitu- tional order could tolerate. Consequently, he favored the Law for the Protection of the Republic, which made sub— version of the Republic a treasonable crime. And he sup— ported restrictions against National Socialist and Com- munist civil servants and the exclusion of National Socialists and Communists from broadcasting over the 64 Until the very end of the Republic Schmitt main— radio. tained this adamant anti-Nazi position. With the Nazi threat looming in the forefront the varying political factions in the Reichstag still in 63Schmitt Interview, November 22, 1972. 64Carl Schmitt, Hugo Preuss: Sein Staatsbegriff und seine Stellung in der Deutschen Staatslehre (Tuebingen, 1930), p. 32. 197 support of the Republic feared that Bruening's defeat would lead to further radicalization. These parties, including the Social Democrats, managed to cooperate in defeating proposals by the radicals calling for the sus- pension of the chancellor's emergency decrees, and the republican forces thereby forestalled a parliamentary con— frontation which could have brought down the government. In doing so these parties followed a course already pre- dicted by Carl Schmitt, in that they were both unable and unwilling to exercise their constitutional controls on the emergency powers of the Reichspresident. For the most part the Reichstag failed to have any further influence in the policies of the Bruening government, and the presi- dential system directed German policy for the next year. In the course of these years Schmitt remained totally unaware of Bruening's plans for the restoration of the monarchy.65 He, of course, personally knew the chan— cellor but he was never accepted into Bruening's confi- dence. Before Bruening's appointment as chancellor the two men had spent a few days together at a conference. From their conversations Schmitt received no indication of 66 Bruening's monarchist tendencies. This was probably the 65Josef Becker, "Bruening, Praelat Kaas und Das Problem Einer Regierungsbeteilung der NSDAP, 1930—1932," Historische Zeitschrift, Bd. 196 (1963), p. 110. Bruening, Memoiren, op. oip., pp. 145-147. 66Schmitt Interview, July 13, 1973. 198 extent of Schmitt's close personal contact with Bruening himself and their personal contact did not continue during the chancellor's term of office. Unaware of Bruening's true future intentions Schmitt continued publicly sup- porting the chancellor's program of emergency decrees in 1930 and 1931. Schmitt would never relinquish his belief in the necessity of the presidential system. Proposals to utilize the presidential system and the crisis as an opportunity for constitutional reform actually disturbed the prophet of stability. Demands from rightist political groups urging constitutional reform existed throughout the Weimar Republic. The government had established a committee of the Reich and the states to study the problem in 1928 and subsequently reform bills were introduced into the Reichstag.67 Pressures for such reform grew stronger in proportion to the intensification of the economic and parliamentary crisis. As a consistent advocate of stability Schmitt felt that attempts at reforming the constitution in the midst of a crisis would involve dangerous risks. His position on the issue emerged quite clearly in a speech he delivered in the fall of 1930 to the Langnam-Verein, a prestigious organi— zation of German industrialists. Fearing a catastrophe Schmitt categorically stated, "I would not c0nsider any 67"Studie zur Reform der Reichsverfassung," BA, R-43—I, Bd. 1865, "Reichsverfassung (1927-1933).“ 199 fundamental constitutional reform at this time."68 As an alternative he offered the constitutional execution of Article 48 to overcome the crisis without tampering with the existing political order. The constitution, he felt, should be left alone and he warned that tampering with it could lead to "incalculable and dangerous experi— ments."69 To invoke Article 48 effectively Schmitt was will- ing to allow the Reichspresident extensive prerogatives. These prerogatives included the suspension of individual articles of the constitution so as to protect the whole constitutional order itself.70 Schmitt later explained that the emergency decrees represented anything but a dictatorship in some revolutionary sense or a Staatsstreich. They do not bring into play a new principle of government, but attempt to protect the existing constitution in a difficult situation 71 against the breakdown of its central organs . . . And it was precisely this intended use of Article 48 which 68Carl Schmitt, "Zur politischen SituatiOn in Deutschland," Der Kunstwart, Jhg. 44, No. 4 (October 1930— September 1931TT— . 255. Carl Schmitt, "Eine Warnung vor falschen politischen Fragestellungen," pop Ring, Jhg. 3, Heft 48, (November 30, 1930), pp. 844—845. 69"politischen Situation," Ibid., p. 256. 70Carl Schmitt, "Die staatsrechtliche Bedeutung der Notverordnung, insbesondere ihre Rechtsgueltigkeit," (1930), Verfassungsrechtliche Aufsaetze, op. oip., pp. 244—245. 71Ibid., p. 260. 200 Schmitt defended against the majority of German jurists present at the last conference of the Association of 72 Most of these German Jurists meeting in Halle in 1931. jurists considered the present practice of the government as an abuse of the constitution. More and more jurists and politicians after this period began speaking of the dictatorial power of the president and referring to Article 48 as the dictatorship article, in spite of Schmitt's precise interpretation of these presidential powers.73 Early in 1931 when pop Hueter do; Verfassung first appeared in book form the issue of the president as the defender of the constitution evoked varying reactions. Schmitt's theory received the public approval of Johannes Popitz, who published a major newspaper article on the subject in Germania. This close confidant and friend of Schmitt proclaimed that the thesis of pop Hueter "agrees completely with the democratic principles on which the Weimar constitution is based."74 Since Popitz was such a respected figure within the bureaucracy his endorsement helped establish the credibility of Schmitt's ideas, 72Willibalt Apelt, Jurist lo Wandel Der Staats— formen: Lebenserinnerungen (Tuebingen, 1965), p. 192. 73Ibid. 74Johannes Popitz, "Wer ist Hueter der Verfassung," Germania, Jhg. 61, No. 176 (April 17, 1931). 201 especially within official circles. But that positive acceptance of Schmitt's thesis contrasted sharply with the interpretation of those unsympathetic to the presi- dential system who, like Hans Kelsen, viewed Schmitt's work as a renewal of the doctrine of constitutional mon— 75 archy. Schmitt's book so disturbed Kelsen that he pub— lished a book in response, wherein he accused Schmitt of constructing an ideology by mixing science and politics.76 Such controversial publicity no doubt added to the recognition of Schmitt's ideas. By delivering an increas- ing number of public lectures to influential groups, com- bined with a prolific series of publications on topics of pressing political concern, Schmitt's renown and popularity continued to soar. Increasingly, his ideas attracted the attention of various sectors of the political community as well as the public in general. Needless to say, his popu— larity mostly centered among those individuals and groups supporting the strengthening of presidential power. The more widespread Schmitt's ideas were disseminated the more distorted and misused they became. If Schmitt had intended that his ideas would only provide the justifi— cation for Article 48 as a defense of the existing con— stitutional order he had greatly miscalculated. 75 sein? (Berlin, 1931). 76 Ibid., p. 56. 202 The publicity accompanying Schmitt's works during the parliamentary crisis impressed the conservative revolu- tionary groups around 91o 3gp, the Herrenklub and the Politisches Kolleg as they began recognizing the value of Schmitt's ideas for their cause. Two of the most prominent conservative revolutionary journals, Der Ring edited by Heinrich von Gleichen, and Der Kunstwart, started reporting 77 on Schmitt's lectures and publications. These conserva- tive revolutionary circles hardly shared Schmitt's concern for the defense of the existing order. They utilized Schmitt's critique of parliamentary government, party pluralism, and his support of a strong presidential system as a justification of their proposals for change, while neglecting the basic goal of Schmitt, which was to apply >residential power as a corrector to the failings of the kimar system. It must be noted that this sudden upsurge i interest in Carl Schmitt among conservative revolu— ionaries occurred after 1929 and the parliamentary crisis ad already begun. The conservative revolutionaries looked to a new tate form to replace the bankrupt Weimar system. One of 77"Umschau," pop Ring, "Zum Kapitel Staatsethik," 19. 3, Heft 40 (October 5, 1930), pp. 701-702, "Carl :hmitt ueber den totalen Staat," Jhg. 3, Heft 51 December 21, 1930), p. 912. Clemens Bauer, "Besprechung, E_Hueter der Verfassung," pop Kunstwart, Jhg. 44 mtober 1935:September 1931), pp. 809-812. Martin Merck, mtikel 48," pop Ring, Jhg. 3, Heft 31 (August 3, 1930), n 547—548. 203 the most influential leaders of 212 $33 circle, Horst Grueneberg, favored the introduction of a democratic dictatorship as a means to a national revival. Grueneberg borrowed much of his terminology and many of his central ideas directly from Carl Schmitt, especially concerning dictatorship.78 But whereas Schmitt saw the use of the president's emergency powers as that of a commissarial dictator authorized to preserve the existing order, Grueneberg promoted the concept of the dictatorship as a transition to a new political order.79 Hans Zehrer, editor of Die Tat and one of the most vocal advocates of the conservative revolution, also made extensive use of Schmitt's concepts. Zehrer mostly relied on Schmitt's critique of parliamentary government and the Reichspresident as the key to solving the existing crisis.80 Even Zehrer himself, however, realized the non- revolutionary and cautious intentions of Schmitt. Zehrer 78Horst Grueneberg, "Warum Diktatur?" Die Tat, Jhg. 22, Heft 5 (August, 1930), Pp. 321-332, "Miffelsfand— politik--Staatspolitik," 213 Egg, Jhg. 23, Heft 3 (June 3, 1931), pp. 191-212, "Die foederalistische Kulisse," Die 33;, Jhg. 23, Heft 4 (July, 1931), pp. 286-303. "_— 79Horst Grueneberg, "Zur Theorie des Antiparla— mentarismus," Die Tat, Jhg. 22, Heft 2, (May, 1930), pp. 120—121, "Diktatur ante portas!" Die Tat, Jhg. 22, Heft 3 (June, 1930), p. 195. 80Hans Zehrer, "Die Kalte Revolution," Die Tat, Jhg. 22, Heft 7 (October, 1930), PP. 484—511, "Rechts oder Links?" Die Tat, Jhg. 23, Heft 7 (October, 1931), PP. 506-559. 204 admitted that "Schmitt and Heller until now shied away from the final consequences of their ideas. They both hold open the way back, perhaps because they themselves see no new goal."81 Thus, it would be a grave error to state that in this period Carl Schmitt was either a driving force behind the conservative or national revolution, or that he was disassociated completely from members of the movement. One of Schmitt's close friends in Berlin was the national revolutionary Ernst Juenger. Just as Popitz brought Schmitt into contact with government circles upon his arrival in Berlin, Juenger served a similar purpose in bringing Schmitt into contact with conservative revolu— tionaries. Through this connection Schmitt first met ‘Ernst Niekisch, the originator of National Bolshevism. :The three men often gathered in intellectual and political 1discussions, while remaining quite independent of each 82 other in political philosophy. In his weekly Entscheidung, Niekisch even attacked Schmitt in 1932 as the defender of a Staatsstreich.83 i? l; i 81Hans Zehrer, "Der Weg in das Chaos: Enthuel— jlungen, Skandale, Sensationen," Die Tat, Jhg. 21, Heft 8 “(November, 1929), p. 568. 82Niekisch, Gewagtes Leben, op. cit., p. 242. 83Ibid. 205 A quite similar situation of personal friendship and ideological dissonance existed between Wilhelm Stapel and Schmitt.84 As editor of Deutsches Volkstum, an impor— tant and widely read journal of a conservative revolu— tionary nature, Stapel had established himself as one of the intellectual leaders of that movement. His political philosophy was a blend of extreme nationalism, a sincere concern for social problems, and a virulent anti—semitic outlook that, curiously enough, was matched only by his contempt for the National Socialists. Certainly a member of the conservative revolutionary movement, Stapel, none- theless, strove to retain a relationship between that move— ment and Christianity. Like other conservative journals, Stapel's Deutsches Volkstum utilized many of the ideas then circulating which owe their origin to Carl Schmitt. The two man first became personally acquainted at a con- ference in 1930. The religious aspect of Stapel's posi— tion held a great attraction for Schmitt, as did Stapel's support of Schleicher's later campaign against the National Socialists. A co—worker of Stapel, Albrecht Erich 85 Guenther, was also a friend of Schmitt. This latter relationship was further solidified by the fact that m 4Heinrich Kessler, Wilhelm Stapel Als Politischen Bgélggigp: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte des konservativen Nationalismus zwischen den beiden Weltkriegen (Nuremberg, 1967), pp. 148- -l49. 85Ibid., p. 147. Carl Schmitt, Hamlet, op. cit., P- 16. 206 Guenther had contact with Colonel Erich Marcks, the closest link of Carl Schmitt with the Schleicher coterie. As was the case with Schmitt's relationship to other conservative revolutionaries, personal friendship did not insulate him from public criticism from these same acquaintances. After using Schmitt's analysis as the basis for several articles on the constitutional crisis Guenther did not hesitate to criticize Schmitt on the question of dictatorship.86 Another point of dissonance between Schmitt and the Stapel circle stemmed from the extreme and irrational anti— semitic tone of Deutsches Volkstum. Anti-semitism consti- tuted no part of Schmitt's appraisal of Weimar's political dilemma. Since early youth Schmitt had closely befriended Jews, and absolutely no anti-semitic tendencies whatsoever can be detected in his Weimar works. Schmitt's rising celebrity did not go unnoticed by more moderate political thinkers. Disagreeing with Schmitt's defense of the presidential system, the direc— tors of the Hochschule fuer Politik in Berlin still be— lieved his work credible enough to invite him to lecture 87 at their institution from 1929 to 1933. This would 86Kessler, Ibid., p. 149. 87Deutsche Hochschule fuer Politik Sonderveranstal- tungen 13 Sommersemester 1929, Ausspracheabende ueber "Probleme oop Koalitionspolitik," Politisches Kolleg, BA, R-118, No. 28, "Beziehung zur Deutsche Hochschule fuer Politik, (1927-1930)." 207 hardly have been the case if they considered Schmitt a serious threat to the continued existence of the Republic. In fact, it was in a forum with Hermann Heller at the Hochschule in 1927 that Schmitt had first introduced his 88 controversial friend-enemy theory. The Hochschule also published other works by Schmitt such as "Die neutralen Groessen im heutigen Verfassungsstaat."89 The popularity Schmitt enjoyed after 1929 paved the way for his appearance as a regular guest lecturer at the Hochschule. It was, of course, the policy of the Hochschule to provide a wide divergence of political viewpoints, but the frequent reli— ance on Schmitt's lectures throughout all of these years demonstrated a more than token willingness to allow Schmitt to express his opinions. Schmitt, for example, was one of the guests invited to the 10th anniversary celebration of the Hochschule along with other public figures of pro- minence such as Adenauer, Braun, Brecht, and Heuss.90 Because of his later association with the National Socialists Schmitt's connection with the Hochschule is 88 . Wolfers, Probleme, op. c1t., p. v. 89Carl Schmitt, "Die neutralen Groessen im heutigen Verfassungsstaat," Probleme opp Demokratie; Eine Ausgabe égp deutschen Hochschule fuer Politik (Berlin, 1931), Pp. 48—56. The original manuscript is in the files of the Hochschule fuer Politik, Geheimes Staatsarchiv, Preussischer Kulturbesitz, Berlin, Rep. 303, No. 181. 90Geheimes Staatsarchiv, Rep. 303, Nos. 168, 169, 246. 208 often conveniently forgotten. Such was the problem with the future president of the German Federal Republic, Theodor Heuss who, in his memoirs, carefully dissociated himself from Schmitt. Heuss admitted candidly that he was present at the Handelshochschule in 1930 when Schmitt delivered a lecture on Hugo Preuss, but Heuss denies that he ever directly participated in the affair.91 Yet, Heuss thought enough of Schmitt and his work to write him a very cordial letter afterwards thanking Schmitt for the "strong intellectual stimulation," remarking, "I sincerely hope that the lecture will be made available in print.“92 Furthermore, Heuss neglected to mention in his memoirs that when he lectured at the Hochschule fuer Politik on world history in the nineteenth century, Schmitt handled the course on the twentieth century in that same series. As late as the fall of 1932 Heuss and Schmitt worked together in a seminar entitled "Die Reichsverfassung in Wortlaut und Wirklichkeit."93 This is not to suggest that there existed any ideological affinity between members of the Hochschule like Heuss and Carl Schmitt. The intention is rather to point out that during this 91Theodor Heuss, Erinnerungen, 1905-1933 (Tuebingen, 1963), p. 303. 92Theodor Heuss to Carl Schmitt, January 20, 1930, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 93Geheimes Staatsarchiv, Rep. 303, No. 168. 209' period Schmitt still received a good deal of respect from moderates and was not condemned and banished by these moderates as an underminer of the Republic. Weimar contemporaries and intellectuals of all political persuasions recognized Schmitt as the great theorist of Article 48 and the Ausnahmezustand, even though a considerable number disagreed violently with his posi— tion. As these subjects became the central issues at the end of the Weimar Republic Schmitt received the attention commensurate with his work on these problems. He did not create the crisis but merely analyzed its causes, proposed solutions, and worked with the government to resolve the problem. Not all of those with whom Schmitt had contact and even personal friendships were willing to accept his support for the presidential system. Even among those favoring the presidential system it meant different things to different individuals. Disregarding Schmitt's proposal for the defense of the existing order, the conservative revolutionaries employed what they found helpful or con— venient in his work and neglected his actual intentions. So far as Schmitt was concerned he still believed he was playing the role of the neutral intellectual who, though active in political affairs, stood above the narrow partisanship of parties and worked for the benefit of the entire nation. Despite his personal relationships to individuals of varYing political viewpoints and 210 allegiances, Schmitt's loyalty still remained with the neutral force represented by the Reichspresident and reinforced by the political activities of the Schleicher clique. This association with Schleicher would prove crucial and pave the way for Schmitt's important role as the Weimar Republic came to an end. CHAPTER VI CARL SCHMITT AND THE END OF WEIMAR, 1932 The convulsive year of 1932 marked the final demise of the ill-fated Weimar Republic. In that fateful year the republican forces failed to unite and take advan- tage of this last opportunity to resist the National Socialist acquisition of power and avoid the historical calamity that followed. Not since the political and eco— nomic upheavals of the early Republic had a single year contained such heightened political intensity and radicalization. The German people were saturated with con— stant political activity which, rather than alleviating their political and economic troubles, contributed to the further deterioration of the body politic. Electoral campaigns, public disorder, and governmental ineptitude dominated the scene. Three successive Chancellors would Prove ineffectual by the end of the year. While the waning Of the German republican experiment rapidly continued the Reich government instituted martial law in Prussia. This action culminated in one of the most famous political trials of Weimar, Prussia versus the Reich, and added to the complexity of the crisis. Germans focused their attention and applied their political energies towards 211 212 Hindenburg's reelection as president, and on two of the most intense Reichstag elections in German history, with a third in preparation. For more than a year political radicalization had reached the stage of street fighting and physical harassment of opponents, mostly between Nazis and Communists, as the threat of civil war loomed in the immediate background. Now in 1932 the Nazis and Communists, who normally faced each other in street confrontations, moved into the center of the political arena as the July elections provided them with a combined majority of seats in the Reichstag. Unwilling to compromise with their ideological opponent, or with any other party, these extremist parties made a governing coalition an impossi— bility. As the year opened the critical question facing the government was how to handle the increasing strength and p0pularity of the National Socialists. Although Hitler was determined to follow a course of legally acquiring power, many Nazi party members were still advocating revolution. Each approach presented a threat to those remaining loyal to the existing constitution, including Hindenburg, who took his constitutional oath qUite seriously. After Hitler had polled almost 37 per cent of the votes in the April 1932 presidential election, and the SA had swollen to four times the size of the German army, these threats appeared all the more ominous. 213 In this tense atmosphere Carl Schmitt wrote his highly celebrated Legalitaet goo Legitimitaet, to warn against the potential destruction of the Weimar constitu- tion through constitutional means.l Schmitt had hoped to avert this tragic eventuality by allowing the president and the cabinet to conduct the business of government unhampered by the stalemate in the Reichstag, and simul— taneously prevent the extremists of the left or the right from seizing power legally or by revolutionary methods. These two essential objectives stood in the forefront of his political beliefs since the early days of the Republic. The greatest threat to the existing constitutional order Schmitt identified as a "value—neutral" and "purely functional" interpretation of the constitution. As a case in point he selected the literal wording of Article 68 Of the Weimar constitution: "Reich laws are enacted by the Reichstag." That article best exemplified the purely functional type of legal thought Schmitt admonished, because it concerned only the legal procedure for passing laws and indicated a certain "neutrality" regarding the actual "substance" of those laws. But every constitution, he noted, embodies certain basic values and principles (e.g. these could include democracy, private property, lCarl Schmitt, Legalitaet und Legitimitaet (Berlin. 1932). _— 214 religious freedom, etc.), which are essential parts of a particular constitutional order. No constitution could remain "neutral" towards its own fundamental values and principles. A "purely functional" interpretation of the constitution, Schmitt argued, would involve a certain "value-neutrality" towards laws which were passed accord— ing to the specified constitutional procedures for enact— ing laws. This would be the case even when the "substance" of these laws might contradict the basic values or prin— ciples of the constitution, or even endanger the entire legal order itself. This "value—neutrality" would also allow any polit— ical party an "equal chance" in the legal acquisition of power. Under a parliamentary, legislative state system law is determined by the majority in the legislature, that is by 51 per cent of the delegates. Each group, party, or movement had the constitutional right of having the equal chance to form this majority and thereby hold the instru— ment of legality.2 Following a strict "value-neutral" interpretation it would be unconstitutional to limit a party's equal chance in the acquisition of power. This method of governing through the formation of simple majorities is sensible under normal conditions and when there exists a substantial homogeneity and consensus 2Ibid., pp. 30-32. 215 within the whole nation.3 As Schmitt had often indicated contemporary Germany lacked this necessary political con- sensus. And anti—constitutional parties had seized upon the tactic of the equal chance as a constitutional vehicle to institute party programs which might involve the destruction of the constitution. A strict value—free and formalistic interpretation would allow this to occur legally, because such formalistic legality consisted simply of a mathematical measurement of a 51 per cent majority. Whoever controlled this 51 per cent could legally relegate the remaining 49 per cent to illegality. The incumbent majority could in a legal manner close forever the door through which it came to power by denying its political opponents the equal chance, and through legal manipula— tions ban these opponents as traitors. "The majority then suddenly is no longer a party; it is the state itself."4 An incumbent party would be assisted in imple— menting these plans by what Schmitt termed the special "political premiums" (politischen Praemien) or advantages that accompany the legal possession of power. Many cru- cial laws, decrees, and administrative functions require interpretation or enforcement. It would be the 3Ibid., p. 31. 4 Ibid., pp. 32—33, 35. 216 prerogative of the party in power to decide on many of these consequential matters and, at the same time, that party would also have at its disposal the entire bureau- cratic state apparatus, which it could use to its own advantage. These "political premiums" would greatly enhance the power of the incumbent party and facilitate the realization of its party goals. It then becomes a question of which group had the legal power in its hands at the moment when finally the whole legal system is thrown aside. That group is then capable of constituting its power on new foundations.5 The ultimate consequence of a "value-neutral" and "purely functional" adherence to the constitution was totally unacceptable to Schmitt who, for years, had argued that a parliamentary legislative state cannot remain neutral towards itself and its own principles.6 Specifically, Schmitt had in mind the legal acqui~ sition of power by either the National Socialists or the Communists. Each in turn would attempt to capitalize on its control of legality and the accompanying "political premiums" to change the constitution legally under Article 76, and institute whatever form of government 217 they desired.7 In this respect it came down to the ques- tion of the limits of constitutional change. That there belonged certain fundamental principles to each constitu- tion which could not be changed through simple constitu— tional revision was a long standing precept in Schmitt's constitutional theory. This included the principle that a constitution could never offer the legal method by which its own legality would be destroyed.8 Besides this parliamentary legality principle there also existed in the Weimar constitution a second type of legality in the form of "plebiscitary legitimacy," which recognized the people as sovereign and as the ulti— mate source of all legitimacy. Article 1, "political authority is derived from the people," clearly acknowledged the legitimacy held by the people. That legitimacy could be appealed to directly through plebiscites under 7Schmitt unequivocally stated that, “regarding the many Gutachten and court decisions concerning the legality or illegality of the National Socialist organizations I would once more like to emphasize that for National Socialists, Communists . . . such questions must in no way be understood in terms of individual, isolated consti— tutional articles . . . but from this fundamental inter— pretation of the system of legality and especially Art. 76." Otherwise Schmitt warned, "all parties must be given the lawful and unconditional equal chance to form the majorities which are necessary . . . in order to bring about its aspired goal--Soviet Republic, National Socialist Reich . . . Monarchy of the old style, Aristoc— racy of some form——and another constitution." Ibid., PP- 50—51. 8 Ibid., p. 61. 218 Articles 73, 74, and 76, which govern referendums and initiatives.9 As the Weimar crisis worsened this "plebiscitary legitimacy" took on an added significance. Owing to excessive pluralism and the paralysis of the present Reichstag the legality and the power of the legis- lative system was in doubt. Each party, therefore, attempted to reinforce its power by appealing to the "plebiscitary legitimacy" of the people. Dissolving the Reichstag had become a normal affair and elections had become plebiscites in search of the legitimacy held by the people. In fact, or so Schmitt believed, this "plebis— citary legitimacy" was the only remaining form of generally recognized political legitimacy.lo The appeal to the "plebiscitary legitimacy" of the people required a government or some other authority, and one that the people could trust, to present the correct questions and alternatives to the electorate and one which would not misuse the tremendous power inherent in that position.11 To fulfill that crucial role Schmitt naturally selected the Reichspresident. As the defender of the legitimate constitutional order he also possessed the legal authorization under Article 48 of the constitution to 91bid., pp. 62-67. loibid., pp. 92-93. llIbid., p. 94. 1.7.71 # Tmifl—aflh—hflayr—r= e F i._ 1 1 219 prevent the legal abuse of power. The Reichspresident alone retained the trust of the German people and conse- quently the right to appeal directly to the "plebiscitary legitimacy" of the people to support his own constitutional legality. Beyond this general framework, however, Schmitt's book contained no precise program or specific proposals. Given the circumstances of late Weimar Schmitt merely saw the alternatives as a recognition of the plebiscitary legitimacy of the people in relationship to the office of the president, or the persistence of a legality system, with its value-neutral functionalism granting the equal chance to all parties. If this "neutral majority functionalism" prevailed it would mean the end of the Weimar constitution. “Dann raecht sich die Wahrheit" (Then reality will avenge itself). Schmitt's Legalitaet poo Legitimitaet and its cogent arguments had enormous relevancy for the events of 1932. Quite understandably the book was widely pub- licized and discussed in political circles from right to left. Each party in the famous trial Prussia versus the Reich utilized its arguments. Unfortunately, in the end the most important lesson of the book was ignored and the Nazis were granted the equal chance legally to acquire power . lzIbid., pp. 97—98. 