"I L was. u... .2. ..A..7..... . 3.1. . .7 .v .. 3“. flnfifiwfi$ Kw . A . g... C‘ at. .. he“. 1 («‘3- plhwr a! fin.» _ .J 9 ...v6..... ~ ski-(tit . \lfihxlixailn {3... fl... ...-. ‘ E 33¢. .. t 1!! . D A “pm“..ww ”1...? ., ‘ + a] 3 Ski. «“13» $.15”, 2 .t .3» Tx .13! {goal a; .uw 1 .?..fi..., i? Iva-ti- ilb‘u) .l‘ .uIlI‘vtll chalgllfila Oh...» anglfl A. :11. $5939.! f! 3.3.6.8131 001...... .1. .. axizflflflvln g?!- 1 .0 . l'n.\!t'v.‘ln" . . ‘b“.“c.".§ql'vl‘1‘ '1 -155... 311.11.- 3. Etta”: auxiltliu‘ nl , 2.513.521.3351? 3i 912.19. 31:2!!! 5.3-3:!!! :15; i}... ‘ v at tu| (n z... \I :3 t) :1..vut.i: \- 0‘. q; .: 25.9.9.9 II...$|DD;....(-Isl‘ tilt. 3:01... 1., .2 ..I.¢s . .Ilul.’ 5.5!? . v E ‘1 ‘ raw. l I...l.~‘.._.. ‘1‘; ' r .' ~' ~ -534. MUCH-$31.51 SiiLe Univ ersty This is to certify that the dissertation entitled ROUSSEAU AND MODERN FAMILY VALUES presented by WILLIAM JAMES GORDON BEWICK has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for the Doctoral degree In Political Science WEN/MM Major Professor’ 5 Signat e April 27, 2010 Date MSU is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Employer PLACE IN RETURN BOX to remove this checkout from your record. TO AVOID FINES return on or before date due. MAY BE RECALLED with earlier due date if requested. DATE DUE DATE DUE DATE DUE 5/08 KrlProlecc8PrelelRC/DateDueiindd ROUSSEAU AND MODERN FAMILY VALUES By William James Gordon Bewick A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILSOPHY Political Science 2010 ABSTRACT ROUSSEAU AND MODERN FAMILY VALUES By William James Gordon Bewick This dissertation is a comprehensive analysis ofthe significance of family throughout Rousseau’s oeuvre. It aims to make clear why, in spite of the wide-ranging scope of this controversial political philosopher, he devoted so much attention to what has come to be called “family values.” After broadly outlining the transformation of the modern family over the last 500 years, the schools of thought that effected this change, and reasons for the inability of contemporary scholarship to adequately defend or critique family-related developments, in the introduction I explain why Rousseau is uniquely suited to help us. In the first chapter, I present Rousseau’s argument for why the individualism, equality, and freedom characteristic of modern life will not bring us the happiness it might seem to promise. His more famous prescriptions for our modern ills fall under two seemingly opposed categories: the fully ‘denatured’ patriotic life in a free and equal republic, or a more natural life which takes its bearings from human sentiments and maintains its healthiness through its withdrawal from corrupted political and civil life. Explaining how family life is a practical middle way between these two extremes that is still consistent with their essential characteristics helps us understand not only why he emphasizes family, but how he can point to such disparate alternatives as legitimately happy lives. Chapter two begins with a detailed account of the state of nature that establishes the centrality of the family in it, despite the utter solitude many scholars take to be the core of Rousseau’s version of our natural condition. After indicating the reasons why the family meets many of our natural necessities, in the second half I present his treatment of why family values are necessary for the health of communities and polities. Particular focus is given here to the theme of sexual differentiation, whether it be for the well-being of a polity (Geneva in Letter to d 'Alembert), or the rural homestead of Julie. While in chapter two the intention is to defend the family on the larger scale as the socializing institution best suited to our natural needs, chapter three looks at the family from the perspective of a boy with a strong desire to find true happiness. I explore the path of love and marriage as not only good public policy, but as that which elevates and satisfies our deepest longings. Emile’s teenage instruction is dominated by sexual education: Rousseau redirects his pubescent powers towards pity and piety before making sexual chastity and the desire for a virtuous wife the core of his character development. The fleeting character of romantic love turns many supporters of family values against it, and against Rousseau for his seductive presentation. Rousseau was very much alive to these concerns. In chapter four I take up Rousseau’s own critique of romantic love, and reconcile the tension between the great commitment required by marriage and the concern for freedom that Rousseau possessed as strongly as anyone today. By addressing the major critiques of the family using Rousseau’s own arguments, I demonstrate not only that his analysis of the issue is extremely comprehensive, but that this sustained consideration of Rousseau’s ideas on family sheds more light on the unity of his thought. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My parents are the cause of this work in many ways. They strongly nurtured my passion for learning from a young age. My father in particular encouraged me to recognize the importance of history and politics and to appreciate the unique character of Western culture. Their success in marriage and family played no small part in not just my own well-being, but in my belief that this is a worthy topic of study. Their quality as parents and unflagging support of my higher education has enabled a young man of ‘common’ birth to enjoy a quality of life and learning better than most conventional aristocrats could wish for. Professor Leon Craig, with help from Heidi Studer and Tom Pocklington, convinced me that political philosophy is not only the field I am best suited to, but the worthiest scholarly endeavour to devote oneself to. Professor Craig’s diligent and insightful editing of my master’s thesis provided me with valuable insights into the art of composition. Professors Melzer and Kautz have furthered this instruction; the weaknesses and errors remaining in this work reflect only my limitations, not their capacity to improve young scholars. At Michigan State, I continued to have the good fortune to learn from excellent professors. It has been an honour and pleasure to take world-class courses from David Leibowitz, Werner Dannhauser, Jerry Weinberger, Steven Kautz, and Arthur Melzer. I have been extremely fortunate to have been exposed to so many people who have not only taught me the value of learning, but demonstrated the value of great teaching. I would also like to thank the many graduate students in Alberta and Michigan who have enriched my knowledge and my life as a student. In particular, I have been blessed in my friendship with Anas Muwais, who has challenged me, inspired me, and taught me. He and the others have ensured that I continually felt the joy of gaining wisdom, and that I appreciated the extent to which fn'endship consists in sharing this joy. Finally, and most importantly, I am happy to have this opportunity to thank my lovely wife, Clara. “Supportive” would be a gross understatement: you have been critical, cajoling, insightful, sympathetic, and have made me understand what it really means to have a “better half.” You have provided me with a whole new education on this subject matter, showing me the value of love and marriage in ways I will never be able to express. I believe that the fact that you have had more to teach me about the topic than I have been able to teach you is not a condemnation of Rousseau but a vindication. It is also a testament to your wisdom and my continued good fortune. TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ........................................................................................ v INTRODUCTION Why this Topic is Appropriate to Political Science ............................................ 4 Why this Topic is Important in Contemporary Politics ...................................... 7 The “Modern Family” ....................................................................................... 14 Modern Political Theory and Modern Family Debates .................................... 26 Why Rousseau is the Political Philosopher We Most Need to Study Further to Improve our Understanding of Modern Family Values ............................... 34 Summary of the Work ....................................................................................... 43 CHAPTER ONE ROUSSEAU’S ANALYSIS OF MODERNITY AND HAPPINESS .......................... 49 Unity and Freedom: The Consistent Core in Rousseau's “Radicalism” ............ 50 The Reasoning Behind Rousseau's “Right-Wing” Rhetoric and Attack on Rationalistic Individualism ................................................................................ 56 Natural Goodness and Modern Slavery: Rousseau's Critique from the Left ..... 69 Independence and the Sentiment of Existence: Rousseau's Understanding of the Good Life ................................................................................................. 78 The Political Solution ......................................................................................... 84 CHAPTER TWO FAMILY: THE BRIDGE BETWEEN NATURE AND SOCIETY ............................. 90 Natural Man ....................................................................................................... 93 Naturally Solitary, Natural Families, or Both? ................................................. 103 Love and Society: Humankind’s Happiest Condition ....................................... 113 The Perils of the Theatre ................................................................................... 125 The Harmony of the Sexes ................................................................................ 128 The Dangers of Degenderization ....................................................................... 137 Modesty and Feminine Virtue ........................................................................... 146 CHAPTER THREE SEXUAL EDUCATION, VIRTUE AND MARRIAGE ............................................... 158 Puberty: The Need for Education to Supplement Nature .................................. 161 Friendship, Pity, Amour-propre: A More Natural Morality .............................. 173 Natural Piety ...................................................................................................... 183 The Revelation and Elevation of Sex ................................................................ 190 Marriage and Morals .......................................................................................... 204 vi CHAPTER FOUR QUALIFIED ROMANTICISM AND THE CHALLENGES OF IN DIVIDUALISM: ROUSSEAU’S LIFE AND OURS ............................................. 216 Julie: Romance Denied ...................................................................................... 221 Emile and Sophie: Romance Destroyed ............................................................ 231 Emile and J ean-J acques: Or, the Solitaries ........................................................ 241 Solitariness, Family, and Freedom Reconsidered .............................................. 255 CONCLUSION .............................................................................................................. 265 BIBLIOGRAPHY .......................................................................................................... 272 vii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS C: Confessions (Kelly translation) D: Dialogues: Rousseau, Judge of Jean-Jacques (Kelly translation) E: Emile (Bloom Translation) E&S: Emile and Sophie, or the Solitaries (Harvey translation) EOL: Essay on the Origin of Language (Gourevitch translation) FD: First Discourse (Masters translation) J: Julie (Stewart and Vache translation) LT: Letter to D’Alembert (Bloom translation) OC: Oeuvres Completes (Pleiade edition) PE: Political Economy (Masters translation) R: Reveries of a Solitary Walker (Butterworth translation) SC: Social Contract (Masters translation) SD: Second Discourse (Masters translation) viii Introduction This study will present Jean-Jacques Rousseau’s analysis and promotion of the family for modern man with the hope of illuminating what his work can teach us about our situation 250 years later. At the peak of his fame and intellectual powers, no issue concerned him more than establishing family bonds on a sentimental egalitarian basis which could endure the impending political upheavals he foresaw. With the force of his insights into the core problems of modernity and the love-based family solution he proposed — a solution being taken up with renewed vigour again in our day — I hope to clarify from Rousseau’s perspective what a strengthening of the family means, how this might help us identify and address our social problems, and how revisiting his teaching can better inform our debates on the tensions between individual freedom and family values. One distinguishing feature of Rousseau’s work is that while he shares many of the scientific and materialistic premises of modern philosophers, he writes with more passion than one finds in most theorists and about less scientifically manageable issues such as honour, duty, souls, moral decay, and above all, love. In fact, Rousseau could sensibly be said to have caused more romantic love than anyone in history. The powerful influence of his depictions of love in Emile, Julie, and his own Confessions have earned him the title in many minds as the “Father of Romanticism” a movement which surely affected all of modernity. Allene Gregory declares in The French Revolution and the English Novel that amongst French philosophers of the time, “Rousseau especially exerted an influence in England which it would be hard to overestimate. . .Julie, St. Preux, Emile, Sophie, and the Rousseau of the Confessions became living ideals in the minds of Englishmen” (41 ). His effect on major novelists such as Stendahl, Goethe, Tolstoy, Balzac, and others is evident and well documented, even if they were not exactly disciples, as was St. Pierre. More than any of these writers, however, Rousseau was not only interested in capturing readers by vividly depicting the power of love: he clearly wanted to turn it to public utility. He saw that romantic love could be the foundation of a renewed, willing devotion on the part of both fathers and mothers to the family. This was needed more than ever, he thought, because the liberal, commercial, rationalistic, and individualistic society of modernity would tend not to provide its 'citizens' with the fulfillment it seemed to promise. For most people, Rousseau believed, there certainly was such a thing as too much freedom. With patriotism and piety becoming weak and always prone to corruption, Rousseau thought that the most viable basis for developing the genuine sense of community most humans long for was instilling a comprehensive respect for family. Emile, the subject of his greatest work, is first given the tools of self-sufficiency and practical wisdom, and then made to be a lover, but this is clearly with a life as a morally serious father and husband in sight. In direct contrast to the popular feminism that seeks full access to the career- centered city life for women, Rousseau hoped to send families out to the country, where men could escape the life of urban competition and superficiality and be more wholeheartedly devoted to their families. He denounced the rejection of matemalism in the strictest terms, and persuaded many of the well-educated and socially powerful aristocratic mothers of his day to breastfeed and take pride in fulfilling the role of nurturing their children, even in the earliest years. He witnessed with penetrating eyes what the results are when people place much more emphasis on artificial and divisive qualities like honour and wealth than on more natural and communal ones like love and fellowship. I hope to establish in this dissertation that our contemporary problems are not so utterly new or bewildering. Not only can we learn from Rousseau as a writer on the family, but as a political philosopher whose insights and exhortations helped shape diverse elements of our modern, liberal, democratic age. Rousseau is also notable in that he transcends the ideological camps we see today. He is castigated on all sides because of powerful strands in his thought which point towards such disparate ideologies as communism, radical egalitarianism, pastoralism, nationalism, sexism, bohemianism, romanticism, and militarism. While many choose to dismiss Rousseau as a serious thinker because of these apparent contradictions, I intend to make plausible the claim that no writer on modern family issues is as alive to the deep tensions between the promptings of individual freedom and the requirements of an orderly society in our individual and collective quest for happiness and justice. I will show that not only does Rousseau have a great deal to teach us about family issues, but that a deeper understanding of his teaching on the family helps us to reconcile the apparent inconsistencies and see the unity in Rousseau's thought. Why this Topic is Appropriate to Political Science Political philosophy is the study of how human beings can live best, a critical reflection on our opinions, customs, and laws with an eye to improving them in terms of the quality of life they make possible or likely. While its practitioners seek a trans- historical understanding of humanity, one cannot help but begin with the world one is most directly in contact with. An alien observer comparing the political systems and public opinions in our Western world with those of the last few millennia would likely come to the conclusion that we have attained an unprecedented degree of political stability and general contentment. But while peace and prosperity have flourished in the West over the last sixty years, a look at the social and moral lives of these solidly liberal democratic people reveals that this period has seen a remarkable change with regard to sexuality and family norms. While the family has not yet been quite as transformed as sexual mores generally, they are inextricably linked, and it is not clear whether this fundamental and most intimate of institutions is only undergoing a notable shift in meaning, or losing its status as a foundation of society. The government and the family have always been two major loci of both social change and stability. Though nobody seriously questions their interrelatedness, a number of factors contribute to them rarely being studied together, even in today’s very diverse world of academic publishing. The first is that our liberal politics is premised in part on the reduction of the moral scope of the state or involvement in the “private lives” of citizens; with the important and often controversial exception of public education, matters of child-rearing and especially sexuality are fimrly within the private realm. A related phenomenon is the reluctance of many academics to involve themselves in controversial moral issues, whether attacking or defending traditional morals, out of a concern with scientific objectivity as well as a fear of persecution. Another factor affecting academic scholarship is the division of the social sciences into fields such as political science and sociology; one examines the relationships between citizens and the government or between governments, while the other examines the vast panoply of social relations only one of which is the family. Political Science rarely descends to the study of the family unit, despite the fact that it is here where the future citizens of the polity are produced and their characters and opinions melded most directly. There have been some exceptions when laws run blatantly enough against accepted individual and group rights (as with the equal rights movement and again more recently over the issue of same-sex marriage), but for the most part political scientists have very little to do with family issues. Even when challenges to the law arise, one is more likely to find legal scholars addressing these debates. Sociology is broken up into many subfields and ideologies, with the result that comprehensive authoritative accounts of the principles of our family structure are hard to find,1 and as with anthropology are too often merely descriptive. Family sociologists also rarely attempt to connect the effects of our family structure to the political realm or ' Sociologist David Cheal: “Students of family and marriage are often puzzled by the conflicted images of family life that are presented in Sociology. Their confusion is not surprising, as family theorists are probably more divided now than they have been at any other time.” (x). 5 vice versa.2 There is, in fact, very little normative content in the social sciences, except from perspectives such as Marxism, queer theory, religious fundamentalism, and others who start from widely-questioned premises. The only field for which the relationship between the family and state is prominent is feminist theory. Women's Studies or Gender Studies departments have been formed in many universities over the last few decades. While “women's equality” has become accepted as a basic liberal premise inside academia and out, the meaning of this notion is far from settled. Specifically, the character of innate differences between men and women and the cultural significance these variations should have is a topic that continues to be debated amongst feminists and is one that men and women in real life continue to grapple with as well. The core of the debate can be roughly distilled into two camps: if women are essentially the same as men, we need to consider how to reduce the barriers to their contributing more equally in the public space; or, if women are importantly different than men, we need to consider how their unique abilities can flourish in a way that contributes to the well being of both women and society. Social science for the most part has thus far made only modest contributions to this debate. While cognitive studies and other psychologists have recently focused more on understanding differences between the sexes, for the most part there is little 'hard' evidence to assist us in resolving these issues. Political Philosophy has its drawbacks as well: in its long history, most of its best and influential contributors have had little to say 2 . . . We Will discuss some exceptions, such as Popenoe, Blankcnhom. and Berger below. 