220 Because of Schmitt's increasing involvement with the politics of the presidential system critics began in 1932 referring to him as the Kronjurist of the central government.13 It was also this connection between Schmitt and the activities of the presidential government during 1932 which has led historians to draw erroneous conclu— sions as to Schmitt's actual involvement in these affairs. One such recent interpretation has been published by Heinrich Muth, who holds that "in the summer of 1932 14 Muth Schmitt was a man of the Papen government." stated further that Schmitt closely identified himself with the plans of Papen, minister of the interior Gayl, and the programs of the DNVP, including proposals for immediate constitutional revision. That Schmitt worked with the central government is la commonly known fact. But one cannot for this reason iconsider Schmitt as the man of Papen, Gayl, and the German iNationalists. After his arrival in Berlin Schmitt had .become intimately associated with the political coterie 1around Schleicher, and it was Schleicher's position that fiSchmitt supported. Without making this basic distinction l . 13 . , Rudolf Morsey, "Die Deutsche Zentrumspartei," nDas Ende, op. cit., pp. 323-324. T, . . l4Muth, "Carl Schmitt In Der Deutschen Innen— politik Des Sommers 1932," Historische Zeitschrift, op. lClt-I pp. 107, 112. ‘__ 15 Ibid., pp. 113, 115—116, 121, 132-133, 136-138. 221 between his attitude toward Papen and Schleicher neither Schmitt's writings nor his activities can be properly understood. For the plans of Schleicher were by no means identical to those of Papen, Gayl, and the DNVP. One of the most significant points of antagonism between Schleicher and Papen concerned the latter's program for immediate con— stitutional revision. Though Schleicher himself had once embraced similar notions he totally disapproved of Papen's constitutional experiments during the period of sustained crisis following the 1930 elections. Such constitutional experiments were completely inconsistent also with Carl Schmitt's belief in the need for restoring order, peace, and stability before tampering with the existing order. As the Weimar Republic came to an end Schleicher and Papen represented two opposing factions. Nevertheless, after the presidential elections of April 1932 Schleicher had selected Papen to replace Bruening as chancellor. At that time Schleicher thought that he could control Papen and that the new chancellor could serve as the link to a right-centrist coalition which would support a presidential government and receive 16 the toleration of the National Socialists. It was Schleicher's expectation that new Reichstag elections 16Earl R. Beck, Prussian Republic, op. 212'! Pp. 73-74. Bracher, Die Aufloesung, op. oip., pp. 458, 579. Hajo Holborn, A History op Modern Germany, 1840- 1945 (New York, 1970), PP. 692—693. 222 would return a favorable rightist parliament drawing away some of the appeal of the Nazis, and that the new cabinet would stand above parties. In pursuit of this policy Schleicher convinced Hindenburg to dissolve the Reichstag on June 4, and schedule new elections for July 31. Backing Schleicher's plans for a move to the right, which he hoped would diminish the appeal of the Nazis, and in fearful anticipation of the further growth of that movement, Schmitt published an article in the conservative Deutsches Volkstum against granting the "equal chance" to anti—constitutional parties.l7 That article was essen- tially a concise version of his work on legality. With the elections approaching the editors of the conservative Taegliche Rundschau found Schmitt's arguments so appro— priate that they had him publish an excerpt in their own journal, to which they added the following conclusion: Our practical application: Whoever provides the National Socialists with the majority on July 31, acts foolishly, even though he is not a National Socialist and sees in this party only the lesser evil. He gives this still immature ideological and political movement the possibility to change the con- stitution, to establish a state church, to dissolve the labor unions, etc. He surrenders Germany com— pletely to this group. Therefore: if under the cir— cumstances it was until now good to encourage Hitler's resistance movement, it would be extremely dangerous l7Carl Schmitt, "Legalitaet und gleiche Chance politischer Machtgewinnung," Deutsches Volkstum, 2 Juliheft (1932), PP- 557-564. 223 so do so on July 31, because 51% gives the NSDAP 18 political premium of incalculable Significance. The thoughts and warning of Carl Schmitt and these small conservative circles never reached the masses of the voters. The July elections ended in a spectacular victory for the Nazis, as they received 37.8 per cent of the seats in the Reichstag. And along with the Communists‘ slight increase to 14.6 per cent, Schleicher's hopes for a non- Nazi rightist parliament came to nought as the Nationalists were reduced to a mere 8.5 per cent. Together the radical parties now controlled 52.4 per cent of Reichstag seats, in Schmittian terms the dangerous absolute majority. Fortunately these two parties were incapable of cooperating with each other to take advantage of this situation and they had to content themselves with simply preventing the formation of any governing coalition. Since the Nazis had more than doubled their vote compared to 1930 returns their potential seizure of power, legally or otherwise, became more distressing. Not only had Schleicher and Papen failed to receive the increased national support they sought, but by their pre-election actions in Prussia they had completely ali— enated the Center Party and the moderate left. For on July 20, Papen had, in the name of the Reich government, l8Carl Schmitt, "Der Missbrauch der Legalitaet," Taegliche Rundschau (July 19, 1932). 224 placed all of Prussia under martial law. That move, less than two weeks before this critical election, drew pro- tests of unconstitutionality from the Center and declara— tions from the Prussian SPD government that it had been the victim of a Staatsstreich. The immediate origins of the struggle between the Prussian and the Reich governments went back to the elec—r tions to the Prussian Landtag on April 24, 1932. The phrase "who controls Prussia controls the Reich" was an accurate political estimation accepted by the left as well as the right. Constituting two-thirds of the national territory, three-fifths of its population, and with its police force of 85,000 men closely approximating the German army, the Prussian state presented a tremendous counter weight to the centralized authority of the Reich. Reforms for changing the relationship between Prussia and the federal government had been debated throughout the Weimar Republic. Most reform proposals had dealt with the merger of the two governments. The continued functioning of the long standing Weimar coalition in the Landtag made Prussia the bulwark of republican democracy in Germany. With the April elections the Prussian Weimar coalition was shattered forever. The Nazis doubled their seats and the election returns reduced the coalition to a minority, leaving the Prussian parliament in the same state of 225 paralysis in which the Reichstag had been suspended since 1930.19 The Social Democratic government in Prussia, no longer supported by a majority in the Landtag, resigned and remained in office temporarily as a "care-taker" government. They were able to do so because of a change in the voting procedure governing the election of the minister president of the parliament. Previously, if no one received a majority in the Landtag, the one receiving the most votes in the second election was to hold that office. Recognizing the possibility of large Nazi gains in the Landtag election the SPD used their pre—election majority to change this procedure before the April elec— tion. Under the new regulations an absolute majority was necessary in order to select a minister president. Thus the SPD government would hold the reins of power until a new majority was formed. The legality of this governmental move was debatable, but the SPD argued that they pursued this course so as to prevent the Prussian government, its bureaucracy and police from falling into the hands of the Nazis. Throughout the Weimar era the republican govern- ment of Prussia had imposed harsh measures against the Nazis. 19Milatz, "Das Ende," op. cit., pp. 766—770. 226 The Prussian situation worsened after the Reich removed the ban on the Nazi SA in May of 1932. Political street battles resulted in 99 dead and 1,125 wounded seriously in the brief period following that repeal of the SA ban. A widespread fear emerged that these disorders might lead to civil war. Papen and his interior minister Gayl, seized upon this opportunity to destroy the power of the Social Democrats in Prussia. By doing so they hoped to prove the effectiveness of their newly formed govern- ment in fighting the Communists and at the same time assure that the powerful Prussian police would not fall into the hands of the Nazis. Pursuing this plan the Papen government on July 20, 1932 proclaimed a state of emer- gency in Prussia under Article 48, dismissed the Prussian SPD government and instituted a Reich commissar for Prussia.20 The affair initiated a most dramatic court— room confrontation before the German supreme court be— tween the incumbent Prussian government and the Reich over the constitutionality of Papen's actions. Carl Schmitt played a central role in these legal proceedings but not in the political intrigues leading up to the removal of the Prussian government. The first discussions regarding the proposed action occurred at a cabinet meeting on July 11. Papen subsequently submitted 20Beck, Prussian Republic, op. cit., pp. 97—101_ 227 21 his scheme to Hindenburg two days later. When the issue was brought to the supreme court, which first considered the Prussian appeals on the 23rd of July, the central government began to make its preparations for the case. In the cabinet meeting of July 25, Papen stated that, "it is already decided that counselor Meidinger as well as professors Carl Schmitt in Berlin, Jacobi in Leipzig and Bilfinger in Halle would be taken into consultation as representatives or Gutachtern for the Reich government."22 This was the first mention of Schmitt's involvement in the affair. Although Schmitt's ideas and publications con- cerning the equal chance, the Ausnahmezustand, and Article 48 took on additional importance in the legal 21Bracher contends that Carl Schmitt was somehow involved in overcoming Hindenburg's hesitations concerning the proposed action against Prussia. But the document cited as evidence contains only the fact that in prepara- tion for the case before the supreme court Schmitt later made himself familiar with the material Papen presented to the Reichspresident. Bracher's source, former General and Ambassador Eugen Ott, merely stated that, "in the subsequent process of the supreme court against the Reichs— government this was represented by professor Carl Schmitt, who for this purpose had to make himself thoroughly familiar with the material." Bracher 212 Aufloesung, ‘92: oip., p. 509. For the source of this argument see: "Auszug des Botschafters a. D. Eugen Ott an den Sohn des jReichskanzlers a. D. v. Papen vom 26.12.1949," Archiv, ,Institut fuer Zeitgeschichte, Munich, 253/52, pp. 00007— ‘00008. 22BA, R-43—I, No. 1457, Kabinettsprotokolle, Juli 1932‘Sept. 1932, "Niederschrift ueber die Ministerbes- ‘prechung am 25 Juli 1932 in der Reichskanzlei: 2) Streitsache zwischen dem Reich und der Preussischen Staatsregierung vor dem Staatsgerichtshof," pp. 186—187. 228 arguments before the supreme court, his ideas in no way served as the motivating force behind the actions of the Papen government. And rather than being a puppet of Papen and Gayl, Schmitt acted merely as the legal adviser on behalf of the Reich government as he had already done with Bruening. The position Schmitt defended at Leipzig he had well developed before anyone considered Papen for the chancellorship. That Schmitt held these views concerning the power of the Reichspresident under Article 48 was very important in the government's selection of him for this case, as obviously was his public and private support for the presidential system since its inception. The decisive factor in the selection of Schmitt was his close associ- ation with the Schleicher clique. Schleicher had insisted that Schmitt actually represent the government in 23 After his selection Carl Schmitt only met with 1Leipzig. iPapen a few times and then only regarding the trial. l At that same July 25 cabinet session Papen reported that "professor Schmitt will publish an article gon July 29, in the Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung concerning ithe constitutional dispute between the Reich and the Prussian state government and support the Reich govern— ment in this article." Gayl added that "together with professor Schmitt he would like to establish the 23Schmitt Interview, July 13, 1973. 229 24 framework of the case." That article appeared on August 1, two months before the scheduled opening of the trial. Nothing in that article suggested that Schmitt sup— ported the Papen-Gayl plans for constitutional reform. The article addressed specifically the case at hand and its arguments were no simple fabrications contrived to support the government's case. This article had been requested of Schmitt by the editorial staff of the Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung.25 There was nothing in the article to indicate the manipulative influence of anyone on the Kronjurist. Schmitt, in effect, reiterated the arguments he had constructed for years relative to the power of the Reichspresident and his position as a neutral 24Muth takes this latter statement to be an indie cation of the working relationship between Gayl and Schmitt, and also as evidence that Schmitt supported the plans of Gayl and the DNVP. There exists, however, abso— lutely nothing in the Gayl Nachlass to indicate this and as will be shown below, Schmitt never supported Gayl's plans for constitutional revision at this time. BA, R- 43- -I, No. 1457, p. 187. BA, Nachlass Wilhelm Freiherr von Gayl, Reichsminister des Inneren. Muth, "Carl ‘Schmitt,“ op. cit., pp. 112-113. 25"Concerning this currently most important and ,topical question we are publishing the following opinion which we requested of one of our foremost constitution~ alists and one of the renowned experts. The Editorial ”Staff." Carl Schmitt, "Die Verfassungsmaessigkeit der Bestellung eines Reichskommissars fuer das Land Preussen," .Deutsche Juristen- Zeitung, Jhg. 37, Heft 15 (August 1, {1932), p. 953. A shortened version of this article had 1already appeared in the Deutsche Allgemeine Zeitung, No. 349, on July 29, under the title, "Ist der Reichskommissar verfassungsmaessig?" A copy of the latter is in the Rihse Sammlung, 5153, Kriegsarchiv, Abt. IV, Munich. 230 force. The Reich government received Schmitt's total support because he believed in the correctness of its position. He had consistently, in public speeches and writings, backed the actions of the Reichspresident ever since his arrival in Berlin. The current situation in Prussia, Schmitt argued, brought both paragraph one and two of Article 48 into operation. Under paragraph one the Reichspresident could, through armed power if necessary, force a state to fulfill its constitutional and legal obligations. In this case he could force the care-taker Social Democratic government from office. Paragraph two authorized the president to utilize any measures necessary to reestablish public order and security. Thus, the introduction of a Reichscommissar for Prussia. The real question Schmitt viewed as more political than constitutional in nature. "There is no doubt," he wrote, "that the essential point of controversy in the case concerns the political evaluation of two parties, the National Socialists and the Communist That in the past Article 48 had been instituted against both parties was a known fact, but it was always executed by a Reichspresident who, standing above parties, acted as a neutral force. Currently the danger was that this type of executive action might become the instrument 26Schmitt, "Die Verfassungsmaessigkeit," op. cit., p. 958. 231 of the contesting political parties, each of whom would use any legal means available to outlaw its opponents. The theory of the "equal chance" would then become a tool of the incumbent party. Here Schmitt was alluding to the actions of the care—taker SPD government and its repres— sive measures against the Nazis. Schmitt in no way favored the Nazis in this case and he restated that "on the other hand it would, of course, be totally impossible to give the equal chance to a party which is an enemy of the state."27 But to prevent civil war a policy excluding any one political party from the equal chance must be directed by the Reichspresident who stood above the con- tending parties in question. What Schmitt did was to interpret conflicts between the Reich and a state as a struggle between the Reich government and parties. That a state government might become the naked power instrument of the incumbent party which would then deny the "equal chance" to its competitors, was not just inserted at this time to justify Papen's actions against the Social Democrats in Prussia. It had been a long-standing prin— ciple of Schmitt's and already in 1931 he noted that "in many law suits between the Reich and a state which are brought before the supreme court it is obvious that not 27Ibid. 232 the Reich and a State, but two competing party coalitions are the real parties in the proceedings."28 Viewing the Papen decrees from a quite different perspective the Prussian SPD government, and those sym— pathetic to its cause, dismissed Schmitt's arguments as mere rationalizations. The SPD ministers and their sup- porters were convinced that Papen had violated the con— stitution with the expressed intention of acquiring abso- lute control over Prussia. Papen's ultimate objectives, as they saw it, were twofold. He wanted to solve the question of Prussian—Reich dualism by force and, in the process, destroy the power of the SPD in Prussia. Both moves would supposedly demonstrate the strength and via- bility of the Papen government and thereby bolster the chancellor's public image and political power. The SPD also suspected that Papen's actions were a concession to the National Socialists in return for Nazi toleration of the policies of the central government. Since the Prussian SPD government had always been the greatest adversary of the NSDAP, removal of the SPD cabinet would certainly be advantageous to the Nazi Party. Throughout the contro— versy that followed the action of July 20, the Prussian government saw the main issue as the defense of its 28Carl Schmitt, "Reichs— und Verwaltungsreform," Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, Jhg. 36, Heft 1 (January 1, 1931), p. 7. 233 constitutional rights, and those of the state of Prussia, against the unconstitutional and authoritarian methods of Papen. The supreme court proceedings finally began on October 10, and in the meantime the parties to the case against the Reich expanded to include Baden and Bavaria, as well as the Catholic Center Party and the SPD factions of the Prussian Landtag. Germany's supreme court, the Staatsgerichtshof which met in Leipzig, was not a permanent judicial body but one assembled to hear such cases. The political ramifications of the trial along with the pres— tige of the trial lawyers attracted a great deal of pub— licity. Several of Weimar's greatest jurists confronted each other in a proceeding that would significantly influ— ence the future of the Republic. Pleading the case for the Reich were Carl Schmitt, Erwin Jacobi, and Karl Bil— finger, opposing Friedrich Giese, Arnold Brecht, Gerhard Anschuetz, Hans Nawiasky, Hans Peters, and Hermann Heller. From a personal standpoint the trial represented a pro~ fessional triumph for Carl Schmitt. He now participated in a public political trial of immeasurable consequences with the attention of the whole nation focused on the outcome of these proceedings. The highest court in Germany now debated the theories he had advocated through- out his career. His works on dictatorship, Article 48, and on the defender of the constitution were requested as 234 29 No doubt Schmitt found reference works by the court. this increased publicity exceptionally gratifying; it reassured him of the importance of his work. Carl Schmitt had reached a peak in his career while still in his early forties. Schmitt's adversaries across the courtroom were equally knowledgeable of the legal intracacies and polit— ical ramifications of the case. Arnold Brecht, then the Ministerial Director in the Prussian Ministry of Finance, for example, was a specialist in the matter of Reich- state relations and the problems of federalism. From his experiences as Prussia's representative to the Reichsrat, where he served on the committee to study Reich reform, Brecht had become intimately acquainted with all aspects of the historic case now before the court. As an author of several works on constitutional law and administration he had also established himself as a prominent legal scholar. In the first opening statement against the Reich Arnold Brecht introduced Carl Schmitt's theory of the "equal chance." Brecht cited several passages from Legalitaet und Legitimitaet to justify the actions of 29"Handakten Dr. D. Arian, Ministerialrat Verfassungsstreitsache der Lander Preussen, Baden und Bayern gegen das Deutsche Reich betr. Verordnung des Reichspraesidenten vom 20.7.1932 vor dem Staatsgerichtshof," BA, Kleine Erwerbung, No. 337-1, 1932, p. 473. 235 30 To such use of Prussia against the National Socialists. his own arguments Schmitt responded with the decisionist phrase, which one finds in his earliest works, "Wer entscheidet?"3l Schmitt reiterated the essential element of his theory that Brecht had neglected. One political party cannot determine the legality or illegality of another. Only an independent government could so decide, in this case that meant the Reich government. The results of such action on the part of the SPD against the Nazis, Schmitt sincerely feared, could lead to civil war. With visions of the upheavals and conflicts of the early Republic impressed in his memory the Kronjurist wanted to avoid a new rash of civil conflicts. Acutely aware of this potential danger, Schmitt knew that the army could not cope with a two front confrontation with the Communists and the Nazis. That was a common nightmare among all members of the Schleicher coterie. Like all the Schleicher cohorts Schmitt believed that the handling of the Nazis, especially after their growing electoral victories showed their popularity with more than a third of the nation, should be left to the Reich government which would proceed cautiously. 0Preussen contra Reich vor dem Staatsgerichtshof. Stenogrammbericht der Verhandlungen vor dem Staatsgerichts— hof in Leipzig vom 10. bis 14. und vom 17. Oktober 1932. (Berlin, 1933), p. 12. 31 Ibid., p. 39. 236 As this complicated trial proceeded the inter— related questions of the nature of the Reich, the presi— dent's emergency powers, and of the constitutionality of Papen‘s actions all came to the forefront. According to Schmitt the Reichspresident merely executed his consti- tutional obligations under Article 48, which authorized him to assure that a state fulfilled its obligations (paragraph one) and to reestablish order and security (paragraph two). The court should consider both para— graphs as one unified authority. By not maintaining order and security and by refusing to follow the policies of the Reich, Prussia had failed to fulfill her obligations to the constitution and the Reich. Consequently, the Reichspresident had the authority to invoke paragraph two as a means to reestablish security, and concurrently invoke paragraph one to force Prussia to fulfill its obli- 32 The jurists for Prussia refused to accept gations. Schmitt's interpretations granting such extensive powers to the president. Anschuetz and Giese, for example, argued that the president's actions could be subject to judicial review and also that Hindenburg did not possess the power to infringe upon the sovereignty of a state or to institute a commissar for a state.33 32Beck, Prussian Republic, op. cit., pp. 136-138. 33Ibid., p. 139. 237 Each of the antagonists in the proceedings launched detailed charges and counter charges relative to the vari- ous aspects of the case and each in turn supported and refuted these with the normal series of evidence and legal arguments. But the proceedings of the entire trial left little doubt about the political nature of the case, as politics kept bursting through the cover of constitutional issues. The realistic Carl Schmitt had few illusions about what he considered the most significant aspect of the trial. He informed his colleagues that "the formal— ities . . . in this process before the supreme court are "34 The no formalities, but very real political matters. supreme court could, he conceded, serve as the legal defender of the constitution in a judicial and formal man— ner. As a political document, however, the constitution also required political decisions and for this reason the Reichspresident was designated under Article 48 as the lawful political defender of the constitution.35 Outwardly the judges did not agree with the polit— icalization of the process that Schmitt seemed to be sug- gesting. Nonetheless, the court finally rendered a highly political decision on the case. Its decisions are often referred to as "Solomon Decisions" because it split in 34Preussen contra Reich, op. cit., p. 466. 35Ibid., p. 469. 238 favor of both parties. As a result the outcome satisfied neither party entirely and the Prussian situation remained in a very dubious state. The court reaffirmed its own right of judicial review of presidential actions, and it rejected the allegations that Prussia had failed to fulfill its obligations under paragraph one of Article 48. There- fore, the Reich had no authority to dismiss the Prussian cabinet and minister president. But the court ruled in favor of the Reich's actions in establishing a commissar for Prussia under paragraph two since there did exist a serious danger to public order and security. This final ruling proved decisive. While the Prussian cabinet returned to office, its authority was in fact only a facade. The real power in Prussia still resided in the 36 The court had reaf- hands of Papen and his commissar. firmed its own role as the legal interpreter of the con- stitution. Yet, in effect, real political power still resided with the Reichspresident as Schmitt had claimed. In the months following the action of July 20 the German political situation had intensified considerably. The election of July 31 had shattered Schleicher's plan for gaining extensive support for the presidential govern- ment, and Papen had distinguished himself as the most unpopular chancellor in German history. After the July 36Beck, Prussian Republic, op. cit., pp. 143-145. Bracher, Die Aufloesung, op. cit., pp. 559—563. 239 setback the alternatives open to the government were dis— cussed in the cabinet session of August 10. At that meet— ing Papen outlined the major tasks of the cabinet as a settling of the issue of Reich-Prussia, reform of voting rights, the establishment of an Upper House of parliament, and administrative reform in the Reich and Prussia.37 Schleicher countered this by stating that the real issues concerned either retaining the present cabinet or in dealing with the National Socialists and possibly bring— ing them into the cabinet. If they followed the first alternative Schleicher saw a possible danger in that a coalition might be formed between the National Socialists and the Center Party causing a constitutional crisis. At that time the leadership of the NSDAP and the Center par— ties were actively engaged in discussions about organizing a coalition government; this fact intensified Schleicher's concern. Dealing with the Nazis was equally difficult because Hitler would demand a position of leadership. For this reason Schleicher doubted that the cabinet could reach any agreement with the Nazis. Gayl agreed with Papen and rejected any notion of even attempting to negotiate with the Nazis. He had other goals in mind. So with the 37BA, R-43—I, No. 1309. Kabinettsbildung (1932), "Auszug aus der Niederschrift ueber die Ministerbesprechung vom 10. August 1932," pp. 181—185. 240 chancellor he proposed suspending the Reichstag without new elections and initiating constitutional reform. The plans of Gayl and Papen for immediate consti- tutional revision disturbed Schleicher. He totally dis— approved of Papen's constitutional experiments during this period of instability. Schleicher agreed with Schmitt that these reform proposals contained the danger of civil war, and he came more and more to disassociate 38 Similar reform plans had himself from Papen's policies. been widely promoted by the conservative revolutionary circles around the Herrenklub and the DNVP. These plans envisioned a "New State" of an authoritarian nature, with the Upper House as a check on the Reichstag, and with a highly restricted system of voting rights. To accomplish this these groups suggested dissolving the current Reichstag and revising the constitution in order to create this "New State" as a replacement for the defunct Weimar system. Although a frequent guest of the Herrenklub, Schleicher never took these plans seriously and he con— tinued to disagree with the Papen-Gayl constitutional schemes.39 38Thilo Vogelsand, "Zur Politik Schleichers Gegenueber Der NSDAP 1932," Vierteljahreshefte Fuer Zeitgeschichte, Jhg. 6, Heft 1 (January, 1958), p. 104. 39Nachlass Schleicher, Militaerarchiv, Freiburg, No. 42, Bd. 7, "Beziehungen zum 'Deutschen Herrenklub," Bracher, Die Aufloesung, op. oip., pp. 471—472. Holborn, Modern Gefmgnx, op. opp., pp. 699, 702. 241 Carl Schmitt had always warned against constitu— tional experiments during a time of crisis. Such schemes were completely inconsistent with Schmitt's belief in the necessity for restoring order and stability before tamper- ing with the existing order. He recognized the need for reform, but he saw the first priority as a settlement of the current crisis. Schmitt feared that reform plans might become the tools of one or more of Weimar's plural— istic parties and interest groups.40 More importantly, he also approached these eventual necessary reforms as a method of correcting the existing system and not as a means of establishing a new state. The exceptional powers of the president, he wrote, ". . . were meant more as cor— rections to certain abuses of the parliamentary system, and therefore were meant to save this system, but were not intended to establish some new kind of state . . . ."41 Whether Schleicher ever read Schmitt's recent book remains unknown. But undoubtedly he was at least acquainted with Schmitt's general line of argument. Schleicher's clOSest aide, Colonel Erich Marcks, had been meeting with Schmitt socially and on political matters for several years. Since August Marcks had attempted to popularize Schmitt's Legalitaet und Legitimitaet, for Schleicher's 40Carl Schmitt, Legalitaet und Legitimitaet, p. 97. 4lIbid., p. 89. as”... _W: 242 political cause. Expressing his sincere thanks to Schmitt for this book, Marcks stated that "in its strict scientific constructions, its deduction and in the rich— ness of its content, it is for us an excellent arsenal in the fight for the future. I know that in popularizing it for political purposes one cannot do justice to your thought, but I hope that this political utilization will not be looked upon by you unsympathetically. Everyone who actually reads your book will realize, in spite of our attempts, that it is geared to a different level which is not a reflection of a momentary political situation."42 Schmitt's writings were receiving a good deal of publicity throughout 1932, both negative and positive. As expected his ideas were far more palatable to the right of the political spectrum than to the left. The conserva— tive revolutionaries used his ideas, especially concerning the friend—enemy relationship and the bankruptcy of the pluralistic party system, in defense of their own cause while never adopting Schmitt's theories completely.43 The 42Erich Marcks to Carl Schmitt, September 6, 1932, Carl Schmitt—Personal Papers. 43Throughout 1932 Schmitt's ideas appeared con— stantly in Deutsches Volkstum, and pop Ring. See: Friedrich Grueter, "Der Rechtsstaat in der Krise," Deutsches Volkstum, 1 Aprilheft (1932), pp. 260~265. Clemens Lang, "Die Ideologie des Widerstandes. Bemerkungen zu Carl Schmitts Begriff des Politischen," Deutsches Volkstum, l Dezemberheft (1932), pp. 959—964. Heinrich Rogge, "Feindschaft als Lebenselement von Staat und Politik? Eine Staatstheoret— ische Warnung," pop Ring, Jhg. 5, Heft 2 (January 8, 1932), 243 left criticized Schmitt on theoretical grounds and most harshly for his support of what they called the Papen 44 dictatorship. But even in their worst criticisms and attacks on Schmitt some members of the left did not hesi— tate occasionally to put a Schmittian concept in Marxist terms. Reinhold Aris stated, for example, "what Schmitt calls pluralism is nothing other than class struggle."45 Both sides referred to Schmitt as the Kronjurist of the central government. Nonetheless, as we have already noted his ideas were not the driving force behind events or the policies of the Papen government. Schmitt simply provided the vocabulary and jargon utilized in the arguments of various political factions. The Papen clique would request Schmitt's advice on specific constitutiOnal ques— tions, without concerning themselves with Schmitt's overall analysis and estimation of the political situation. pp. 16-18. Michael Horst, "Naturrecht, Legalitaet und das Zentrum," pop Ring, Jhg. 5, Heft 33 (August 12, 1932), pp. 548—550. Karl Lohmann, "Die Waffe der Legalitaet," 22E Ring, Jhg. 5, Heft 37 (September 9, 1932), pp. 608— 611. See also: Hans Zehrer, "Revolution oder Restaura— tion?" poo goo, Jhg. 24, Heft 5 (August 5, 1932), pp. 353—393. 4Thomas Eck, "Das Volk als Hueter der Verfassung," Neue Blaetter fuer Sozialismus, Jhg. 3, Heft 7 (July, 1932), pp. 347-355. Kurt Hiller, "Ewiger Friede in Gaensefuesschen," Die Weltbuehne, Jhg. 28, No. 40 (October 4, 1932), pp. 498-500. 45Reinhold Aris, "Krisis der Verfassung. Die gegenwaertige Situation," Neue Blaetter fuer Sozialismus, Jhg. 3, Heft 1 (January, 1932), p. 27. 244 Only with Schleicher and his aides Marcks and Ott, could Schmitt's political viewpoints have had any direct influ— ence. The extent of this influence is difficult to estab- lish, but there did exist a direct parallel between the ideas of Schmitt and the policies pursued by Schleicher. A possible Nazi-Center coalition, which Schleicher had foreseen and brought out in the August 10 cabinet meeting, still posed a potential threat when the Reichstag reconvened. Nazis and Centrists alike were hoping to pre— vent another dissolution order by allowing a coalition government to function with the confidence of the Reichstag. But Hindenburg by this time refused to accept any government dependent solely on the Reichstag and he decided to retain the presidential system. Under these circumstances Papen planned immediately to dissolve the new Reichstag when it failed to support his policies and then institute his programs for constitutional revision.46 The Nazis perceived Papen's intentions to dissolve the Reichstag as an effort to deny them the fruits of their electoral victory and force upon them the burden of another expensive and exhaustive campaign. At the center of these conflicting plans was the issue of whether a cabinet could stay in power after receiving a vote of no confidence. Party member Dr. Erich Zwade had informed the 46Beck, Prussian Republic, op. cit., p. 125. W‘jfiw’ . 1 245 Nazi leadership that "the Reich—government, as is well known, had requested a Gutachten from the constitutional— ist Prof. Carl Schmitt concerning whether it must resign in the event that it receives a vote of no confidence from the Reichstag. As far as I know," Zwade stated, "Schmitt has declared the continuation in office, despite a vote of no confidence, as compatible with the constitu— tion."47 The Nazis were thus preparing to foil Papen's plan to dissolve the Reichstag. They joined the Com- munists in returning a vote of no confidence immediately at the opening of the first session on September 12, before Papen could present the dissolution order he had brought with him already signed by Hindenburg. Consider— ing the government as already overthrown the Nazis refused to accept the order of dissolution. Shortly thereafter the Nazis finally reconciled themselves to the fact that the Reichstag had been dissolved. With the expected failure to achieve the support of the Reichstag Papen moved closer to attaining his goal of leaving the Reichstag dissolved for an indefinite period and introducing his constitutional revisions. To post- pone the elections for more than the sixty days prescribed in Article 25 would clearly violate the constitution. 47Dr. Erich Zwade to Rosenberg, August 26, 1932, Rosenberg—Akten, Institut Fuer Zeitgeschichte, Munich, II, 76, MA-251 (22-23). 246 Still, the general consensus of the cabinet was that sixty days would hardly be long enough for the government's programs to have sufficient impact in the economic and political spheres, so that the people would return a majority in its favor in the next election. On the ques— tion of new elections Schleicher agreed that it would be senseless to schedule new elections which would only lead to another deadlock and still provide no majority support for the government's programs. He believed that new elec- tions could be postponed on the grounds that the welfare of the nation, the people, and the economy precluded an election which would not change the existing state of 48 Schleicher's advisor Ott had political paralysis. spoken with Carl Schmitt, Jacobi, and Bilfinger on September 13, the day after the Reichstag was dissolved, and they agreed that postponement of the elections could be constitutionally justified.49 This did not contradict Schmitt's public pronouncements concerning the defense of the constitution. He had always maintained that the Reichspresident could, as the defender of the constitution, temporarily suspend various articles of the constitution on the grounds of Article 48 provided it was only 48BA, R—43—I, No. 1865, Reichsverfassung (1927— 1930), "Auszug aus der Niederschrift ueber die Minister- besprechung vom 14. September," (1932), pp. 255—257. 49Ibid. 247 temporary and done in order to preserve the constitution as a whole. Until this point in his career Carl Schmitt had exempted Article 25 from suspension under Article 48, because the Reichstag was part of the organizational minimum immune from presidential infringements. Suddenly Schmitt was willing to allow the postponement of elections which, according to his own constitutional theory, was not authorized under Article 48. He had always held as a basic political belief, however, that no strict formalistic interpretation of the constitution and no individual con- stitutional article should be allowed to endanger the con— tinued existence of the entire constitutional order. And although Article 48 did not authorize the suspension or postponement of elections during a state of exception (Ausnahmezustand), Schmitt did leave open the possibility for handling such a contingency in a state of emergency (Staatsnotstand, i.e., an extreme danger to the existence of the state itself). Staatsnotstand could pertain to Article 25, "if an extreme case should occur in which elections are completely impossible or the Reichstag could no longer be assembled, because the greater part of German territory was occupied by enemies or for similar extreme "50 reasons . . . . Apparently Schmitt considered the current political condition of Germany as an “extreme 50Carl Schmitt, Die Diktatur, pp. 246—247. See also: Carl Schmitt, Politische Theologie, p. 18. 248 reason" warranting temporary postponement of the elections. Schmitt's modified position in this matter did not include any plans for constitutional reform during the interim in which the Reichstag did not meet. Schleicher was also wary of constitutional revi— sions. In the October 20 cabinet meeting Schleicher revealed his own plan. After conferring with various party leaders Schleicher would then convince the Reichs- president that no possibility existed for a working majority in the Reichstag, and urge Hindenburg to prevent the Reichstag from meeting until a viable majority could be achieved. Schleicher also "requested that the question of reforming the constitution in the current exceptionally tense situation be set aside."51 The Schleicher plan, of course, interfered with the intended schemes of the other cabinet members, like Papen and Gayl, who wished to seize the opportunity to declare a state of emergency, intro— duce a dictatorship for an unspecified time, and accord- ingly make the needed constitutional revisions.52 Owing to his association with the central govern— ment, and particularly the publicity surrounding his service in the case Prussia versus the Reich, Schmitt aroused distrust in numerous political circles. Certain 51BA, R-43—I, No. 1309, Kabinettsbildun (1932), pp. 331-333. _______g 52 Ibid. 249 politicians failed to believe Schmitt's public statements against immediate constitutional reform. In a letter to Papen the director of the Bavarian ministry of finance, Schaeffer, confirmed the existence of such suspicion. He wrote, “yesterday I was informed that Professor Dr. Karl Schmitt is commissioned to draft a new constitution. Professor Karl Schmitt as a result of his publication has become a controversial personality. It would be partic— ularly doubtful, however, if he in his manner of thinking shows sympathy for sound federalist ideas. I would there— fore like to inquire if this rumour is correct and if he particularly was commissioned as the sole constitutionalist “53 engaged with the draft of a new constitution. 54 Papen could honestly deny this rumour. For Carl Schmitt was never involved in or commissioned for such a task, though he probably would have been elated over the pos— sibility of being the father of a new constitution once normality returned. That the much debated elections took place on November 6, as required by the constitution, most likely was due to Hindenburg's desire not to violate his 53Staatsrat Schaeffer, Director of the Bavarian Finance Ministry, to Chancellor von Papen, September 24, 1932, BA, R—43—I, No. 1865, Reichsverfassung (1927—1933), PP. 289-290. 54State secretary Planck to Staatsrat Schaeffer, October 4, 1932, Ibid., pp. 291-293. 250 constitutional oath. Hindenburg approached the constitu- tion in the strict formalistic manner which Schmitt had opposed. The letter of the constitution had been fulfilled but the election had not in the least alleviated the paral- ysis of the Weimar party system. Though suffering losses in the election the Nazis were still the largest party in the Reichstag. Their remaining seats combined with the increased number of Communist seats continued to provide the extremist parties with the absolute majority. When the cabinet convened at various times in the post election period to consider the alternatives open to the government, Papen and Gayl persisted in their plans for reform. Schleicher still preferred a more cautious policy. He feared that instituting constitutional reform at that time through emergency decrees could lead to civil war and that the army was inadequate to cope with such a situation. One of the strongest defenses of Schleicher‘s approach came from Johannes Popitz, who was Schmitt's closest friend in Berlin. Popitz had recently been appointed Reich minister-without-portfolio and served as an official in the Papen commissarial government in 55 It is interesting to note the triangular Prussia. relationship between Popitz, Schmitt and Schleicher. All three figures were personal and working acquaintances who Opposed immediate constitutional revision. 55Beck, Prussian Republic, op. cit., pp. 155, 165. 251 With the impending issue of constitutional revision and governmental alternatives in mind Schmitt appeared before a conference of Westphalian industrialists on November 23. This industrial association had originally attempted to engage both interior minister Gayl and the Reich commissar for Prussia Franz Bracht, to speak on the question of constitutional reform. When the contro— versial nature of the problem prompted Gayl and Bracht to refuse that invitation, the association called upon 56 Under these Carl Schmitt to deliver the main lecture. circumstances Schmitt surely surprised his audience as he proceeded to speak against immediate constitutional reform. Schmitt placed the blame for the incessant crisis directly upon political parties and the Reichstag. The Weimar party state Schmitt defined as a "Quantitative Total State," because it interfered in every aspect of life as it was pressured to do so by one interest group or another. Submission to this pressure proved that Weimar was a weak state rather than a strong one.57 A few 56Dr. M. Schlenker to Dr. Paul Silverberg, November 15, 1932, BA, Nachlass Dr. Paul Silverberg, No. 417, Bd. 5 (1932—1933), "VerEIn zur Wahrung der gemeinsamen wirtschaftlichen Interessen in Rheinland und Westfalen, Duesseldorf (Langnamverein), Allgemeine Schriftwechsel und Einladungen." 57Carl Schmitt, "Gesunde Wirtschaft im starken Staat," Mitteilungen des Vereins zur Wahrung der gemein— samen wirtschaftlichen Interessen in Rheinland und 252 powerful political organizations had a monopoly of control over the masses, each organization represented a special interest and none represented the entire nation. "Five organized inimical systems, each of which in and of itself is total, stand next to each other and between which the people are supposed to decide five times in one year."58 Without the Reichspresident and his cabinet the country would have already lapsed into complete chaos. The solu— tion to the crisis should therefore come from the Reich government and not from the parties. "We need first of all," Schmitt said, "a strong viable state equal to its great problems. When we have that then we can create new organizations, new institutions, new constitutions. In my opinion, it is high time and we no longer have many pos- sibilities, also no longer much latitude for great con- stitutional experiments . . . . I believe, therefore, that it is better first of all not to establish authority through new institutions . . . . (Instead) the government should utilize all constitutional means, but all consti- tutional means, which stand at its disposal . . . ."59 Only when the government restored order and stability should plans for constitutional revision be pursued, Westfalen," Jhg. 1932, No. 1, Heft 21 (November 23, 1932), PP. 16—18, Nachlass Silverberg. 58Ibid., pp. 19—20. 59Ibid., pp- 30-31. 253 otherwise the crisis would only be aggravated. Meanwhile, Germany would have a strong economy only within the con— fines of a strong state. A great force in opposition to violating or sus— pending articles of the constitution was the Catholic Center Party. Schmitt had closely associated himself with the Centrist position throughout most of the twenties, but gradually became alienated from it and its formalistic literal interpretation of the constitution. The Center viewed itself as a strict constitutional party. Support— ing a strong central government the Center at the same time refused to violate the letter of the constitution.60 In the fall of 1932 the Center Party wanted a return to parliamentary government in conjunction with the presi— dential system. The leadership of the party, including Bruening and Prelate Kaas, believed this could only be accomplished by a coalition with the National Socialists, with whom they had negotiated for months.61 At a meeting of November 18, Kaas informed Hindenburg of the Center Party designs. Their goal was to achieve a “national concentration" of parties in support of an "authoritarian 6ODetlef Junker, Die Deutsche Zentrumspartei und Hitler 1932/33: Ein Beitrag zur Problematik des politischen Katholizismus 12 Deutschland (Stuttgart, 1969), pp. 88, 232. 61Becker, "Bruening, Praelat Kaas," op. cit., p. 111. 254 government" without violating the constitution. So long as no one violated the constitution the Center was pre- pared to back any of the President's policies. Using Schmitt's terminology Kaas told the Reichspresident that the Center Party ". . . sees in you the most conscientious Hueter opp Verfassung."62 Basically the Reichspresident and the Center agreed that the constitution must not be violated. Both viewed the constitution, to Carl Schmitt's dismay, in terms of a functional, value-neutral legality, according to which every article of the constitution was sacrosanct, each group had the equal chance to achieve power, and a legal government must have the support of 51 per cent of the Reichstag. But the needed legal major- ity could only be formed with the participation of the Nazis, and Hitler insisted on the chancellorship. Harbor- ing a disdain for the Nazis and a sincere desire not to violate the constitution, Hindenburg rejected both the Centrist plan and the Papen scheme for constitutional reform. Instead, Hindenburg opted for Schleicher‘s proposal of gaining the support or at least the toleration of the labor unions, the SPD, and the bourgeois parties. Schleicher also hoped to split the NSDAP in order to 62"Aufzeichnung ueber die Besprechung des Herrn Reichspraesidenten mit dem Fuehrer der Zentrumspartei, Praelat Kaas, am 18. November 1932, nachmittags 6 Uhr," Nachlass Schleicher, No. 31, p. 2. 255 acquire the cooperation of the Strasser faction.63 On December 3, Hindenburg appointed Schleicher as chancellor to succeed Papen. It appeared that Carl Schmitt, as an adviser to Schleicher, might play an even more significant role in ending the political crisis. Along with programs for economic recovery Schleicher followed a policy of conciliation. When the new Reichstag, for example, voted to revoke certain emergency decrees Schleicher complied by suspending more than those requested. But the new chancellor's hopes and plans were never to materialize. He could neither split the NSDAP nor gain the toleration of the left. By January 1933 Papen had commenced plotting with Hitler against Schleicher. With the threat of a Papen- Hitler cabinet and the failure of his own plans, Schleicher concluded by January 23, that the situation demanded declaring a state of emergency. He requested that Hindenburg initiate another dissolution of the Reichstag, postpone elections, and under Article 48 issue a ban on the Communist and the Nazi parties. Had Hindenburg com— plied with this request he would have fulfilled Carl Schmitt's notion of the defender of the constitution and denied the "equal chance" to unconstitutional parties. Schleicher was the only leader in a position to prevent 63Bracher, Die Aufloesung, op. cit., p. 589. 256 the Nazi acquisition of power, if the Reichspresident had only granted him this authorization.64 Having lost faith in Schleicher, fearing civil war, and trying to avoid violating his oath to uphold the constitution, Hindenburg refused. Consequently, Hitler acquired power not through the use of Article 48, but because it was not utilized against him.65 Also fearing a violation of the letter of the constitution, Prelate Kaas wrote to Schleicher on January 26, warning him against ". . . the entire basic tendencies of Carl Schmitt and his followers to relativize consti— tutional law . . . ."66 The postponement of new elections, he pointed out, would be a direct violation of the consti— tution. An illegal and unconstitutional state of emer- gency was not the solution. The proper course lay rather with a return to constitutionally sanctioned governing coalitions. The fact that such a return to parliamentary government might bring the Nazis to power remained hidden behind the Center's strict formalistic approach to the 64Theodor Eschenburg, "Die Rolle Der Persoenlich- keit in der Krise der Weimarer Republik: Hindenburg, Bruening, Groener, Schleicher," Vierteljahreshefte Fuer Zeitgeschichte, Jhg. 9, Heft 1 (January, 1961), p. 27. 65Junker, Deutsche Zentrumspartei, op. cit., PP. 70-71. _*‘ 66 Prelate Kaas to Chancellor Schleicher, January 26 1933, BA, R-43—I, No. 1865, Reichsverfassung (1927—1933), PP. 403-405. —“‘_—" I 257 constitution, and the illusions it held about possible cooperation with the National Socialists. Kaas sent a copy of this letter to Hindenburg, and later printed it on the front page of the Centrist paper Germania on January 29, along with the announcement of Schleicher's resignation.67 The resignation of Schleicher on the 28th of January had a disillusioning effect on Carl Schmitt. He had been the friend and advisor of Schleicher, whom he supported from the beginning of the presidential system. Schmitt had met with Schleicher's aide Colonel Marcks on the 27th and was then informed Schleicher would have to resign and that either Papen or Hitler would receive the 68 chancellorship. Reminiscing in later life Schmitt described his immediate reaction to that news. "I was eliminated from the race," Schmitt noted, "in so far as I was ever really in the race as a behind the scenes "69 advisor. Then the Kaas letter appeared publicly on the 29th and Schmitt was undecided as to whether he 67"Kaas warnt vor Illegalitaet: Ein Schreiben an Schleicher und Hindenburg," Germania, Jhg. 3, No. 29 (January 29, 1933). 68 Carl Schmitt, "Zeitgenossen, op. opp. 69Interview by Ansgar Skriver with Carl Schmitt, in "Hitlers Machtergreifung vor 40 Jahren im Gedaechtnis von heute: Eine zeitgeschichtliche Befragung," West~ deutscher Rundfunk, Hauptabteilung Politik, second PrOgram, 8:45 p.m., January 30, 1973, p. 13. 258 should vindicate himself. Popitz tried to dissuade Schmitt from responding to the letter, but he finally 7° Schmitt's decided to retort to Kaas' accusations. diary contains the following notation for January 30: "In the morning I went to Frau Abel in order to write a letter to Kaas."71 Copies of the letter were drafted and sent to Hindenburg and Papen, who was then acting on behalf of the Reichspresident. In his retort Schmitt challenged Kaas' warning against the illegality of his constitutional interpre— tations. Schmitt replied that "one would find in none of my publications and in no authentic verbal remark even one phrase which could justify such diminishing of my constitutional teaching. My constitutional expositions are entirely concerned with the attempt to convey recog— nition of the meaning and consequence of the German con— stitution, without regard to the changing party interests, and to oppose degrading it to a tactical instrument and tool. I do not relativize constitutional law, but struggle against a misuse which destroys state and constitution, against the instrumentalizing of the concept of legality 7°Ibid. 71Carl Schmitt Personal Diary, as cited in Skriver, "Hitlers Machtergreifung," op. cit., p. 11. 259 and against a value and reality neutral functionalism."72 The two significant points for Schmitt were the value neutral functionalism, represented by the strictly legal interpretation of the constitution practiced by the Center and Hindenburg, and the use of this legality by the Nazis as an instrument for the acquisition of power. The final result would be, as Schmitt had predicted, the destruction of the very legal system and constitution Kaas had feared violating. The Center Party soon recognized its mistake. Later in the Center Party discussions over the Enabling Act, Bruening, who did not favor this act, said he sup— ported the election of Hindenburg because "Hindenburg was the guarantor and trustee of the constitution. Now there exists the greatest dangers to the entire constitution "73 After dictating this letter Schmitt went to the cafe Kutschera where he first heard that Hitler had been appointed chancellor. Schmitt noted in his diary that he was "irritated and yet somehow relieved: at least a decision." While that evening the victorious Nazis staged 72Carl Schmitt to Prelate Kaas, January 30, 1933, BA, R-53, Stellvertreter des Reichskanzlers Vizekanzlei goo Papen, Bd. 77, pp. 136-137. 73Protokollentwurf ueber 922 Sitzung opp Zentrums- fraktion des Reichstags vom 2;. 2' 1933 (Entwurf betr. das Ermaechtigfifigsgesetz mit—Efklaerung des damaligen Schrift- fuehrers der Fraktion Jean Albert Schwarz vom 8. 6. 53, BA, Kleine Erwerbung, No. 44, pp. 2-4. 260 a seven hour torchlight parade through the Brandenburg gate, Schmitt remained retired at home. Wilhelm Stapel paid him a visit and they discussed Prussia over a bottle of red wine. Although an anti-semite and advocate of the "New State," Stapel had opposed the appointment of Hitler. Now disappointed with events, Stapel told Schmitt that 74 "Hindenburg is for him no Prussian." Schmitt reacted philosophically and had the feeling that something had come to an end. It was the suicide of the Weimar system.75 Schmitt was already preparing to leave Berlin. On April 1, 1933 he was scheduled to accept the chair of public law at the University of Cologne vacated by the death of Stier-Somlo. A myth about Schmitt's departure from the Handelshochschule has been perpetuated by Moritz J. Bonn. According to Bonn, Schmitt decided to leave Berlin a few weeks before Hitler's appointment as chancellor because he no longer held similar political 76 viewpoints to the liberal minded Bonn. The fact of the matter was that though they were personal friends, Bonn and Schmitt were never politically compatible. And Schmitt's decision to leave Berlin was neither political nor a quick decision made in December. 74Carl Schmitt Personal Diary, as cited in Skriver, "Hitlers Machtergreifung,“ op. cit., p. 12. 751bid., p. 18. 76Bonn, §o_Macht Man, op. cit., p. 331. 261 As early as April 1932 the Cologne law faculty had attempted to attract Schmitt to their university.77 Schmitt was actually offered the chair on August 6, 1932, and this was followed by a constant campaign among law faculty members, including extensive and cordial entice— ment by Schmitt's old opponent Hans Kelsen, urging him to 78 accept this position. M. J. Bonn was already trying to hold Schmitt in Berlin as early as August and he knew that Schmitt's attraction to Cologne was actually motivated by 79 other factors than politics. To leave the business school for a position at the University of Cologne would have been temptation enough for any professor. In addi— tion, in October the Reichcommissar for Prussia had removed the Handelshochschule from the jurisdiction of the Ministry of Culture. For Bonn this signified "the end of the Handels—Hochschule," as he felt it would no longer be sufficiently funded to keep prominent full professors, and 77Professor Nipperdey to Professor Eckhardt, April 7, 1932, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 78Professor Windelband, Ministerialrat in Prussian Ministry for Science, Art and Education, to Carl Schmitt, August 2, 1932. Professor Nipperdey to Carl Schmitt, August 11, 1932. Professor Heinrich Lehmann to Carl Schmitt, August 12, 1932. Hans Kelsen to Carl Schmitt, September 3, 1932, September 7, 1932, October 7, 1932. Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 79Carl Schmitt to Moritz Julius Bonn, August 20, 1932. Moritz Julius Bonn to Carl Schmitt, September 5, 1932. Moritz Julius Bonn to Carl Schmitt, October 5, 1932. Nachlass Bonn, BA, No. 56. 262 that they would then be replaced by “poorly paid, young Dozenten from the provincial universities." Bonn's real interest in keeping Schmitt in Berlin was to prevent the flight of these full professors and to protect the pres- tige of his own institution. Bonn also knew that Schmitt was informed that if he went to Cologne he would later be called to the University of Berlin, and that offer actually materialized in the fall of 1933.80 Such a prestigious future promotion Schmitt was not about to overlook. Understandably Schmitt accepted his call to Cologne on December 6. Had this been a political decision Schmitt would certainly have elected to stay in Berlin. On December 2, Schleicher, whom Schmitt served as a political advisor, was appointed chancellor. If Schmitt ever had any real political influence it was then at its peak and for political reasons he would certainly have desired to stay near the center of power in Berlin. The years Schmitt spent in Berlin were full of political activity and excitement. He had been in the very midst of the political controversies leading up to the final demise of the Weimar Republic, and he received a great deal of public attention and criticism as the Kronjurist of the presidential system. Schmitt was never the moving force behind the presidential system. The 80Secret Memorandum, Moritz Julius Bonn, October 28, 1932, Ibid. 263 political leaders used his ideas in defense of their own plans and disregarded his advice and ideas when they did not coincide with their schemes. Schmitt was well informed of most developments but always remained a secondary figure, an intellectual trying unsuccessfully to have an impact on political events. He actually thought that his writings and counsel would have the effect he desired. He came closest to this goal with Schleicher's efforts to stop the National Socialists. In the final analysis his political and legal ideas failed significantly to alter political developments, and whatever influence he might have had ended with the fall of Schleicher. With the final failure of the presidential system and the appointment of Hitler, Schmitt felt that his excursion into the political arena had ended and that the Reich government would no longer require his services. While making preparations to move from Berlin to Cologne Schmitt had no indication that the end of one political career would be the beginning of another. The next few months would bring him once again into the political and public limelight as the Kronjurist of the Third Reich. CHAPTER VII THE KRONJURIST OF NATIONAL SOCIALISM, 1933-1936 The first few months of 1933 found Carl Schmitt in a similar predicament to that of 1919. Once again he experienced an abrupt change from one legal and political order to a new order whose precise nature and future course remained uncertain. He had always viewed the Nazis with the same apprehension that he did the Communists. In 1919 he wondered how far the Communists and Socialists would succeed in destroying the institutions of the Second Reich and in instituting the dictatorship of the proletariat. The National Socialists now presented a similar problem concerning the extent of their success in destroying Weimar institutions and establishing the dictatorship of the party. There were, however, a few significant exceptions with regard to the National Socialists. Schmitt could, for instance, at least display approval of many of the nationalist aspects of the Nazi movement, such as their opposition to the Versailles Treaty. Their ability to attract the support of more than a third of the German people also captured his interest. More important, in the months immediately following January 30, Schmitt 264 265 still felt somewhat reassured by Hindenburg's power to dis— miss Hitler if the need arose. Nevertheless, Schmitt‘s anxiety about Nazi extremism, especially now that they controlled the state apparatus, left him with the same feeling of bewilderment about Germany's future that had overwhelmed him in the early stages of the Weimar Republic. Schmitt's fear that an anti-constitutional party might acquire legal control of the state was now a reality. Yet, in these first months of 1933 Schmitt, like most Germans, harbored doubts about how far the Nazis would succeed in destroying the Weimar constitution and state, and in introducing a new order. At first he believed the Reichspresident and the army might be able to hold Hitler in check. Early in February he told Ferdinand Hermens that Schleicher and the army would do everything possible to bring about an end to the Nazi adventure. It was the purpose of civilians, Schmitt said, to propose solutions to Germany's economic, political, and constitutional prob- lems; and he stood prepared to direct his own attention to these ends.1 But by spring Schmitt had abandoned any hope Of controlling the Nazis. He joined the party, began aiding the National Socialists in instituting their lFerdinand Hermens, Zwischen Politik und Vernunft: Gesammelte Aufsaetze aus drei Welten (Berlin, 1969), PP. 158—159. 