6 ——-—'— about women, and what they have said is usually dismissive or otherwise unhelpful in our debates today. We will in this study analyze one of the most comprehensive attempts at uncovering the principles of family bonds and reforrnulating them for the benefit of modern society from J ean—J acques Rousseau: a man who contributed to all of social science, but who is best considered a political philosopher. Why this Topic is Important in Contemporary Politics Despite the deficiencies in the academic approaches, family issues remain at the fore of our political debates. In the last twenty years the demand for recognition of alternative arrangements in the expansive government and corporate benefits systems, the desire to address the needs of those affected by the strains of single parenting, as well as the emboldened effort from the left to rid the political landscape of the discriminatory vestiges of the old society are chief among the developments that have brought sexual politics to the fore in a number of sectors of public policy. Besides the issue of same-sex marriage, other directly related contemporary public issues are sex education, public decency, spousal abuse, gender equality in the workplace, “deadbeat dads,” teen pregnancy, home schooling, and whether the government should support parental or professional child care. Many of these issues are hotly contested in our time, but it is clear that much of the debate is made up of polarizing tropes and mantras from the ideological left and right, without it being clear how well—rooted the understandings of their expositors are. When one side speaks of equality, rights, and the family as an incorrigibly oppressive patriarchal institution while the other speaks of the degeneration of society and the need to inculcate virtue in the face of hedonistic nihilism, it can easily seem that there is no shared ground. Most of the discussion of these issues occurs with little attention given to the complex theoretical underpinnings of the ’traditional' family, especially with regard to how its supporters in the last few centuries saw its promotion as a necessary counterweight to the dangers that liberal democracy poses to the morals and happiness of its citizens. In taking this subject up from the vantages political philosophy affords, this study aims to help inform our family debates. In particular, this perspective takes a broader viewpoint from which we can better understand both liberal democracy and the modern family in light of the alternatives from which they have been consciously directed. Regardless of whether one supports the de-stigmatization of the many alternative living arrangements we see today, few would argue that this unprecedented transformation of values regarding the family is not producing casualties (although, to be sure, some would argue there were more casualties before this change). Despite the near extinction in most quarters of taboos against non-marital sex, homosexuality, divorce, and having children outside of wedlock, various studies make clear that at least the latter two tend to cause psychic harm to some parents and many children. There is considerable evidence that more than any other factor, being raised by one's married parents improves a child's likelihood of maturing into a healthy responsible adult (e. g. Moynihan ed. 2004, Popenoe ed. 1994). One of the most indisputably negative occurrences in civil society is crime. Based on an influential study authored by Elaine Kamark and William Galston, among others, Barbara Whitehead asserts that “controlling for family configuration erases the relationship between race and crime and between low income and crime. This conclusion shows up again and again in the literature.” Family values proponents criticize the push to embrace the acceptance of diversity in family arrangements because the negative outcomes associated with it are clear and quantifiable. Moynihan et.al., in The Future of the Family, surveys the social factors which have declined along with the family transformation; they conclude that having a single parent is by far the most robust predictor of poverty, poor education, crime, and teen pregnancy (which usually means disadvantaged single-parentage all over again). The authors cite Jonathan Rauch's work from 2001, where he suggests that “America's families and children may be splitting into two increasingly divergent and perpetuating streams — two social classes, in other words — with marriages as the dividing line,” and note Isabel Sawhill's finding that “the proliferation of single-parent households 9') accounts for virtually all the increase in child poverty since the early 1970's (xxi). Most attempts to explain this phenomenon point to the shortcomings of single parenthood. Single parents have difficulty fulfilling all the roles children require. Two parents are better able to both financially and emotionally support children. Popenoe and others also argue that the lack of an authoritative father figure (the vast majority of single parents are mothers) inhibits the proper development of a child's sense of right and wrong, especially a son's. In cases of divorce, while each parent might still be part of their children's lives, there is often a loss of respect for trust, sacrifice, and honesty in the children no matter how loving the parents are towards them.3 Supporters of “family values” argue that promoting the acceptance of and support for alternatives to the conventional family contributes to a degradation of the moral bonds of society as well as the characters and happiness of individuals. They also assert that the corresponding demystification of life-long love and marriage (which cannot be praised too highly without blaming the altematives) has affected the short- and long-term prospects for happiness for many: even those who spend their lives married with children, insofar as the many arguments against the institution makes them more deeply uncertain about their choices. Supporters of the dismantling of these taboos argue that the stricter expectations of the past caused too many victims in and out of maniage, especially female victims given the patriarchal character of family relations. Increased divorce rates from this perspective are not something to bemoan, but rather a reflection of people exercising their 3 The argument that strong families make better children is quite simple. Humans cannot rely on instinct to live. By nature they are forced to learn how to provide for themselves and as social beings must learn how to act in accordance with the prevailing norms to live agreeably alongside others. Learning to govern desires and emotions to a sufficient degree is a lengthy process, and requires instruction and the example of attentive adults. Although today we see this socialization taking place more and more in public settings like schools and daycares and through the influence of mass media, few would deny that a substantial degree of character development still takes place in the home. This learning occurs in large part as children observe their parents going about their lives, but more directly through the praise and blame their parents give to their conduct as well as that of others. There is an innate respect that virtually all children (at least pre-pubescent ones) display towards their parents, and a corresponding fear of displeasing them. It is also the case that parents usually care more than anyone about how their children turn out; their love and nurturing are argued by some to be the most important resources a child can have. While it is true that they can pass on bad habits as well as good ones, and that because parents are not formally educated in child development there is bound to be pernicious ignorance in some degree, traditionalists and Rousseau agree that the bonds of blood, gratitude, and natural affection make the parents the best candidates for the role of raising children. 10 right to leave unhappy relationships that in the past they would have had to miserably endure. Unplanned teen pregnancies are unfortunate, but the issue calls for better birth control and sex education, not a misguided religion-fuelled chastity campaign. As for adult women, single motherhood is considered a basic expression of women's freedom, and should be supported by the state so as to mitigate the effects of loss of income and other support a spouse can give. Non-marital sex and homosexuality are defended as natural and healthy in comparison to the repression and oppression seen in the strict regimes of old. Wherever the truth lies between these two camps, it is clear that the ideal of two virgins entering into lifelong marriage is not only rarely seen, but only remains an ideal amongst the few remaining devoutly religious subgroups in the West. Stephanie Coontz perhaps goes too far in asserting that “relations between men and women have changed more in the past thirty years than they did in the previous three thousand” (4), but the fact that such a statement is even debatable supports the notion that no period in history has experienced such a rapid transformation in family values. There has been a radical rethinking of the norms concerning sex, marriage, and gender in the last half-century, and this demands more serious reflection than it has received. The superficiality of public debate is a barrier to this deeper reflection. While some cling unthinkingly to traditional ways of thought, others today rest their opinions on these controversial issues too easily on simplistic notions of freedom and equality. Rather than grapple with the murkier concepts of education, higher culture, virtue, ll reverence, community, and duty, many choose to take the side which dismantles the reigning prejudices of old in favour of liberty from judgments about personal matters. That is, they are consciously or unconsciously guided by the opinion that freedom and equality mean a general freedom from moral expectations and an acceptance of all ways of life as fundamentally equal — at least so long as they do not directly involve harming others. When these avid promoters of tolerance look back at westem history, they see above all different modes of institutionalized discrimination against groups of people: the very real injustices in many of the instances colours the entire picture for them in a negative way. While I am sympathetic to most of the particular claims of these very progressive- minded individualists, I believe that in general they tend to place unwarranted hope in how much happiness greater freedom and equality can bring us, especially in regard to the lower expectations regarding social conduct that this barer notion of liberty entails. Put simply, fighting too hard for personal freedoms means eliminating what might be one of the most important conditions for human happiness: the freedom to be a member of a sovereign community that upholds substantive claims about how to live well. Too often liberal progressives dismiss the social and cultural traditions and institutions outright inasmuch as they tend to be inherently inegalitarian and impose expectations upon people in a way not obviously conducive of freedom. While the success observed in modernity in attacking patriarchal injustice and establishing related personal freedoms has created a more just society in many ways, it appears that respect for marriage and family bonds is unnecessarily falling victim to these developments, and in so doing threatens this success. 12 While radical feminists, Marxists, and other post-modemists applaud the decline of the marriage-based family model as a necessary step towards their notions of a just society, and reactionary conservatives apocalyptically lament that this is proof that all of the liberal advances of the last century have been so many steps towards our doom, I believe most of us are in a middle ground where we want families that emphasize and protect freedom and equality while providing a stable environment where parents and children can find a dynamic happiness. We recognize, however, that both getting married and deciding to have children are huge compromises of our individual freedom. However clear statistics might be about the declining birth rate in the West or the social advantages in widespread marriage, in an increasingly atomistic culture we need good arguments to convince us and powerful depictions to persuade us to willingly commit to what custom and the social order used to impel us to do. As we will see in chapter one, Rousseau is very modem in that he supports a scientific, liberal, and egalitarian outlook towards politics. What sets him apart from other writers of early modern times is his thorough grasp of the classical notions of what keeps a community healthy and individuals happy. This compelled him to critique the direction modernity was taking, and to see the need to provide support to social institutions like education and marriage in the wake of retreating state and church influence. The comprehensiveness of his thought and the power of his writing have made him one of the first and most profoundly influential critics of modernity as we know it. However well-known he may be for his proposals for Spartan—style citizenship and 13 solitary communion with nature, no prescription for remedying the modern dilemma preoccupied him as much as devotion to a child-centered family founded on romantic love. No respected philosopher before or since has devoted so much attention to cultivating a respect for family bonds as the most important basis for a happy life and healthy society. I expect that presenting this analysis of the family in the context of Rousseau’s startlingly insightful understanding of modernity will enable us to better understand the principles underlying the promotion of 'farnily values'. Before returning to an outline of his thought and its unique relevance to our understanding of family issues, a brief and general review of the development of the modern family and the debates surrounding it is in order. The “Modern Family” In the last fifty years there has been a radical shift in the institution of the family both legally and culturally in the West. Legally, we have seen divorce laws loosened, rights of unmarried couples strengthened, state support for single parents increased, provisions for gender equality in the workplace introduced, and most recently many jurisdictions have extended marriage rights to same-sex couples. These legal changes have variously encouraged and reflected changes in public attitudes towards marriage, gender, and family. Stigmas surrounding many of the family values with which traditional morality concerned itself have been drastically reduced: couples are more free than ever to decide whether or not to marry and divorce; women are freer than ever to choose whether to have children, a career, or both; people are freer than ever to choose to 14 engage in heterosexual or homosexual relationships; and, the dichotomy of gender expectations applies to fewer categories all the time. In this section we will review the characteristics which distinguish the early- and late-modem family structures. The push for legal equality and protection of some basic “human rights” began, if not essentially then in earnest, in 17th Century England. Amidst a flourishing of respect for modern science over the ancient and medieval outlooks, Thomas Hobbes, John Locke and others pushed for a scientific approach to politics that would similarly overthrow earlier ways of thinking. They argued that the feudal structure was deeply flawed, and that so long as political legitimacy was rooted in faith-based principles like Divine Right of Kings or Papal Infallibility it would be rife with abuses, corruption, and inefficiency. They believed that a demystification of political principles would place political authority on a more solid and rational basis, and that a greater respect for individual freedom would generate much more peace, prosperity, and happiness for future generations of citizens. They led a radical push against the religious and aristocratic authorities in favour of rationalism and egalitarianism. By shifting Europe's intellectual focus from a preoccupation with antiquity and aesthetics to a progressive concern with public utility and modern science, these writers turned the “Renaissance” into the “Enlightenment.” Although the social change is coming to its individualistic fulfillment a considerable time after the fundamental political change, it would be naive to think that the principles sanctified in the latter are not fuelling the former, or that these political principles are not still being refined, for better and worse. There is a wealth of insight to 15 be obtained in the study of the best thinkers and humanists of the beginning of this era not only because of their transcendent genius but because they saw more of what was at stake to lose, or what the altematives are to our way of life. When the role that the nobility and religious leaders had played in uniting nations and cultures was much more vivid, even if decaying, it was far easier to be concerned about the steady decline in their authority to uphold standards of conduct which bound their subjects together. Rousseau, like Montesquieu before him and Tocqueville after him (to name but two prominent examples) opposed these decaying authorities strongly, but worried about whether something better or worse would replace their influence, and if the unifying moral realm could be harmoniously distilled into the legalistic respect for rights and fundamental equality that Hobbes and Locke wrote in favour of. While Rousseau was a strong advocate of individuals being treated as political equals, and had a powerful mistrust of established authorities, he does not agree with the opposition expressed by many progressivists to the family as a uniform institution. Rather, he sought to reform the family in a way that would coincide with modern principles but protect it from certain dangers. The most distasteful aspect of this bourgeois family model for contemporary sensibilities is the gendered roles in it. Progressives today insist that it is a systematic violation of women's rights to expect women to act on a more domestic and informal level and men to be more public. While this position has succeeded in becoming most people's idea of a basic egalitarian principle, in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries the gendered model was in fact a branch of a rather progressive women's movement (Berger 99-134). As the industrial l6 revolution urbanized agrarian Europe, a large proportion of families shifted from being cohesive units fulfilling a function in and around a village (farm, store, smith, livestock, etc.), to collections of wage-eamers in the factories of growing cities. Women and children, who had a productive and cooperative role in the rural household, often went off to earn a wage working long gruelling hours in a factory, just as the man of the house (or small apartment) did. There was a struggle at the outset of the 19th Century involving various women's, religious, and other social activist groups across western countries to secure the 'rights' of women and children not to work (Berger 109-11,). Eventually the norm was established across much of Europe and especially in the English-speaking parts of the New World that there should be a substantial middle class where a mother could devote her labour to her home. Like Rousseau, and often directly following his lead, the male and female advocates of this position argued that women were not being 'subj ected' in this model, but rather elevated to a cherished and respected position. Today adherents of this viewpoint insist that they treat husbands and wives as “different but equal.” Rousseau is an extremely influential early proponent of this position: while we might refer to them today as conservative or traditional feminists, in his time this elevation of women to the role of ‘domestic empress’ was quite an egalitarian innovation. Another common error in considerations of the history of the western family is to conclude that until the industrial revolution urbanized the population and forced greater mobility, the norm was to live in a larger household with a number of couples living 17 under the authority of the oldest male. While this was certainly more prevalent when rural life was the norm and in the days before seniors' homes were a part of every community, two-generational households have constituted the majority for as long as reliable records have been kept in Europe (Wall 217, 222; Berger 5). While among the aristocracy it was more common for their large manors and castles to house some extended family as well as servants, and there have certainly been many cases where elderly parents live with one of their adult children, in the West it has always been very unusual for grown adults to live with their siblings; rather, a married couple and their children have formed the nucleus of the household throughout the history of western civilization. While there are some different norms regarding living with adult siblings and parents in certain Eastern cultures like India, this is not a peculiarity of the West. Anthropologists have uncovered a handful of alternatives where men did not live with women, or eras where the concept of fatherhood seems to have been unknown (such as upper Palaeolithic Europe), but these exceptions are fairly rare throughout history. As Blankenhom argues, even if other forms have prevailed in certain times and places, it is notable that none of their cultures lasted or left a mark; rather, as he explains through analysis of the cradles of civilization in Egypt and Mesopotamia, the historical record suggests that it is only when marriage is taken seriously that a culture advances and endures (Blankenhom 37-40, 41-68, 87). The two-generational household is repeatedly referred to in sociological and anthropological literature as the earliest and most universal social institution. Although elderly parents often lived with one of their children, 18 mortality rates and fertility rates in the past have meant that this has not been prevalent enough to be an institution. Sociologist Talcott Parsons and Bronislaw Malinowski — an early anthropologist who studied the Trobriander tribe, who were unaware of a father's biological role but still had him live with and care for his children — are among many who go so far as to say that the household of a married couple and their children is found in such a preponderance of societies across history that it can be considered a universal human norm (Parsons 102-4, Malinowski 62-63). Although the two-generational aspect with some form of marriage holds up over time, the disposition of the members to each other and the society at large varies greatly between eras and cultures. In the strongest traditional cultures, people's lives are very much dominated by their ties to their extended families and classes, whether or not parents or other family elders shared the same roof. One of the clearest indicators of the power of family bonds is in how much choice young people have in who they marry. When marriage is arranged by parents and work is generally done with or in support of one's extended family, self—identity is largely bound up with familial ties and the concept of individual firlfillrnent is deeply buried if not foreign. Last names matter much more than first ones. These ties are still very prominent in many Eastern and African societies today and were the norm in Europe at the beginning of modernity. The proponents of the Enlightenment sought to break this predominance of ancestral or familial authority in addition to that of the Nobility and Church. 