266 policy of Gleichschaltung, and for the next four years he appeared to play the role of Kronjurist of the Third Reich. Carl Schmitt's sudden change of attitude towards the Nazis is one of the most perplexing historical prob— lems surrounding the man. No single factor alone accounts for the ability of the author of a work on the defender of the constitution so quickly to transfer his allegiance to the usurper of that constitution. Neither opportunism for personal gain nor compatibility with the Nazi ideology suffices to explain Schmitt's National Socialist career. Instead, the reasons for Schmitt's collaboration with the Nazis lie in a labyrinth of personal and situational involvements closely intertwined with his basic political and intellectual philosophy. Through a rapid series of events early in 1933 Schmitt became thoroughly involved with the Nazi state. Decisive for Schmitt's change of direction was the Enabling Act of March 24, 1933. Under this act Hitler received almost absolute dictatorial power over Germany. Laws could now be decreed not only by the Reichstag but by the government itself, and these laws could deviate from the constitution.2 For Schmitt the 2"Gesetz zur Behebung der Not von Volk und Reich. Vom 24. Maerz 1933," Reichsgesetzblatt, Teil I, No. 25 (March 24, 1933), p. 141. 267 Enabling Act marked the beginning of the end of the Weimar system, and the genesis of a new legal and political order. Now the Nazi party had legal and dictatorial control which it could use as a basis for instituting whatever form of political and legal order it desired. Because the consti— tution itself was never officially eliminated many Germans continued to hope that some legal restrictions on the Nazis still existed. The political realism of Carl Schmitt allowed no room for such optimism, although he also had underestimated the extremism and dynamism of the movement. Schmitt, along with several other conserva- tives, thought that the Reichspresident could act as a restraint on the Nazis. Hindenburg still maintained his emergency powers under Article 48, his supreme command of the army, and the right to appoint and dismiss the chan- cellor. Aside from these political restraints inherent in the power of the Reichspresident, however, Schmitt real- istically foresaw the coming of wide ranging changes. He presented this realistic appraisal in an article wherein he lifted the veil of legality hiding the true implica- tions of the Enabling Act. That act, Schmitt informed his colleagues, represented "the victory of the National Revolution," which was equivalent in impact to the 268 revolution of 1918, and "in reality is the provisional constitution of the German Revolution." With this article began Schmitt's conciliatory attitude towards the Nazis. The previous reservations he had about immediate constitutional revision seemed unim- portant in light of recent events; he now accepted such reform as a major goal of the new government.4 An extreme critic of the pluralistic Weimar party state, Schmitt had reconciled himself after 1929 to the fact that political and constitutional changes were required. But he had feared that constitutional changes under the presidential system before a settlement of the political crisis would have led to civil war. Now the Nazis, one of the major parties to such a potential conflict, controlled the government, held a legal mandate after the March 5, elec— tions, and were sufficiently strong under the Enabling Act decisively to solve these problems. The Nazis were already eliminating their opposition and were then in the process of instituting their policy of Gleichschaltung in order to gain control over the state governments. While still dis— trusting and disapproving of the Nazis Schmitt had to 3Carl Schmitt, "Das Gesetz zur Behebung der Not von Volk und Reich," Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, Jhg. 38, Heft 7 (April 1, 1933), pp. 455—458; and Carl Schmitt Das Reichsstatthaltergesetz (Berlin, 1933), p. 9. 4"Das Gesetz," Ibid., p. 457. 269 adjust himself to the reality that they were now the dominant force in German politics. Subsequently, Schmitt underwent a process of reevaluating his own position and debated within himself what part he as a constitutionalist should play in coming political and constitutional developments. One obstacle to Schmitt's having any role in these developments was his previous association with Schleicher and his opposi- tion to the National Socialists. Schmitt had no prior contact with the Nazis and at this time he was still an outsider with far fewer possibilities of influencing politics than he had under the presidential system. In spite of these disadvantages a series of events brought Schmitt step by step into the service of the National Socialists. And the Nazis showed an unusual willingness to overlook temporarily his past and to utilize his pres- tigious name in support of their consolidation of power. Of immediate importance to the Nazis was how to force the state governments to comply with Reich policies and gain complete control over these state governments. To achieve this goal they passed a law for the coordina- tion of the states with the Reich on March 31. All state governments, except Prussia's, were dissolved and recon— structed without elections. These Nazi controlled govern— ments could now deviate from their state constitutions and pass laws without the consent of their legislative 270 bodies. Desiring additional assurances that their policies would be complied with, the Nazis went one step further. In the cabinet meeting of March 31, it was decided that a new law should immediately be introduced to give the Nazi central government absolute control over the state governments. Vice-chancellor Papen moved quickly to establish a commission to settle this affair. On that same day Papen wrote to Schmitt requesting the jurist to report to him for the first committee meeting on April 1.6 That meeting paved the way for Schmitt's first stage of cooperation with the Nazi government. He was selected for this task by Papen and complied with this directive for several reasons. First of all Schmitt was obeying the legally constituted state authority in Germany. Just as he had transferred his loyalty in 1919 from the Second Reich to the Weimar Republic, he now accepted the Nazi revolution as the beginning of a new legal order. Also, Schmitt had a familiarity with the nature of the problem from his experience with the case of Prussia versus the Reich, 5Martin Broszat, Der Staat Hitlers: Grundlegung und Entwicklung seiner inneren Verfassung (Munich, 1969), PP. 143—144. 6Papen to Carl Schmitt, March 31, 1933, BA, R-S3, Stellvertreter des Reichskanzlers Vizekanzlei von Papen, No. 77; and BAT—R-43—II, Reichskanzlei (1933—___ 1945), No. 1309, "Gleichschaltung der Laender mit dem Reich." 271 and he did favor the cause of the central government. Papen and Schmitt had already met on February 16, allegedly to discuss Schmitt's retort to Kaas' letter.7 Undoubtedly, the question of Prussia came up during their discussions since on February 6th, Papen had defied the supreme court decision, replaced Braun as the Prussian minister presi— dent, and dissolved the Landtag. Papen quite naturally again relied upon Schmitt's talents. Carl Schmitt accepted this opportunity once more to play an active role in politics and to complete the work he started the year before in seeking to solve the Prussian problem. Equally important in Schmitt's decision to comply with Papen's request was his friendship with Johannes Popitz. In addi— tion to minister of the interior Frick, Popitz was the only other member of this special committee. Where Popitz previously brought Schmitt into contact with the Schleicher clique he now acted as the agent in bringing Schmitt into contact with Nazi circles. The so—called Reichsstatthaltergesetz was quickly composed by this small commission and passed by the government on April 7. Under this law the chancellor could empower a personal representative, or Reichs— statthalter, to supervise the administration of state 7Papen to Carl Schmitt, February 13, 1933, and Carl Schmitt to Papen, February 14, 1933, BA, R-53, No. 77, pp. 138-139. 272 governments so as to assure compliance with Reich policies. In writing this law Schmitt thought of himself as acting on behalf of the German state and the Reich rather than as providing a service for the Nazi party. He had finally achieved his longstanding goal of a strong central govern— ment unhampered by federal and particularistic domestic 8 But his cooperation was no longer an extension strife. of his previous activity in the case against Prussia. He was actually aiding in the Nazi consolidation of power and its elimination of resistance. Not only had he placed his talents at the disposal of the Nazis but he gave addi— tional credibility to the regime by associating his own prestige and respect with its activities. He had committed the sin of political romanticism. Schmitt saw the Nazis gradually establishing abso— lute control over Germany and in the process of removing their opponents from political, academic, and bureau- cratic positions throughout the country. The Nazis had instituted the Law for the Restoration of a Professional Civil Service on April 7, 1933. That law removed the constitutional rights of civil servants, including tenure for university professors, and allowed for the legal purging of educational institutions. Schmitt knew that his own position as a prominent professor of 8Carl Schmitt, Das Reichsstatthaltergesetz, op, Cit., pp. 3, 8—9. 273 constitutional and public law was in no way immune from these measures, particularly when one considered his past opposition to the Nazis. Prominent law professors such as Radbruch, Bonn, Cohn, Heller, Kantorowicz, and Kelsen from Schmitt's own faculty at Cologne, were being 9 Before the Nazis finished their purges over released. 1,500 professors would be released. Adding to the prob- lem, the rather large and highly active body of Nazis in the student community waged, in the early spring, an extensive campaign of disruption and boycotts against Jewish, liberal, socialist, and non-cooperative profes- sors. The personal decisions facing Schmitt in these uncertain times were the most difficult he would ever encounter. Resistance to the legally constituted authority was incompatible with Schmitt's style and political philosophy, and completely out of the question due to the legal and dictatorial power the Nazis then exercised. Emigration at this stage of his life would have brought Schmitt as much uncertainty and hardship as the loss of his academic position. He had reached the peak of his career and not many Germans, with so much to lose, left their academic posts willingly. The uncertainties of an unknown future, and concern for personal and family welfare 9"Personalien," Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, Jhg. 38, Heft 9, (May 1, 1933), p. 613, Heft 10, (May 15, 1933), pp. 678—679. 274 greatly influenced the decisions of many individuals in the early stages of the Nazi regime. Like many of these Germans Schmitt took a wait and see attitude. Furthermore, the Hobbesian relationship of protection and obedience had always been a basic principle of Schmitt's political philosophy. When the Weimar legal system could no longer protect him, Schmitt no longer felt obligated to support it, and he transferred his obedience to the new regime as long as it granted him protection.10 The coercion, boycotts, and reprisals against pro- fessors were accompanied by a rapid accommodation and even some enthusiasm for the new regime within the universities. Early in March hundreds of university professors, with hundreds still to follow in the next few months, showed their public support to the Nazis. By the end of April even the prestigious professorial association, The 11 The University League, came to terms with the regime. general trend in the universities was definitely running in favor of the National Socialists. Literally hundreds of thousands of individuals throughout German society flocked to join the party, motivated by opportunism, fear, 10Carl Schmitt, Ex Captivitate Salus: Erfahrungen der Zeit 1945/47 (Cologne, 1950), pp. 20—21. llKarl Dietrich Bracher, "Die Gleichschaltung der deutschen Universitaet," in Nationalsozialismus Und Die Deutsche Universitaet (Berlin, 19665, p. 132. 275 and sincere enthusiasm. Reinforcing this trend were the pronouncements of certain prominent intellectuals in support of the new regime. One such thinker rallying early to the Nazi cause was the existentialist philosopher Martin Heidegger. In a letter to Schmitt on April 22, 1933 Heidegger urged Schmitt to work with the Nazis and stated, ". . . I am hoping for your non—obligatory col— 12 laboration." By this time Schmitt's close friend Johannes Popitz had already made his accommodation with the regime by accepting his recent appointment as Prussian finance minister in Hermann Goering's cabinet. Two of Schmitt's most promising and later prominent law students, Ernst Rudolf Huber and Ernst Forsthoff, were even profit- ing by the university purges. Forsthoff replaced Hermann Heller at the University of Frankfurt and Huber replaced Schuecking in Kiel.13 With this turn of events Schmitt made his decision to join the Nazi party. Since the Enabling Act he had debated within himself and discussed with his friends the course of action he personally and as a professor of 12Martin Heidegger to Carl Schmitt, April 22, 1933, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 13"Personalien," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 38, Heft 10 (May 15, 1933). p. 679. 276 14 On May 1, constitutional and public law should take. 1993 Carl Schmitt joined the Nazi party in Cologne. His party number of 2,098,860 attested to the fact that since January over a million Germans had joined the party before Schmitt decided to follow.15 Nationalism, anti—liberalism, the strong leadership principle, and the replacement of the pluralistic Weimar system with a strong, centrally controlled state with the goal of alleviating the internal struggles then plaguing Germany, all aided in making the new regime palatable to Carl Schmitt. Nonetheless, Schmitt had held these positions before the Nazi acquisi— tion of power and had still opposed the National Socialists. He could have opted for continuing to foster similar con— cepts without joining the party, follow the path he had pursued throughout the Weimar period, and stay aloof from direct activity in party politics. Decisive in Schmitt‘s entry into the party was concern for his personal welfare and his academic position, combined with a naive belief that he could work with the Nazis. His entry into the party was a show of loyalty to the new regime, which he l4Carl Schmitt, "Beantwortung des Vorwurfs: Sie haben an der Vorbereitung des Angriffskrieges und der damit verbundenen Straftaten an entscheidender Stelle mitgewirkt," (Nuremberg, April 20, 1947), Carl Schmitt- Personal Papers, 11, p. 3. 15Personal File Carl Schmitt, “Party Records Gau Koeln-Aechen," and "Nazi Party Records Central Munich,“ Document Center Berlin. 277 felt would tolerate nothing less than total allegiance and he hoped that this would help assure his personal and pro— fessional welfare. At the same time he naively thought that he might be able to influence the development of con— stitutional and legal matters in the Third Reich. In this respect he assumed he was following in the footsteps of figures like Popitz and Heidegger. After joining the party Schmitt commenced immedi— ately supporting the new regime through a series of arti- cles in which he presented certain of his own concepts which were applicable to the current situation. As the Nazi policy of Gleichschaltung proceeded in the spring and early summer of 1933 with the elimination of other political parties, Schmitt hailed the one—party state as the state of the twentieth-century. Schmitt criticized Weimar as a nineteenth-century pluralistic state which tore the nation apart. Gleichschaltung was only a means to achieving the homogeneity and unity of the German people and was a sign that the Germans were learning to 16 distinguish the friend from the enemy. The friend—enemy concept was not racial, and Schmitt viewed it purely from a political standpoint and as a prerequisite to the 16Carl Schmitt, "Das gute Recht der deutschen Revolution," Westdeutscher Beobachter, Jhg. 9, No. 108 (May 12, 1933), pp. 1-2, and "Der Staat des 20. Jahrhunderts," Westdeutscher Beobachter, Jhg. 9, No. 151 (June 28, 1933), PP. 1—2. 278 internal unity of Germany. What he actually had in mind was the elimination of pockets of political resistance to the state. Schmitt, of course, was enlightened enough to realize that the Nazis were considering Jews as enemies of the state merely on racial grounds. So he was probably aware that this friend—enemy terminology might also be misused as a convenient rationale for coercive measures against German Jews; but at this time that was certainly not his intention. In fact, he would not address the Jewish question for two years, and even then none of the anti-semitic rhetoric contained in a few articles he pub— lished in 1935-36 was racially based. Although in the fall of 1933 he did begin to insert a few occasional phrases about race into his works, he would never succumb to a belief in the biological racism characteristic of the National Socialist ideology. These first early remarks about race, so irrelevant to the content of his works and so artificially placed within the text of his writings, reveal his obvious purpose. Schmitt wanted to show himself in tune with the new regime by spouting the Nazi cant then coming into vogue. Carl Schmitt would never have the influence in the constitutional developments of the Third Reich that he desired. Despite his party offices, titles, including that of Kronjurist, his prolific publications in support 279 of the regime, and his attempts at providing the Nazis with theoretical foundations, he would never be more than a figurehead. His only real influence was that he assisted the rapid Nazi consolidation of power and added credibility to the future acts of the regime. In consolidating their control the Nazis were quite willing to have the backing of such a prominent figure. After his entry into the party Schmitt immediately became the subject of a long article in the Cologne Nazi organ Westdeutscher Beobachter. Lauding his opposition to the Weimar Republic the paper hailed Schmitt as "the most renowned national constitu— tionalist in Germany."17 While the Nazis made these occasional uses of Schmitt's reputation his position within the party would always remain doubtful and suspect. Many important party members objected to his status as a late comer to the Nazi cause, or a "March-violet" as they were called by the old fighters within the party, and they expressed jealousy and suspicion concerning his brilliance and intelligence. Some remembered that he had never supported the Nazis and, in fact, had opposed the movement during its desperate years of struggle. They knew Schmitt had never fully accepted their ideology and that even his later anti—semitic utterances lacked the 17“Der grosse nationale Staatsrechtslehrer Pro— fessor Dr. Carl Schmitt an die Koelner Universitaet berufen," Westdeutscher Beobachter, Jhg. 9, No. 107 (May 11, 1933), p. 3. 280 proper racial foundations. Most significant of all the Nazis neither desired nor needed anything other than Schmitt's reputation for their cause. They had their own ideology and plans for its institutionalization. They resented the interference by intellectuals who presented new or varying theories, and more so if such prominent intellectuals like Carl Schmitt threatened to overshadow the second-rate theories of established party members. By the time Schmitt realized that this was the case his own life and work was intimately interconnected with the Nazi regime. If party membership and a few treatises supporting the new regime constituted the limit of Schmitt's col— laboration his National Socialist career would hardly be a subject for such critical attention. But Schmitt throughout 1933 continued becoming more and more involved with the Nazi state. Until this time Schmitt had had no contact with the Nazi leadership. Then Johannes Popitz, Goering's finance minister, brought Schmitt into direct association and cooperation with Nazi circles and insti— tutions. Without this personal connection with Popitz it is doubtful that Schmitt ever would have entered into the inner Nazi circles and played the role of figurehead Kronjurist. The first possibility for such contact came with Goering‘s reorganization of the Prussian State Council. 281 Goering wanted the new State Council to serve as a type of advisory Upper House which, although having no legis— lative power, would serve as a link between the government and other segments of society. In this effort Goering received the support of Popitz, who hoped to develop this institution as a conservative counterweight to party con- trol.18 On Popitz's suggestion Goering appointed Carl Schmitt to the office of Prussian State Counsellor in early July 1933. Popitz and Schmitt intended that the Council should serve as an institution for discussing and 19 Unfortunately handling actual administrative problems. the plans of Popitz and Schmitt never materialized as the Council turned out to be merely a pet show—piece for Goering. The Nazis never intended to allow the Council to have any real significance. At the very first conference of the Council on September 16, the true party intentions for the Council were quite clear. On the question of public administration and municipal self-administration in a National Socialist state, Schmitt's factual discussion of the actual nature and formation of municipal self- administration was eclipsed by the ideological concepts l8"Abschrift. Sitzung des Preussischen Staats— ministeriums," Berlin, May 29, 1933, Geheimes Staatsarchiv Preussischer Kulturbesitz, Berlin, Rep. 90, Preussisches Staatsministerium, "Staatsrat," No. 13. PP. 247—251. 19Carl Schmitt, "Beantwortung des Vorwurfs,“ Op. cit., p. 4. 282 20 That stressed by Terboven, the Gauleiter from Essen. was just the beginning of the party's rejection of Schmitt's attempt to influence their political and consti— tutional policies as well as their theories. The formation of the Prussian State Council played an important part in Schmitt's theoretical approach to the Nazi regime. From the organizational structure of this Council Schmitt drew up his theoretical model for the constitutional foundations of the Third Reich.21 And it is interesting that Schmitt had first presented this analysis of the future Nazi state in early June when the Council was first proposed. The Prussian State Council was divided into three groups, consisting of the state secretaries, party members, and societal representatives from the churches, economy, science, arts, etc.22 According to Schmitt‘s analysis 20“Erste Arbeitstagung des Staatsrats," in Cuno Horkenbach, Das Deutsche Reich von 1918 his Heute, 1933 (Berlin, 1935), p. 396. 21Carl Schmitt, "Die Bedeutung des neuen Staats— rates," Westdeutscher Beobachter, Jhg. 9, No. 169 (July 16, 1933), and "Die oeffentliche Verwaltung im neuen Reich," speech of June 13, 1933 before the Berlin Verwaltungs-Akademie, in "Der Geist des neuen Staats— recht," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 38, Heft 14 (July 15, 1933), p- 959. 22"Gesetz ueber den Staatsrat. Vom 8. Juli 1933,“ Preussische Gesetzsammlung, No. 46 (July 10, 1933), pp. 241—243. BA, R-43—I, No. 2300, “Akten betreffend Preussischer Staatsrat (1921—1936),“ Membership List February 17, 1934. 283 each group corresponded to the organizational parts of the new twentieth century state, i.e. the state, the movement, and the people.23 The state was the political-stately part with administrative authority, the party or movement the politically dynamic part which leads the nation, and the people the unpolitical sphere of public life. These three groups were . . . different but not separate, d."24 united but not merge It was the party that pene- 25 The trated, led and united the state and the people. Law on the Securing of the Unity of Party and State, of December 1, 1933 had legalized this party function. Thus the party served this purpose through Hitler's position as both the head of state and the leader of the party. As Schmitt pointed out, the party was not an organ of the state and its union with the state was solely based upon this “personal—union" of the Fuehrer with the state.26 Although Schmitt did not specifically mention the fact, the duality of state and party remained. If the Nazis had completely destroyed the old state apparatus and adminis- tration and instituted a one-party state along the lines of the Soviet Union this duality would have disappeared. 23Carl Schmitt, Staat, Bewegung, Volk: Die Dreigliederung der politischen Einheit (Hamburg, 1933). 24 Ibid., p. 21. 251bid., pp. 11-12. 26 Ibid., p. 20. 284 The Nazi inroads into the state apparatus were never extensive enough to remove this duality. Party and state existed side by side throughout the Third Reich, and the Nazis achieved the primacy of the party only in certain 27 Still, the Nazis never ceased in their per— instances. sistent attempts to turn the state into merely an adminis— trative apparatus of the party. Schmitt had conceived of the Third Reich in terms of an authoritarian state rather than a totalitarian one. This authoritarian state Schmitt envisioned as a qualita— tive total state ruled from above by a sovereign, in this case Hitler, governing and attending to the affairs of state. In a state of exception when the state was suf— ficiently endangered the sovereign had almost unlimited power to intervene in all aspects of life, though under normal conditions the state would not interfere in the private spheres of life. The totalitarian state which actually characterized Nazi Germany, in contrast to Schmitt's scheme, was a quantitative total state that completely and constantly interfered into every aspect of life, both public and private. Schmitt had criticized Weimar for approximating such an intervening quantitative total state, but now the dictatorship of the party far 27Karl Dietrich Bracher, The German Dictatorship: The Origins, Structure, and Effects of National Soc1alism —.——__.._—_________ (New York, 1970), pp. 231-236. 285 surpassed the total control Schmitt had criticized. Where the Nazis failed to achieve complete control of the state they did manage to gain control over many aspects of soci— ety. The fact that Schmitt applied this authoritarian approach to the National Socialists in his early days of collaboration attests to his shortsightedness and naivete concerning the true nature of the Nazi phenomenon. With the prestigious office of Prussian State Counsellor and his direct access to Hermann Goering, who liked to think of himself as a patron of the arts and intellectuals, Schmitt moved quickly into other areas of Nazi legal affairs. Before this time Nazi legal theore- ticians paid little, if any, attention to Carl Schmitt. While Schmitt received probably more attention than any other constitutionalist in legal journals throughout the era of the presidential system, and even more during the 1932 crisis, the Nazi legal journal Deutsches Recht never even mentioned his name.28 Now suddenly Schmitt not only attracted the attention of the Nazis, but he rose to a place of distinction in Nazi legal institutions. Schmitt became a member of the recently organized Nazi Academy of German Law, worked on several of its committees, and 28Deutsches Recht Monatschrift des Bundes N—S Deutscher Juristen, ed., Hans Frank, Jhg. 1—2 (1931- 1932). 286 29 By delivered lectures at its major conferences. November he received the directorship of the University Teachers Group of the National Socialist League of German Jurists, and in June 1934, Hans Frank appointed him editor of the Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung.30 From outside the Nazi party structure it appeared that Schmitt was actually functioning as the Kronjurist of the Third Reich. There appeared some continuity between the publicity he received during 1932 and the prestige arising out of his newly acquired closeness to the National Socialist power structure. In the spring Schmitt was offered the prestigious chair of constitutional law at the University of Heidelberg formerly occupied by Gerhard Anschuetz, and in July he received an offer from the University of Munich. The faculty as well as the studentbody of the University of Cologne urged Schmitt to refuse these offers and remain as their "intellectual leader."31 Schmitt finally accepted the chair of public law at the University of Berlin in October 1933. Much of 29Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, Records of Nazi Cultural and Research Institutes, U.S. National Archives, No. T—82, Roll—23, Serial-28, Reel—806. 30Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, Jhg. 39, Heft 11 (June 1, 1934), p. 690-692. 31Professor Nipperdey to Carl Schmitt, May 29, 1933, Carl Schmitt—Personal Papers, and "Die Student— schaft an Professor Carl Schmitt," Koelnischer Zeitung, No. 390 (July 21, 1933). 287 this attention granted to Schmitt resulted from the Nazi purges of the universities which made it difficult to fill the vacuum with renowned nationalist professors. Even his old opponents, however, felt that Schmitt had some influence within the Nazi regime. Congratulating Schmitt on his appointment as Prussian State Counsellor, Arnold Brecht, who had opposed him in the trial Prussia contra Reich, solicited Schmitt's assistance. Brecht wrote that, "the ministry of state, in which no one any longer knows me personally, is threatening me with temporary retirement by employing paragraph four of the Professional Civil Service Law. Could you as an old opponent say a word for me in this regard."32 This outward appearance of influence would never conform to Schmitt's own major expectations regarding his security and his ability to influence constitutional and legal developments in the Third Reich. Aside from Goering and Frank, Schmitt never came into contact with the Nazi upper echelons of Himmler, Goebbels, Rosenberg, Hess, and Hitler.33 In so far as Schmitt was a renowned professor and a member of his Prussian State Council, 32Arnold Brecht to Carl Schmitt, August 16, 1933, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 33Carl Schmitt, "Beantwortung der Frage: Wieweit haben Sie die theoretische Untermauerung der Hitlerschen Grossraumpolitik gefoerdert?" (Nuremberg, April 18, 1947), Carl Schmitt—Personal Papers, I, p. 2. 