19 As with virtually every society besides advanced liberal democracy, throughout the early period of this transition in Europe social expectations often differed for the elites. While vestiges remain today (especially in parts of Europe — compare, among many examples, President Mitterrand of France's domestic arrangements or Silvio Berlusconi's exploits with President Clinton's near impeachment), before the decline of aristocracy it was widely accepted that the elites did not follow the same norms as did the commoners; this held for family life as well as it did for careers, manners, political power, and education. Besides having much more to do with ruling than being ruled, elites had larger estates and family titles. This provided opportunity and motive to keep parts of the extended family (most notably adult heirs) living under the same roof. A larger family did not equate to a closer family, however. Those of the upper class, even mothers, generally had little or no direct part in their children’s lives. Child-care was considered menial labour; as with all such work, those with means hired people to do it for them. Rousseau thought it was essential that upper-class parents, especially mothers, spend much more time with their children, and he succeeded in shifting elite opinion in this direction. The presence of young servants in the home not only relieved the owners of domestic and parental duties, but also presented an alternative to what could most unflatteringly be considered 'spousal' duties. Much more relevant to the chastity of spouses was that in much of Europe there was little or no expectation of fidelity or love between aristocratic parents. As is still the case in many parts of the Eastern world today, marriages were based on considerations of estate and title, and if the parents did not 20 entirely arrange the match, they held and usually exercised a veto power through their ability to disown children who decided for themselves who would enter into the family through marriage. Stephanie Coontz adds that assisting the parents in this role were “kin, neighbours, and other outsiders, such as priests, or government officials” (7). Rather than marriage being a celebration of love and commitment, the emphasis was in doing honour to one’s ancestry by strengthening the extended family through advantageous marriages. Romance was still prized in some of these circles, whether it was among the medieval knights or the members of the great courts of Europe. Because of the propertied and honorific character of marriage, however, one could only rarely hope to find any romance there. Rather than providing an alternative to the practical realm of generating wealth and prestige, marriage was decidedly businesslike. This gave a superficial character to marriage, and generated an understanding that it was outside of it that one would find passionate attachments and more individual fulfillment. In addition to the generation of disrespect because of the character of their marriages, the upper classes often spent much of their time in mixed company at leisure, affording them considerable opportunity to develop romances in adulthood. Much to his chagrin, in Rousseau's time it was quite widely expected that after producing an heir or two an aristocratic young woman would move on to pursue romantic affairs and remain joined to her husband in only an official capacity. While the widespread acceptance of this practice seems to have peaked in Rousseau's France amongst the highly educated elites he lived with in Paris, it is still observed in some contemporary elites or in those who claim to have “open” marriages and relationships; even with our entirely voluntary 21 marriages, the appeals to nature and freedom from those who oppose monogamy echo in many of the arguments against family values today. While those of the lower classes did have property considerations of a sort to make — in terms of how productive a spouse could be — they also usually had the ability to marry those they had fallen in love with, or at least had affection for. It may still have been thought by many that this motive was dangerously impractical, but their parents were not the arbiters of their marital fate to nearly the same degree as in the propertied classes. The expectation of sexual fidelity was held more firmly among these people; their greater piety and lack of leisure and mixed company would have made this chaste ideal easier to realize. In addition to the greater chance that marriages of the lower classes would be contracted on the basis of emotional affinity, there was the more intimate daily interaction between the spouses and amidst their children to help secure the family bond. The distinguishing characteristics of these families were that there was little or no education or prospect of class mobility. While the lower classes were less directly bound to ancestry, they were indirectly bound to a meagre lot in life because of their lowly birth. Their goals in raising children rarely extended beyond training them to perform the same functions the parents carried out. This changed with the Enlightenment's arguments for, and the economy's facilitation of, the emergence of a more fluid class structure. As modernity took hold, and a middle class came to prominence, there came to be more and more incentive to provide one's children with the tools to be more successful in life. Through the 19‘h 22 Century the older family patterns were replaced by a model of marrying for love and taking great pride in the rearing and educating of one's children.4 Rousseau played an important part in this shift from the household being bound to the past to the family holding the hopes of future happiness for the parents and their children. He contributed to this transition not only by arguing for greater political freedom and equality as other modern theorists did, but by directly emphasizing the importance of children's upbringing in their spiritual or character development and by generating devotional respect for not just love but romantic marriage. Though today there is still a notable expectation of direct involvement with one’s children's development, especially in North America, it is clear that the hope for everyone to have a successful career combined with the permissibility and frequency of divorce has resulted in a situation that resembles the aristocratic society of Rousseau’s time in the sense of a devaluation of commitment to maniage in favour of personal freedom and ambitions. It is, however, importantly different. To begin with, the expectation of fidelity within marriage is held across all strata in our society, but chastity before marriage now holds less regard than it did in perhaps any other civilization. Despite adultery being frowned upon, divorce has gained unprecedented acceptability in recent decades. While we have certainly done away with much of the hypocrisy of Rousseau's day, then, there is a similarity in that the power of marriage as an institution in adult life is unusually low by historical standards. 4 According to Brigitte Berger, the literature on the distinct character of modern family life stresses: “The centrality of children in the life of the modern nuclear family and an obsession with the methods to be used in their instruction” (1 18). 23 It is also the case that there are class differences in our time, but now — with the exception of the famous — the wealthier tend to be married for most of their adult lives, often only once. As indicated above, it is low income people today who are more likely not to remarry after a divorce or not marry at all, and accordingly their children grow up in a home disadvantaged further by not having two parents in it. Kay Hymowitz's Marriage and Caste in America is one account of how the acceptance of 'altemative' living arrangements and a turn away from the promotion of the traditional family only deepens the socioeconomic divide by reinforcing the status of lower-class children of single parentage and disincenting many from seeking out the marriage that, statistically speaking, would do the most to improve their children's fortunes. Another pertinent difference between early modern families and ours is that rather than most marriages being entered into at a young age with little personal choice in the matter, people today are free or rather obliged to find their own spouse and are taking longer to do so. Contraception and acceptance of cohabitation has led to a pattern in which people have often had a few serious relationships, or trial marriages, not to mention less serious relations before getting married. Marriage itself is perhaps not directly undermined in this scenario, but as with Europe's aristocrats sex and marriage are not tied together. While some of the more progressive today think the institution to be irrational or outdated, others with considerable respect for marriage think they are not ready for it, or their prospective spouse is not, or they cannot afford it, and instead find their adult lives fully developing — even becoming parents — before they ever seriously contemplate undertaking this step. This greater amount of freedom, including that not to 24 marry, forces those of today to question the value of marriage more deeply than those who have only to think of how to behave in a marriage, taking the if, when, and whom as given. Despite these important differences, then, there is a distinct similarity between our views towards marriage and those of Rousseau's aristocratic Europe. Both societies accept forms of extra-marital sexual relationships and many are of the opinion that sustaining a faithful and contented marriage is at best a common success, at worst a delusion or prison, and in any case not something we can reasonably expect of most people. An important and related similarity is that a considerable proportion of children in each society grow up without one or both parents. Besides a higher mortality rate for parents, Rousseau's Paris grappled with an increasing number of children in government- run and religious orphanages. Many of our children live with only one parent because of divorce or because their parents never married. Broadly speaking, our two societies grant men and women the freedom to put their personal interests and ambitions ahead of marriage and children in a way that is far from the norm throughout the rest of human history. Far more than being a critic of a family situation with some resemblance to ours, however, Rousseau is worth studying as an early and powerful proponent of strong family bonds being compatible with natural freedom and the pursuit of happiness. He had many accurate concerns about the spiritual well-being of the emerging middle class, who he called the “bourgeois”; as a remedy to the dishonestly superficial lives he feared 25 they would lead, he made a thorough appeal to them to embrace freely the bonds of family not as a duty handed down from the past, but as the best way to secure their enduring happiness in the future. He sought to reinvent marriage in accordance with his discernment of both passion and consent as bedrock principles of human associations. To understand better the complexity of this appeal, in the next section we will unpack more fully the principles of modern political thought, because they and the “post-modem” reaction against them inform the ideologies at war in the family debates. Modern Political Theory and Modern Family Debates As mentioned above, feminists have produced most of the debate and theories about family issues within academia in contemporary times. There are certainly different feminist theories, and feminists who hold divergent views on all the salient issues, but for our purposes the generally accepted “three waves” of feminism will be used to outline the developments in feminist thought and the close parallels in social theory generally over the last century. From the outset of the Enlightenment there have been advocates who sought to reduce gender differences and extend the burgeoning notions of freedom and equality for all men to include women. Botting provides a sample of such authors of the era (5), and it is well known how much sway the women who ran Paris' salons held in the intellectual circles of the Enlightenment in Paris. Mary Wollstonecraft is the best known of the early feminists; in the late 18th Century she argued that if women simply had an education as 26 good as men's they would not only be better wives and mothers, but prove to be quite capable of equalling men in most respects, including political judgment. While she did think that men and women tend to excel in different ways, in that she considered the expectation that women would aspire above all to being a good wife and homemaker to be grossly unjust in theory and in practice, she is an early theorist of a more strictly egalitarian, 'degendered' feminism. The “first wave” fought for basic legal equality of women with regard to property and politics, and peaked with the suffrage victories obtained a century ago. It coexisted with related struggles on behalf of the poor and racial minorities to achieve fundamental equality before the law and at the ballot box. The “second wave” arose in the 1960's as a reaction to the fact that despite decades of essential equality from a legal standpoint, culturally speaking the gender roles were as strong as ever. A new generation of feminists began to take aim at cultural norms, using media as well as legislation to go beyond de jure equality and reduce the barriers that continued to keep women from matching men in the public sphere. As Rosemary Tong explains in Feminist Thought, while there were certainly theorists of difference who were either more radical or more conservative than the mainstream feminists of this era, the movement was largely directed at making it possible for women to have similar opportunities and similar lives to men (25-7, 204); that is, their goal was to expand the fruits of 'enlightened' modernity fully to women by reforming, but not overthrowing, Western social norms. This liberal movement found a unified voice through groups like the “National Organization for Women,” and achieved considerable success through the 1970's with the passage of various supporting legislation (such as 27 Title IX of the education amendments in 1972). A general consensus was established in politics and the judiciary that rooting out discrimination against women was a worthy objective and that as with racial discrimination some proactive steps would be required to overcome cultural barriers. The “third wave,” or post-modem feminism, opposed mainstream liberal feminism for its uniformity, or perceived bias in favour of educated, white, heterosexual women desiring careers. Rather than seek to make an equal place for women in the modern world, they reject the Enlightenment ideals of rationalism, scientific conquest, capitalism, etc. as incorrigibly patriarchal, and reject any institutions that seek to provide norms of behaviour and identity: especially maniage (Banaszak, 45-69). Race and sexuality take a newfound prominence in this movement. Tong asserts that diversity is cherished above all by third-wave feminists, who believe that “difference is the way things are. Moreover, contradiction, including self-contradiction, is expected and even willingly welcomed by third-wave feminists” (285). Marrying together the insights of Marxists, Freudians, and existentialists, these and other post-modem theorists have made a radical and pervasive attack on the family, liberalism, and capitalism, overturning the terms and concepts of modern thought and self-understanding. An example of this is Linda Nicholson's contribution to Feminism and Families, titled “The Myth of the Traditional Family,” where she bemoans the various stigmas attached to households with a single parent, “alternating households,” husbands taking on the role of homemaker, and homosexual couples, arguing that 28 Such family types are no more 'altemative' to what preceded them than had been the 1950's type to its historical predecessors . . . the specific type of privileging we today give to the 'traditional' family — in either its 19505 or 19905 form — has morally dubious origins, being strongly associated with the post WWII period's racism and tendencies to marginalize poverty.(28) ‘ While post-modern thought is for the most part directly influential only in academic and literary circles, the prominence of the desire to respect diversity in public debate about social issues, and an increased suspicion of institutions and long-established norms are indications of the extent to which post—modemism is much more than a scholarly fad. It has succeeded in undermining all kinds of institutions and norms, especially those related to the family and traditional moral judgments. However successful this more extreme feminism has been, in most Western nations there is a widespread expectation of the promotion of tolerance for and equality of diverse family arrangements. In light of the opinion shared by the promoters of this position that the continuing advancement of individual freedoms over institutions and social prejudices is inherently good, this group is appropriately termed “progressivist.” They have succeeded in removing from public discourse virtually any acknowledgment of any 'double-standards' for men and women, establishing the legal and for the most part social acceptance of women pursuing any career they wish and not being expected to set it aside to care for their family. Similar acceptance has been garnered for women's freedom to have sex and children outside of wedlock, or not have children at all, and divorce is easier to obtain now than at any time in history. 29 The relatively rapid achievement of these aims has met with a backlash from social conservatives and communitarians. Over the last three decades, there has been a prominent movement to encourage what are often called “Family Values” as the remedy to many of our social ills. Its proponents believe that the family plays an essential role in educating the young to be good people and in influencing adults to make responsible choices in life. Like Rousseau, supporters of family values believe in the institutional role of the family as a teacher of morals for children and a preserver of morals among adults, arguing that the wellbeing of children and society relies on the prevalence of, and indeed the prejudice in favour of, couples marrying and raising their children in a stable loving home. They believe that in order to maximize the health and happiness of the community and the individuals in it, a high esteem of marriage needs to be socially promoted and even legally protected. They would have men and women encouraged to marry and have children, and then to order their lives around commonly defined norms derived from their roles as spouses, parents, and citizens. Rousseau's advocacy of treating children's education seriously as an end in itself and his influential celebration of marriage as a romantically spiritual bond that can enhance our virtue and goodness directly contributed to the origin of this pro-family position in the wake of the more businesslike feudal model (Botting 5). In contrast to the thrust of second wave, or mainstream liberal feminism, some of these traditionalists think it important to preserve differences in the spousal role of men and women. Historically, the husband's role is to be the chief breadwinner and protector of the house and community, while the wife's is to embrace the role of chief nurturer of 30 the children and manager of the household. She might work for a wage, just as he would contribute effort to the home when not at work, but she would do so only insofar as it is necessary to make ends meet, or if it is convenient because children have not come yet or are now grown. Ideally, however, in addition to giving parental care, women would be involved with community-building activities that enhance the moral character of society, and other activities worth doing for their own sake, as opposed to that which is done for a wage. I will often refer to this perspective in the contemporary terms of “conservative” or “traditionalist”, but it is crucial to recall that it was a substantial departure from the feudal model it replaced. Above all, the freedom of men and women to choose their spouse and the priority given to raising children make this “bourgeois family” very modern; despite the gender roles, one cannot fairly say that it is merely a continuation of the patriarchal oppression of pre-modem Europe. However liberal or progressive its origins may have been, however, its supporters today tend to have a more communitarian outlook than those who argue against this family model. They fear the advance of thoroughgoing individualism because it diminishes the bonding and ennobling powers of community and culture which they consider essential to giving people better lives. They believe that to make people healthy and happy they need more than freedom from barriers; rather, they need a certain amount of moulding through education and other social guidance. For all of his love of nature, freedom, and self-legislation, Rousseau agreed that people should be guided toward a certain model of family life. 31 Without question, traditional orders are often unfairly exploitative of groups like the poor, foreigners, and (but to much more varying degrees) women. Insofar as they are traditional, however, they are not only less chafed at, but categorically less offensive than in cases where one is merely exploited for a specific mortal's ease and aggrandizement. Traditions achieve what law strives for — they are followed not because of fear of punishment, or even of embarrassment, but because acting in accordance with them is simply who one is. To the extent that they rely on the enforcement of opinion, one cherishes the opinion holders as like oneself, as those who look on you as you would like to look at yourself when you get above your passions to judge your conduct 'obj ectively'. The cumulative character of it takes the sting off of the frowning glance of any individual — it is the common wisdom working through a fellow, and not some pretentious other's reaction. Besides the fact that the source of the wisdom is usually taken to be God, its mere existence through generations makes its subjects more disposed to feel themselves part of an order, one where their personal perspective is neither the center nor the ultimate standard. It is humbling, and the capacity to subject oneself to a law outside of oneself is the core of virtue. The inability to do so is a sign of vanity and while in some geniuses it leads to noble things, in most it merely engenders vice. There are certainly reasons for a conservative like Burke vehemently to oppose Rousseau, but in many ways, and especially from a contemporary perspective, Rousseau holds some very conservative political principles. As a complement to his scepticism about rationality ruling people or cities, Rousseau thought we would increasingly become subject to the inconstant wills of individuals and the collective in the vacuum left by the 32 death of custom. Not only are we social creatures but political: in any shared enterprises there needs to be order, and because of our individuality (which features not just vanity but laziness) there needs to be an authority both to plan the order and enforce it. When the authority fell to men and institutions in a seemingly pre—ordained way, as a kind of toned down version of divine right, resignation is reasonable and one can peaceably get on with the non-political aspects of life. But when tradition is overthrown in the name of 'reason' and 'empowerrnent of the people' (which need not go together), everyone's opinion matters, and we are expected to know best how to do everything in our lives, both individually and collectively. There are bound to be disagreements, but besides the barest 'don't harm others' notions, we are left with nothing from which to appeal effectively in order to solve them. Not only do the old ways lose the power to command, but as the ideals of progressivism take hold, the old ways lose the power even to recommend. In this overturning of customs, individuals are left on their own to determine how to live. While this may seem quite promising in some respects, Rousseau believed that the institution of the family needed to be refounded in a stable way, preserving some of the traditional grounds which were conducive to its effectiveness. To put the issue more broadly, under the contemporary influence of the enlightened progressives, in domestic or public relationships between people new patterns are not just allowed but expected, and we are each supposed to chart our path according to our own lights. Anything which looks too much like the old ways is viewed sceptically, and suspected of being just a result of unimaginative, cowardly prejudice; unique modes are praised because they are a sign of progress, regardless of the kinds of 33 motivations behind them or their likelihood of success. The criteria by which we are to guide ourselves in choosing a path, though, inevitably — and even intentionally — get lowered and more narrowly self serving. This is inevitable inasmuch as asking the majority of people to follow their inclination without much outside guidance is bound to reduce things in large part to pleasure and security, and intentional inasmuch as the leading prophets of the new age want to lower our collective sights in the name of security and prosperity, both for theoretical and practical reasons. Why Rousseau is the Political Philosopher We Most Need to Study Further to Improve our Understanding of Modern Family Values Having considered the history and interrelatedness of modern theory, politics, and the family, we will close out the introduction by establishing why this particular study of this particular writer is important and necessary. We will elaborate upon Rousseau's unique perspective on the modern family and consider the reasons his contributions have been neglected in academic and popular literature on modern family values. From Machiavelli, Bacon, Hobbes, and Locke until today, 'practical' commentators have sought to end the rule of those who believed in the higher things because they inevitably clash with other idealists and all are argued to lose out when rational, material progress is dismantled in the superstitious wars that follow. Instead, these influential early modern writers felt that only a politics based on 'low, but solid' foundations and which elevates the rational over the traditional could succeed. Rousseau is a unique critic because he accepts the basic materialistic and democratic premises of 34 the modern social science which emerged in 17th Century England. Echoing Montesquieu, however, Rousseau laments that instead of political ends and debate being about virtue, politics in 'our' age is all about money (the notion that things have not changed is supported by the mantra for a winning Presidential campaign three centuries later: “It's the economy, stupid”). In a time of materialism, individualism, and progressivism, people are radically freed in terms of how they conduct their lives, and have many roles they can choose to move through along the way; this is directly opposed to 'traditional' times and places, where you get yourself used to your role as it is handed down, because it is your calling, your place. In addition to the lack of reliable guides, Rousseau warns us that even when traditional ways are improved upon, change itself can be corrupting because there is a power in the reverence for old things that is useful for generating respect for law in general. In attacking the learned progressives who would like to constantly tinker with laws and mores to gain improvements he declares that The slightest change in customs, even if it is sometimes for the better, invariably proves prejudicial to morals. For customs are the morality of the people; and as soon as the people ceases to respect them, it is left with no rule but its passions, and no curb but the laws, which can sometimes keep the wicked in check, but can never make them good. Besides, once philosophy has taught the people to despise its customs, it soon learns the secret of eluding its laws. (Preface to Narcissus, 102-3) This is Rousseau the 'revolutionary' at his most conservative, but helps us understand a key strain in his thought. He himself wishes to make reforms, especially regarding the 35 family, but for all his radicalism and polemics, we will see that most of his reforms are traditionally-minded ones which, while finding their root in our somewhat distant natures and natural relationships, also try to accommodate existing prejudices (at least when they are not too baleful, tangential, or decrepit). This will be perhaps most evident in Julie, where most of the second half consists of praise for a marriage she consented to strictly out of duty to her father, despite the vivid, enthralling depiction of romance which said respect supplants (both literally and literarily). While there is no question but that Rousseau wants romantic sentiment and future-oriented concerns to take on a much larger role than it did in this time of decaying notions of aristocratic privilege, by no means does he counsel open revolt against paternal influence. Yet, as has been said, there is a reason why Rousseau has been attacked as a revolutionary. For all his recognition of its benefits, he does not simply support traditions as such; he is willing cast some aside and utterly transform others to bring about more harmony in the liberal age he saw dawning. As we will elaborate in the next chapter, Rousseau presents some radical challenges to the existing and emerging orders, and from seemingly very different perspectives. Unlike Rousseau, many of the commentators arguing for family values (most are outside of academia) base themselves in a theologically-rooted perspective. They are often compelled to retreat to mystical dogmas such as “two in one flesh” or references to explicit commandments of God. Alternatively, they use the language of natural laws, which laws are usually insufficiently grounded in that at some deeper level they rely on some mysterious divine sanction. Insofar as this is the case they flounder in their attempts to persuade nonbelievers, even if it is here that they best persuade those who share the same faith. Like them, Rousseau is greatly concerned with the loss of shared morals and he enhances his justification for the family in a context of deism as well as natural law. Unlike many of them, though, he also celebrates the individualist impulse, refuses to accept biblical revelation as a standard, and believes that we do not have a fixed nature. We will attempt throughout this work to establish that Rousseau's teaching on the value of a strong attachment to family is effective, reasonable, comprehensive, and attractive on an individual level in ways many of our commentators would profit from imitating. This examination of Rousseau's teaching about 'family values' will touch upon the effects of stable, caring relationships on the children, but will focus primarily on its effects on adults. Not only do broken homes correlate with more crime, drug use, and unwanted pregnancy in teens, but not being married correlates with similar phenomena in adults, especially the more naturally unruly men. Unattached younger men are far more likely to be involved in crime than any other adults, and divorced men are more prone to suicide. Without strong family bonds, mass, liberal, commercial society makes it quite easy for people to become anonymous, socially detached, and underdeveloped in terms of morality and responsibility. Not only does this point away from law-abidingness, it reduces the likelihood of people being happy in their social relationships. The virtues one must develop to function well in a household are many of the same virtues that lead one to be a responsible member of society. We will see that these themes are all 37 addressed by Rousseau much more thoroughly than we have the opportunity to hear in the polarized and fragmented discussions of these issues today. Despite this claim, in the scholarly attention that is given to forestalling the perceived decline of the family (Kass, Himmelfarb, Elshtain, Popenoe, Gairdner, etc.) there is scarce mention of Rousseau, despite the great influence his argument for the legitimacy of and need for strong family bonds in the modern age had, especially in the 19th Century. Widely recognized for his impact on the Romantic movement, few commentators investigate the passionate and powerful effort Rousseau mounted to use the power of romantic love to solidify a stable, child-centered family, which he thought could in turn preserve virtue and authenticity in the face of the pressures of individualistic, relativistic, ‘bourgeois’ society. This is in part because Rousseau champions controversial views across and outside the spectrum of what today we consider bounded by the “right” and “left.” In addition to the contributions to the 'family values' camp being outlined here, anarchist, communist, fascist, unionist, religious, atheist, and conservationist groups comprise a disparate sample of those who could claim inspiration from Rousseau. Accordingly, even when his thought is not misunderstood a writer with any partisanship is reluctant to rely upon him. More often, however, he is dismissed from consideration because too much emphasis is placed on one of these diverse aspects of his thought. One otherwise very lucid commentator, for example, lumps Rousseau into an 'anti-family' group of thinkers with Plato and Marx based on his elevation of citizenship over family in the just regime 38 of the Social Contract (Gairdner). In stark contrast, Brigitte Berger condemns the “Rousseauian vision of human freedom which underlies all the demands of the current women's liberation movement” (quoted in Schwartz, 2). Despite these proto—Marxist and radically individualistic strains in his thought, he manages to still be an enemy of progressive feminists because he turns differences between men and women into the foundation of very different roles for husbands and wives (Susan Okin and Penny Weiss are two of the more objective representatives of this position). The lack of reliance upon Rousseau in the family literature is certainly attributable in part to his fame for writing 'paradoxically'. He makes dramatic and enigmatic statements such as “man is born free, but is everywhere in chains” and that people need to be “forced to be free.” But more than that, and as the references just mentioned indicate, across his oeuvre he praises seemingly irreconcilable notions such as his defence of primitive humans on the one hand and promotion of radically “denatured” Spartan-like citizenship on the other. Added complexity arises when comparing his public writing with his autobiographies and personal life. He vehemently argues against books, cosmopolitanism, and contemplation in favour of a life kept busy with practical work, devotion to family and country, and engagement with one's community. Yet he tells us in his extensive autobiographical writings that he was devoted above all to solitary contemplation, interrupted only occasionally by attempts to write books that could shape mankind for the better. He sought out a life of the mind with such determination that he withdrew from society, and refused to have any family beyond the 39 companionship of the illiterate laundress he cohabitated with for twenty-three years before marrying.5 While mainstream authors neglect to use Rousseau, there has been work done in academia on Rousseau's family teachings. Most recently, Eileen Hunt Botting's Family F euds provides a thoughtful account of Rousseau's promotion of the rural family as the essential foundation of a healthy republic. Going beyond the similarly themed work by Nicole Fermon, Domesticating Passions: Rousseau, Woman, and Nation, She interestingly weaves together the Social Contract and Constitutional Project for Corsica with Julie and Emile. She also draws out interesting parallels between Rousseau and Burke, especially with the fundamental role Burke saw for the family as the “little platoon” in which one's character and sociability are formed. Wollstonecraft is the heroine of her book, however; accordingly, her presentations of Rousseau and Burke are geared towards contrasting them — and also finding a surprising degree of similarity — with Wollstonecraft's Vindication of the Rights of Man and Vindication of the Rights of Woman. While she capably outlines the features of Rousseau's model of the domestic empress, she sides with Wollstonecraft's equality of sameness from the outset and accordingly fails to treat Rousseau's gendered version seriously. Similarly, Penny Weiss critiques Rousseau on the basis of not granting wives the same equality as he gives the husband as a citizen. Throughout our work we will elaborate upon the case Rousseau makes for refusing to treat the domestic partnership as equivalent to a political one. 5 Rousseau weakly suggests that the laws of France disqualified him from marrying on religious grounds, but never refutes his statement in the Confessions that he informed her at the beginning of their relationship that he would never marry her. Readers disposed to discredit Rousseau as an authority due to his personal example should skip ahead to the section on Rousseau‘s personal life in chapter four. 40 An author who takes Rousseau's considerations regarding the differences between men and women very seriously is Joel Schwartz, author of The Sexual Politics of Jean- Jacques Rousseau. Schwartz comprehensively details the interdependence in Rousseau's conception of marital relations, cataloguing the strengths and weaknesses of social men and women and explaining how the needs and desires of each make this a political relationship. Schwartz puts a great deal of weight on the individualistic impulse guiding part one of the Second Discourse, the autobiographical works, and others, to emphasize the equivocal character of marriage in Rousseau's larger system of thought. His observations are valuable for rounding out Rousseau's understanding of the tensions between individualism, family, and community, but his focus on these tensions and related equivocations fails to do justice to the potential utility and rhetorical intention of Rousseau's family teaching. One difference my analysis has with the vast majority of scholars who promote the family is that I do not begin from any scripturally-based or even teleological conception of how humans should live. As with Rousseau, my sole criterion is human happiness, and I assume that in different times and places much different ways of life may be most conducive to it. Most specifically, I am open to the possibility that the family may not always be a core institution required for the well-being of society. That said, I have a great deal of trouble imagining any future society that can successfully leave it behind. Rather, it seems clear to me that today, as in Rousseau‘s time, there are misguided ideologies and a thoughtless political drift that are undermining the family 41 without a conception of how the ‘freedom’ of the future individuals will concretely contribute to their happiness. Though the conservative commentators seem to be having some successes, at least in America, where there is an enduring conservative presence in government, it is clear that the religious, ‘old—fashioned’, and acerbic tone of their discussion limits its effectiveness. Though I will be discussing some ‘old-fashioned’ topics (like devotion, chastity, responsibility, and virtue) I hope to address more effectively the concerns of my contemporaries, who, like myself, agree that families are a good thing for society, but are unsure if a life committed to one is the best thing for them. I also hope to contribute to a better understanding of the principles which underlie the importance of family so as to improve our debates and decisions about the character of family in our generation. Regardless of how far I get in these aims, I am confident that returning to the analysis provided by the first major theoretical supporter of the modern family will help shed valuable light on our situation and the paths ahead. Summary of the Work Chapter One In chapter one, I show the remarkable astuteness with which Rousseau predicted many of today’s problems, especially those related to materialism and the breakdown of community. Much of the chapter explains why Rousseau opposes the Enlightenment, especially the principles of rationality and individuality that still reign today. I then 42 describe his theory of the sentiment of existence and how it sets a framework for a return to lives made happier and more meaningful either because they are more moral or more psychically healthy. His prescriptions can be seen to fall under two opposed categories: the fully ‘denatured’ patriotic life in a free and equal republic, or a more natural life which takes its bearings from human sentiments and maintains its healthiness through its withdrawal from corrupted political and civil life. In the non-political category, Rousseau variously proposes the adoption of a Christian-influenced natural religion or a life of contemplation (shared with friends if possible), but most of all he exhorts bourgeois man to dedicate his heart to his home, and fully indulge himself in his love for his spouse and children. Chapter Two Given that modern man cannot look upon his interdependent fellow citizens as brothers, most of all Rousseau supported the idea that he devote himself to the group that he cannot help but think of as family: his family. In chapter two I explain why the family is so conducive to happiness according to Rousseau’s understanding of our natures, including his conception of it as facilitating the non-alienating extension of one’s sentiment of existence. I begin by examining Rousseau’s account of the naturalness of the family in the Second Discourse and Essay on the Origin of Languages. Although he is famous for his depiction of the solitary savage in the former, we are struck by the fact that the latter 43 begins with roaming nuclear families and no mention is made of any previous condition. I analyze some of the complexities of Rousseau’s treatment of this issue, but the main conclusion is that while men and women do not strictly speaking need each other, it is by no means against their natures to live in a family; rather they are inclined to it, and it generally serves them well. This inclination is supported both by the natural affection they quickly develop for each other, and that which they instantly develop for children — especially, but not only, in the case of the mother. These affections, as well as the more advanced form of love that emerges, are the basis from which all our subsequent socialization can be understood. The full development of the family augments our happiness, as does the growth of primitive society: all this is part of the state of nature. By clarifying these natural developments, we are well prepared to turn to an analysis of why Rousseau thinks family-based community life is most in accordance with our nature, and why people should be encouraged to place their family at the center of their lives in light of the socializing effects and psychological benefits it can provide. A helpful application of Rousseau's thoughts on the importance of family values for society is in his Letter to d'Alembert on the Theatre, written between the Second Discourse and Julie. Our analysis of this work sheds light on Rousseau's understanding of how reinforcing gender expectations and sexual modesty is legitimate and can counteract the moral dangers in the advance of modernity. We will also outline some of the important advantages and possibilities of married life presented in the remarkable picture Rousseau presents of C larens, the small Swiss 44 estate where Julie lives with her husband Wolmar. Though the fact that the marriage was arranged forms a cloud that turns out never to have quite dispersed, it also brings into starker relief the benefits of marriage apart from romantic love. The effect that marriage to Julie has on the passionless, atheistic, rationalistic husband is meant to charm the most ‘enlightened’ of modems. Despite his belief in virtue simply for what it provides, he fully devotes himself to his estate and life with his wife and children there becomes the source of all his happiness. Rousseau, in his second preface, or “Conversation about Novels,” makes clear the effect he intends this depiction to have: I like to picture a husband and wife reading this collection together, finding in it a source of renewed courage for their common labors, and perhaps new perspectives to make them useful. How could they behold this tableau of a happy couple without wanting to imitate such an attractive model? How will they be stirred by the charm of conjugal union, even in the absence of love’s charm, without their own union being reconfirmed and strengthened? (J 15) These letters are also replete with references to the effect of marriage on virtue. Drawing on the experience of the very passionate Julie, who from the moment she is married finds an unexpected mastery over the forbidden but undying love she has for St. Preux, we will begin to see why Rousseau believes that “the attraction of domestic life is the best counter-poison for bad morals” (E 46). Chapter Three While in chapter two the intention is to defend the family on the larger scale as the socializing institution best suited to our natural needs, this chapter looks at the family 45 from the perspective of a boy with ordinary faculties but a strong desire to find true happiness. We explore the path of love and marriage as not only good public policy, but as that which elevates and satisfies our deepest longings. Whereas the last chapter looked to the many benefits of committed domestic partnership for men and women and their community, this chapter is about the satisfactions of love for human beings with imaginations and wonder. We will engage in a detailed analysis of how Rousseau educates Emile to be very independent but at the same time convinced that his happiness lies in a life dedicated to his wife and children. This is achieved not by the kind of abstracted meta-analysis of what is good for society presented in the previous chapter, but by an education that makes one care for virtue, respect the spirituality in sexuality, and see an order to the universe which links that which has public utility to that which is individually fulfilling. Rousseau thought the character of romantic love could be an even more solid basis than mere affection and interest in order to make us committed to and fulfilled by family bonds. Charming as Wolmar and Julie’s lives are, J ulie’s deathbed confession of love for St. Preux shows that despite all the harmony and charm in her marriage she felt the lack of something important. In the education of Emile, however much he might be suited to married life and it to him, he