288 Goering patronized him in the same manner that he patron- ized certain artists. Within Nazi legal organizations Schmitt's position rested solely upon Hans Frank's recog— nition of his talents. Frank protected Schmitt from the jealousies and attacks by older party members who, viewing Schmitt as an opportunist, doubted his ideological and 34 political sincerity. Actually even in these legal organizations Schmitt was not the Kronjurist and the older Nazis dominated the scene.35 In January of 1934 the press office of the German Legal Front requested that Schmitt write an article for Deutsches Recht on the first anni- versary of Hitler's chancellorship. Using his title as Staatsrat Schmitt respectfully declined on the grounds that he had numerous other obligations. The press office reacted harshly and rejected the idea that Schmitt's work within the party ". . . can be dependent upon other obli— gations," and demanded that the article appear as they had d.36 planne The fact that the article appeared as scheduled 34Carl Schmitt, "Beantwortung des Vorwurfs," 92- Cit. I pp. 4—5- 35BA, R—43—II, Reichskanzlei 1933-1945, No. 1509, "Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht 1933—1935." 36Carl Schmitt to Oberregierungsrat, January 13, 1934, and Press Office of Bund Nationalsozialistischer Deutscher Juristen to Reichsgeschaeftsfuehrer Dr. Hueber, January 15, 1934, Personalakte Carl Schmitt (Sch 32), "Nazi Party Records Berlin," Document Center Berlin. 289 indicates the precarious position of Schmitt within the party and the hollowness of his titles.37 During the first years of the Nazi regime Schmitt continued to believe that he could play a role as the Kronjurist and direct Nazi policy toward a conservative framework. He worked prodigiously on various legal and theoretical aspects of the new regime under the double illusion that this would assure his rulers of his loyalty and at the same time he could influence legal affairs. By 1936 Schmitt had published five short books and over thirty—five articles in support of the Third Reich. The Rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens, represented Schmitt's final theoretical shift from Decisionism to what he called 38 Concrete Orders. For Schmitt the classical exponent of Decisionism was Thomas Hobbes, who defined a sovereign as one who establishes order, peace, and security. All law, norms, and order arise out of the decision of this sovereign, and this "sovereign decision is the absolute beginning and the beginning is nothing but sovereign decision."39 That 37Carl Schmitt, "Ein Jahr nationalsozialistischer Verfassungsstaat," Deutsches Recht, Jhg. 4, No. 2 (January 25, 1934), pp. 27-30. 3 . . . 8Carl Schmitt, Ueber Die Drei Arten Des Rechts— 39Ibid., pp. 27—28. 290 was the legal and political theory Schmitt espoused during the Weimar Republic. Now Schmitt began to modify his position on the origin of order and law as emanating through an absolute decision of the sovereign. He held that there existed certain concrete institutions or orders, such as the family, church, Estates, army, bureaucracy, etc., which serve as the basis for order and laws.40 He no longer held that the decision could be born out of nothing. All of German life must be organized along the lines of these concrete orders, an idea which in many respects resembled a corporate state. To a conserva— tive like Schmitt it was very important that traditional institutions such as the family, church, army, and bureauc- racy remain in existence. Although Hitler would remain sovereign and the party would be the unifying factor between the concrete orders, Schmitt did not see the party as exercising constant and complete totalitarian control over every aspect of German life. He drew the distinction between the private and the public spheres of life. The latter being Subject to political control and the former not. In times of crisis the sovereign could interfere anywhere; but Schmitt assumed that under normal circum— stances the concrete orders would be left alone. 4°Ibid., pp. 42-44. 291 The absolute sovereignty of Hitler was exemplified most dramatically in the purges of the SA in June 1934, when he ordered the murder of the most powerful SA leaders. Hitler pursued this course in order to placate the army which feared SA encroachments, and to prevent the emer- gence of the SA as a counterweight to his own authority. Shortly thereafter Schmitt published an article acknowl- edging Hitler as the highest judge and justifying these murders on the basis of necessity.41 By taking this position Schmitt was favoring the army as a concrete order against its possible mergence into the SA. This action on the part of Hitler had also destroyed the radical left wing of the movement which many conservatives like Schmitt feared. Schmitt had accepted the fact that for all practical purposes Hitler was the absolute sovereign in Germany and could make such decisions over life and death and circumvent the normal legal process in cases of emergency. As early as the fall of 1933 Schmitt had dis- regarded Hindenburg as a check on Hitler, stating that the Reichspresident "reigns but does not govern."42 The motivation for Schmitt's public claim that the "Fuehrer protects the law" was closely related to 41Carl Schmitt, "Der Fuehrer schuetzt das Recht," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 39, Heft 15 (August 1, 1934), pp. 943—950. 42 PP. 9-10. Carl Schmitt, Staat, Bewegung, Volk," gp. cit., 292 other events intertwined with the SA-army controversy. Germany in the pre-purge months was experiencing the pub— lic expression of discontent among traditional conserva- tives. Supported by Edgar Jung and the Catholic Action Group, Papen sought to acquire the intervention of Hindenburg against the excesses and recent trend of the regime. This discontent culminated in Papen's speech at the University of Marburg where he publicly criticized the excesses of the party. General von Schleicher had also returned to the political scene from his retirement and begun criticizing the regime; this conjured up various rumours of a possible Putsch. During the purges Schleicher, his close associate General von Bredow, Edgar Jung, and two of Papen's aides were brutally murdered. Two prominent figures in the Catholic movement, Bruening and Treviranus, escaped. Papen was arrested and removed from office.43 Under these circumstances Schmitt feared he might also fall prey to the purge.44 As a conservative Catholic and former advisor to Schleicher, Schmitt was a likely target for the Nazis. He had worked closely with Schleicher to prevent the Nazi rise to power and he was 43Wheeler—Bennett, Nemesis 9: Power, gp. cit., pp. 314—324. 44Schmitt Interview, November 22, 1972. 293 still in contact with Schleicher's former aide Colonel Erich Marcks. To Schmitt's good fortune the Nazi purges remained quite limited, and his momentary fears were unnecessary. Schmitt naturally had no way of knowing this would be the outcome and for the rest of his life he would believe that only the intervention of Goering saved him from the fate of his former colleagues.46 Schmitt's article on the purges was another public affirmation of his total loyalty to Hitler. For Schmitt it was a matter of his realistic philosophical belief in the relationship between protection and obedience. He would obey Hitler so long as the Fuehrer protected him. Such affirmations would in the end never suffice to secure Schmitt within this totalitarian regime. His support of these murders merely associated him closer with the excesses of a regime in which many party members continued to reject his sup- port and deny his loyalty. Schmitt could have attempted to flee Germany like Bruening, but he doubted that he could succeed. Assuming he could succeed there remained little hope for a satis— factory future abroad. In the public eye he was already too closely associated with the regime and would not fare 45Colonel Erich Marcks to Carl Schmitt, June 9, 1934, Carl Schmitt-Personal Papers. 46Schmitt Interview, November 22, 1972. 294 very well with German emigres who held him partially responsible for their losses and suffering. Furthermore, his own nationalism hindered emigration and, considering his precarious position in the Third Reich, Schmitt still profited by that system. His status as State Counsellor, professor in Berlin, and director of the Nazi University Teachers Organization, played upon his vanity and sense of importance. By compromising himself for protection, self— aggrandizement, and public attention Schmitt had set him~ self up as the enemy of those who fled the regime. One of his most despicable compromises dealt with the issue of anti-semitism. Before the Nazi seizure of power there was not the slightest indication of anti- semitism in any of Schmitt's works or personal relation— ships. Many of his closest friends were Jews. He had dedicated his Verfassungslehre to Fritz Eisler, a Jewish companion who died during World War I, and Schmitt had written a lauding work on Hugo Preuss. Erich Kaufmann, Moritz Julius Bonn, Franz Blei, and Otto Kirchheimer were amongst his close Jewish friends and colleagues. With the advent of the Nazi regime Schmitt commenced paying lip service to the anti—semitism of the party by occasionally inserting merely a few anti—semitic remarks into the text of his works. Although at times Schmitt used such terms as race and blood his anti—semitism would never reach the Stage of biological racism. And anti-semitism constituted 295 only a very minor aspect of Schmitt's work and collabora— tion. When the Nazis instituted repressive measures against the Jews Schmitt started referring to Jews as heterogeneous elements inhibiting the homogeneity of the German nation. He was aware that historically not only Jews, but at various times also Christians, Moslems, Protestants, the bourgeois class, and other minority or heterogeneous groups were declared enemies of a state and faced banishment or persecution. He accepted Nazi anti— semitism in terms of these historical precedents. If anti-semitism had not been such a vital issue for the Nazi regime, Schmitt probably never would have involved himself with the Jewish question. The closer Schmitt tied himself to the new regime the more anti—semitism entered into his work. As a title holder of a high party office he was expected to conform to the party line. He also had to overcome the party suspicion about his past close professional and personal involvements with Jews. As his position within the party became more and more precarious he expounded the party line more vociferously. Schmitt‘s extreme anti—semitic utterance in the years 1935 and 1936 can only be properly understood in terms of the fact that he was increasingly under attack from within the party and from abroad. Schmitt had already encountered theoretical diffi— culties with the Nazis as early as 1934. There were grave 296 discrepancies between his proposals for organizing the state, the party and the people, and the organizational schemes of the Nazi theorists. As a conservative Schmitt hoped that the state apparatus would remain as the essen— tial administrative institution. Schmitt had intended that the party would be the politically decisive group linked to the state through the Fuehrer, but that no merger of party and state would take place. The Nazis on the other hand unsuccessfully attempted to take complete control of the state apparatus. For them the state was to become merely an instrument of the party. Theorists like Rosenberg feared that if they continued to emphasize the state then eventually the concept of the state would pre- dominate over that of the movement. In the fall of 1934 Rosenberg let it be known that he had doubts about the 47 "ideological side" of Carl Schmitt. Unlike the suspect Schmitt, the state for Rosenberg and other Nazis was not to have any significance in and of itself. Another point of contention between Schmitt and the Nazis concerned the role of the people. The final goal of the entire movement according to Nazi theorists 47Alfred Rosenberg, "Totaler Staat," Voelkischer Beobachter (January 9, 1934), in Alfred Rosenberg: Selected Writings, ed., Robert Pois (London, 1970), pp. 191-192. Staff Director in Rosenberg's office to Professor Wirz in NSDAP Hochschulkommission, September 20, 1934, Gemeinschaft studentischer Verbaende, Institut fuer Zeitgeschichte, Munich, MA-ll63, NSDAP (IV, 24), 95620- 95622. 297 was the realization of the political will of the German people as represented by the Fuehrer.48 In his theory Carl Schmitt had relegated the people to an apolitical position "in the protection and shadows of political decisions."49 Probably more disturbing to the Nazi theorists was that Schmitt's entire scheme was not racially based. And it was on the question of race that Schmitt received his first public rebuke from the Nazis. Otto Koellreutter, a law professor at Munich and one of the leading advocates of a racially oriented political policy, led the ideological assault on Schmitt. Koellreutter argued that Schmitt had contributed nothing substantial 50 to National Socialist legal thought. To convinced Nazis like Koellreutter Schmitt's theories appeared "avoelkisch" and neglected the fundamental biological 51 foundations of political life. Beyond these bitter 8Hans Fabricus, Bewegung, Staat, und Volk in ihren Organisationen (Berlin, 1935). 49Carl Schmitt, Staat, Bewegung, Volk, pp. cit., p. 12. 50Otto Koellreutter, Deutsches Verfassungsrecht: Ein Grundriss (Berlin, 1935), pp. 3-4, 26. 51Otto Koellreutter, Volk Eng Staat in ger Weltanschauung des Nationa15021alismus (Berlin, 1935), pp. 6-11. This—wark was first presented as a lecture in 1934 before the general meeting of the Kant-Gesellschaft at the University of Halle. That speech was for the most part an attack on the teaching of Carl Schmitt. For Koellreutter the foundations of Nazi politics was the 298 published attacks on Schmitt, Koellreutter initiated intrigues within the party against his conservative rival. He attempted to capitalize on the disapproval of Schmitt displayed by other party members. The past incongruencies with the Nazis, which Schmitt had hoped were forgotten, were now being discussed in various party circles. Numerous arguments against Schmitt began to surface. He had been an opportunist and late-comer to the movement 52 who previously closely associated with Jews. But the time was not yet ripe for the party's reckoning with Schmitt. Many party members who viewed Schmitt in a highly negative manner believed that his position was still unassailable.53 Schmitt's status as Goering's State Counsellor and the associate of Hans Frank discouraged lesser party members from challenging him. Yet, by the fall of 1934 rumours spread that Schmitt would shortly be removed from his party offices.54 "people as a biological organic unit." He repeatedly criticized Schmitt's Nazi works and his friend—enemy theory as "a—voelkisch." See also: Otto Koellreutter, Der Deutsche Fuehrerstaat (Tuebingen, 1934), p. 16. 52Bornhack to Koellreutter, April 22, 1934, and June 1, 1934, Heckel to Koellreutter, October 6, 1934, "Schmitt, Karl Dr. Prof.," Sicherheitsdienst des RFSS SD Hauptamt, Institut fuer Zeitgeschichte, Munich, AKZ 4062/ 68 Fa 503, Bd. I, pp. 7, 11. 53Gerland to Koellreutter, June 16, 1934, "Schmitt," SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68 Fa 503, Bd. I, p. 10. 54Schwinge to Koellreutter, September 10, 1934, "Schmitt," SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68 Fa 503, Bd. I, p. 6. 299 These party intriguers were not the first to instigate public scrutiny of Schmitt's past and challenge the sincerity of his National Socialism. The German emigres, many of whom were former intimate friends and colleagues of Schmitt, now took their revenge on the Kronjurist. Shortly after joining the party Schmitt had criticized the German intellectuals living abroad for attacking Germany, and stated that they were not true 55 In return Germans and should be banished forever. these emigres viewed Schmitt's collaboration as treacherous opportunism and it became the intent of some to discredit him in the eyes of the Nazis, even at the cost of his life. The first emigre attack on Schmitt came on October 1, 1934 from his former friend Waldemar Gurian, writing for the Schweizerischen Rundschau under the pseudonym Paul Mueller. A similar article was published on the 26th in Deutsche Briefe, a journal organized in Switzerland by Gurian and Otto Knab, another emigrant 56 journalist. These articles confirmed in the most explicit terms all of the Nazi suspicions concerning Schmitt. They noted that Schmitt began his career with 55Carl Schmitt, "Die deutschen Intellektuellen," Westdeutscher Beobachter, Jhg. 9, No. 126 (May 31, 1933), PP- I"?- 56"Carl Schmitt, Der Kronjurist Des III. Reiches," Deutsche Briefe (October 26, 1934), in Huerter, Deutsche Briefe, Bd. I, op. cit., pp. 52—54. 300 the aid of liberal, non-aryans, that he befriended Jews, and adhered to Roman Catholicism. More significant, Schmitt had struggled against the National Socialists and had once referred to the movement as "organized mass insanity.“ These authors also emphasized that Schmitt could never be a true National Socialist and claimed he was using the party simply for his own ends. Such expo- sures continually emanated from Deutsche Briefe for the next two years, with no other figure being so bitterly attacked and morally defamed as Carl Schmitt.57 The venge- ful goal of discrediting Schmitt with the party eventually resulted in complete success. And those party members who opposed Schmitt found these articles to be evidence of his disloyalty and as grounds for his removal from party offices.58 Beginning in 1934-1935 Schmitt's position within the party was weakening. Although Goering and Frank still patronized Schmitt a new force, the SS, was emerging within the Third Reich and would neutralize the influence of Schmitt's protectors. Heinrich Himmler had taken over the police power from Goering and the SS quickly ascended to a dominating position, restricted only by Hitler 57Huerter, Waldemar Gurian, gp. cit., p. 13. 58Koellreutter to Mirow, November 1, 1934, Becker to Koellreutter, November 15, 1935, "Schmitt," SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68 Fa 503, Ed. I, pp. 8, 16-18. 301 himself. During 1934 and 1935 the SS introduced an extensive purging of enemies of the state. Thousands were arrested for the least suspicion of anti-state behav- ior. It was under these circumstances that Schmitt's anti-semitism reached its peak. He made a concerted effort to prove his loyalty and lend his full support for Nazi anti—semitic policies in order to overcome his own past. While publishing a series of articles justifying the repressive measures against Jews, Schmitt went so far as to declare the Nuremberg Laws the constitution of free— 59 dom In the spring of 1936 he prepared for the first time to introduce an anti-semitic program within the National Socialist University Teachers Group which he 60 directed. At the conference of University Teachers held in October 3 and 4, 1936, he launched his most devastating attack on Jewish influences in German law and presented 59Carl Schmitt, “Die Verfassung der Freiheit," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 40, Heft 19 (October 1, 1935), pp. 1133-1135, and "Die nationalsozialistische Gesetzgebung und der Vorbehalt des 'ordre public' im Internationalen Privatrecht," Zeitschrift deg Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, Jhg. 3, Heft 4, (February 20, 1936), pp. 204-211. 60"Aus der Deutschen Rechtsfront," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 41, Heft 11, (June 1, 1936), pp. 695-696. "Das Judentum in der Rechtswissenschaft: Tagung der Reichsgruppe Hochschullehrer des NSRB," Mitteilungensblatt des National—Sozialistischen Rechts- wahrerbundes, Jhg. 1936 (Berlin, 1936), pp. 200—201. 302 his suggestions for purging the "Jewish Spirit."6l It must be noted that this was related solely to the policies of excluding Jews from public life and had nothing to do with the terror acts and the genocide that later character— ized the regime. Whether Schmitt would have condoned the barbarous crimes against Jews after 1936, had he not fallen out of favor with the regime, is, however, a sub— ject for serious speculation. In the end he accomplished nothing by this anti-semitic offensive with regard to securing his own welfare, instead he inflicted a permanent blemish on his own reputation and character. His opponents at home and abroad were still not convinced of his sincerity. The editors of Deutsche Briefe repeatedly taunted the party for overlooking Schmitt's past Jewish relationships and for their credulous accept- 62 ance of his recently acquired anti-semitism. Such an affront to the reputation of the Third Reich could not be tolerated by the SS. As the most powerful organization 61Carl Schmitt, "Die deutsche Rechtswissenschaft im Kampf gegen den juedischen Geist: Schlusswort auf der Tagung der Reichsgruppe Hochschullehrer des NSRB vom 3. und 4. Oktober 1936," Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Jhg. 41, Heft 20 (October 15, 1936), PP. 1194-1199. 62"Bin Bolschewistenfreund als Nationalsozialist— ischer Kronjurist," Deutsche Briefe (March 13, 1936), "Der NS Kronjurist Carl Schmitt ueber das Plebiszit," QB (April 3, 1936), "Carl Schmitt gegen Carl Schmitt," DB (May 22, 1936), "Der Fall Eschweiler, Das Opfer Carl—— Schmitts," DB (June 19, 1936), "Staatsrat Carl Schmitt," DE (October—9, 1936), in Huerter, Deutsche Briefe, Bd. II, 9p. giE., pp. 107, 130, 204—205, 240, 405-406. 303 within the party the SS now represented the cause of Schmitt's party opponents, who were previously unable to confront Goering and Frank. Since the summer of 1936 the SS had conducted an extensive investigation of Carl Schmitt and prepared its case against him. There is little doubt that Schmitt was informed of the inner-party conspiracy against him and that this was the primary motivation for his preparation of a conference on the Jewish question. The fall of 1936 was full of intrigues by the SS to remove Schmitt from party offices counterbalanced with efforts by Schmitt to secure his own position. A wide— spread surveillance of Schmitt‘s activities by the SS revealed that he intended to strengthen himself within the party by gaining the sympathy of members close to Hitler. Allegedly with this in mind Schmitt had invited Gauleiter Julius Streicher to the conference on Jewry. The SS viewed the entire conference as an attempt by Schmitt to rehabilitate himself within National Social— 63 ism SS officials believed that Schmitt had further ambitions which involved his appointment as a state secretary when Hans Frank assumed the office of minister of justice.64 The SS not only made sure that the 63"Teilnahme des Gauleiters Streicher an einer Tagung von Carl Schmitt,“ SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. I, pp. 47-49. 64"Ernennung Franks zum Reichsjustizminister,“ Ibid., PP. 42—43. 304 exclusion of Schmitt was a precondition of Frank's appointment, but they urged Frank to remove Schmitt from his posts in the Academy of German Law. Under pressure from the SS Frank allowed Schmitt to be intentionally isolated within the Academy, thwarting Schmitt's ambitions in that organization by the end of November.65 Frank assumed that Schmitt would retain his direc— torship of the University Teachers Group in the Nazi Jurists' Association. As early as January 1936, however, the SS had already suggested that Frank replace Schmitt as director of the Teachers Group with a true National Socialist. Further pressure from the SS and other Schmitt opponents forced Frank to prepare for Schmitt's 66 removal from that office by the end of 1936. In a last attempt to secure his party standing Schmitt wrote 65"Ausschaltung Carl Schmitts aus der Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht," Ibid., Bd. I, pp. 90, 96-98, 112-113. 66George Schwab, The Challenge, op. cit., p.138, stated that Schmitt resigned this office— willingly after the Jurist conference in November 1936 when he realized the conflict between his own anti—semitic remarks and the biological racism of the Nazis. But despite this dif— ference, which Schmitt certainly recognized earlier, he desired to continue working with the Nazis and it was actually the Nazis who rejected him and forced him from office. See: Reinhard Hoehn to Koelnische Zeitung, October 16, 1936, Vermerken Hoehn, October 20, 1936, October 25, 1936, October 26, 1936, Hoehn, "Besprechung mit Reichsminister Frank nach der Tagung des Polizeirechts— ausschusses, October 24, 1936, “Bericht: Staatsrat Carl Schmitt," and Professor Eckhardt to Hans Frank, January 24, 1936, Ibid., Bd. I, pp. 66, 80-83, 99—101, 110, Bd. II, pp. 126, 215. 305 directly to Himmler on December 2, describing the extensive work of his Teachers Group in purging Judaism from German law. Schmitt informed Himmler that his group was prepared for any cooperation in the struggle against Judaism.67 Schmitt's final plea came too late and the following day the SS publicly attacked Schmitt for the first time in their paper Das Schwarze Korps. This first public attack was rather mild and directed mainly against an article lauding Schmitt written by Guenther Krauss, one of his former students.68 A second article which appeared in the SS organ the following week actually signaled the end of Schmitt's Nazi career. The SS arguments against Schmitt were those printed for the last two years in Deutsche Briefe. Schmitt was essentially a Catholic thinker, and had joined the party out of oppor— tunism. His past personal relationship to Jews and his reliance on Jewish scholarship was not hidden by his recently acquired anti-semitism. The SS noted that con- trary to the Nazi doctrine of race Schmitt had stated in his early work Nordlicht, that "the entire romanticism of racial teaching is based upon similar, namely 67Carl Schmitt to Heinrich Himmler, December 2, 1936, Ibid., Bd. II, p. 125. "Ein peinliche Ehrenrettung," Das Schwarze Korps, Folge 49 (December 3, 1936), p. 14. 306 morphological speculations . . . ."69 The reliance of the SS on these arguments was due mainly to the fact that they had as yet not compiled their own documented reports about Schmitt's past works and activities. These docu- mented reports were only completed after the public attack on Schmitt. That public attack was obviously not the end of the SS concern with Schmitt. Up to this time the SS had been merely gathering a diffuse range of every possible piece of evidence against Schmitt. A decisive factor in this whole affair, and a point not mentioned in the news- paper articles on Schmitt, was that the SS considered Schmitt as an avowed opponent of their organization.70 To rid themselves of this adversary the SS had been working behind the scenes for months to destroy his stand— ing in the party. The forced resignation of his director- ship of the Teachers Group was just the beginning of the intended vilification of Schmitt.7l There existed a 69" . . - - 1" Es w1rd immer noch peinlicher. Das Schwarze Korps, Folge 50 (December 10, 1936), p. 2. 70"Aeusserungen Carl Schmitts ueber die Arbeit der SS," SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. I, pp. 35-36. 71"Reichsgruppe Hochschullehrer," Mitteilungens— blatt des National—Sozialistischen Rechtswahrerbundes, Jhg. 1936 (December 15, 1936), p. 248. "Carl Schmitt ausgeschieden aus den Aemtern des NS-Rechtswahrerbundes," Berliner Tageblatt, No. 602 (December 20, 1936). 307 general fear within the SS that now that the discrepancies between Schmitt's work on National Socialism and the actual Nazi Weltanschauung were exposed Schmitt was trying to secure himself through another method. Supposedly, Schmitt planned to move into the field of international law so as to avoid his complete scholarly isolation.72 Consequently, the SS would be satisfied with nothing less than the complete exposure of Schmitt's disloyalty and probably eventually his elimination. To fulfill this goal the SS began in mid—December 1936, immediately procuring a collection of Schmitt's works and further personal evidence on which to base their case. 73 The result was two extensive reports finished 74 early in 1937. According to these reports, older Nazi party members had opposed Schmitt as early as 1933, but his true political position was first exposed by the foreign emigre press, which used him as an opportunity to ‘72"Besprechung ueber Carl Schmitt, November 4, 1936," "Bericht Staatsrat Carl Schmitt,“ SA Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. I, pp. 84—87, 99—101. 73"Schriften von Carl Schmitt, December 14, 1936," SD Hauptamt to SD Oberabschnitt Sued, Munich, December 14, 1936, Telegram Braune SD Hauptamt to SD Oberabschnitt Elbe, Leipzig, December 14, 1936, SD Hauptamt to State secretary Lammer, ibid., Bd. II, pp. 132, 138, 140, 154. 74"Professor Carl Schmitt,“ and “Der Staats— rechtslehrer Prof. Dr. Carl Schmitt," Mitteilungen Zur Weltanschaulichen Lage, No. 1/3 (January 8, 1937), ibid., Bd. II, pp. 184-220, 266—281. 308 attack National Socialism.75 Aside from the problems of Jewry, Catholicism, and opportunism, most striking about the reports was the documentation of Schmitt's past anti— National Socialist activity. As the Kronjurist of the presidential system he advocated the constitutional repres— sion of National Socialism. The theory of the "equal chance" as embodied in his Legalitaet BBQ Legitimitaet was expressly intended to prevent the legal acquisition of 76 Such documentation of anti-Nazi power by the party. work wielded by the SS against most individuals in Nazi Germany usually meant at least imprisonment. When the critical articles appeared in Das Schwarze Korps it appeared that the end was near for Carl Schmitt. While his Nazi opponents lauded his final removal from party offices, the editors of Deutsche Briefe rejoiced at the fruits of their work.77 Regarding Schmitt's changing fortune they noted that so long as he served a purpose for National Socialism the Nazis could overlook his past; now 78 he was superfluous. Flaunting the fact that their journal had long exposed Schmitt's true nature, the 75"Professor Carl Schmitt," ibid., pp. 184-185. 76Ibid., pp. 194-203. 77Ibid., pp. 155, 161—168. 78"Der NS Kronjurist Carl Schmitt Als Mohr . . .," Deutsche Briefe (December 11, 1936), in Huerter, Deutsche Briefe, op. cit., pp. 489-491. 309 editors of Deutsche Briefe prematurely and wishfully pre- sented the alternatives for him as "emigration or a con— centration camp."79 But the SS reports were never made public and the attacks on Carl Schmitt soon ceased. In spite of the endangered position of Schmitt, the final consequence of the entire affair merely meant the end of his work within the party rather than the end of his professional career. The day after the second attack on Schmitt appeared, Hans Frank came to Schmitt's defense. In a protest letter to d'Alquen the editor of gas Schwarze Eggpg, Frank criticized these articles as a repetition of the hate propaganda which appeared in the Jewish emigre press.80 All of this propaganda, Frank claimed, was directed at destroying Schmitt's reputation and intellectual influence. If the editors were familiar with Carl Schmitt's work over the last three years for the goals of National Socialism, Frank said, these articles would never have appeared. In further protest Frank sent a copy of this letter to Himmler. 79"Die NS Treibjagd gegen NS Kronjuristen Carl Schmitt hat eingesetzt," Deutsche Briefe (December 18, 1936), and "Auf dem Wege in die Emigration oder ins Konzentrationslager?" Deutsche Briefe (December 24, 1936), ibid., pp. 498-499, 510. 80Hans Frank to Gunter d'Alquen, December 11, 1936, SD Hauptamt to SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. II, Pp. 128-129. 310 Frank lacked sufficient power within the party, however, to resist the wishes of the SS. Over the past few months he had gradually given in to the SS by removing Schmitt from party offices. His most recent concession was the forced resignation of Schmitt as editor of the Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung.81 When Himmler sided with Das Schwarze Korps, Frank's protest came to nothing.82 Only through the direct intervention of Hermann Goering were Schmitt's life and professorship spared. Like Frank, Goering was disturbed that a prominent figure with whom they had worked was now being publicly defamed. Further- more, as a Prussian State Counsellor Schmitt fell into Goering's party sphere of influence and thus had immunity guaranteed by Goering to all State Counsellors. Writing to d'Alquen, Goering stated that even if the content of the attack was factually correct the public injury to the reputation of Carl Schmitt was unjustified, because Goering could not tolerate the degradation of a personality that he himself had called to high public office.83 81Carl Schmitt, "Schlusswort des Herausgebers," and Hans Frank, "Zum Abschluss," Deutsche Juristen- ieitung, Jhg. 41, Heft 24 (December 15, 1936), pp. 1449— 456. 82Heinrich Himmler to Hans Frank, January 5, 1937, SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. II, p. 240. 3Hermann Goering to Gunter d'Alquen, December 21, 1936, ibid., p. 235. 311 Goering requested that the public attacks cease immedi— ately. No doubt Goering and Himmler agreed upon some type of arrangement concerning the fate of Carl Schmitt. Fortunately for Schmitt, Goering jealously guarded the prerogatives of his allotted sphere within the Third Reich, and prided himself on his patronage of artists and intellectuals. Carefully watched by the SS for the dura— tion of the regime, Schmitt retained his professorship at the University of Berlin. The only official title Schmitt held thereafter was that of State Counsellor with its protection of immunity upheld by Goering, even though the Council was by this time a defunct organization that never assembled after 1936. Although he never again worked within the party or dealt with domestic politics Schmitt did fulfill his goal of handling problems of international law and politics in the latter stages of the Third Reich. For the second time the ideas of Carl Schmitt failed to influence politics as he had intended. Polit— ical leaders utilize ideas as instruments for their own ends and completely disregard those ideas which do not conveniently serve their immediate purposes. This was especially the case in totalitarian societies where ideas serve only the goals of the ruling party and the slightest deviance was not tolerated. In this respect Carl Schmitt‘s National Socialist career was doomed from the beginning. 312 His total support for the regime was not enough. The Nazis wanted his total ideological and intellectual con— formity and left no room for originality or intellectual activity outside the confines of party control. Carl Schmitt had Viewed the Nazis as a premature movement, which required further development of its theoretical legal and political foundations. The Nazis had absolutely no need for such assistance and rejected the interference of intellectuals in their organization. They willingly accepted his public support during the early stages of the regime because it gave their activities credibility at home and abroad. As soon as Schmitt attempted to have some real impact on developments in the Third Reich the fight to eliminate him began. Opportunism certainly played a role in Schmitt's activities, but far more important was his own belief that he could play the role of Kronjurist and establish a constitutional frame— work for the Nazis. The editors of Deutsche Briefe so aptly summed up Schmitt's predicament in 1936 with the pithy, "the Moor has done his duty, the Moor can go."84 84"Der NS Kronjurist Carl Schmitt als Mohr . . .," 9p. cit. CHAPTER VIII THE INTELLECTUAL IS BANISHED: CARL SCHMITT AFTER 1936 The SS affair had once again placed Carl Schmitt in a quandry. Terrified by his adverse change of fortune the former Kronjurist wondered about the possible alter— natives of emigration or a concentration camp. Not wanting to play into the hands of the SS, Schmitt in the end never attempted to emigrate. The renowned advocate of Decision- ism was unable to decide on an immediate course of action. Instead he hesitated and anxiously awaited the decision of the Nazis. Fortunately the matter was settled to his relative advantage. But he now suffered the fate of the intellectual in a totalitarian society. No longer requiring the services of his intellect, the Third Reich still demanded his absolute allegiance and complete con— formity of thought. Numerous German intellectuals, similarly disillusioned with the Nazi regime, entered a state of "inner-emigration“ and avoided public issues by 1 escaping into esoteric areas of scholarship. At first Schmitt attempted to follow this path. When the SS lRinger, German Mandarins, gp. cit., pp. 442—443. 313 314 ceased their attacks on him, a relieved yet suspicious Schmitt withdrew from public life. Eventually, he proved incapable of overcoming the difficulties facing a pro— fessor of public and international law who seeks to avoid contemporary legal and political issues. After 1936 Schmitt completely ended his work within the party. Never again did he provide legal or political advice for Nazi officials or institutions. Schmitt never met with Goering after 1936 and even his association with his friend Hans Frank was limited to a few brief encounters in the years that followed.2 Domestic politics never again served as a topic for his work. Taking refuge in his professorial duties at the University of Berlin, Schmitt no longer received any public attention, though he occasionally delivered lectures to scholarly groups. The Kronjurist passed quickly into obscurity. Before 1936 Schmitt had found little difficulty in justifying the authority of the Nazis to enforce their will at the expense of Jews, liberals, socialists, and other heterogeneous elements. He rationalized his support partially on the grounds that once a strong authoritarian state was established individual citizens would be allowed to fulfill their private lives within the security of this 2Carl Schmitt, "Wieweit haben Sie die theoretische Untermauerung der Hitlerschen Grossraumpolitik gefoedert?" Carl Schmitt—Personal Papers, I, pp. cit., p. 2. 315 strong state. With his own life now threatened Carl Schmitt finally faced the reality of Nazi totalitarian control which tolerated no private sphere. The basic function he had assigned to the state, that is, to provide for the security of its citizens, appeared absent, as the arbitrariness of the party finally affected him. Beginning with a 1937 work on Thomas Hobbes, Carl Schmitt started to express disillusionment with the totalitarian nature of the Nazi regime. Still fearing for his safety, Schmitt would never criticize the Nazis directly; but, unmistakably, the Nazi state was the real object of his critique. Schmitt would cloak his dis— satisfaction with Nazi totalitarianism in scholarly erudition concerning Hobbes and the problem of the Leviathan. For Hobbes, like Schmitt, the highest and most important goal of the state was to secure the physical existence of its citizens.3 Schmitt argued that, for centuries, writers had incorrectly Viewed Hobbes as the representative of the type of absolute state that western democracies understand as totalitarianism. This gross 3These views were first expressed by Schmitt early in 1937 in an article entitled, "Der Staat als Mechanism bei Hobbes und Descartes," Archiv fuer Rechts— 2nd Sozialphilosophie, Bd. 30 (1936/1937), PP. 622-632, which he later expanded into, Der Leviathan i3 deg Staatslehre ggg Thomas Hobbes: Sinn gig Fehlschlag eines Politischen Symbols (Hamburg, 1938), p. 55. Citations are to this later edition. 316 misinterpretation was completely inconsistent with Hobbes' philosophy of the state and the relationship between pro— tection and obedience. It would be ridiculous, Schmitt wrote, for the poor human individual, out of total fear of the state of nature, to flee into the total control of a Golem or Moloch.4 "The state machine functions or it does not function. In the first case it guarantees me the security of my physical existence; for this it demands unconditional obedience to the laws of its functions. All further discussions lead into a 'pre-stately' condition of insecurity, in which one's physical life is no longer secure." If the protection ceases, then the state itself also ceases to function and with it ends each obligation of obedience. At this point the individual once again wins his natural freedom.5 Nevertheless, Schmitt would never advocate or sup- port resistance to the Nazis. Like Hobbes, he believed that resistance to the power of the state would be a fruitless absurdity, since the state monopolized the means to destroy any resistance. And this power was more dis- tinct in the totalitarian Nazi state. If the state did not possess this irresistible power it could not maintain peace and security, and civil war or rebellion would occur. 4Ibid., pp. 111—112. 5Ibid., pp. 69, 113. 317 Under these conditions of conflict a state of nature would exist and mark the end of the state.6 Thus, Schmitt felt himself in the precarious position of the individual whose existence is no longer entirely secured by the state and yet to whom resistance appears hopeless. As the momentary danger to his life represented by the SS passed, the state did reward Schmitt's obedience and acquiescence with the preservation of his life. There also existed a limitation on the extent of Schmitt's inner—emigration. Although he attempted to avoid further confrontations with the party and to keep himself out of the public eye, Schmitt still wanted to retain his reputation within the academic and legal pro— fession. He hoped to accomplish this by turning away from the problems of Nazi ideology and domestic politics in order to concentrate on international law and politics. Excluding his Hobbes studies, each of his publications between 1937 and 1945 dealt with international politics. Contrary to his expectations Schmitt would experience some undesirable problems with the Nazis in this area. The Nazis were turning their attention to foreign affairs and consequently international politics emerged as a highly significant public issue. To write on international politics without acknowledging recent developments in ‘vm . =3 318 European foreign affairs was an impossible task for Schmitt. His own mode of thought precluded theoretical abstractions in favor of analyzing problems in terms of a concrete existing situation. Throughout his life Schmitt had displayed a special talent for quickly recognizing the emerging political issues of a period, and he had directed most of his writings at such contemporary issues. As he had done in the past Schmitt now attempted to main— tain the attention of the academic community by addressing himself to the relevant problems then facing Germany. What he had not anticipated was renewed public attention and future confrontations with Nazi theorists. Even the institutions which still offered Schmitt an opportunity for his scholarly productivity provided no sanctuary. One of his most ardent opponents, professor Reinhard Hoehn, replaced Rudolf Smend in the law faculty at the University of Berlin after the Nazi seizure of power. As an SS officer and friend of Himmler, Hoehn wielded considerable power and influence at Berlin. Hoehn's involvement in the 1936 SS investigation and attack on Schmitt created a good deal of tension between the two 7 Despite his pretentions, Hoehn's intellectual professors. capacities never approximated the brilliance of Schmitt, further aggravating the tension. At this time the two 7Reports and correspondence of Reinhard Hoehn, SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. I, pp. 66, 80—83. 319 professors never spoke to each other. Hoehn served as director of the Institute for Government Research since its transfer from Kiel to the Berlin law faculty in November 1935.8 Under his leadership the institute pro- moted the development of a completely new foundation for National Socialist constitutional and administrative law.9 This was the arena Schmitt had originally hoped to dominate by playing the role of Kronjurist. After 1936 he conceded this position to true Nazis like Hoehn. Aside from personal animosity the theoretical approaches of both professors conflicted. Underlying Schmitt‘s thinking was the concept of the state as a con— crete existing political unit and order. Hoehn, on the other hand, remained committed to the Nazi voelkisch ideology. At least in theory, the Volk was the primary pillar of the Nazi system and all other aspects of the movement emanated from this source. For the Nazis the Volk represented far more than the people or the nation, it was an organically developed racial community. Each Volk had its own identity, nature, and vital life source out of which grew all culture and institutions, including the state. As a part of this organic community the 8Institut fuer Staatsforschung, Ministerium fuer Wissenschaft, Kunst und Volksbildung, Geheimes Staats— archiv, Berlin, Rep. 76, No. 46, “Universitaet Berlin," p. 160. 9 Ibid-, pp. 258—260. 320 individual had significance only in so far as he was inte- grated into the whole. The state, whose purpose it was to preserve the existence of the Volk, was constantly omni- present in all areas of society, allowing no private sphere for the individual. SS members like Hoehn stressed the biological makeup of each Volk as the factor that determined the essence and unity of the racial community. This entire approach contrasted sharply with the Schmittian theory of the state. Schmitt never conceived of the state in racial terms, his second wife Duschka Todorovitsch, in fact, was of Serbian origin and hardly a member of the aryan master Volk. His state presupposed the distinction between private and public spheres of life. Furthermore, the Schmittian authoritarian state was relatively static, with stability as paramount, as compared to the dynamism of the Nazi state. At the University of Berlin Schmitt attracted the traditional conservative and nationalist students, with the voelkisch and racially oriented students following the Nazi line of Hoehn. To protect himself Schmitt never meddled in political controversies and referred students with questions concerning domestic politics to his SS colleague. It was under these closely scrutinized and tense conditions that Schmitt was forced to pursue his academic career in the latter years of the Third Reich. 321 The Nazis also forced Schmitt to operate under similar conditions in the Academy of German Law. By the end of 1936 the SS had gained control over several impor— tant committees in the Academy and succeeded in eliminating Schmitt from official positions. Another ardent opponent of Schmitt's, professor Otto Koellreutter, who had launched the first public attack on Schmitt, continued to advance his campaign against Schmitt in the Academy.10 Only with the assistance of his friends in the Academy such as Werner Weber, and only so long as he remained unobtrusive and in the background, was Schmitt allowed to continue his connection with that institution. In this manner he continued to attend conferences and publish articles in the Academy's journals.ll At the Academy Schmitt still remained reluctant to become involved in any facet of domestic politics, especially if it involved constitutional questions, or would lead to the slightest 12 confrontation. Instead he concentrated on the problems 10Otto Koellreutter to Werner Weber, May 28, 1937, Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, BA, R—61, No. 78, "Rechtsforschung." Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, ibid., Nos. 64, 11 78, 80, 84, 88, 109, and Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, Records of Nazi Cultural and Research Institutes, U.S. National Archives, No. T—82, Roll-23, Serial—28, Reel— 806, and Roll—24, Serial-29, Reel—807. 2Werner Weber to Freytagh—Loringhoven, October 9, 1937, and Freytagh—Loringhoven to Werner Weber, October 12, 1937, BA, R—6l, No. 80. 322 of international relations, where he hoped his strong nationalism and his power—political approach would prove more compatible with the position of the National Socialists. But with regard to international relations Schmitt still declined to deliver his works as lectures to the Academy, and he did not take part in discussions during the conferences he attended. Before his fall in 1936 Schmitt had taken an interest in the changing course of international relations. He was gratified that the Versailles system and the League of Nations were weakening, and that Germany was finally escaping from the oppression of the Diktat. Schmitt wholeheartedly supported the repudiation of the military clauses of Versailles and the remilitarization of the Rhineland.13 He was fascinated by the fact that the world was entering into a new phase of international conflict exposing the futility of the League. The Italian affair in Abyssinia and the outbreak of the civil war in Spain drew his immediate attention. In pursuit of this interest Schmitt intended to organize an Institute for International Law in conjunction with the Italian pro— fessor Costa Magna, a close friend of Mussolini's.l4 13Carl Schmitt, "Sprengung der Locarno—Gemeinschaft durch Einschaltung der Sowjets," Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung, Jhg. 41, Heft 6 (March 15, 1936), pp. 337—341. l4"Bericht: Staatsrat Carl Schmitt," SD Hauptamt, AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Bd. I, pp. 99-101, 114—115. 323 Although this never materialized Schmitt did continue writing on various aspects of international politics. Between 1937 and 1939 he concentrated essentially on the concept of war and the reaction of the League to the world crisis.15 These works were distinctly academic and scholarly, though of a timely nature. Neither the Nazis nor the public in general took any note of his work; out- side the German academic world Schmitt lived for two years in obscurity. Until 1939 Schmitt approached international rela— tions from the standpoint of the traditional state system, of competing sovereign states. He had already realized in 1937 that significant changes were occurring in the tradi— tional state system and that the existing system of international politics was at its end; but at this point he had no indication of what new system or order would replace it. Then Hitler began dismantling the existing state system in central and eastern Europe. In a speech before the Reichstag on February 20, 1938 Hitler promised to protect German minorities outside the Reich. By mid— March the Nazis achieved the Anschluss with Austria and Hitler started preparations for his demands on Czechoslovakia. Subsequently, the Munich agreement of 15Carl Schmitt, gig Wendung EBB diskriminierenden Kriegsbegriff (Munich, 1938), and "Ueber das Verhaeltnis der Begriffe Krieg und Feind (1938)," Positionen und Begriffe, gp. git., Pp. 244-251. _—— 324 September 1938, which ceded the Sudetenland to Germany, was violated by Hitler's occupation of Bohemia and Moravia on March 15, 1939. The pattern for Germany's further expansion and hegemony in central and eastern Europe was now clear. For Carl Schmitt it signified the introduction of a new concept into international law and politics to replace the defunct state system. It was the concept of Grossraum. The notion of Raum (space) had been a widely dis— cussed topic among German political theorists for over two decades. In a general sense the concept of Raum was already inherent in the Mitteleuropa theories of Friedrich Naumann and others, so popular during World War I. Raum theory was first established as an acceptable field of study when in the twenties it became an integral part of the developing science of geo-politics. The adherents of the geo-political school emphasized the influence of geography on politics, particularly concerning economic and strategic considerations. Naturally the type and size of a Raum was a crucial factor in any geo—political study. The leading proponent of this new science was Karl Haushofer who, as a professor of geo—politics at the University of Munich, founded the Zeitschrift fuer Geopolitik in 1924. Under his sponsorship the field grew in importance until it acquired a good deal of respecta— bility among German academicians. Those receptive to 325 geo-political ideas also included liberals such as Adolf Grabowsky, a professor at the Hochschule fuer Politik, who clearly acknowledged the significance of concepts like Raum in understanding politics.16 But Haushofer's intentions went far beyond these legitimate scholarly and theoretical pursuits; he wanted geo—politics to serve as the basis for a German expan- sionist policy. It was from Haushofer, the mentor of Rudolf Hess, that Hitler plagiarized the idea of Lebensraum.l7 At first Haushofer saw Lebensraum in terms of the right of a country to acquire territory commen- surate with the needs of its population. After the Nazis assumed power he directed the Institute for Geo-politics and began mouthing the National Socialist doctrine of 18 biological racism as a counterpart to Lebensraum. In l6Adolf Grabowsky, "Staatserkenntnis durch raeum— liches Denken," in Politik als Wissenschaft: Zehn Jahre Deutsche Hochschule fuer Politik, ed., Ernst Jaeckh (Berlin, 1931), pp. 34—54, and Politik (Berlin, 1932), pp. 30, 45. 17Norman Rich, Hitler's War Aims: Ideology, the Nazi State, and the Course of Expansion (New York, 1973), 18See: Karl Haushofer, Weltpolitik von heute (Berlin, 1935), especially the sections on face, pp. 211- 215, and Macht und Erde: III, Raumueberwindende Maechte (Leipzig/Berlin, 1934), ed., Karl Haushofer. His son, who was shot for his involvement in the conservative resistance to Hitler, also wrote extensively on Raum theory and geo— politics. See: Albrecht Haushofer, £33 Problematik des Raumbegriffs (Heidelberg/Berlin, 1935), and Allgemeine— politische Geographie upd_Geopolitik (Heidelberg, 1944). 326 doing so he distorted the promising and quite reputable science of geo—politics. Thus, Schmitt's audience was well prepared when on April 1, a few weeks after Hitler's Reichstag speech, he first presented his own concept of Grossraum at a lecture before the Institute for Politics and International Law at Kiel University. With this work he hoped to introduce the concept of Grossraum as a principle in the science of 19 international law. In this respect Schmitt's ideas fell into the tradition of Raum studies promoted by respected German scholars since the twenties, and to whom he owed an intellectual debt. He dissociated his concept from the Haushofer school because for him geo-political concerns alone, though significant, constituted no distinct polit— 20 Similarly, ical order and, therefore, no Grossraum. Grossraum was not synonymous with Lebensraum, or as Schmitt called it the "demographic right" of a stronger nation with an expanding population to make territorial 21 demands. Many of the nonracial aspects of these demographic and geo-political concepts were closely 19Carl Schmitt, Voelkerrechtliche Grossraumordnunq mit Interventionsverbot fuer raumfremde Maechte: zum Reichsbegriff im_Voelkerrecht (Berlin, 1939), p. 8. 2°Ibia., pp- 13-16. 211bid., p. 16. 327 connected with the idea of Mitteleuropa, which he also distinguished from Grossraum.22 Schmitt viewed a "political idea" as the essential element in a Grossraum and that "political idea" could never be separated from a concrete existing Raum. Each Raum must have a distinct "political idea" which, carried by a distinct nation, always has a specific opponent in mind. In essence, that "political idea" would be based on the distinction of friend and enemy. He selected the American Monroe Doctrine as the precedent case for his theory. The major part of the Monroe Doctrine he adopted . . . . 23 was the nonintervention of foreign powers in a Raum. Schmitt stated that the originators of the Monroe Doctrine saw their enemy in the form of the European monarchical— dynastic principle of legitimacy, on whose behalf European powers claimed the right of intervention. America carried the political idea of free and independent states opposed to the interventionism of the European system.24 Now, the western democracies, which used liberal—democratic and capitalistic legitimacy principles to maintain the status quo, were in the same situation as the former members of 22Carl Schmitt, "Reich und Raum: Elemente eines neuen Voelkerrechts," Zeitschrift der Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, Jhg. 7, Heft 13 (July 1, 1940), p. 201. 23 Carl Schmitt, Voelkerrechtliche Grossraumordnung, OP- cit., p. 23. 24 Ibid., pp. 33-36. 328 the Holy Alliance. Both Britain and the United States followed a policy of universalism which included the doctrine of intervention to introduce and protect its principles of legitimacy. Britain maintained this policy to protect its empire and to assure the status qgg. The United States since Theodore Roosevelt and Wilson had followed such a policy of universalism and intervention, although it opposed such intervention in its own hemis- phere or Raum.25 From Schmitt's point of view this system of uni— versalism and intervention was disintegrating under the emergence of a new Grossraum in central and eastern Europe. A central component of this Grossraum was the concept of Reich. A Reich served as the leading power in an area and as the carrier of a distinct political idea, and the Reich excluded intervention by foreign 26 powers in its Raum. The new political idea represented by the Reich was introduced with Hitler's assumption of the responsibility of protecting German minorities in central and eastern Europe. The protection of minorities existing under the universalism and interventionism of Versailles and the League was ended in this area of Europe. More precisely, the political idea represented by the 251bid., pp. 53—54. 26Ibid., p. 69. 329 Reich included uniting German minorities with the new German Reich, so as to assure their protection and at the same time assure the development of the national unity of the German people by preventing their assimilation into other national groups. Every national group in this area, German and non-German alike, would be allowed to live as individual national entities, though under German hegemony. And, in effect, the Reich would determine the future political order of this area, to the exclusion of foreign powers. Grossraum and Reich, however, were not synonymous, since not every state or national group within a Grossraum was a part of the Reich. The Reich was merely the dominating political unit in an area. Neither was the German Reich an empire, for empire usually presupposes universalism and assimilation of nations, and the Reich would supposedly respect the existence of each individual national group living side by side. Germany's Reich in the middle of Europe would stand between the universalistic and national assimilating liberal—democratic western powers and the universalism of the world revolutionary Bolshevik east. In this respect, the new concept of a concrete Grossraum took its place between the traditional concept of law between individual sovereign states and the concept of world universalism.27 27Ibid., pp. 70—71, 86-89. 330 No doubt the foreign policy successes of Hitler in central Europe had pleased Schmitt. For two decades his intense nationalism manifested itself in a harsh critique of Versailles and he was now elated over the reemergence of a strong Germany playing a new historic role. His life- long goal of a strong internally unified Germany capable of distinguishing friend and enemy, and overthrowing the burdens of the Diktat had become a reality. But it should not be construed that Schmitt advocated war or the Nazi expansion over all of Europe. His immediate concern involved the changes in central Europe and its effect on international law. Schmitt provided no predetermined theories or plans, rather he analyzed the changes that had already taken place in the concrete political situation. Only after the Nazis conquered most of Europe did Schmitt expand his theory from a central and eastern European centered Raum to a "continental European" Grossraum con— 28 cept. The essential problem in each case remained the same—-Grossraum versus universalism. One cannot deny that Schmitt attempted to justify German hegemony in Europe once that was an accomplished fact. The emphasis he placed on noninterventionism, for instance, was definitely related to the problem of 28Carl Schmitt, "Raum und Grossraum im Voelker— recht,“ Zeitschrift fuer Voelkerrecht, Bd. XXIV (1941), P. 168. 331 potential opposition that the Germans might face as a con- sequence of their recent foreign policy. When Schmitt first introduced his theory before the outbreak of the war he was obviously concerned with the possibility of British, French, or Russian intervention to counteract German moves in central Europe. During the early years of the war the decisive element became the potentiality of American intervention in the conflict. His perspective in these years was reminiscent of the Mitteleuropa pro— grams that followed the early German successes in World War I. Although reluctant to go to war in 1939 some con- servative nationalists, like Schmitt, were most willing to accept the fruits of victory and quickly turned their attention to the question of dealing with the newly acquired territories. As the war progressed Schmitt actually came to believe that the world was being divided into larger political units or Grossraeume. The United States, the British Empire, the Soviet Union, and the new Japanese Empire each had their spheres; it appeared that Germany's Raum would be Europe. That he tried to furnish some overall theoretical framework for this process is self—evident. This is not to say, however, that he provided the theoretical foundations for National Socialist expansion in Europe. Nazi foreign policy aims had been formulated long before he had begun to deal with Raum theory, and 332 his work quickly came under sharp criticism from the National Socialists. As the Nazis pointed out, his theory was nothing more than a general concept containing no description of the actual internal nature or precise political order of the Grossraum. Schmitt simply intro- duced a new idea into international law which he believed conformed to the reality of the newly developed concrete situation in Europe. The further refinement of the theory was a future goal he set for German legal and political science. The actual theoretical foundations of Hitler's expansionary policies stemmed from other sources, and for the most part from the Nazi racial doctrine of Lebensraum. This doctrine had already existed in Mein Kampf and had been expanded by Nazi racial theorists like Rosenberg; it received considerable reinforcement from the Nazified geo-political school of Haushofer. Most important for the Nazis was always the biological concept of race and the eventual hegemony of the Germanic or aryan race in Europe. Although he mentioned national groups, Schmitt's theory never encompassed any form of biological racism. And he had disregarded Lebensraum as the essential element of Grossraum when he distinguished his concept from that of the theory of “demographic rights" to territory, albeit he would never criticize openly, or even handle, the 333 Nazi doctrine of Lebensraum. He had intentionally avoided dealing with any Nazi theories since his rebuke in 1936. Considering his public isolation over the past two years Schmitt never expected his theory to attract any attention outside academic circles. In his usual style he had selected a timely theme for his lecture at Kiel, with no idea that it would once again bring his name into the public arena. As it turned out Schmitt's lecture appeared so relevant that several German newspapers, including the prestigious Frankfurter Zeitung, published articles 29 With Hitler's describing his new Grossraum theory. recent territorial acquisitions still dominating the European scene, the foreign press also took note of Schmitt's theory. Two British papers, the Times and the Daily Mail, presented Schmitt as the theorist behind Hitler's expansionary policy. On April 5, the Daily Mail reported that, "Herr Hitler and Professor Schmitt will now, it is believed, devote themselves to completing the framework of this conception, and the Fuehrer will soon give it to the world as his justification for Germany's 29"Das Reich im Voelkerrecht, Ein Vortrag Carl Schmitts in Kiel," Frankfurter Zeitung, No. 172 (April 3, 1939), "Grossraeumiges Denken. Professor Carl Schmitt sprach in Kiel," Deutsche Allgemeine Zeitung, No. 158 (April 3, 1939), Karl Heinz Bremer, "Voelkerordnung und Voelkerrecht. Arbeitstagung des Institutes fuer Politik und internationales Recht in Kiel," Muencher Neueste Nachtrichten, No. 116 (April 26, 1939). 