is clearly led into it by the means of a lofty, romantic love. It is no accident that Rousseau is thought by many to have founded ‘romanticism’: these books and the Confessions contain a remarkably thorough account of even the smallest of feathers on the wings of Eros. Few theorists put as much emphasis on the power of our imaginations and the need for humans to satisfy deeper 46 longings than simply security, prosperity, and a sense of freedom. In this chapter I argue that as an alternative to the corrupting channel of commercial ambition, Rousseau thought that the realm of love was a healthier avenue for the natural longings of modern man. While he was well aware of the dangers of its extremes, he also powerfully demonstrates the dangers that the erotic deadening of increasingly atheistic, hedonistic, individualistic people would have for the broader prospects of democratic society. This chapter analyzes almost exclusively the material from books four and five of Emile. Rousseau’s teaching on love entails a discussion of the link between moral education and sex education, as well as the significance of puberty for religion and the need for religion to help direct sexuality without distorting it. We also take up his case for the necessity of marriages being chosen by the spouses, and elaborate upon his defence of differentiating the roles and behaviours of men and women. Chapter Four Despite Rousseau’s powerful style, no doubt many of today’s youth (and tomorrow’s parents), even after shedding a tear at Julie’s deathbed, would still be profoundly sceptical about the chances and even the desirability of a life-long partnership. One reason is that the ethos of personal freedom we have proudly developed is considered to be at odds with the bondage and expectations of entering into marriage. Romantic love is still widely cherished, but many also consider it too transient to be relied upon for long-term happiness. Its fleeting character actually turns many supporters 47 of family values against it, and against Rousseau for his seductive presentation ofit. Rousseau himself, however, was very much alive to these concerns. In this chapter I take up Rousseau’s own critique of romantic love, and his attempt to reconcile the tension between the great commitment required by marriage and the desire for individual freedom that he possessed as strongly as anyone today. Certainly Rousseau is no straightforward polemicist for love at all costs, or even for the necessity of committing oneself to family life. His personal life stands out in this regard: he ‘cohabitated’ with a sweet but illiterate and simple woman for decades before marrying her in old age, and also put all the children they had into orphanages. This kind of inability to live up to one’s ideals would hardly be the first example among public moralizers, but what makes Rousseau unique is the extent to which he engages with this tension, and overcomes it inasmuch as he presents an understanding of human nature and society in which both paths are legitimated. By addressing the major critiques of the family using Rousseau’s own arguments, we will demonstrate not only that his analysis of the issue is extremely comprehensive, but that it sheds more light on the unity of his thought 48 Chapter One Rousseau's Analysis of Modernity and Happiness To take seriously the assertion that Rousseau's teaching on family life can make us happier, it is sensible to begin with an analysis of what he thinks happiness is and what the barriers are to our attainment of it. For if we are not persuaded by his conception of the problem or the goal it would hardly seem urgent to read his account of the importance of family as the solution. In this chapter, I will lay the groundwork for an understanding of the importance of the family in Rousseau's teaching by elaborating what he thinks a flourishing human is, the tensions that must be overcome in civil society generally, and the peculiar barriers we face in modem, liberal, commercial — or bourgeois — society. Above all, I hope to show that his penetrating insights into the threat that egalitarian individualism poses to our well-being are for the most part as relevant as ever, if not more so, and that his prescription for wholehearted devotion to one's family bonds not only has not expired, but has a couple of centuries of clinical trials to support it. We will begin with a brief outline of Rousseau's unique analysis of what constitutes happiness, showing that a flexible but coherent notion of freedom and inner unity is shared by all the different lives Rousseau considers happy. To help prepare the reader to grasp his teaching properly, though, we will elaborate upon Rousseau's attacks on our modern outlook before filling out his alternative understanding later in the chapter. We will first consider the more conservative and communitarian side of Rousseau's critique of the rationalism and individualism of the Enlightenment, to understand better 49 the prominence he insists that sentiment has in our existence and that community has in our well-being and capacity for virtue. We will then turn to the more radically 'left—wing' anti-bourgeois attack and his belief in the natural goodness of man to understand his critique of Lockean commercialism and the peculiarly insidious character of the modern 'pursuit of happiness'. Having made more clear what the flaws in the general modern outlook are, we will be in a better position to elaborate upon the concepts of the sentiment of existence and independence as the fundamental elements of happiness. We will close by outlining how all the themes in this chapter are reconciled in Rousseau's depiction of a true citizen. Unity and Freedom: The Consistent Core in Rousseau's “Radicalism” Rousseau writes in praise of ways of life that might easily appear to be utterly incompatible. The paradigmatic opposition is that between the citizen and the solitary. The first feels so utterly subsumed under the duties and laws (or general will) of his sovereign state that his existence, identity, and happiness are entwined to the utmost with that of his fellow citizens; the solitary’s life is utterly independent of all human things but those which lie within him. Rousseau defends these radically different lives as happy because each is unified and free. The true polity unites our social, religious, and erotic longings within a stable and genuine community within which we feel whole. It is stable because of the sacredly trenchant character of custom and law which govern it, and genuine because of the sincerity and depth of the shared existence of the members. These citizens are entirely free insofar as they align their wills with the law; unlike most modem 50 theorists, who sought merely to make conflict manageable, Rousseau believed that good laws with good education could virtually eliminate conflict. As a solitary, one is more obviously unified and free. Rather than finding a common basis upon which to unite with others, however, the solitary finds unity by divorcing himself from all social ties, and finding wholeness within, or in his unique relationship with the world. These alternative models are presented as a contrast to the bourgeois: the small- minded, self-centered, dependent yet anonymous product of the 'modem' age. The bourgeois is neither free nor unified. Rousseau argues that we have had our natural freedom and self-concern mostly replaced by a very artificial, unhealthy vanity, or amour-propre, rendering us: double men, always appearing to relate everything to others and never relating anything except to (our)selves alone....Swept along in contrary routes by nature and by men, forced to divide ourselves between these different impulses, we follow a composite impulse which leads us to neither one goal nor another. Thus, in conflict and floating during the whole course of our life, we end it without having been able to put ourselves in harmony with ourselves and without having been good either for ourselves or for others. (E 41) F uelled by imagination, amour-propre typically creates a fictional world that corresponds more to what people would like us to be, and what we would like to be in their eyes, than what is natural to us. For perspectives which take nature to be flawed, this creation of culture or civilization beneficially, even redemptively alters our world. We will see that in the example ofthe citizen, and to a considerable extent in all civilized lives including the dedicated spouse, Rousseau agrees that the artificial addition of civilized concerns 51 can be a notable improvement. Far too often, however, when we go beyond nature we do worse: Rousseau has a unique mistrust of society and “progress.” Led chiefly by our unsocial ambitions, we generate conditions where we shrink or split our existence around those we are dependent on but still regard as enemies. Insincerity eats away at us tainting any of the satisfactions we obtain. It will still be the case that the family — and indeed any human life — will involve illusion, or creation, but as we will see with the example of the citizen, and then next chapter in the family, there are ways Rousseau wants to teach us to make this power act in accordance with nature, or more specifically the nature of human happiness and society. Rousseau believes in the goodness of nature. This does not mean that we are morally impressive by nature, but that there is not in our origins much strife or misery: our natural condition was not a war, but it was beastly. Rousseau admits that selfishness is natural, but by nature our love of ourselves is benign to others and good for us because we are independent and have little trouble tending to the few desires and needs we have. Our independence in nature makes us strong. Strength, according to Rousseau, is relative, and determined by the degree to which our powers exceed our needs. While on the one hand modern society seems to provide its members with life’s essentials far more reliably than in other times, we have long since lost the ability to provide for ourselves, and in so doing we are weaker — at least as individuals. Becoming rich is not the same as being strong, for rather than making you self-sufficient, it creates dependence on guards as well as servants (which goes a considerable way towards describing our dependence on the political order). One need only consider the effects of a one-day, or one-week, 52 “power outage” on our lives to see how powerless we can easily become ~ which is to say how powerless we have become. In his description of how wealth and property have made slaves and enemies of us all, he charges: having formerly been free and independent, behold man, due to a multitude of new needs, subjected so to speak to all of nature and especially his fellow men, whose slave he becomes in a sense even in becoming their master; rich, he needs their services, poor, he needs their help; and mediocrity cannot enable him to do without them...in a word, competition and rivalry on the one hand, opposition of interest on the other, and always the hidden desire to profit at the expense of others. (SD 156) Rousseau uses two terms which can both translate into self-love to describe this difference: amour de soi is the healthy, original form of it and amour-propre is the civilized form. Amour-propre is appropriately a reflexive formulation: it is informed by the image we believe we project in society. This kind of vanity is highly dependent upon the way our appearance is judged by others, and inasmuch as our society does not judge soundly, it is necessarily tainted. By tracing all our vices to vanity, and describing our natural state as that which existed before vanity arose, Rousseau is able to redeem us without turning to the church, schools, or state for large-scale help, as most alternative understandings do. In fact, the remedies proposed by Christianity, Plato, or Hobbes all turn out to be closer to the crux of the problem: each relies on a mix of abstract thinking and instituted authority6 — the main developments which brought our corruption upon us. By making vanity a 6 The latter is arguably not the case with Plato inasmuch as his ideal rulers are natural and not 'instituted'. 53 modification of otherwise praiseworthy self-love, instead of a separate element within us (thumos, or sinfulness) Rousseau can also maintain that we are by nature not only good but unified, and that it is the distortion of our self-love caused by the 'progress' of civilization that renders us miserably torn, not some inevitable element of our individual or even collective natures. In certain respects, the extreme models of the true citizen and the solitary coincide with the warring camps in our family debates discussed in the Introduction. Communitarians and traditionalists, like the citizen, cherish their bonds to the broader community. They believe that the maintenance of various and wide-ranging standards of conduct is an important educative role that any civilization worth the name must embrace. lndividualists are obviously attracted to the more radical notion of freedom embraced in Rousseau's defence of solitariness, and his attack on the hypocrisy and oppression in most social and political authority from which it emerges. Rousseau presents these alternatives in their extreme forms to properly contrast them with the unhappy bourgeois, who is set apart above all because he lacks the unity of either the citizen or solitary. He is told he is free to pursue his happiness selfishly, but finds himself in need of the assistance and good opinion of a multitude who have been encouraged to be just as selfish as he. His economic and social dependence is devoid of the sweet bonds of love or sincere commitment to an ennobling community that can make freedom worth giving up. He is constantly forced to care about the respect of people he neither respects nor otherwise cares about. The citizen genuinely cares for and respects those in his community; the solitary is freed from any such cares. 54 Acknowledging the rarity of either the noble citizen or happy solitary, in most of his writings Rousseau encourages us to cultivate and embrace a position that combines the two: devoted parent and spouse. The family, unlike the city, has strong natural bonds which impel us to embrace responsibilities towards each other, and these bonds in turn reduce the (also natural) pull of individualism that detracts from any true feeling of community. In families, most notably in the relationship between parents and children, we see repeated throughout history the phenomenon of people freely sacrificing for a common good, which phenomenon all legislators have endeavoured to instil across whole societies. While there is a kind of parallel between the family member and the citizen, then, the family is also so small that insofar as it is capable of being self—sufficient it can achieve a substantial degree of solitariness in the sense of healthy isolation for its members as well. When we are happy in our family setting, we can ignore the pressures of vanity, profit, and dependence in the outside world that the solitary shuns and which threaten the bourgeois. Rousseau's justification for commitment to the family lies in his contention that happiness is found in the unified extension of the sentiment of our existence, and in the argument developed throughout his works that our natures are constituted such that the best hope most of us have to achieve the delicate blend of independence, sincerity, and sociality is to be dedicated to family life, preferably located in a rural or other small community. In this chapter I will explain the basic features of Rousseau's penetrating and influential account of what the typical modern barriers to attaining happiness are (such as rationalism, alienating interdependence, and vanity), and then return to his account of what happiness requires. I will close by outlining how his 55 conception of family values emerges from a profound analysis of the tensions between our natures and modern society and why it is the practical altemative to true citizenship. The Reasoning Behind Rousseau's “Right-Wing” Rhetoric and Attack on Rationalistic Individualism Rousseau is by no means a typical political theorist. He writes with a more passionately polemical style than one normally finds, and in addition to a few more formal treatises he composed plays, novels, and autobiographical work that not only succeeded as entertainment but served to educate readers and elaborate his teaching. In this section we will show how Rousseau's opposition to the Enlightenment was not only political, but epistemological and pedagogical. Understanding this prepares the path not only to grasping his conception of happiness and support of the family, but his manner of persuading his audience to pursue family bonds as the best means to happiness. Rousseau's teaching is directed against the prevailing unhappiness he felt was sweeping across Europe. This mood arose out of a loss of a sense of community, and the attendant focus on individuality without sufficient grounds for fulfillment or direction. Under the reign of the church, Christianity had supplanted classical citizenship, and the existence of clerical authorities continued to be a practical and theoretical barrier to national self- government. Rousseau criticizes in various ways the effects of this hegemony, especially regarding the shortcomings of its emphasis on otherworldliness and the inherent practical tendency towards corruption in any system where the elites hold authority over the fate of people's eternal souls. Insofar as religion contributes to the 56 morals and spirituality of a people, however, he praises it. He makes clear in the “Profession of Faith” in Emile and elsewhere that he thought irreligiosity had a pernicious effect on morals and character. As has been more or less the case since then, religion in his time was in decline, as were the monarchies that had for the most part entwined themselves with it in one way or another. He saw that the logical consequence of these related phenomenon was that very little would hold modernized communities together but economics and laws which did little more than preserve property rights. Accordingly, the period he found himself in was by almost any measure a turning point from the life of inherited duty prescribed by the hegemonies of Monarchy and Church to one where people were expected to decide for themselves what was moral and good in life and determine how to pursue it. Whereas most celebrate the remarkable advancement of individual freedom in modernity, even in concepts shaped by Rousseau himself, he often wrote of the dangers he foresaw in the coming centuries. As will be elaborated below, he diagnoses vanity as the central cause of our unhappiness; individualism is accordingly especially invidious inasmuch as it does not generate independence, but unleashes vanity from the constraints of tradition and community- mindedness. As discussed in the last chapter, traditions not only place all individuals under their shadow so that none can shine too brightly, but in their cumulative effect they prescribe and codify a way of life, habits or mores that give guidance and boundaries for us in choosing among the seemingly infinite variety of lifestyles one could partake of in a single lifetime. We are naturally excited by the prospect of shaking off the duties — indeed all expectations — placed upon us by authorities we do not feel close to or trust. 57 Rousseau saw plainly, however, that popular opinion would continue to buffet us so long as we were attached to anything public; moreover, this opinion would not necessarily become better guided by being unhinged from tradition. Family values are a case in point: Rousseau attacks many of the traditional nomrs around marriage and children, but also demonstrates that as practices were coming to be determined by the innovations of fashionable and self-centered opinion, they were in important ways getting even worse. He is often progressive and conservative; a task of this chapter will be to persuade that it is less Rousseau's inconsistencies than ours which makes him appear to many to be overly paradoxical. We will begin by unpacking his teaching on the tendency of reason and individualism to promote vanity and degrade happiness by undermining community, healthy sentiments, and virtue. The hope which characterized the Enlightenment is that reason will rule for the common good once it is unshackled and supplants the superstitions of the past. Rousseau in all his books emphasizes the need to be wary of the necessary shortcomings of reason in matters political as well as moral, metaphysical, academic, literary, pedagogic, etc. He rose to fame with his attack on the intellectual class in his Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, where he made an award-winning argument that not only is science likely to undermine the virtue and character that keeps societies good, but science requires leisure, which in turn requires luxury, and luxury necessarily corrupts. Having chastened the men of letters as well as their patrons, he then made them his enemies when he showed them how serious he was by filling out the principles of his largely anti-civilization 58 perspective in the Discourse 0n Inequality and summarily moving out of Paris to the woods!7 After fleeing urban life, he wrote works that, among other things: explained the origin of language, or logos, in love and music; praised romantic love and domestic bliss as the antidote to the illnesses inherent in aristocratic and bourgeois life; and, in his masterpiece Emile, argued that the key to a successful education was to keep a child isolated from society, especially its books. It is necessary to explore the foundations of this great thinker's hostility to reason and the rule of rationality, for it is crucial to being able to grasp his praise of love and family as well as his conceptions of virtue and happiness. Rousseau teaches that we are passionate creatures more than rational ones, that our love of self has primacy over our love of truth, and that love of virtue is almost always worth far more than knowledge of it. He also questions (in his own voice but perhaps most movingly through the Savoyard Vicar) whether there even are any authoritative moral truths that can be found solely by reason; that is, without the heart or conscience — fuelled by some supra-rational element within us — being the ultimate judge. Alongside these pious notions sit observations regarding the similarity between man and the other animals, and an emphasis on the impact of sensations on us and the manner in which these combine with experience and instinct: a materialistic analysis which makes us humbly question in a radically different way our notions of reason-based morality. 7 To be more accurate, he first moved to an old groundskeeper's lodgings on a large estate owned by an acquaintance who became one of his first patrons, Mme. D'Epinay. He regularly joined her evening company, which included many leading Enlightenment figures, but not without mixed feelings, according to his Confessions. 