334 relentless expansion."30 That report appeared verified when on April 28, Hitler spoke before the Reichstag and responded to President Roosevelt's message asking for guarantees against further aggression. In his reply Hitler referred Roosevelt to the Monroe Doctrine and stated that a similar doctrine applies to the interests 31 of the German Reich in Europe. Of course, the works of Carl Schmitt were unknown to Hitler. Probably one of Hitler's aides provided him with the idea of a European Monroe Doctrine then circulating in the press. Conse— quently, the concepts of a European Monroe Doctrine and Grossraum were to become a topic for discussion among German theorists until the end of the Third Reich. Owing to this publicity the Kiel Institute published Schmitt's lecture as a separate book which went through several editions, whereas every other conference lecture was 30The Times reported on April 5, 1939 that "Hitherto no German statesman has given a precise defini- tion of his aims in Eastern Europe, but perhaps a recent statement by Professor Carl Schmitt, a Nazi expert on constitutional law, may be taken as a trustworthy guide." The Daily Mail made similar claims when it noted that, "Herr Hitler's 'key' man in this policy is Professor Carl Schmitt, middle—aged and handsome, who is the leading international lawyer in Germany." See: Joseph Kaiser, "Europaeisches Grossraumdenken: Die Steigerung geschicht— licher Groessen als Rechtsproblem," in Epirrhosis: Festgabe fuer Carl Schmitt, 92. gig., pp. 538, 542. 31Ibid., p. 543, and Alan Bullock, Hitler, A Study in Tyranny (New York, 1964), pp. 500—503. 335 published in a collected work and received no further attention. Outwardly it appeared that Carl Schmitt had returned to the Nazi fold as their theorist of expansion. As Germany expanded throughout Europe the Schweizer Weltwoche compared Schmitt's role in Nazi Germany to that of Rousseau's for the French Revolution.32 In reality the intellectual had not returned to politics, and Schmitt's precarious position in Nazi Germany had not changed. The antagonisms between Schmitt and the party never lessened in intensity and there was never any attempt from either side to bridge the rift. After Hitler's speech of April 28, Schmitt received a phone call from Hans Frank who informed him that the Fuehrer prided himself on his originality, and warned Schmitt that he should remain silent about the true origins of the concept of a European Monroe Doctrine.33 Schmitt heeded this advice and made no effort to play again the role of Nazi Kronjurist. Carl Schmitt was still in the position of the intellectual in a totalitarian society whose intellectual capacities were no longer required. During a discussion with Ernst Juenger in Paris in the fall of 1941, Schmitt 32Schweizer Weltwoche (December 6, 1940), as cited in Kaiser, "Grossraumdenken," 9p. cit., p. 543. 33Schmitt Interview, November 22, 1972. 336 compared his own situation to that of Captain Cereno in Melville's novel Benito Cereno.34 In the novel Benito Cereno was a Spanish captain of a slave ship which, after a revolt, came under the control of black slaves. The slaves then forced Benito Cereno to sail the ship towards Senegal. During an encounter with an American ship the peculiar behavior of Benito Cereno was observed by the American captain. Unaware of the slave revolt the American could not understand the unusual behavior of Benito Cereno and the activity on board his ship, because the Spanish captain retained the outward appearance of still being in control of his vessel. Only after Benito Cereno escaped and explained that he was merely a figurehead controlled by the slaves did the American comprehend the affair. The myth of Benito Cereno was adopted by Schmitt to explain his own helpless situation after 1936. Contrary to the outward appearance he never had any control over the course of political events in Nazi Germany. Since the Fuehrer's proclamation of a European Monroe Doctrine, and particularly once the Germans had to administer the large European land mass they had conquered, Grossraum became an attractive concept to many writers.35 34Ernst Juenger, Strahlungen I (Munich, 1964), p. 65. 35Carlo Costamagna, "Autarkie und Ethnarkie in der Voelker— und Staatsrechtslehre der Neuordnung," Zeitschrift der Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, Jhg. 8, Heft l3 337 The main problem with Schmitt's theory from the point of view of Nazi theorists was its nonracial nature and the fact that it neglected the idea of Lebensraum. Nonethe- less, several racially oriented Nazi theorists found the concept useful and around 1940 began working on the theory of a "Biological Monroe Doctrine." The leading exponents of this doctrine were Werner Daitz, a former associate of Rosenberg, Dr. Werner Best, former legal adviser to Hitler and the Gestapo legal expert who later became Reich plenipotentiary ruler of Denmark, and Schmitt's SS opponent at the University of Berlin, Reinhard Hoehn. Beginning in 1941 Best and Hoehn co—edited a new journal entitled Reich, Volksordnung, Lebensraum to develop further the theory of a biological Grossraum. Using Schmitt's concept as a point of departure these theorists proceeded to criticize his work for its abstractness, and its lack of substance and racial content. They attempted to remove the inadequacies of the theory by remolding it into a program for racial order and rule (July 1, 1941), pp. 201-203, Hermann Jahrreiss, "Wandlung der Weltordnung: Zugleich eine Auseinandersetzung mit der Voelkerrechtslehre von Carl Schmitt," Zeitschrift fuer oeffentliches Recht, Bd. XXI (1941), pp. 513—536, Gustav Schmoller, "Der voelkerrechtliche Status der Vereinigten Staaten nach Inkrafttreten des Englandshilfegesetzes," Zeitschrift der Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, Jhg. 8, Heft 10 (May—15, 1941), pp. 153-155, Ernst Wolgast, "Grossraum und Reich: Bemerkungen zur Schrift Carl Schmitts: 'V0elkerrechtliche Grossraumordnung," Zeitschrift fuer oeffentliches Recht, Bd. XXI (1941), pp. 20-31. 338 36 in Nazi occupied Europe. Never straying from the official Nazi ideology they tried to present "Grossraum as 37 Lebensraum." Hoehn initiated a program at his Institute for Government Research in Berlin to study the problems 38 For similar purposes of Grossraum administration. Daitz helped organize the Society for European Economic Planning and Grossraum Economy in 1941. Daitz, like other Nazi theorists, believed that "the coming order-principle of the world, therefore, will consist of the proclamation "39 These beliefs and of biological Monroe Doctrines. programs never materialized and Grossraum order never extended beyond this small group of theorists and this brief theoretical stage. 36Werner Best, "Voelkische Grossraumordnung," Deutsches Recht, Jhg. 10, Heft 25 (June 22, 1940), pp. 1006-1007, Roger Diener, "Reichsverfassung und Grossraum- verwaltung im Altertum," Reich, Volksordnung, Lebensraum: _—__——_—_—_._____.—_____ Bd. I, Jhg. I (1941), pp. 177-229, Guenther Kuechenhoff, "Grossraumgedanke und voelkische Idee im Recht," Zeitschrift fuer auslaendisches oeffentliches Recht und ______—___—_——_—________——___ Voelkerrecht, Bd. XII, No. I (September, 1944), pp. 34-82. 37Reinhard Hoehn, "Grossraumordnung und Voelkische Rechtsdenken," Reich, Volksordnung, Lebensraum, Bd. I, Jhg. I (1941), p. 287, Hans Spanner, "Grossraum und Reich: Bemerkungen zu Band I der Zeitschrift 'Reich, Volksordnung, Lebensraum," Zeitschrift fuer oeffentliches Recht, Bd. XXII (1942), p. 34. 38Institut fuer Staatsforschung, Geheimes Staatsarchiv, Rep-76, No. 46, pp. 339-341. 39Max Weinreich, Hitler's Professors: The Part of _._.__—...__ Scholarship 1p Germany's Crimes against the Jewish People (New York, 1946), p. 125. 339 Carl Schmitt continued to write and lecture on Grossraum and related topics until 1943. He never addressed himself to the problems the Nazi theorists saw in Grossraum, nor attempted to compromise his theory with Nazi racism. Although he published three articles in Das Reich, this did not signify a change in party policy 40 toward Schmitt. Goebbels had started Das Reich as a weekly in 1940 for purposes of psychological warfare. To strengthen public morale Goebbels utilized the talents of numerous writers from the inner—emigration such as the poet Oskar Loerke and the Christian writer Gertrude Lefort. Within party circles Schmitt was still considered as a representative of the most dangerous form of Catholicism, and condemned on ideological and political grounds.41 Even his Grossraum theory remained suspect by some Nazis and was considered to have only limited value.42 He still suffered the fate of the intellectual whose ideas are never accepted in pure form, but whose ideas, when useful 40Carl Schmitt, "Die Raumrevolution: Durch den Totalen Krieg zu einem totalen Frieden," Das Reich, No. 19 (September 29,1940), p. 3, "Das Meer gegen *das Land," No. 10 (March 9, 1941), pp. l7-18, "Beschleuniger wider Willen oder: Problematik der westlichen Hemisphere," (April 19, 1943). 41NSDAP, Beauftragte des Fuehrers fuer die Ueberwachung der qesamteng geistigen und weltanschaulichen Schulung und Erziehung der NSDAP, Reichsleitung (Zentral- registratur), Institut fuer Zeitgeschichte, Munich, MA—129/ 5, Rosenberg- Akten, 67, 50343. 42 Ibid., MA—129/3, Rosenberg-Akten, 62, 47566. 340 to others, are plagiarized and distorted for the propaganda and political needs of the moment. Since 1936 Schmitt lived in an atmosphere of insecurity, never knowing when he might be devoured by the fickle Leviathan he obeyed. In the end Goering's cherished immunity for his Counsellors sufficed. But Schmitt could never be sure. Isolated from his friends in the party he found little friendship in the circles of the inner— emigration. Mistrusted by all, he was too insincere for the party and too close to the party for others. Even among his closest friends he was viewed as politically unreliable. The Schmitt—Popitz relationship was a typical point. Schmitt had maintained a close personal friend~ ship with Johannes Popitz since 1929 and throughout the Third Reich. Socially both families were most intimately related, and in the midst of the Allied bombing of Berlin, Schmitt and Popitz sat together night after night in shelters discussing various subjects. When the Allies bombed Schmitt's home he moved in with the Popitz family 43 for a short period. During all of this time Popitz never allowed Schmitt to discover that he was working with the resistance. After the July 20, 1944 attempt to assassinate Hitler, Popitz was arrested, tried and hanged. Upon 43Schmitt Interview, November 22, 1972. 341 hearing the news of Popitz's arrest Schmitt sat silent, shocked at the fate of his friend and his own ignorance 44 He also feared that the Nazis of the entire affair. might perceive him as a party to the conspiracy, because of his closeness to Popitz. Subsequently, in his report to Hitler, Kaltenbrunner did mention Schmitt‘s name; but his life was not threatened. The aftermath of the July 20th incident merely caused Schmitt more anxiety and uncertainty. Popitz had broken the Hobbesian covenant of protection and obedience in resisting the all powerful Leviathan. Schmitt never disobeyed the Leviathan and it rewarded him with the protection of his physical existence. With the final collapse of the Third Reich sovereignty passed to the Allied victors, who would now distinguish the friend from the enemy. The Russians arrested, interrogated and released Schmitt. Unlike the Russians, who, Schmitt claimed, treated him as a gentle- man, the Americans later interned him for a year.45 Before the Americans arrested Schmitt, he wrote a Gutachten in which he challenged the legality of trying individuals on the grounds of conducting a war of 44Author's interview with Professor Heinrich Popitz, son of the former Prussian Finance Minister Johannes Popitz, Freiburg, March 20, 1973. 45Schmitt Interview, July 13, 1973. Schwab, The Challenge, op. cit., pp. 17-18. 342 aggression.46 War, for Schmitt, was a natural function and phenomenon of international politics. Since his earliest writings on the problem he had always rejected such concepts as just and unjust wars and wars of aggres— sion. He held this position mainly because the eternal problem of, Who decides? was never solved. He was real- istic enough to recognize, however, that political power now rested with the Allies who, as sovereigns, could decide legality and illegality, life and death. Owing to his notoriety and National Socialist career the legal section of the military governor's office took a special interest in Carl Schmitt. In March of 1947 the Americans sent Schmitt to Nuremberg as a potential war criminal. The Allied prosecutors believed that Schmitt, through his Grossraum theory, had involved himself in the planning of an aggressive war. After several weeks of questioning Schmitt in his cell, pro- secuting attorney Robert Kempner found no legal grounds for charging the theorist of legality. Like Benito Cereno, the Kronjurist had been merely a figurehead and had played no central role in the politics of the Third Reich. Never having been accused, Schmitt was released in two months. Consciously aware of his own precarious 46Carl Schmitt, "Das internationalrechtliche Verbrechen des Angriffskrieges und der Grundsatz 'nulla poena sine lege," unpublished Gutachten (August, 1945). 343 position Schmitt let it be known that he would withdraw "into the security of silence."47 Germany was in the process of another drastic political change and its future once again remained unknown. Schmitt had frequently lived through similar changes before, in the Revolution of 1918, in the Presidential System, and in the Nazi Revolution. Through this disruptive course of German history he often felt that his own life was endangered, as was the case during the Communist Revolution in Bavaria, and his disconcerting troubles with the Nazis in 1934, 1936, and 1944. Through- out the Second World War he had been pessimistic about Germany's future. With the end of the war he once again faced a new insecurity. Totally disillusioned and sus— picious, Schmitt did not return to Berlin. Instead he retreated to Walberberg, a Dominican Cloister between Bonn and Cologne. He fled back into the arms of the Catholic church, to which he once attributed the role of defender of western civilization and values. The intellectual brilliance of Schmitt could not be kept silent for long. While in Walberberg he already resumed his writing and after he left the Cloister he 47Author's personal interview with Robert M. W. Kempner, former attorney for the prosecution at Nuremberg, May 7, 1973. See also Robert M. W. Kempner, "Hat Profes- sor Carl Schmitt die Jugend vergiftet?" 22E Dritte Reich fig Kreuzverhoer (Munich, 1969). 344 anonymously published his first post—war works in its 48 journal. Since then he has published over forty works on various topics. His most recognized post-war work was Der Nomos der Erde im Voelkerrecht des Jus Publicum Europeam. Schmitt's Der Nomos had actually been started during the war and dealt with the development of the traditional state system in Europe and its final demise. He would never again make another attempt to involve himself in politics, though he would follow political developments with the utmost interest. His legacy as Kronjurist would plague him forever and, as a result of his past misadventures, his academic career was terminated. The life and work of Carl Schmitt was to become one of the most controversial subjects in twentieth— century German history. Recognition of his brilliance and originality was to be counterbalanced by critical attacks, moral indignation, and vilification of his thoughts and activity, often buttressed by a deep emotional hatred. After his short stay in Walberberg he moved to his birthplace in Plettenberg, where he resided ever since. Schmitt had not changed his basic method of analysis or thought, and he still prided himself on most of his 48Carl Schmitt, "Donoso Cortes in gesamteuropae— ischer Interpretation," Neue Ordnung, Jhg. 3, Heft I (1949), pp. 1-15, and "Francisco de Vitorio und die Geschichte seines Ruhmes," Neue Ordnung, Jhg. 3, Heft 4 (1949), pp. 289-313. Both articles appeared anonymously owing to Schmitt's immense unpopularity in the immediate post-war years. 345 political and legal writings. Following decades of post— war denunciation the publicity surrounding his eighty- fifth birthday on July 11, 1973, showed a changing attitude towards him. He was no longer condemned out- right; instead he was granted the benefit of the doubt and handled as a highly controversial thinker. Although com- forted by this changing attitude, Schmitt still viewed himself as the intellectual in exile, like Machiavelli and Hobbes, suffering the fate of the intellectual who dared address himself to contemporary political problems. Carl Schmitt calls his house, situated between the peace— ful mountains of the Sauerland, "San Casciano." Machiavelli lived at San Casciano while in exile after losing favor with the Medici family. EPILOGUE Carl Schmitt will probably continue to be a con— troversial subject, even after we clarify his ideas and bring to light the actual nature of his political activity. In a certain sense he is a very elusive figure. He wrote so much, and on such a variety of subjects, that differing interpretations of his ideas are an expected consequence. Because the career of this enigmatic thinker extended through four distinct political systems Schmitt's changing political loyalties further complicate the problem. Schmitt was a man of many different pasts. Gradually he alienated one political faction after another until no group would accept him as their own. During the early Republic he was hailed as a great Catholic thinker. By the end of Weimar the Center Party attacked him as the advocate of constitutional relativism and dictatorship. Shortly thereafter the German emigres criticized him for his role as the Kronjurist of the Third Reich. In turn the National Socialists condemned him as anti—Nazi and as a representative of the most dan- gerous form of political Catholicism. After the Second 346 347 World War the stigma of his National Socialist past would assure his isolation from public and academic life. A certain understanding of Schmitt's ideas and political behavior can be acquired by studying the inter- action between his basic political philosophy and the circumstances he confronted. At times, he was motivated by self-interest. Yet in most cases, sincere political convictions, and what he believed to be political realism, determined his position. Professor Ulrich Scheuner has suggested to this author that Carl Schmitt was a brilliant thinker who, though fascinated by the "aesthetics of power," remained unaware of the true functioning of power politics. Schmitt's fascination with the "aesthetics of power" was undoubtedly a counterpart to the almost obses- sive attention he paid to the actual workings of power politics. Few thinkers were so conscious of the harsh realities of political life as Schmitt, who had proudly declared himself Machiavelli's heir and proclaimed Thomas Hobbes as his intellectual brother. Although certainly not ignorant of the real workings of power politics, Schmitt's fault lay in his overestimation of his own potential political influence and importance. The keen Sense of political realism so characteristic of his writings, ideas, and instincts was counterbalanced by his own naive belief that, through his ideas and his advice to political leaders, he could influence political 348 developments as he desired. He failed to recognize that in the political arena his ideas would be used and dis- regarded at the convenience of the powerbrokers he served. Consequently, his political career led only to banishment. Like his intellectual predecessors, Machiavelli and Hobbes, Carl Schmitt became an object of contempt. B IBL IOGRAPHICAL ES SAY BIBLIOGRAPHICAL ESSAY The available information on Carl Schmitt provides a relatively accurate account of his ideas and activities. Not only are his ideas clearly expressed in a wealth of publications, but these works can be supplemented with documentation from public archives, personal interviews, and the information given to certain researchers by Schmitt himself. Nonetheless, the historian who attempts to acquire a comprehensive understanding of Schmitt will immediately encounter several difficulties. He will dis— cover that while he has a vast amount of source material at his disposal, on which he could base numerous studies, the sheer quantity of sources makes mastery of this sub— ject a long and demanding process. At the same time the historian will realize that he is deprived of one of the most crucial sources of information, namely Schmitt's personal papers, and until these papers are opened to scholars a final definitive study on the life and work of this perplexing jurist cannot be written. Carl Schmitt Interviews and Personal Papers Some of the most valuable sources utilized in the above study were my interviews and correspondence with 349 350 Carl Schmitt. For rarely are historians fortunate enough to confront and question directly the subject of their research, an experience that is both personally rewarding and academically fruitful. These interviews were con- ducted on November 22 and 23, 1972, and on July 13, 1973, a few days after Schmitt celebrated his eighty—fifth birthday. This personal access to Schmitt allowed me the opportunity to acquire insights into aspects of his person— ality and viewpoints that are not easily discernible from written records. He spoke freely on all topics, except the anti~semitic issue, clarifying his ideas and expounding upon his work and political behavior. Aside from providing important biographical and factual information, Schmitt also brought the Weimar and Nazi eras to life through his vivid depiction of historical personalities and situations. Of central importance to my research were his answers to specific questions concerning his actual political moti- vations and activities. I also relied upon the Schmitt interviews conducted by Dieter Groh and Klaus Figge in, "Zeitgenossen," Suedwestfunk, Zweite Program, 6 p.m., February 6, 1972, and by Ansgar Skriver in, "Hitlers Machtergreifung vor 40 Jahren im Gedaechtnis von heute: Eine zeitgeschichtliche Befragung," Westdeutscher Rundfunk, Hauptabteilung Politik, Zweite Program, 8:45 p.m., January 30, 1973, pp. 11, 12, l3, 18, 38. 351 Naturally this author was not so credulous as to accept Schmitt's explanations without critical evaluation. The problems of memory, bias, and an aging man's desire for vindication were considerations to which I paid special attention. Information that either appeared implausible or could not be supported by documentation was not included in this study. Although I did not have access to Schmitt's per— sonal files he did furnish me with some of his papers and others were provided by George Schwab of The City College of New York. These documents have not previously been examined by scholars and copies are in my possession. When combined with published works and archival documents these papers present a new perspective on Schmitt's life and activities and on the changing manner in which his work has been perceived over the decades. Several letters of the period 1929—1932 from Colonel Erich Marcks, State Secretary Zweigert, and Otto Meissner, clearly connect Schmitt with the Schleicher coterie, and show the use of his ideas by those involved in the presidential system. Another series of letters refutes Moritz Julius Bonn's explanation of Schmitt's transfer to Cologne University in 1932. Personal letters from Arnold Brecht, Theodor Heuss, and Franz Neumann also tend to present Schmitt in a dif- ferent light from the descriptions of him found in many secondary accounts. One interesting document is a letter 352 dated April 22, 1933 in which Martin Heidegger urges Schmitt to cooperate with the new regime. Schmitt also provided three sets of personal papers which contain his explanation of his affiliation with the Nazis. These are in the form of long written responses he made during the interrogations in his cell at Nuremberg in 1947, and they do not appear in any of the Nuremberg documents. Since he wrote these papers while incarcerated they must be weighed in light of his pre— carious situation as a potential war criminal. But when corroborated by other documents and our general knowledge of the Nazi experience they are an invaluable source. In the first set, "Beantwortung der Frage: Wieweit haben Sie die theoretische Untermauerung der Hitlerischen Gross— raumspolitik gefoerdert?" (Nuremberg, April 18, 1947), Schmitt disassociates himself from Nazi theories on foreign policy. The second set, "Beantwortung des Vorwurfs: Sie haben an der Vorbereitung den Angriffskrieges und der damit verbundenen Straftaten an entscheidender Stelle mitgewirkt," (Nuremberg, April 28, 1947), presents substantial infor— mation on his offices and activities in the Third Reich. As indicated by the third set, the Nuremberg prosecutors were quite interested in Schmitt's analysis of the Nazi regime. In, "Staatsrechtliche Bemerkungen zu der mir gestellten Frage: Die Stellung des Reichsministers und Chefs der Reichskanzlei," (Nuremberg, April 28, 1947), 353 Schmitt held that the Reich Ministers were responsible for their actions. He also provided the prosecutors with additional information on this subject, such as an expla- nation of "Warum sind die Staatssekretaere Hitler gefolgt?" (Only a part of this document was made available to me by Robert M. W. Kempner.) These sources are indicative of the type of infor— mation found in Schmitt's personal files. Once they are made available his papers will not only be an invaluable source for studying his own career but also for the Weimar and Nazi periods in general. Together with his corres— pondence with countless historical figures, two signifi- cant sources will be his extensive notebooks and the diary, now multivolume, which he has kept since before the First World War. Public and Archival Documents Of the accessible material on Schmitt the least utilized have been archival sources. Only two other authors, Lutz-Arwed Bentin and Heinrich Muth (cited below), have ever attempted to use these important docu- ments, and both relied upon a very limited part of this information. The general neglect of these sources can be attributed to the belief on the part of many German scholars that since Schmitt's real significance lies in the realm of theory and ideas one need only consult his published works. Furthermore, many German scholars have 354 expressed doubt that archival research would yield any new or significant information, an attitude reinforced by the fact that there existed no Schmitt Nachlass and his name was usually not mentioned in the archival indices. Part of the problem is that no single collection holds any sub— stantial amount of material directly concerning Schmitt. But by combining the few documents found in each collec- tion one begins to develop a perspective on Schmitt and his activities that is quite different from the estima- tions of him presented in works which are based solely on published materials. Archival Guides For a list of the various archives in Germany and Austria one should consult, Verzeichnis ger Archivare an deutschen End oesterreichischen Archiven, ed., Verein deutscher Archiv, 10 Ausgabe (Wiesbaden, 1968). The most valuable guides to archival documents related to Carl Schmitt and his times are: Hans Branig, Ruth Bliss, and Winfried Bliss, ed., Uebersicht ueber die Bestaende des Geheimen Staatsarchivs in Berlin-Dahlem, Teil I, Provinzial— BBQ Lokalbehoerden (Grote, 1966), and Teil II, Zentralbehoerden Andere Institutionen Sammlungen (Grote, 1967); Friedrich Facius, Hans Booms, and Heinz Boberbach, ed., Boppard, 1968); Wolfgang A. Mommsen, ed., Die Nachlaesse in den deutschen Archiven (Boppard, 1972); 355 der Bundesrepublik Deutschland (Boppard, 1969). Regarding the holdings in the German Democratic Republic one should refer to, H. Loetzke, ed., Uebersicht ueber die Bestaende deg Deutschen Zentralarchivs Potsdam (Berlin, 1957), and H. Herricht, "Die Nachlaesse im Deutschen Zentralarchiv II, Merseburg,“ in Archivmitteilungen, Jhg. 1954, No. 1, though both of these are certainly dated. Finally, no account of the documentation on this period would be complete without reference to the captured German war documents. The best guides to this material are: The American Historical Association Committee for the Study of War Documents, Guides to German Records Microfilmed at ___—____.—.