59 We will consider more fully in the next chapter his famous reconsideration of what in fact natural man would look like and the implications that his more pacific and. inherently contented version have for any who seek to use human nature as guiding principle for political theory. What is pertinent here is that in his characterization of our natures, our unique intelligence is a late addition. While its emergence certainly has a profound effect on us, our natures were largely fashioned before our rational capacities evolved. While Rousseau is hardly the first thinker to suggest that the average person is guided by passions which are not produced or adequately directed by their reason, he goes much farther than most in defending the non-rational aspects of human life; specifically, he presents a model of human happiness which is threatened — often fatally — by too much reasoning. Like Hobbes, Rousseau thinks reason is ultimately a tool for the aid of feeling (though with conscience it would seem to be a divine one); also like Hobbes — but perhaps more than any great thinker, and from his First Discourse onward — he is severely sceptical of the tool's usage in the hands of mortals, proclaiming that its chief beneficial use is in undoing all that millennia of its misuse has done to our internal and social constitutions. He repeatedly condemns books and their authors for their corrosive effects on the souls of their readers, who write to shine in literary circles as opposed to improving the lives of their fellow citizens. “Virtue” is the “sublime science of simple souls,” he declared in his first writing, avidly maintaining that 'knowledge' — i.e. 'Enlightenment' — does not equal happiness: on the contrary it is for the vast, vast majority the chief obstacle. He devoted his last days to elaborating in The Reveries of the 60 Solitary Walker how daydreams and an absence of constraint let him immerse himself in his sentiment of existence, and how this alone — not the pursuit or attainment of wisdom — made him as happy as he had ever been. Reason is not the bright sunlight that will lead us out of our lowly condition but the torch which has burned our beards after leading us down into ugly, dark, holes. It has left us despairingly lost much more than it has given us helpful light. Whereas for theologians and some leading philosophers the unruly passions in us are usually seen as proof of original sin or desire at war with reason — i.e. constitutional flaws in us that can only be overcome through the most extreme piety or wisdom (if at all), Rousseau instead attributes the cause to developments forced upon us by the unnatural effects of society. In this he resembles Hobbes, in that both consider selfishness natural and not evil - but unlike Hobbes he does not consider this selfishness across the species (unaided by the rule of reason) to result in an evil condition. Whereas Hobbes saw life as characterized above all by desire, Rousseau sees wholeness at the core — natural desires are extremely few since “the only goods he knows in the universe are nourishment, a female, and repose” (SD 116). Human adaptability, to speak simply, means that there is not a general condition of scarcity but plenty. Rousseau acknowledges that there will be occasions where one might take the food or shelter of a weaker fellow rather than do the work himself, but posits that this does not result in war because without vanity the weaker will simply find more elsewhere, and not plot the prideful revenges and diffident pre-emptive strikes that define 61 Hobbes' natural condition. There is no lust for glory or resentment in Rousseau's original condition. The loser sees nothing but a random act — as if the wind had blown his food over a cliff (SD note (0)). There is no maliciousness in the transaction because before the conception of reputation, which is the object of vanity, the only thing that affects our actions aimed at self-preservation is 'natural' pity, which is a repugnance to see or hear suffering in others. The self-love which propels us to forestall our own suffering is also originally tempered by a lack of foresight, or a general ignorance, reflected and protected by an extremely crude, essentially domestic language. We might add Rousseau's assertion that humans are incredibly lazy to round out his drastic revision of Hobbes' desiring, fearful, plotting natural man. And solitariness — Rousseau's most radical (but as we will see perhaps also his most tentative) feature of our natural condition — ensures that we have no dependence on another often-scarce commodity: the positive goodwill of others. We will explore in detail how the family remains natural so long as it remains 'solitary' in chapter two. Rousseau de-emphasizing the significance of reason in our natural constitution has various implications upon his political outlook and rhetorical style. Instead of widespread knowledge combined with the freedom to make one's own opinions and publicly challenge prevailing beliefs being the means to public felicity, Rousseau argues that it is the general character of the passions that are produced by a way of thinking - judged in terms of happiness, or sentiment — that decides the worth of the way of thinking, and not the 'truthfulness' of it.8 To illustrate this point, consider the following 8 After the hostile 'Frenchman' of his Dialogues overcomes his prejudices, he says: 62 defence oflove's irrationality in Emile: “In love everything is only illusion. I admit it. But what is real are the sentiments for the truly beautiful with which love animates us...Does the lover any the less sacrifice all of his low sentiments to this imaginary model?” (391). While this is an extreme example that Rousseau later qualifies, he believes that things like taste and ideals are essential guides to good conduct, and can never be reduced to the level of rationality without their power being compromised. Reason has limited authority in our imagination and the spiritual elements which guide our will, which means that it cannot be the standard we rely on. The fallibility of reason is also problematic because it means that we will come to many different opinions if left to make them on our own. From a political perspective, it is often more important that opinions be held in common than that they be close to the truth, or open to improvement. The First Discourse critiqued the 'advancement of arts and letters' because this advancement necessarily brought with it a decline in the unity of a community and the respect for the simple virtues upon which a harmonious society relies. The flaws in the principles upon which the authority of most if not all political structures are based are covered over by pieties of one sort or another, and so the widespread celebration of rational enquiry into the legitimacy of social opinions degrades social cohesion. Only in the most oppressive cases - those calling for a revolution — does Rousseau think the advancement of rational scepticism can be beneficial. In order to judge the true goal of these books, I didn't apply myself to picking apart a few scattered sentences here and there; but rather consulting myself both during these readings and as I finished them, I examined as you desired the dispositions of soul into which they placed and left me, judging as you do that it was the best means to penetrate through to that of the Author when he wrote them and the effect he proposed to produce. I don't need to tell you that in place of all the bad intentions that had been attributed to him, I found only a doctrine that was as healthy as it was simple, which without Epicureanism and cant was directed only to the happiness of the human race. (O.C. 1.929-30; D 209) 63 Clifford Orwin helpfully encapsulates the challenge to public enlightenment in this position when he concludes that: If in every society not reason but opinion will reign, it follows that we must not judge the reigning opinions in terms of their reasonableness in the primary sense — i.e., their correspondence to the conclusions of reason. The indicated standard is rather their reasonableness as opinions — i.e., their adequacy to the social task of opinion. Not truth but health is the test of opinion — and Enlightenment, as Rousseau will contend in the Discourse, promotes a climate of opinion as harmful as it is bogus. He thus implies the necessity of contriving a viable alternative to it. (Orwin, 176) Reason certainly aids us in understanding the order of things, and even in sensing that there might be one, but it is the passionate love of order that makes us not only act in accordance with it, but seek to know it as best we can. Virtually all political philosophers are aware that the moral and political elites always have substantial influence in dictating what is publicly acceptable; Rousseau, like no other besides perhaps Plato, emphasizes that those in positions of authority (whether in government, society, or the family) also need to recognize that they have a great influence in determining whether the citizenry willingly does what is 'acceptable', whatever it is. That is, beyond setting the appropriate limits, or promoting the correct model of just behaviour, there is an even more fundamental role in disposing the members of the community to respect limits and models, or to love contributing to the general order. Both writers saw this as a far superior method for influencing behaviour than a strong police. This explains why Rousseau calls the Republic an educational treatise and why he says that education is 64 “certainly the State's most important business” (PE 223). It also helps explain why he suggests that censorship is an important part of education — and not only for children. More than Plato or any other thinker before him, however, Rousseau believes that this disposition towards respecting order and caring for others must be instilled from infancy by loving parentsg Marriage resembles patriotism in that both are threatened by the Enlightenment's push to promote reason-based individuality. Despite its even greater natural basis than particular civil societies, marriage as an institution is artificial (at least in the pledge for life-long exclusivity and support); accordingly, and this is what is so fundamentally offensive to libertarians and egalitarians, Rousseau believes that there must be prejudices built into social opinions and law according it an exclusively privileged status. Moreover, just as patriotism requires the directing of inchoate longings for a meaningful order, taking advantage of the potential in sexuality to romanticize marriage is a crucial step in strengthening it, especially in the face of the declining power of traditional and social opinions. Rousseau 'romantic' side, which so many traditionalists see as a direct affront to their idea of the institution, emerges out of a connected understanding: he believes our imaginations inevitably play a central role in all of our lives, but could play a 9 This emphasis on patriotic education, censorship, and following a general consensus whether it is in accordance with the 'truth' or not, has engendered a vocal field of criticism from both the left and the right. As indicated in the introduction, Rousseau is often accused of counselling totalitarianism and cited as a major precursor to both the fascism and communism of the last century. While this is not altogether unfair, it goes considerably beyond the scope of this work to consider it, and fortunately others have addressed the charge adequately (see Chapman, Rousseau: Totalitarian or Liberal or Melzer (95-1 1 1)). It is nonetheless true that, because political society is fundamentally artificial, he does believe that a successful polity requires a certain degree of nationalistic impression-making on the youth if they are to be happily dedicated members. We will explore the issues surrounding sex education and romantic love in chapter three; Bloom provides the best overall treatment of the subject. 65 bigger and healthier one if we were in a patriotic environment, and/or in one which held up a model of romantic marriage as a worthy goal. This brief overview of the importance he places on what one could call “erotic education” in the light of his critique of rationalism helps us see why Rousseau is very sceptical of a strategy like declaring some universal rights of man to be self-evident and leaving people free to recognize them as such with the aid of an 'objective' education (whatever that might be). Also, despite his own scientific approach to some of these issues, he fears the consequences of a move to make science and individualistic free thought utterly dominant in society over religion, traditional morality, or any other form of shared ideals. Instead, in the very scientific Social Contract he declares the need for a “Civil Religion,” which strongly affirms the rather vague notion that a providential God reinforces morality, and approves of (all) the laws of the state. He insists that the magistrates are responsible for administering a fairly comprehensive form of censorship, especially from foreign influences. He also suggests that a founding Legislator would have to persuade the vulgar of his surpassing wisdom with the use of miracles. These dangerously subjective and illiberal notions are the source of considerable opposition to Rousseau's political thought; however, many fail to recognize that like Plato's Republic, the regime of the Social Contract is his presentation of the elements that would make up the most legitimate state possible: it is an ideal. In illustrating how far Enlightenment politics is from what Rousseau thinks the ideal community could achieve, the effect is less to inspire radicalism than to moderate one's enthusiasm for the 66 possibilities of citizenship. Instead, it is the prominent place of the family and its humanizing role which is the biggest source and safeguard of whatever hopefulness Rousseau might have for restoring or preserving virtuous communities in the scientific future. In the following chapters, we will see that he has a thoroughgoing pessimism about the possibility of a true polity; rather than the home being a subordinate breeding ground for nationalistic citizens, he raises the family unit up to the status of being at least a rival community to the polity in order to combat the power of unjust regimes and their unhealthy educations. Recognizing these two related features of his thought, his suspicion of reason and his politic style, brings to the fore two elements in Rousseau's thought that make it difficult to grasp his teaching confidently. The first is the belief he shares with Plato, that the true knowledge needed for properly ordering human affairs10 is at best extremely difficult to acquire, and even harder to communicate; thus we should not expect these truths, if present, to be easily understood in his writing. The second emanates from his explicit charge against the proponents of the Enlightenment regarding their lack of concern for the potential effects of their 'proj ect' on the health of opinions in their polity. While he shared most of their animus against existing institutions, he saw the practical embodiment of their new Enlightened and denuded regime in the weak, fashion-minded aristocrats of his day along with the flat bourgeois money lovers. Faced with this bleak future he dedicated the bulk of his efforts to replacing the debunked pieties with higher ideals more firmly based in reason and nature but not simply reducible to these modern '0 Especially the affairs of others — i.e., as required of a Legislator; conversely, Rousseau contends that the essence of personal virtue is accessible to the commonest among us if we are not too disfigured. 67 standards. This should make us wary in reading Rousseau himself: that is, aware that he might be less than forthright — if not intentionally misleading —- regarding knowledge that may be harmful to the healthy opinions of members of his audience. This is what in large part makes an author 'political' — keeping the impact on the reader’s opinions (and not just mood or knowledge) in mind while writing — and in this sense Rousseau's books are outstandingly 'political'. Rousseau speaks regularly of who his intended audience is for a given work and occasionally of how that affects what he says— he even signs his works differently for different audiences. As an added complexity, for both prudential and pedagogic reasons he says some of his most intriguing things through characters, such as the “Savoyard Vicar” in Emile, “Rousseau” in the Dialogues, and the letter-writers in the novel Julie. His second-last major work, Dialogues: Rousseau Judge de Jean—Jacques is a conversation between a sympathetic Genevan (named “Rousseau”) and a hostile “Frenchman” trying to reconcile the virtue and goodness the former sees in “J ean-J acques'” books with the monstrous opinion people have of him in France. It is of little wonder that so many commentators consider Rousseau not just paradoxical but schizophrenic; with the help of some of his best commentators, however, we will see in this chapter why Rousseau's claims to have a consistent system of thought are legitimate; through elaborating in the rest of the work the complex case he makes for the family in modern life we will make this coherence even more manifest. In this vein, we will now turn to aspects of Rousseau's critique that would be considered from the other extreme of the political spectrum. 68 Natural Goodness and Modern Slavery: Rousseau's Critique from the Left While Rousseau is not generally considered to be conservative, we outlined in the introduction and the last section many of the reasons he supports religion, censorship, public standards of conduct, authorities embracing a role of community bonding, as well as his distrust of too much individual freedom.H There is, however, cause for less careful commentators to overlook this side of his thought because he is even more profoundly a critic of authority, wealth, inequality, and the marketplace. While Rousseau has deep concerns about people's ability to be guided by reason and the breakdown of community traditions, he also attacks the Enlightenment from the left in opposition to its emphasis on reducing freedom to the freedom to make money, or the tendency to reduce equality to equality in pursuing financial success. In this section we will focus on the more peculiarly modern problems caused by the success of these principles and the (sometimes) subtle but pervasive dependence and vanity in our overly developed societies. We will begin by describing his unique presentation of natural goodness, for it is the foundation of his critique of modern dysfunctionality. His belief in natural goodness in fomrs all his works, especially the Second Discourse and Emile. In the latter, for example, the epigraph (a quote from Seneca) is “we are sick with evils that can be cured; and nature, having brought us forth sound, itself helps us if we wish to improve,” and his opening sentence declares that “Everything is H I again ask the reader's forgiveness for the crudeness of my generalizations with regard to the tenets I attribute to conservatives, liberals, etc. 69 good as it leaves the hands of the Author of things; everything degenerates in the hands of man.” After outlining his case for our natural goodness in the first section of the book he intones: “Let us set down as an incontestable maxim that the first movements of nature are always right. There is no original perversity in the human heart. There is not a single vice to be found in it of which it cannot be said how and whence it entered” (E 92). Most of his works consist of an elaboration on this central theme — the genealogy of the heart and soul of human beings, from our original goodness to our degeneration “in the hands of man.” Our natural goodness does not mean that originally and deep down we are little angels. Rather, we are simply not disposed to cause trouble for others and in the primitive condition are not compelled to by social competition. In his preface he explains that there are two pre-rational principles that guide the natural man of the Second Discourse: self-preservation and natural pity. While there was not a general condition of scarcity that forced us regularly to choose between these two impulses, he acknowledges that when forced to do so we would act for our own well-being before another’s. This original pity is simply an aversion to the suffering of others,12 and with quiet imaginations and full stomachs, there is plenty to guard against a condition of war. Natural man, he explicitly states, is amoral — but good. To a considerable extent, this goodness is essentially that of a bear, or other animal that is essentially solitary but very able to take care of himself and a few offspring. '2 In a recent Jules Masserman study, monkeys soon quit inflicting electrical shocks on their fellows even for food rewards. 70 Our corruption is caused above all by dependence, a phenomenon much broader than not 'owning the means of production'. In fact, Rousseau suggests that the rich are even more enslaved than the poor: not only do they have more business going on with more people, including employees, but they have more at stake in maintaining the social order. “Your freedom and your power extend only as far as your natural strength, and not beyond. All the rest is only slavery, illusion, and deception” (E 83). The rich rely on the goodwill of so many, and get so much of their happiness from things relying on — and envied by — so many that they are the most vulnerable. Rousseau compels the reader to imagine a kind of Machiavellian, if not simply modern 'success': Take everything, usurp everything; and then pour out handfuls of money, set up batteries of cannon, erect gallows and wheels, give laws and edicts, multiply spies, soldiers, hangmen, prisons, chains. Poor little men, what does all that do for you? You will be neither better served, nor less robbed, nor less deceived, nor more absolute. You will always say, “We want,” and you will always do what the others want. The only one who does his own will is he who, in order to do it, has no need to put another's arms at the end of his own; from which it follows that the first of all goods is not authority but freedom. The truly free man wants only what he can do and does what he pleases. That is my fundamental maxim. (E 84) One may indeed balk at the apparent extremity of this depiction, but Rousseau adds a psychological account to help persuade us of its plausibility. Excellent work has been done in recent decades on Rousseau’s influential analysis of the crisis of modern civilized life (e. g. Bloom, Melzer, Cooper). As has been indicated, individualism in a dependent and competitive social setting is the core of the problem. Our dependence makes us weak, and given the character of our society it forces 71 us to take on roles we would not choose to adopt otherwise: we are compelled to be insincere with others and ourselves. When we need the goodwill of others, the positive regard of strangers, or near-strangers, we are inevitably forced to alter our conduct to meet their expectations. We cannot and do not expect them positively to like us simply for 'who we are' (an admittedly fuzzy concept, but one which includes our peculiar lusts for tyranny and other outright defects, our more neutral but blameworthy characteristics like laziness and gluttony, and whatever positive traits we possess that threaten them); accordingly, to gain and maintain approval we become actors, disengaging ourselves from our natures, as “Incessantly politeness requires, propriety demands; incessantly usage is followed, never one's inclinations” (FD 38). As society becomes more complex, more abstract qualities than singing or strength become sought after, qualities which rely on opinion: “And these qualities being the only ones which could attract attention, it was soon necessary to have them or affect them; for one's own advantage, it was necessary to appear to be other than in fact one was. To be and to seem to be became two altogether different things...” (SD 155). We are constantly, and for better or worse mostly subconsciously, melded into a character society demands in order to survive in its midst. I 3 Rousseau argues that bourgeois interactions are generally characterized by widespread slavery and the worst parts of mastery. Our version is even more dangerous than the classical notions of tyranny or slavery because it is much more subtle, and even '3 To be sure, husbands and wives have some expectations put upon them, not all of which they might embrace from a Rawlsian original position; as we will see below, though, Rousseau argues that in addition to affection and permanency there is usually a natural basis to the classification of the sexes which does not exist in the other, artificial, realms. 72 exists under the guise of freedom. Most today try to bring about equality by ensuring that women can enter the workplace just as easily as men. Rousseau's perspective enables us to radically reconsider whether any healthy person would pursue this path if not misled by prejudice. This is a direct attack on the Lockean/American idea of promoting capitalistic individualism as the road to take in 'the pursuit of happiness'; while many have famously followed strands of Rousseau's thought in communist, bohemian, agrarian and other directions, in his writings Rousseau himself tries to steer people back into the direction of the family as a refuge from the soul-destroying tyranny of careerism. Most do not consider their modern, sanitized dependence as anything like slavery, but Rousseau argues vehemently that deep down we all feel our servitude; inasmuch as we do not, it is due to our shrunken souls — not our labour laws ensuring reasonable work hours and statutory holidays. As for our freedom to choose where we work and for whom, in Rousseau's estimation this is little more than the freedom to be enslaved by your choice of masters. Because the ‘equality of sameness’ theory of the family that prevails today relies so much on assumptions about the positive value of women having the 'freedom' to pursue a career, and because his critique combines so many relevant aspects of his thoughts concerning human relations, the rest of this section will detail his argument concerning the ills of careerism and why he considered it to be at the core of modern problems. To the notion that there is a zero-sum environment in which someone's profits are inevitably at the expense of another, pro-market supporters since the era of Locke have replied that this does not apply when a nation's wealth is growing; theoretically, an 73 expanding economy can make everyone richer. Even in cases of overall growth (i.e. a growing GDP or even a successful partnership), however, there are countless individual examples of bigger groups squeezing out smaller ones, bankruptcy, insider trading, monopolization, and in general a fear of getting cheated combined with a “desire to profit at the expense of others.” Rousseau presents a psychological analysis that could very easily be applied not only to the marketplace, but to the modern office,‘4 where you are competing with all your 'co-workers' for raises and promotions. This means that the people you spend most of your day with, and whose goodwill you rely on not only to bear your day contentedly, but to succeed at work because of your interdependence, are people you have to outshine. Not only in the more typically observed tensions between the boss and those he pays wages to, then, but within the 'brotherhood' of employees there is plenty of cause for simmering battle beneath a veneer of camaraderie. From this perspective, most careerists intentionally dedicate their energy and existence to the place where they are surrounded by their enemies. The result is powerfully depicted by Rousseau, when in response to the argument that all this interdependence forces us to cooperate and thereby forges a common good he counters: What a wonderful thing, then, to have put men in a position where they can only live together by obstructing, supplanting, deceiving, betraying, destroying one another! From now on we must take care never to let ourselves be seen as we are: because for every '4 This is less the case within most trades, since the work often speaks for itself and there is less disparity in rewards; competition also obviously goes down where seniority is the sole criterion for advancement, though this tends to give rise to different kinds of resentment. There are also obviously careers which are to some degree intrinsically rewarding. It is also worth noting that even the ancient city had many within clamouring for individual regard, which is not itself really shareable even if it is in terms of courageous devotion or justice. Still, insofar as the general character of ambition is in the sense of “who can contribute the most to the reputation of the city,” they are quite different than monetary concerns, where nobody really takes a prominent degree of satisfaction for his corresponding “contribution to GDP.” 74 two men whose interests coincide, perhaps a hundred thousand oppose them, and the only way to succeed is either to deceive or ruin all those people. This is the fatal source of the violence, the betrayals, the treacheries and all the horrors necessarily required by a state of affairs in which everyone pretends to be working for the profit or reputation of the rest, while only seeking to raise his own above theirs and at their expense. (Preface to Narcissus 100) Accordingly, an honest, independent life is not only out of reach for the rich — who need their servants and forts — but virtually all modern people. Without the cooperation of our fellows, i.e. cast out of society, few of us would expect to survive a week, to say nothing of living out the rest of our lives happily. In turn, we are compelled to make ourselves useful to an ultimately faceless, heartless entity. Within it we form friendships and pleasant acquaintances we take solace in, but the fact remains that we are not free either in our minute to minute relations or generally. We might look at the alternative of a hermit and say we freely choose this civil life with its pros and cons, but Rousseau would counter that we have been so indoctrinated since birth that we cannot get to any kind of objective standpoint from which to make this judgment — we are too weak and blind to see our bonds for the chains they really are. Not only have we borne them for as long as we remember, but they are covered enough that we almost never notice them. Deep down, however — and often not so deep — we know they are there, that we never really put them on ourselves, and that we will not have enough of a say in how they are used in the future. Moreover, Rousseau says that our indoctrination has not been done very well: we claim to preserve the essence of our natural sentiments and character but in such a tepid way that we end up with not much of anything at all, given the unnaturalness of our 75 environment. As opposed to the true citizen, whose model we will return to close the chapter, we are told that we are free individuals, and believe we pursue our own path and activities in accordance with our free desires, or 'the natural rights of man'. For the most part, we are encouraged to think of society as a means to this individual pursuit, and not the end to which we dedicate ourselves and from which we take our bearings. As a result, we spend our public lives pursuing our self-interest among others doing the same, all in a broader context we mutually regard as a means. Melzer helpfully categorizes these modem ills under two chief camps: “the twin evils of injustice towards others, and especially disunity of soul” ’ (Melzer 59). He also elaborates on how their twinning provides an answer to a major question that faces any conception of justice: why should I not strive merely to seem just, as opposed to really practicing it? Rousseau, like Plato and Aristotle, argues that gains to be had from exploitation are poisoned, that the exploitative life is one of feverish insecurity and worry. Whereas for the ancients this is condemned for making wisdom and justice impossible, for Rousseau, it makes unhappiness inevitable above all because it divides us, it breaks the unity of our existence.'5 Bourgeois man is raised to look out only for himself and live by his own standards. Yet his soul is split, because he depends on the esteem of others in order to prosper. This tension runs so deep in him that, as said above, his natural love of himself, or ‘amour de soi’ is transformed into vanity, or unhealthy ‘amour—propre’ with the pernicious result that when he interacts with others he thinks '5 A fair description of this difference would be that Rousseau sees contemplation as only one form of unified and extended existence: by no means is it the only legitimate expression, even if it is the 'purest'. 76 C) n l y of himself— and yet he cannot conceive ofthat ‘self’ except through the eyes of others. Rousseau, at the close of the Second Discourse, summarizes the difference I) e tween the 'savage' (who is guided by healthy self-love) and a civilized European: Such is, in fact, the true cause of all these differences: the savage lives within himself; the sociable man, always outside of himself, knows how to live only in the opinion of others; and it is, so to speak, from their judgment alone that he draws the sentiment of his own existence. (SD 179) T‘ hi 5 kind of existence is really none at all in our individualistic age, as he polemically d ec I ares in the opening of Emile: He who in the civil order wants to preserve the primacy of the sentiments of nature does not know what he wants. Always in contradiction with himself, always floating between his inclinations and his duties, he will never be either man or citizen. He will be good neither for himself nor others. He will be one of the men of our days: a Frenchman, an Englishman, a bourgeois. He will be nothing. (E 40) There is a lot that can and will be said about these passages. To summarize how they Pertain to the terrain we have covered thus far, the liberal principles of modernity have engendered a social and economic climate that has uprooted us from the primitive and even the premodem society which people thought of as an organic whole of which they were connected parts: we are no longer ‘Athenians’, 'Frenchmen', or 'Englishmen', but 77 s i mply 'bourgeois' individuals. We have secured our natural rights and have been 6 ncouraged to develop our natural potential (much more now than in Rousseau's time), b L1 1: not only is it a tremendously difficult responsibility to chart our individual path, we sti l 1 need the approval of many in order to move along it, with it being increasingly unc lear what will be approved of. Forced to interact with others more than ever, but si me erely caring about them less than ever, it is little wonder that individuals should be unhappy and the moral fabric tenuous. Independence and the Sentiment of Existence: Rousseau's U' nderstanding of the Good Life There is somewhat more involved, however, in Rousseau’s calling the bourgeois “r1 0thing.” How is it, we might wonder, that just because someone is torn about how to act and whom to impress they become a nullity, and not simply confused, or weakened, or even... more interesting? Rousseau teaches that the feeling of the sentiment of exi stence is the core of happiness and thereby the goal in life. He argues that when one is not unified, one cannot feel existence in a positive way: “To be something, to be oneself and always one, a man must act as he speaks; he must always be decisive in making his Choice, make it in a lofty style, and always stick to it” (40). In other words, being cOl'lStantly torn between conflicting impulses is to be nothing, whereas wholehearted deVotion to an action engenders greater existence, which brings about greater happiness. We Saw in the last section why the socially-dependent selfishness that characterizes modern life makes us “double-men” who are forced to care about the opinions of so many people we do not care about, judges who in fact are our competitors. The answer 78 to this dilemma is either to remove the competition from society (as in the ideal polity we W i l 1 close the chapter with), or become independent from the opinions of these social (:0 mpetitors. This desire for independence finds its basis in our natural condition, and its rrl Odem extreme in the solitary wanderer of Rousseau's autobiographies; in the practical rec ommendation for the majority of us it points to the 'solitary' family, where we can ex tend our existence and satisfy social longings while remaining unified because we genuinely care about and respect those we share dependency with. Unity of soul, which can also be understood in terms of sincerity or honesty, is a prerequisite for any kind of happiness. This was present in the primitive human, but he lacked the development of valuable faculties that Rousseau believes can increase our happiness so long as they do not divide us. Unlike classical philosophers, upon whose terms only the greatest thinkers and (perhaps) statesmen lived lives worth commending, Rousseau broadens his conception of happiness through his theory of the sentiment of CXiStence to include various others. So long as a human being is unified, he is happy; to the extent his existence is enlarged while preserving this unity, his happiness is increased. His theory is first put forward in the Second Discourse and elaborated upon Chiefly in Emile. The Discourse will be our focus in the first half of the next chapter, and Em i l e will be analyzed in chapter three, so this description will hopefully be excusably introductory. As opposed to the dualistic or tripartite conceptions of the soul in Christian doctrine and Plato, Rousseau posits that man is by nature one. We are indeed sensual, PaSSionate, and psychological beings, but Rousseau denies the possibility of 79 F L1 ndamentally separating these aspects in us except as intellectualized concepts.16 Rousseau rejects the attempt to isolate piety or rationality as the 'essence' of human. Rather it is the enjoyment of the sentiment of our existence, uplifting our heart and mind I) y its extension into things and people that we live for — and in line with our discussion at th e: outset, this is a unified state offeeling much more than it is one ofthinking. Savage man and Emile are perfectly free because they do everything they want. They can accomplish this while remaining good because their desires are few, true, uni fled, and in accordance with nature. Rousseau's stoic side is shown in his constant attempts to teach the reader to reduce his desires in order to be happier, declaring for ex ample that, “It is by dint of agitating ourselves to increase our happiness that we convert it into unhappiness” and that “a being endowed with senses whose faculties equalled his desires would be an absolutely happy being.” Unlike the contented Primitive, we create for ourselves needs and desires which are unattainable and thereby Pel‘rn'cious. He points his finger at what seems like the chief culprit, saying: It is imagination which extends for us the measure of the possible, whether for good or bad, and which consequently nourishes the desires by the hope of satisfying them....The real world has its limits; the imaginary world is infinite. Unable to enlarge the one, let us restrict the other, for it is in the difference between the two alone that are born all the pains which make us truly unhappy. Take away strength, 16 Although the Savoyard Vicar insists man cannot be one, there is little else in the rest of Rousseau's oeuvre to support the contention. Cf., however, Lawrence Cooper, who does an admirable job of insisting on the importance of conscience. We will return to that subject in chapter three, but suffice it to say R0‘rlSSeau offers little evidence of any religion beyond the 'natural' one of the Vicar having any effect on his thought. He does, however, refer to the 'Author of things' in enough ways and enough places to make it di flCult to consider him an atheist; granting this is not, however, the same as saying that our spirit and body are divisible. 80 health, and good witness of oneself, all the goods of this life are in opinion. (E 80-1) KO usseau retums repeatedly to the argument that our imaginations create desires that we ei ther cannot achieve, or which are not healthy, and that this is where most of our unhappiness comes from. The vain pursuit of reputation is the foremost manifestation of th i. 5 creative capacity and it has many modifications (thus the need for Rousseau to write V arious very different works to try and regulate it). While in the decent citizen as well as the husband and wife Rousseau encourages the salutary directing, or education, of the imagination as a source of strength, merely encouraging ambition or gainfulness or other (I esires that are perpetual or unlikely to be attained can be crippling. This is why Rousseau can assert rather bluntly that “all wickedness comes from weakness” (E 67), and yet can still maintain that it is amour-propre which causes our vicious actions (SD note ‘0’, 222) as well as our unhappiness. The need to be approved of is a dependence, Which when based on anything but a solid and reliable basis — such as fiiendship or virtue - i s a dangerous vulnerability. Emile, unlike the savage, has amour-propre, which involves imagination and prej udice transforming desire and perception, but as the natural man made for society, it Wol‘ks in accordance with his nature. Because he only really needs the approval of his Wi fe and a few decent fiiends — people he has chosen to depend upon because of their 800dness and judgment — it is safeguarded.l7 Rousseau's solution to the dangers of imagination is not to stifle it; nor is it simply to reduce desire to ease unhappiness, for r7 Though this chapter attempts to set out the framework for understanding how this might be so, this neceBSsarily cursory statement will be elaborated throughout the dissertation. 81 were we to kill desires for things in our power “a part of our faculties would remain idle, and we would not enjoy our whole being” (E 80). Accordingly, the primitive savages are no t an actual model for us, because their brutishness does not allow our unique im aginations the chance to grow in a way that complements our existence — the po ssibility Rousseau wants above all to engender. The importance of sincere affection in n aking dependence healthy will be a theme of the next chapter, and the presentation he n akes in support of channelling the imagination into a commitment to marriage through romantic love will be the subject of chapter three. We have seen that Rousseau uses a blend of ancient wisdom and modern principles to generate a whole new attack on the bourgeois model emerging from the En] i ghtenment movement. He rejected the shift from morals to business in the public realm as enervating of community due to the necessary vanity and insincerity that attends 00mmerce. Happiness is found in the pure feeling of the sentiment of existence, and as we have said the bourgeois man cannot enjoy this because he is never really himself. For Rousseau, one must be whole, or unified, if one is to be happy at all. One can then increase one’s happiness by extending it, something fully developed humans are naturally inclined to do. But according to Rousseau, we can only extend our existence over others as far as we can care for them for their own sake. In modern society, we are taught to care about wealth, honour, and power, and these are not shareable goods.18 Insofar as ———_\ 18 These have been approved of by other regimes throughout history, but usually in the service of, and not to Fhe exclusion of 'higher' ends like God and country. One could quibble with this contention by citing Ar lSt()tle's description of Carthage, or, conversely, President Bush's exhortation to American patriots to just keep shopping after 9/1 1, but there is a great deal to be said of the radical shift in rhetoric about 'the econOmy-. where it may often have been the truly most important political factor in various time and places, 82 this is ‘doing well’, we cannot sincerely wish it for all our fellows since we want it instead for ourselves. Among friends and family, Rousseau points out, this is rarely a fundamental problem: besides some issues concerning dependency, and even with sometimes ugly sibling rivalries, we sincerely care about the happiness of those we love and vice versa. Indeed, the extent to which their good becomes part of ours renders any strictly individualist account of social interactions limited and necessarily hypothetical. The cold environment we face in the city is radically transformed by the warmth of the hearth. We freely make sacrifices and compromises for those whose happiness is part of ours, in stark contrast with the more anonymous situations where we struggle to put on a smile while we act for others (unless we are confident of a greater repayment). Although dependency can exist without resentment and insincerity in the close-knit group, modern society is not close-knit. In contrast to claims that the co-dependency in any city can be a bond for the citizenry (most notably Plato's use of the division of labour in the city in speech), Rousseau does not see this working out psychologically except in rare cases like Sparta and the Roman republic. His theory of happiness being based in a sentiment of existence premised on inner unity enables him to push the Lockean 'captain of industry’ / congressman model —— a debased form of what Aristotle calls the “active life” (Politics Book 7) —- right off the stage of possible paths to happiness, and makes room for various new models like the patriot, the priest, the poet, the romantic lover, the pastoral family (and even an ape!) to compete with the philosopher as happy lives worth emulating. only recently has it become permissible to give money-making political priority without dressing it up in more civilized and virtuous robes. 83 To close out this introduction to Rousseau's thought, I will go over the account he gives of citizenship — the paradigmatic case by which people overcome their narrow selfishness and immerse themselves in something larger. Exploring Rousseau's penetrating and somewhat revolutionary depiction of civic virtue and the way it engenders happiness is not only useful as a template for virtue, but as a way of illuminating in their extreme the features of virtue, or social goodness, which Rousseau believes are nurtured and more likely to be found in the family. We will see in chapters two and three the ways in which his account of the family incorporates crucial elements of both patriotism and piety. The Political Solution To understand Rousseau's argument for marriage and to help put these themes into context, it is helpful to examine the depiction he gives of the true citizen, since this is the extreme case of subsuming one's will under that of an institution aimed at a collective good. Like Hobbes, Rousseau bases sovereignty in consenting to give up one's natural 'right' to everything on the condition that everyone else around you does the same. While Hobbes does not seem too eager for the government to be democratic, Rousseau is adamant that this is the only legitimate form of government, since this allows us to give up our personal will in exchange for a general will we can truly be a part of. Looked at from a somewhat more practical viewpoint, in the 'Dedicatory Letter' to the Second Discourse he speaks of the need for the sovereign and people to “have only one and the 84 same interest, so that all movements of the machine always tended to the common happiness” (SD 79). Also, whereas Hobbes limits obedience to the point where your life is at stake (since his politics are above all about safety) Rousseau insists in the Social Contract that the alienation of rights must be total (since his politics are about love of the community utterly supplanting self—concem): “If the prince deems it expedient for the state that you should die, you should die.” If we are merely hiring someone to keep us safe, it is unlikely we will sincerely be loyal, even if we respect contracts; yet, this is the thrust of Hobbes' (largely successful) argument for what politics should be based on. Rousseau insists that citizenship be the foremost aspect of one's self-identity if we are to happily live in a regime where citizenship places notable demands upon us. To avoid becoming the “double men” mentioned above, or “nothing,” - i.e. to restore our unity and thereby enjoy our existence — Rousseau’s stated preference is to make citizens love their fatherlands such that their interdependence does not have this psychically maiming effect. Whereas the savage is unified because his unimaginative desires are limited and within his power, the citizen is unified because his desires are essentially those prescribed to him by the customs of his polity and the general will: he desires above all to be a patriot, and accordingly takes on freely the duties prescribed to one. As opposed to limiting himself to his unimaginative inclinations, the citizen silences his inclinations in favour of habituating himself to that which is prescribed for him and his fellows. 85 This strikes us as most unnatural, which Rousseau entirely affirms: as indicated, the artificiality of political life requires great art to manage, and citizens' imaginations need to be educated to aspire above all to live in a glorious nation in harmony with their fellow citizens. Rousseau famously asserts that the citizen is “denatured,” he “believes himself no longer one but part of the unity and no longer feels except within the whole. A citizen of Rome was neither Caius nor a Lucius; he was a Roman. He even loved the country exclusive of himself” (E 40). The citizen's sense of self is so enmeshed in his country that he cannot think of his good apart from his community — like the team player who is sad after a loss despite playing the best game of his life, or ecstatic after winning a championship despite sitting on the bench. In the context of the above quote, Rousseau describes the citizen as one who, after running for office and losing, is pleased that there are men more capable than him to serve the fatherland. Not only is he devoid of jealousy for the winners, he does not doubt for a moment the wisdom of the people's choice. This mindset — placing one's sense of happiness in the community, and trusting the votes of your fellows to be enlightened and selfless enough to come more or less to the best solutions — is not easily arrived at, but nor is it entirely fanciful. While Rousseau is as sensitive as anyone to the internal factions that compete for dominance in society under the guise of justice and the common good, the waves of nationalism over the last four centuries and of democracy in the last two attest to the potential for us to become communitarian democrats. The fact remains, however, that Lockean liberal and commercial — or 'bourgeois' —— democracy has been even more successful in spreading itself, in part because the strictest communitarian models have degenerated into abusive 86 dictatorships whose ideology became a mere facade. Rousseau is aware of this potential (even inevitability); accordingly in his most political works he focuses more on ways to restrain the magistrates than to unify the populace. That said, the capacity to subsume oneself under a greater good is crucial to acknowledge and nourish in the face of radical individualism, for as we will see, a milder, more natural version of it — perhaps the original version of it — is what holds the family together, and provides the grounds for the kind of dedication Rousseau would have us non-Spartans embrace. His understanding of the true principles of politics and citizenship are elaborated upon most thoroughly in the Social Contract and applied practically in his writings for Corsica and Poland. We get the best encapsulation of the psychological principle behind his reasoning, however, in an illuminating passage from Emile, where he explains that There are two sorts of dependence: dependence on things, which is from nature; and dependence on men, which is from society. Dependence on things, since it has no morality, is in no way detrimental to freedom and engenders no vices; dependence on men, since it is without order, engenders all the vices, and by it master and slave are mutually corrupted. If there is any means of remedying this ill in society, it is to substitute law for man and to arm the general wills with a real strength superior to the action of every particular will. If the laws of nations could, like those of nature, have an inflexibility that no human force could ever conquer, dependence on men would become dependence on things again; in the republic all the advantages of the natural state would be united with those of the civil state, and freedom which keeps man exempt from vices would be joined to morality which raises him to virtue. (E 85) In short, he sees that the Enlightenment attempts to reduce social duties can only go so far in practice. His attempt to balance desire and duty looks more at how public- 87 spiritedness can be cultivated in wise legislation, thus enabling the citizens to willingly and sincerely work for the common good as they rule themselves in an ideal democracy. The citizen has chains (like all of us), but his are covered in garlands. In the “Dedicatory Letter to Geneva” attached to the Second Discourse, he speaks of the “honorable yoke” of the laws that is proudly worn by citizens, especially when they see. the same one borne by all their fellows: this is what it is “to live and die free” (SD 79). The husband and wife too will bear “honorable yokes” insofar as all marriages entail duties, cares, and privations which would not be chosen for their own sake but are willingly, even cheerfully, consented to as part of an identity or a role one has freely embraced. In a society where marriage is a durable institution, the actions it prescribes hold the character of longstanding laws, and are honoured as something to live up to more than they are chafed at. Rousseau's analysis provides a coherent standpoint from which one could argue that liberating marriage from the bulk of traditional expectations, or deinstitutionalizing it, would not necessarily make it easier for people to enjoy, or a more desirable commitment. Disputing over who fulfills the duties it necessarily entails could chafe much more than if the expectations were clearly defined at the outset, even if gender roles risk pushing some square pegs through round holes. Besides the practicalities surrounding the division of labour, growing up impressed by widespread social esteem for fulfilling the role of husband or wife also makes it easier to decide to commit to a family in the first place. 88 What many of his pro-family critics fail to see is that Rousseau saw the achievement of his just regime of true citizens as a monumental task unlikely of success. His political teaching seems to be aimed at persuading that only this ideal democracy is a legitimate government, but for the many who are not lucky enough to live in it, find something less corrupt than politics to devote yourselves to. To help in this, he writes about solitude, arts, religion, and of course family. Having described the general picture of what Rousseau thinks happiness is, and having outlined the barriers to it he saw in modem life, we will now chart the progressive importance family bonds, marriage, and love had on his thought. We will begin chapter two by exploring the centrality of family in his depiction of human nature and the progress of society in the Second Discourse. 89 Chapter Two Family: The Bridge Between Nature and Society In the last chapter, we surveyed the pertinent aspects of Rousseau’s thought concerning the human condition and the specific problems we face in mass, commercial society. In this chapter, we will outline Rousseau's understanding of the social value of strong families as a corrective to these dangers. We will begin with an examination of the unique place the family unit occupies in his historical account of human development, and argue that a close reading of the Second Discourse, considered alongside the related statements in other works, compels us to re-evaluate the presentation of the solitary wanderer he presents in part one as the original condition of man. In particular, we will challenge the claim that this presentation is a refutation of the natural character of the family. We will then turn to a consideration of the vital place he imagined the family occupying in modern society, analyzing the Letter on the Theatre as well as relevant aspects of the particular household depicted in Julie. While Emile is his most famous treatment of the issue, we will see here that the principles that support a pro-family teaching were well developed in the works leading up to it. With the exception of an interlude on sexual modesty later in the chapter, we will reserve most of our analysis of Emile for the next chapter, where we will _, as Rousseau did -~ turn to a detailed analysis of the choiceworthiness of family for individuals seeking profound happiness, the connection between one’s views concerning sexuality and morals, and the kind of education that can encourage esteem for family values. There we will explore the psychological, pedagogical, and erotic considerations upon which Rousseau bases his elevation of romantic marriage for modern man. This chapter will be more historical and 90 sociological: here we will lay out the macro-level observations upon which Rousseau premises his call for the promotion of family bonds for a healthy society, with the emphasis initially on human nature and later on the demands of society. The focus of the first half of this chapter will be on the argument in the Discourse on the Origin and Foundations of Inequality, often referred to (as it is here) as the Second Discourse. By tracing out the developments that bring us from a beastly condition to a corrupted, all-too—human one, we will see the pivotal character of the family: both as a natural end in itself and as a bridge to the fuller human existence found in primitive society, or “the veritable prime of the world.” This account will also help fill out the picture of unhappiness we outlined above; by locating our happiest epochs in eras where family was the chief association, Rousseau lays the groundwork for the argument in later writings that a retreat to the family is prudent for most of us because it provides virtually all of what human nature requires with virtually none of what threatens our unity. The Second Discourse presents the bulk of the theoretical foundation of all his works; while we will demonstrate the importance of the family association in it, it cannot adequately be described as a book about family values. His next major writing,19 however, emphatically is. The Letter to d'Alembert on the Theatre is written in response to d'Alembert's Encyclopaedia article about Geneva, where Rousseau takes issue with its suggestion that Geneva revoke its law prohibiting theatres; in outlining the fatal effect luxury and the arts has on republicanism, the predominant aspect of his analysis turns out ‘ '9 One could certainly suggest that the unpublished Essay on the Origin of Language is his “next major writing”; our pending discussion of it will show that it is much more overtly family-centric as well. 91 to be the character of relations between men and women. By focusing on the conservative practical application of his principles for his native Geneva, we will be able to get more concretely into the argument Rousseau makes against the alienating life in commercial society and why he thought the remedy for this is for society to emphasize the essential status of the family, including sexual modesty and the preservation of gender differences. In describing the virtues of men and women keeping separate company, Rousseau places a footnote in the Letter to d’Alembert explaining that the idea is elaborated and clarified in a forthcoming publication. This principle, like so many others, is expanded upon in Rousseau’s first attempt to reconcile many of his ideas about republicanism, families, and independence in an almost realistic setting: the extremely popular novel Julie, or the New Heloise: Letters of T wo Lovers who Live in a Small Town at the Foot of the Alps. Rousseau makes clear in his later, or “second” preface that this is meant to be a work which would inspire deeper family bonds in the face of the countervailing temptations of Enlightenment, or Bourgeois, society. He meant to provide a model for modern people by which they could reorganize their values in accordance with his conception of our natural capacities and needs. By focusing on the second half of the novel (as opposed to the romantic first half), we will see how he thought a very well— ordered family would look, how it can make its members more virtuous and durably happy, and how it functions as a small fatherland within which well-adjusted people capable of more moral and public spirited lives are bred. It is notable that the novel contains passionate and persuasive arguments against arranged marriage, but in his plot 92 the heroine breaks with her beloved and goes on to make a model family with a husband chosen by her father.20 This device in the novel allows us to separate neatly — more neatly than is practicable as it turns out — the romantic element from the rest of what goes into a marriage and family. At the end of the chapter, in discussing the barrier to the fullest happiness for Julie, we will begin a reconsideration of the kinds of love people in families feel, and this will set the stage for a new discussion centering on Rousseau’s teaching on love and the romanticization of marriage in the next chapter. Natural Man Both sides of the family debate seek to found parts of their arguments upon claims about what is natural for men, women, and children. For proof that marriage is ordained not only by virtually all successful religions and societies, but by nature itself, pro- marriage supporters usually cite phenomena such as the requirements of the reproductive process, the historical predominance of marriage, the benefits accruing to children raised by biological parents, and, more recently, even studies of the biochemical processes that incline people to love and nurture. Opponents tend to note the lack of uniformity in the family arrangements of mammals, the varying types of human sexuality, or the barbarous reinforcement of monogamy used by many societies, to argue that the institution of marriage is a blunt artificial instrument used to create confonnism and the oppression of women in opposition to the flexibility or diversity natural to human sexuality and 20 Although the practice of arranged marriage has been substantially put behind us in the western world. it is still instructive to return to the arguments in favour of each side of that issue, both for the sake of appreciating elective attachment itself, and because even in this increasingly ‘globalized’ world a substantial number of people still think this is not a prudent way to arrange such a fundamental aspect of social ordering. 93 freedom. Few authors cite nature as a guide more broadly than Rousseau. As we will see in the remainder of the work, while in most of his works Rousseau argues that nature speaks in a strong and unmistakable voice in favour of family values, in his groundbreaking initial account of human nature this is not at all clear: in fact, the truly natural man is presented as a solitary devoid of even family associations. The Second Discourse is usually referred to as a basis for interpretation of Rousseau's teachings on any subject, including the family. The biggest puzzle it presents (at least for our purposes) is his assertion that there were no families at the outset of human existence. Not only does anthropological evidence fail to substantiate this postulate, Rousseau himself never clearly reiterates the notion in any of the subsequent works we are analyzing. The statement near the beginning of the Social Contract: “The most ancient of all societies, and the only natural one, is that of the family” (SC 47)21 seems to fit better with the picture drawn shortly after the Second Discourse in the Essay on the Origin of Language (hereafter referred to as the Essay on Language or EOL), where the pre-social, grunting, independent stage of original man is assumed to feature families as a norm. It is necessary to take some time to establish why he proposes such a radical notion of asociality in his most famous account of human nature and show that even here the family is still a natural association that serves a vital function in enhancing our existence without causing alienation. 2' It must be acknowledged that this statement does not actually contradict the story of the Second Discourse since “most ancient” does not mean eternal. What is more important is that it is still emphatically natural, and we will demonstrate this to be true for the Second Discourse as well. 94 In addition to the general consensus in his other works, Rousseau makes a number 0 f statements in the Second Discourse directly attesting to the conjectural character of his depiction and the utility of the notion of the state of nature as a theoretical construct more than an anthropological tool. In the preface, he warns that the reader should not take him to be claiming to have seen our true history, “for it is no light undertaking to separate What is original from what is artificial in the present state of man, and to know correctly a state which no longer exists, which perhaps never existed, which probably never will GXiSt” (SD 92-93). He also adds, just before the beginning of part one, that “the researches which can be undertaken concerning this subject must not be taken for hi StOl‘ical truths, but only hypothetical and conditional reasonings better suited to clarify the nature of things than to show their true origin” (SD 103). There has been scholarly deb ate over these and related passages concerning the rhetorical intention in light of the preVailing philosophic doctrines of the day (Pufendorf, Grotius, Hobbes) and the obvious Clash with religious sensibilities (since Genesis provides an account of the origin of huIrlans). These debates are adequately summarized in Victor Gourevitch's “Rousseau's Pul‘e State of Nature,” where he puts forth a generally persuasive case that “The quest for the putative state of nature is a thought-experiment, a systematic “bracketing” of all arti fice and of all moral needs and relations” (3 7).22 In focusing on the description of the faInily in this state of nature, we will see that stripping natural man of family relations is a problematic but illustrative example of this, and that while there is an important \ Heinrich Meier is among the worthiest who think that there is more veracity than rhetoric in Rousseau’s epiCtion. Among other things, he notes that Rousseau goes so far as to suggest that the quite solitary Orang-utan could be a human in the original condition I fully confess that I have not discovered nature itself, nor fully grasped its meaning for Rousseau. As we go through the first half of the chapter, however 6lieve that I build an adequate case for the claim that sex differences and family are importantly natural or Rousseau, even if they never entirely overcome our individuality. 95 rhetorical effect in depicting us as utterly alone, a closer reading of the text confirms that the family is very natural. Rather than diminishing the importance of family, by trying to strip natural man of this connection and then see how it might develop, we in fact see what is natural about the family and the fundamental role it plays in the development of our humanity. In the ‘first part’ of the Second Discourse, Rousseau makes the case for human SOlitariness, which features not only independence, but durable contentment as our original condition. Taking aim at Hobbes as well as others, he argues that the unruly paSSicns which cause so much disorder today and throughout recorded history are not as inhate as is claimed; rather, they are the product of the unnatural progress of social dependence and imagination. We saw in the last chapter how he conceives of our ul'll‘uappiness as a result of our unnatural dependence, or weakness, and how in public life this weakness compels us to be insincere, which. is essentially an annihilation of outselves. He starts his speculations about what our beginnings tell us about who we are by examining our natural needs. He finds that they are essentially only those needs pettaining directly to our self-preservation, and ones which humans would usually have 1ittle trouble satisfying. In primitive man he sees An animal less strong than some, less agile than others, but all things considered, the most advantageously organized of all. I see him satisfying his hunger under an oak, quenching his thirst at the first stream, finding his bed at the foot of the same tree that furnished his meal; and therewith his needs are satisfied. (SD 105) 96 The foremost element of this, nutrition, is easily obtained: as Opposed to the other animals, firmly ruled by their instinct and limited physiology in selecting foods, man “appropriates them all to himself, feeds himself equally well with most of the diverse foods which the other animals share, and consequently finds his subsistence more easily than any of them can” (SD 106). He adds that our bodily constitutions would be far stronger than the civilized versions we see today, noting that not only do we live a much SOfier life, but that diseases are almost unheard of outside of cities or other overpopulated at'fiBaS (except when transported from them). In addition to being internally robust, Rousseau argues that savage men would not (311d in his time did not) fear much in the way of external threats. As for the beasts, he ta1