________._ Human Resources Research Institute (Maxwell Air Force Base, Alabama, 1952), and Supplement to the Guide to the Captured German Documents (Washington, D.C., 1959). Koblenz The files of the Bundesarchiv in Koblenz are essential to any study of the Weimar and Nazi periods. An important source concerning Schmitt's political activity under the presidential system are the records of the Reichskanzlei, 1919—1933, R—43I: "Kabinettsbildung, 1932," 356 and "1933-35," Nos. 1309-1310; "Kabinettsprotokolle, Juli 1932—Sept. 1932," No. 1457; "Reichsverfassung, 1919-1926," and "1927-1933," Nos. 1864—1865; "Ermaechtigungsgesetz, 1923-1931," No. 1869; "Art. 48 der Reichsverfassung, 1924- 1930," No. 1870. Reichskanzlei, 1933-1945, R-43II, covers the Nazi era, with specific information on Schmitt in, "Reichsreform und Neugliederung des Reiches, 1933- 1934," No. 495; and "Gleichschaltung der Laender mit dem Reich," No. 1309. On the Nazi Prussian State Council see: R-43I, "Akten betreffend Preussischer Staatsrat," No. 2300. Additional material in the Bundesarchiv on Schmitt and the Weimar Republic includes: Stellvertreter deg Reichskanzlers, Vizekanzlei yen Papen, R—53, No. 77, Bd. 3, which holds some correspondence between Schmitt and Papen; Politisches Kolleg, R—118, provides an indication of the limited relationship of Schmitt to conservative revolu- tionary organizations; and on the case of Prussia versus Reich see: "Handakten Dr. D. Arian, Ministerialrat Verfassungsstreitsache der Laender Preussen, Baden und Bayern gegen das Deutsche Reich betr. Verordnung des Reichspraesidenten vom 20.7.1932 vor dem Staatsgerichtshof," Kleine Erwerbungen, No. 337-1. Relevant collections on the Nazi period are: Reichsministerium deg Innern— Staatssekretaer Pfundtner, R—18," "Reichsreform, 1933- 1934," No. 5436; Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, R—61, Nos. 64, 78, 80, 84, 88, 109, 208, parts of which show 357 Schmitt's difficulties with the Nazis; Reichsministerium fuer Wissenschaft, Erziehung und Volksbildung, 1934—45, R—21, No. 144, has some biographical information; see also, Hauptamt fuer Erzieher-Reichswaltung des Ngfi Lehrerbundes, NS-12, here the absence of any information on Schmitt is most interesting, considering that he headed the jurist section of the Lehrerbund. Several Nachlaesse in the Bundesarchiv are also pertinent to Schmitt and his times. Some previously neglected correspondence between Schmitt and Moritz Julius Bonn is contained in the Bonn Nachlass, Nos. 49, 50, 56. The Nachlass of Paul Silverberg, No. 417, has some information on Schmitt's position in 1932. An ori— ginal typed copy of Schmitt's ”Gutachten zu der Frage der Anwendung der Wahlordnung fuer das Saargebiet vom 29.IV. 1920 auf die Gemeinde Saarlouis-Roden," (1925), lies in the Richard Thoma Nachlass, No. 47. A strongly worded letter of November 11, 1931, in which Schmitt severely criticized the opponents of his constitutional teaching, is in the Nachlass of Friedrich Saemisch, No. 68. Although containing no direct information on Schmitt the following Nachlaesse and files provide a necessary background for understanding the presidential system and the events leading up to the end of Weimar: Wilhelm Freiherr von Gayl, especially Nos. 4, 7, 14, 31, 36—39, 43, 45; Koch— Weser, No. 40; Friedrich Sieling, Kleine Erwerbungen 484, 358 Nos. 1—2; Reichspraesident von Hindenburg an Dr. Friedrich von Berg, Kleine Erwerbungen 332—1; Praelat Ludwig Kaas, Kleine Erwerbungen 190, Nos. 2-3; Protokollentwurf ueber die Sitzung der Zentrumsfraktion des Reichstags vom 23.3.1933, Kleine Erwerbungen 44; Niederschrift des Reichstagsabgeordneten Dr. Hans Eugen Fabricius (NSDAP) betr. Ruecktritt der Regierung von Papen Fuehlungsnahme des Zentrums mit NSDAP, 17.11.1932, Kleine Erwerbungen 114; Albert Grzesinski, Kleine Erwerbungen 144; Erich Zweigert, Kleine Erwerbungen 279-2. On the Third Reich there is the Nachlass of Hans Frank, which holds no material on Schmitt, but clearly indicates how insignificant that Kronjurist was to Nazi legal theory and practice. Below is a short list of the files which hold nothing directly related to a study of Schmitt: Eduard Spranger, Heinrich Triepel, Hans Peters, Wilhelm Frick, Katherina Kardorff and Siegfried Kardorff. Munich The Institut fuer Zeitgeschichte in Munich has one of the best collections on National Socialism. In its archives is a copy of the SS file on Schmitt, "Sicherheitsdienst des RFSS SD Hauptamt (1936) P.A. 651C, Schmitt, Karl Dr. Prof," AKZ 4062/68, Fa 503, Nos. 1—2. This file is the most valuable unpublished source on Schmitt and his place in the Third Reich. Only recently discovered in the Wiener Library, London, this file has 359 not previously been exploited by Schmitt scholars. For the Nazi attitude towards Schmitt see also: Rosenberg Akten, 62, MA—129/3, 47566; 67, MA-129/5 50343; Rosenberg Akten (II), 76, MA-251 (22-23); NSDAP (III), 83, MA-603, 20363—20382; NSDAP (IV), 24, MA—ll63, 95620—95622. An important document on Schmitt and the Schleicher clique in 1932 is "Auszug des Botschafters a. D. Eugen Ott an den Sohn des Reichskanzlers a. D. v. Papen vom 26.12.1949." Schmitt's war record is located in the Bayerischen Hauptarchiv, Munich, Abt. II, Kriegsarchiv, "Kriegsstam- mrollen—22," No. 89. The Rihse Sammlung, a collection of newspaper articles and clippings from the Weimar and Nazi eras, has numerous articles on Schmitt not listed in the, standard bibliographies, and can also be found in the Kriegsarchiv. See: "Der allmaechte Staat, Ein Referat Prof. Schmitts vor dem Langnam—Verein," Berliner Tageblatt, No. 557 (November 24, 1932); "Die Studentenschaft an Professor Carl Schmitt," Koelnische Volkszeitung, No. 390 (July 21, 1933); "Carl Schmitt: Ein Lehrer der Politik und des revolutionaeren Staatsrechts," Muenchen N.N., No. 201 (July 25, 1933); "Vom Wesen der Politik," Frankfurter Zeitung, No. 673/75 (September 10, 1933); Carl Schmitt, "Richtertum und Politik," Bremer Nationalsozialistische Zeitung, No. 335 (December 11, 1933); "Staatsrat Prof. Carl Schmitt uebernimmt die herausgabe der Deutsche Juristen-Zeitung," Muenchen N.N., 360 No. 142 (May 28, 1934); "Gleichberechtigung und Voelker— recht, Staatsrat Prof. Dr. Carl Schmitt: Die innere Leere der auf Versailles beruhenden Voelkerbundsystems," Voelkischer Beobachter, No. 2021 (July 21, 1934). Berlin The Geheimes Staatsarchiv in Berlin has a few relevant documents on Schmitt. Noteworthy are the files of the Hochschule fuer Politik, Rep. 303, Nos. 168-169, 172-173, 181, 244, 246, 265, which show Schmitt's con— nection with that institution. Number 181 contains the original manuscript of his "Die neutralen Groessen im heutigen Verfassungsstaat,“ (1931). Rep. 90, Preussisches Staatsministerium, Akten Reichs- und Staatsbehoerden, Staatsrat, No. 13, has some information on the Nazi Prussian State Council. There are a few documents on Nazi Grossraum thought as expressed by Reinhard Hoehn in, Ministerium fuer Wissenschaft, Kunst und Volksbildung, Rep. 76, Universitaet Berlin, No. 46, Institut fuer Staatsforschung. The Nachlass of Wilhelm Drews, the incomplete portfolio of Johannes Popitz, and Rep. 77, Preussischen Ministerium deg Innern, contain nothing on Schmitt, though they are important for the Study of Prussian administrative and financial affairs. For research on Nazi party members the Document Center in Berlin could provide a wealth of material. Schmitt's party records are listed under various headings: 361 Personalakte (Sch—32), Party Records Central Munich, Party Records Gau Koeln-Aechen, NSD Dozentenbund- Reichsfachschaft I N.S. Lehrerbund. The file on Reinhard Hoehn presents an interesting case on the type of SS theorist that opposed Schmitt. Freiburg In the absence of any scholarly biography of the former chancellor and general, the incomplete Nachlass of Kurt von Schleicher in the Bundesarchiv-Militaerarchiv, Freiburg, is crucial to any research dealing with the presidential system. Although holding nothing specifically on Schmitt, the background material in this Nachlass directly relates to the issues he confronted, and it reveals a good deal about the type of political leaders with whom he associated. Bonn The archives of the University of Bonn have little on Schmitt. Only four letters concerning his appointment to that university remain in the archives of the law faculty, and these are insignificant. Schmitt‘s pre- World War I civil service record and a few letters are located in the Bundesministerium fuer Justiz, Bonn, Personal—Akten des Justizministerium, IIf., "Dr. Karl Schmitt 1915," Litt. S. No. 4590. While there is no information on Schmitt in the Archiv der Sozialen 362 Demokratie of the Friedrich Ebert Stiftung, the Nachlass of Karl Severing is useful for studying the Weimar left. Mappen 38, 63-68, deserve particular attention because they concern the SPD outlook on Article 48 and the case Prussia versus Reich, in which Severing was personally involved. Cologne Two Nachlaesse pertinent to any study of the Catholic Center Party and Weimar are those of Wilhelm Marx and Karl Bachem in the Stadtarchiv Cologne, but neither contains anything on Schmitt. The files on Schmitt at the University of Cologne are still closed. They could eventually shed some light on the controversy surrounding his academic appointment there and the removal of Kelsen shortly thereafter. Washington The microfilms of the captured German War Docu— ments in the U.S. National Archives provide an abundance of easily accessible material on the Nazi period. Schmitt's activities in the Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht are documented in the "Records of Nazi Cultural and Research Institutes," A.H.A. American Committee for the Study of War Documents, No. T-82, Roll—23, Serial—28, Reel—806, and No. T-82, Roll-24, Serial-29, Reel-807. 363 There are several sources of information, not available to this author, which could prove to be quite valuable to the study of Carl Schmitt. The following records in the Deutschen Zentralarchiv, Potsdam, could contribute to our knowledge of Schmitt's political involve- ments in Weimar and Nazi Germany: Praesidialkanzlei (06.01); Reichsministerium deg Innern (15.01), Abt. I, Verfassung, Verwaltung, Beamtentum; Reichsjustizministerium (30.01); §§2§EI Gliederungen Edd angeschlossenen Verbaende (53 NS—l) NSDAP—Dozentenbund; Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht. Equally important are the Nachlaesse of Waldemar Gurian (Notre Dame University), Johannes Popitz (family possession), and Wilhelm Stapel (family possession). Interviews This author found personal interviews with friends, critics, and students of Carl Schmitt to be very helpful in acquiring a balanced impression of his per- sonality and work, as well as of the controversy sur- rounding the man. These interviews expanded my knowledge beyond the written sources in such areas as biographical information, historical context, and particularly the intensity of feeling on various issues. The limitations of memory and bias were, of course, taken into account. Interviews included: George Schwab of the City College of New York, a close friend of Schmitt, who published the only book in English on the subject. Helmut Rumpf of 364 Bonn, who published extensively on Schmitt and was a close personal acquaintance of his since the thirties. Ulrich Scheuner, a prominent legal scholar at the University of Bonn who, though no close friend of Schmitt, was able to provide first hand knowledge of Schmitt's behavior and the attitude towards him during the thirties and forties. Ruediger Altmann, a former Schmitt student at the Univer— sity of Berlin, who recounted Schmitt's Nazi entangle— ments while at that institution. Robert M. W. Kempner, a harsh critic of Schmitt who served as a prosecuting attorney at Nuremberg and interrogated Schmitt in his cell for weeks. Heinrich Popitz, provided information on the relationship between Schmitt and his father the former Prussian Finance Minister Johannes Popitz and also related his recollections on Schmitt's attitude during the late Nazi years. Published Sources Carl Schmitt The most fundamental sources for scholarly research on Schmitt are still his extensive publications. Fortun- ately, references to most of the work by and about Schmitt have been compiled by the Belgian scholar Piet Tommissen and published in three exceptionally dependable bibliog- raphies: "Carl—Schmitt-Bibliographie," Festschrift fuer Carl Schmitt zum 70. Geburtstag, ed., Hans Barion (Berlin, 365 1959), pp. 273—330; "Ergaenzungsliste zur Carl-Schmitt— Bibliographie vom Jahre 1959," Epirrhosis: Festgabe fuer Carl Schmitt, ed., Hans Barion (Berlin, 1968), pp. 739- 778; Versuch einer Carl—Schmitt—Bibliographie (Duesseldorf, 1953). Since works on Schmitt are continually appearing Tommissen is currently preparing a revised edition of his bibliographies. Instead of duplicating Tommissen's present citations my bibliography will include only a limited list of the more important and the more recent publications used in this study. It should be noted that in the absence of a single collection of Schmitt's works the original editions of some of his major publications, and many of his articles, are often difficult to locate. A complete edition of his major works would be a most valuable contribution. Schmitt himself has published two minor collections, 1923—1939 (Hamburg, 1940), and Verfassungsrechtliche Aufsaetze aus den Jahren 1924—1954: Materialien zu einer Verfassungslehre (Berlin, 1958). The title and the content of each clearly reflects the differing periods in which they were released. Both the commentary and what is included and excluded from each collection reveals a good deal about Schmitt's changing predicament. The pre—World War I books of Schmitt mainly concern legal problems. He now considers these as merely 366 "stylistic exercises,“ but indications of his later Decisionism and political ideas are quite evident. See: Ueber Schuld und Schuldarten--Eine terminologische Untersuchung (Breslau, 1910), Gesetz und Urteil-—Eine Untersuchung zum Problem der Rechtspraxis (Berlin, 1912), Der Wert des Staates und die Bedeutung des Einzelnen (Tuebingen, 1914). Schmitt's Theodor Daueblers "Nordlicht“--Drei Studien ueber die Elemente den Geist Edd die Aktualitaet deg Werkes (Munich, 1916), shows his disenchantment with the war and the European intellectual climate. By far his most productive period was during the Weimar Republic. Politische Romantik (Munich, 1919), is a contentious interpretation of political romanticism that reflects the uncertainty Schmitt felt immediately after the war. Ede Diktatur—-yed deg Anfaengen deg modernen Souveraenitaetsgedankens bis zum proletarischen Klassen- kampf (Munich, 1921), established Schmitt's reputation as a political analyst and served as the foundation for much of his later work on dictatorship and Article 48. The second edition of Ede Diktatur (1928), includes an appendix on, "Die Diktatur des Reichspraesidenten nach Art. 48 der Weimarer Verfassung," which is his classic interpretation of the exceptional powers of the presi— dent. He presents his theory of Decisionism in, Politische Theologie—-Vier Kapitel zur Lehre von der 367 Souveraenitaet (Munich, 1922). Schmitt's partiality to the Catholic political and intellectual cause pervades his Roemischer Katholizismus und politische Form (Munich, 1925). The problems of Weimar parliamentary government and democracy are confronted in, Die geistesgeschichtliche Lage des heutigen Parlamentarismus (Munich, 1923), and Volksentscheid dgd‘Volksbegehren—-§dg Beitrag egg Auslegung deg Weimar Verfassung dgd egg gegge gee deg unmittelbaren Demokratie (Berlin, 1927). One of his greatest achievements, Verfassungslehre (Munich, 1928), is still regarded as a standard work on constitutionalism. It also presents the most systematized version of Schmitt's ideas concerning the Weimar constitution and the relationship between law and politics. In, Qeg Begriff deg Politischen (Berlin, 1928), he introduces the con- troversial definition of "political" as the distinction between friend and enemy, a concept essential to under— standing most of his work. Two of his more renowned books, Qeg Hueter deg Verfassung (Tuebingen, 1931), and Legalitaet Edd Legitimitaet (Munich, 1932), were written in defense of the presidential system. One of Schmitt's earliest acts of collaboration with the Third Reich involved the policy of Gleichschaltung between the states and the Reich, an issue he discusses in, Das Reichsstatthaltergesetz (Berlin, 1933). Examples of his unsuccessful attempts to provide 368 the National Socialists with a theoretical foundation are: Staat, Bewegun , Volk—-Die Dreigliederung der politischen Einheit (Hamburg, 1933), and Ueber die drei Arten des rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens (Hamburg, 1934). In the latter work he turns away from Decisionism and towards "Concrete Order" theory. For his unique approach to the problem of Grossraum, see Voelkerrechtliche Grossraum— ordnung mit Interventionsverbot fuer raumfremde Maechte-— dg Captivitate Salus--Erfahrungen der Zeit 1945/47 (Cologne, 1950), is a good introduction to Schmitt's personal sentiments immediately after World War II. He went a long way towards regaining his scholarly reputation with Qeg gemeg deg ggde dg Voelkerrecht deg deg Publicum Europaeum (Cologne, 1950), a classic work on the emergence and demise of the European state system. In, Theorie deg Partisanen—-Zwischenbemerkung egg Begriff deg Politischen (Berlin, 1963), Schmitt addresses the post—war phenomenon of guerilla warfare and national liberation. Major Interpretations The best introduction to the ideas of Carl Schmitt is George Schwab, Tee Challenge 9g £22 Exception: 52 Introduction to the Political Ideas of Carl Schmitt between 1921 and 1936 (Berlin, 1970). This survey has laid a solid foundation for a more comprehensive study. Hasso 369 Hofmann's Legitimitaet gegen Legalitaet: Der Weg der politischen Philosophie Carl Schmitts (Berlin, 1964), is a fairly accurate exposition of Schmitt's writings, but it is based solely upon published materials. Another effort at a comprehensive analysis of Schmitt's published works is Peter Schneider, Ausnahmezustand und Norm——Eine Studie egg Rechtslehre gee Egg; Schmitt (Stuttgart, 1957). Major distortions in Schneider's book result from his method of beginning with Schmitt's latest works and tracing his ideas back to his earliest ones without sufficient regard for varying contexts and periods. Unreliable is Juergen Fijalkowski, Die Wendung zum Fuehrerstaat: Ideologische Komponenten gg der politischen Philosophie Carl Schmitt (Cologne, 1958), which presents Schmitt as a consistent ideological advocate of totalitarianism who saw the frui— tion of his work in the Machtergreifung of Hitler. Two similar misinterpretations are: Christian Graf von Krockow, Die Entscheidung: Eine Untersuchung ueber Ernst Juenger, Carl Schmitt, Martin Heidegger (Stuttgart, 1958), and Karl Schultes, Qeg Niedergang deg staatsrechtlichen Denkens gg Faschismus: Qge Lehren deg Heggg Professor deg; Schmitt, Kronjurist deg Gegenrevolution (Weimar, 1947). One of the earliest books on Schmitt, which appeared while he was still in opposition to the Nazis, is equally misleading. For Heinrich Wohlgemuth in, Das Wesen des Politischen £2 der heutigen deutschen neoromantischen Staatslehre: Ein 370 methodenkritischer Beitrag gd seiner Begriffsbildung (Erlangen, 1932), compares Schmitt with Spengler and contends that Schmitt is a proponent of an irrational Lebensphilosophie. Wohlgemuth's book does contain a use— ful bibliography of all Schmitt's publications before 1932. Peter Paul Pattloch in, Recht als Einheit von Ordnung und Ortung: Ein Beitrag zum Rechtsbegriff £2 Carl Schmitts Nomos der Erde (Aschaffenburg, 1961), continues this tra- dition by relating Schmitt's legal concepts to the thoughts of Nietzsche. The most recent books on the subject are: Helmut und aktuelle Bedeutung mit einer Abhandlung ueber: Die Fruehschriften Carl Schmitts (Berlin, 1972), and Lutz— (Munich, 1972). The sections on Hobbes in Rumpf's work are weak, though he presents many thought provoking insights into Schmitt's ideas. Bentin merely reflects the standard anti-Schmitt bias without contributing anything new to our knowledge; his chapters on Popitz do provide some new information and are worth serious attention. Heinrich Muth, "Carl Schmitt in der deutschen Innenpolitik des Sommers 1932," Historische Zeitschrift, Beiheft 1, Beitraege zur Geschichte der Weimarer Republik (1971), pp. 75-147, is well researched and well written. But his entire argument is faulty because he mistakenly 371 assumes that Schmitt was a part of the Papen-Gayl-DNVP clique rather than an associate of Schleicher. An interest- ing article on Schmitt's outlook on the total state in the Third Reich is Martin Jaenicke, "Die 'Abgruendige Wissen— schaft' vom Leviathan zur Hobbes-Deutung Carl Schmitts im Dritten Reich," Zeitschrift fuer Politik, Jhg. 16, Heft 3 (September, 1969), pp. 401-415. George Schwab addresses the charge of Schmitt's opportunism in, "Carl Schmitt: Political Opportunist?" paper presented to the European Seminar of the Graduate Center of the City University of New York (March 7, 1973). Two critical analyses of the friend-enemy concept are: Mathias Schmitz, Qge Freund-Feggd Theorie gegl Schmitts: Entwurf dgd Entfaltung (Cologne, 1965), and Hasso Hofmann, "Feindschaft-—Grundbegriff des Politischen?" Zeitschrift fuer Politik, Jhg. 12, Heft 1 (February, 1965), pp. 17-39. Noteworthy also is the balanced and highly instructive article by Leo Strauss, "Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitts Begriff deg Politischen," Archiv gdeg Sozial— wissenschaft Edd Sozialpolitik, Band 67 (August-September, 1932), pp. 732—749. Journals and Newspapers The works of Carl Schmitt have been published, reviewed, and commented upon in over one-hundred-fifty different journals, newspapers, and reference books. Among the leading legal journals are: Archiv des ‘r*.——"‘:..f:‘ x/z—‘r'g’r‘l—rfiérrfi = 7»: “edit; .._.. m: ”.7 _7 ._ _- l l, 372 oeffentlichen Rechts, Archiv des Voelkerrechts, Archiv fuer Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, Archiv fuer Rechts- und Wirtschaftphilosophie, Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung, Deutsche Richterzeitung, Juristische Wochenschrift, Zeitschrift fuer die gesamte Staatswissenschaft, Zeit— schrift fuer die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, Zeitschrift fuer oeffentliches Recht, Zeitschrift fuer Voelkerrecht. For the literary, political and historical viewpoints of German intellectuals one should survey articles in such publications as Hochland, Kantstudien, Archiv fuer Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, Zeitschrift fuer politik, and Historische Zeitschrift. Relevant newspapers are: Berliner Tageblatt, Deutsche Allgemeine Zeitung, Frankfurter Zeitung, Germania, Koelnische Volkszeitung. During the fifties Christ und Welt carried numerous articles by and about Schmitt. The major journals of the conservative revolu- tionary movement are: Deutsches Volkstum, peg Kunstwart, peg Rgdg, Ede Egg, and Taegliche Rundschau. From the Nazi period there are: Deutsche Kolonial— zeitung, Deutsche Verwaltung (an organ of the Fachgruppe des Bundes National—Sozialistischer Deutscher Juristen), _—.—_~___——___.~—_——_—___—__—_—_ Deutsches Recht (the first Nazi legal journal), Monat— shefte fuer Auswaertige Politik, Raumforschung und Raumordnung, Das Reich, Reich—Volksordnung-Lebensraum, 373 Voelkischer Beobachter, Volk und Reich, Westdeutscher Beobachter, and the Zeitschrift fuer auslandisches oeffentliche Recht und Voelkerrecht. The Nazi Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht published three major journals: Deutsche Rechtswissenschaft, Jahrbuch der Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht, and Zeitschrift der Akademie fuer Deutsches Recht. See also: Deutscher Juristentag Juristen), and Mitteilungen des National—Sozialistischen Rechtswahrerbundes. For the period 1933-1936, the sections of the Deutsche Juristen—Zeitung entitled "Aus der Deutscher Rechtsfront," "Personalien," and "Vermisch- tes," are most enlightening. They often provide infor- mation on the activities of Schmitt and on the general trends in the legal profession during these years. For similar information and for the emigre attitude towards Schmitt see: Deutsche Briefe: Egg Blegg_deg Katholischen Emigration, I, 1934-1935, II, 1936—1938, ed. Heinz Huerten (Mainz, 1969). Memoirs and Related Works A basic source on the end of Weimar is Franz von Papen, Memoirs, trans., Brian Connell (London, 1952), though the reader must keep in mind Papen's desire to vindicate himself. Heinrich Bruening, Memoiren, lglg" 1934 (Stuttgart, 1970), is more reliable, but still requires careful evaluation. On the inner-workings of 374 the presidential system see Hermann Puender, Politik gg deg Reichskanzlei: Aufzeichnungen egg deg Jahren lggg—gggg, ed., Thilo Vogelsang (Stuttgart, 1961). For the perspec- tive of a Social Democrat one should consult Carl Severing, Mein Lebensweg (Cologne, 1950). Ernst Niekisch, Gewagtes Leben: Begegnungen und Begebnisse (Cologne, 1958), con— tains the recollections of a former conservative revolu- tionary. A more moderate View is that of J. V. Bredt, the head of the Wirtschaftspartei and Minister of Justice in 1930. See: Erinnerungen und Dokumente von Joh. Viktor Bredt, 1914—1933, ed., Martin Schumacher (Duesseldorf, 1970). There are numerous works by representatives of the academic and legal professions. See: Willibalt Apelt, (Tuebingen, 1965), Moritz Julius Bonn, g9 Macht Man Geschichte: Bilanz eines Lebens (Munich, 1953), Arnold Zweite Haelfte, 1927—1967 (Stuttgart, 1967), Friedrich Glum, Zwischen Wissenschaft, Wirtschaft und Politik: Erlebtes und Erdachtes in Vier Reichen (Bonn, 1964), Adolf Grabowsky, Demokratie und Diktatur, Grundfragen politischer Erziehung (Zurich, 1949), Fritz Hartung, Jurist unter vier Reichen (Cologne, 1971), Ferdinand Hermens, Zwischen Politik und Vernunft: Gesammelte Aufsaetze aus drei Welten (Berlin, 1969), Theodor Heuss, 375 Erinnerungen, 1905—1933 (Tuebingen, 1963), Ernst Jaeckh Weltstaat: Erlebtes ggd Erstrebtes (Stuttgart, 1960), Gustav Radbruch, peg innere Weg (Stuttgart, 1951). The political and intellectual atmosphere of Berlin appears to come alive in Harry Graf Kessler, Tagebuecher, 1918—1937 (Frankfurt, 1961), and Katherina von Kardorff—Ohemib, Politik ggd Lebensbeichte, ed., Else Reicke (Tuebingen, 1966). Robert M. W. Kempner has published excerpts from his interrogations of various personalities associated with the Third Reich in, Das Dritte Reich im Kreuzverhoer: egg deg unveroeffentlichten Vernehmungsprotokollen deg Anklagers (Munich, 1969). Published Documentation and General Reference A most valuable reference on the political affairs of the Weimar Republic is, Das Deutsche Reich vom 1918 bis Heute, 1933, ed., Cuno Horkenbach (Berlin, 1935). Aside from a reliable chronology of the daily political events of this time, Horkenbach provides information and statistics on the major political parties, elections, various governmental departments, and pressing issues, as well as biographical information on the major politicians and ministers. A published account of the famous trial of 1932 in which Schmitt took part is, Preussen contra Reich vor den Staatsgerichtshof: Stenogrammbericht der 376 Verhandlungen vor dem Staatsgerichtshof dg Leipzig vom 10. bis dd. und vom 17. Oktober 1932 (Berlin, 1933). On Nazi legislation see, Die Gesetzgebung des Kabinetts Hitler, ed., Werner Hoche (Berlin, 1933—1939). Selective Secondary Works Excellent bibliographies of the major works on Weimar and Nazi Germany are available in Karl Dietrich Bracher, Ede Aufloesung deg Weimarer Republik: gdge Studie egg Problem deg Machtverfalls dg deg Demokratie (5th ed.; Villingen, 1971), and dge German Dictatorship: Egg Origins, Structure, ggd Effects ed National Socialism (5th ed.; New York, 1974). gde Aufloesung, presents one of the most convincing analyses of the factors involved in the disintegration of the Weimar Republic. gge German Dictatorship is equally authoritative but not as analy— tical. Useful for understanding the background to the intellectual climate of twentieth~century Germany are: Georg Iggers, The German Conception ed History: The National Tradition of Historical Thought from Herder to Mosse, The Crisis ed German Ideology: Intellectual Origins ed the Third Reich (New York, 1964), Fritz Ringer, The 377 Decline of the German Mandarins: The German Academic Community, 1890-1933 (Cambridge, Mass., 1969), Fritz Stern, The Politics ed Cultural Despair: g Study dg the Rise ed the Germanic Ideology (Berkeley, 1961), Peter York, 1961). Highly informative are the relevant chapters of The Third Reich, ed., Maurice Baumont (New York, 1955). Peter Gay provides a good introduction to the problem of Weimar intellectuals in, Weimar Culture: gge Outsider gg Insider (New York, 1968), but his thesis is highly debatable. More specialized, though more reliable, is Istvan Deak, Weimar Germany's Left-Wing Intellectuals: (Berkeley, 1968). Kurt Sontheimer, Antidemokratischen (Munich, 1964), is a standard account of the intellectual forces antagonistic to the Republic. The two major works on the right-wing intellectuals of the conservative revolu— tion are written by historians who reflect a personal understanding of the conservative cause. See: Klemens von Dilemma in the Twentieth Century (Princeton, 1957), and *_—_—_—_—_______ Armin Mohler, Die Konservative Revolution in Deutschland, ______._____—___—_______ 1918—1932: Grundriss ihrer Weltanschauung (Stuttgart, 1950). The most recent works on figures associated with 378 the conservative revolutionary phenomenon are Heinz Huerten, Waldemar Gurian: Ein Zeuge der Krise unserer Welt in der ersten Haelfte des 20. Jahrhunderts (Mainz, 1972), and Heinrich Kessler, Wilhelm Stapel als Politischer Publizist: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte des konservativen Nationalismus zwischen den beiden Weltkriegen (Nuremberg, 1967). Despite its ideological orientation, a solid con— tribution to our knowledge of German intellectuals in the twentieth century is Walter Struve, Elites against For the background to legal thought and the Weimar constitution see: Willibalt Apelt, Geschichte der Weimarer Verfassung (Munich, 1964), Rupert Emerson, State and Sovereignty dg Modern Germany (New Haven, Conn., 1928), and Ulrich Scheuner, "Die Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer in der Zeit der Weimarer Republik," Archiv des oeffentlichen Recht, Band 97, Heft 3 (September, 1972), pp. 349-374. One of the best studies of the Hindenburg govern— ment is Andreas Dorpalen, Hindenburg ggd gge_Weimar Republic (Princeton, 1964). An insider‘s viewpoint on this regime is provided in Hermann Puender, peg Reichs— praesident dg deg Weimarer Republik (Bonn, 1961). Still useful for understanding the emergency powers of the president under Article 48 are Clinton Rossiter, 379 Modern Democracies (Princeton, 1948), and Frederick Watkins, The Failure ed Constitutional Emergency Powers under the German Republic (Cambridge, Mass., 1939). On the related issue of the Prussia—Reich controversy the best works are: Juergen Bay, Der Preussenkonflikt 1932/33: 1932—1934 (Tallahassee, 1959), and Thomas TrumPP, Franz NSDAP dg Preussen: Ein Beitrag zur Vorgeschichte des g9. Juli 1932 (Marburg, 1965). Comparable to Bracher's authoritative work on the disintegration of the Weimar Republic is Erich Matthias and Rudolf Morsey, ed., Egg ggde deg Parteien dgdd (Duesseldorf, 1960). Concerning the personalities and problems involved in the final Weimar crisis see: Werner Conze, "Die Krise des Parteienstaates in Deutschland 1929/30," Historische Zeitschrift, Band 178, Heft 1 (1954), pp. 47—83, Josef Becker, "Bruening, Praelat Kaas und das Problem einer Regierungsbeteilung der NSDAP, 1930- 1932," Historische Zeitschrift, Band 196, (1963), PP. 74— 111, Theodor Eschenburg, "Die Rolle Persoenlichkeit in der Krise der Weimarer Republik: Hindenburg, Bruening, Groener, Schleicher," Vierteljahreshefte fuer 380 Zeitgeschichte, Jhg. 9, Heft 1 (January, 1961), pp. 1—29, Detlef Junker, Die Deutsche Zentrumspartei und Hitler Katholizismus dg Deutschland (Stuttgart, 1969), Thilo Vogelsang, "Zur Politik Schleichers gegenueber der NSDAP 1932," Vierteljahreshefte fuer Zeitgeschichte, Jhg. 6, Heft 1 (January, 1958), PP. 86-118. A comprehensive analysis of the Nazi seizure and consolidation of power is presented in K. D. Bracher, W. Sauer, and G. Schulz, Ede Nationalsozialistische Herrschaftssystems dg Deutschland 1933/34 (Cologne, 1960). See also Hans Schneider, "Das Ermaechtigungsgesetz vom 24. Maerz 1933," Vierteljahreshefte fuer Zeitgeschichte, Jhg. 1 (1953), pp. 197-221. The legal aspects of the Nazi state are surveyed in Martin Broszat, Der Staat Hitlers: sozialismus: Ein Ueberblick (Stuttgart, 1968). TATE UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES IIIIII III II IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII II