EROTIC IDENTITIES AND THE POLITICS OF SEXUALIZATION
By
Sophia Pavlos
A DISSERTATION
Michigan State University
in partial fulfillment of the requirements
Submitted to
for the degree of
Philosophy — Doctor of Philosophy
2018
ABSTRACT
EROTIC IDENTITIES AND THE POLITICS OF SEXUALIZATION
By
Sophia Pavlos
This dissertation is an investigation into how sexualized individuals, and specifically highly sex-
ualized women, navigate through experiences of sexual objectification and sexual subjectivity in
order to complicate existing accounts, and re-center the embodied experience, of the erotic. My
goal is to generate a discursive space primed to investigate the phenomena of sexualization, lust,
and desire by paying attention to not just the oppressive structural aspects, and the hyper-indi-
vidualistic “personal choice” aspects — but by looking at how these phenomena impact women’s
lives, world-building, and identity-creating practices if we understand individuals as being both
constrained by existing narratives and free to reinterpret meaning, both accountable to a commu-
nity while demonstrating capacities of personal agency and autonomy, and capable of making
choices for immediate survival as well as progressive change, in order to move beyond the
shadows of legacy to build a liberatory sexual politics.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Thank you to my chair, Kyle Whyte, and my committee, Kristie Dotson, Lisa Schwartzman, and
Jamie Nelson, for their support throughout this process. I would also like to thank my partner
Steph, and my friends Jennifer, Zach, Charlotte and Raythia, as they provided encouragement
and most importantly, editing, for the last two years. Thank you to the department of philosophy
at Michigan State University for providing me the opportunity to pursue this degree.
iii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Introduction ……………………………………………………………………………………….1
Citrus Salad …………………………………………………………………………………….. 10
Bitch ……………………………………………………………………………………………..11
Chapter 1: Phenomenology of Sexualization ……………………………………………………12
Samson …………………………………………………………………………………………..45
Chapter 2: Love a Man Dead ……………………………………………………………………46
Goodies ………………………………………………………………………………………… 82
Chapter 3: The Power of Pleasure ………………………………………………………………83
Daddy ..…………………………………………………………………………………………120
Chapter 4: False Consciousness ………………………………………………………………..121
Conclusion ……………………………………………………………………………………..158
WORKS CITED ……………………………………………………………………………….162
iv
Introduction
My old philosophy department had two big glass doors at the entrance, above which read
a quote by Plato: “Philosophy begins in wonder.” It was a little pretentious, but so was I as a
young philosopher-in-training. In those early years, I understood Plato’s remark as referring to
the big questions: What is the meaning of life? What does it mean to be a good person? What is
existence? These were lofty questions, and I felt important contemplating them.
And then I realized that in my philosophy classes, we only studied men’s thoughts, many
of whom explicitly disparaged me, calling me the darkness to their light, the irrational to their
rational, the unknowable to their known. It was, in some ways, mortifying, because I had thought
I was one of them. I, who studied Aristotle, and Hume, and Kant, and even Hegel, hadn't noticed
that it took four years to read words written by a woman because I had assumed that these men
spoke for me, too. So much for my insight and superior intellect.
Forced to reconcile this particular blindness, I reconsidered what it meant to be a woman
in philosophy. I learned to read ‘men’ in the particular rather than universal, recognizing that it
had most likely been written with that intention. After all, I was in a space not meant for me,
studying the knowledge of people who, at best, hadn't considered women as philosophical sub-
jects, and at worst, considered women to be subhuman, especially in terms of their intelligence.
It was…disheartening.
And so I turned to feminist theory, looking for well articulated critiques of the field that I
had until recently felt a part of, and then suddenly apart from. And I found those critiques —
about the lacunas inherent in the traditional male perspective, the phallocentric metaphysical
tropes, and the gendered dichotomies of knowledge — but I also found so much more. I found
!1
women engaged in world building through knowledge production, and the worlds that they cre-
ated sparked in me a new kind of wondering: What might it mean to be a woman in philosophy?
What did it even mean to be a woman in the world?
This line of questioning has led me to wonder about the quality of life I can expect as a
woman. Especially as the type of woman that I appear to be. I wonder what it would take to feel
safe. I wonder what the world would need to look like for someone like me to flourish. I wonder
what would have to change to not have to change myself, and still be treated with dignity and
respect. And, most pertinent to this dissertation, I wonder about the impacts of sex and sexualiza-
tion on my ability to navigate my various social and professional spheres.
People talk about sex a lot. We talk about how sex sells, how women are sexually objecti-
fied by advertisements and the media, we gossip about who is having sex with who, and try to
figure out how many sexual partners celebrities have had. We debate what kind of sexual educa-
tion is appropriate for children, we censor the word sex in songs on the radio, we elect presidents
who brag about sexually assaulting women. There is power inscribed in the way we interact with
the sexual in our world, in our society. There is a politics of sex, a politics of sexuality.
I also think about sex a lot. Sometimes in positive ways and sometimes not. It is a present
part of my daily lived experience, from the erotic fiction that I read, to explicit texts that I ex-
change with my partner, to the comments I get from strangers. I have been negotiating sexual
power dynamics for all of my adult life, and a good portion of my childhood, and consider my-
self to have a certain practical expertise in the subject matter. People say ‘write what you know.’
Well, this is what I know.
!2
As will become clear very quickly, this project is personal and self-reflective — docu-
menting a journey through understanding how I engage, on a personal level, with sexual politics.
My main objective is to analyze how eroticism functions in my life, especially in relation to
power and the possibility of empowerment and powerlessness. I am particularly interested in the
viability of ways in which I have attempted to engage in sexual politics, and how I have taken on
sexuality as a dominant part of my identity. How it has come to be something that makes me feel
like me, that ties me to myself. And while the sexual, the sensual, writ large, has been forced
upon me in so many different ways, it has also come to be something exquisitely valuable, even
essential, to my understanding of self.
By sexuality I refer not to sexual preference, or sexual orientation, but rather sexuality as
eroticism — the quality or character of being recognized as a sexual being and partaking in per-
formances of sexual desirability. I am interested in the experience and structure of sexual desire,
how lust and power relate to each other, and how the relation of desire and power both manifest
in people’s lives and impact their agency and autonomy. Because I am in part interested in eroti-
cism as a phenomenological experience, I will be especially attentive to sexual desire and plea-
sure as they manifest in embodied experience. I want to present alternative narratives for under-
standing women’s engagement with lust/desire that do not automatically assume a paradigm of
victimization but rather explore how women’s agency may involve sexual desire.
I believe an attentiveness to how individuals navigate through intersubjective experiences
of desire will help complicate existing accounts of sexualization, and re-center the embodied ex-
perience of the erotic. My goal is to generate a new discursive space to talk about the phe-
nomenon of sexualization by paying attention to not just the oppressive structural aspects, or the
!3
hyper-individualistic “personal choice” aspects — but by looking at how it works in people’s
lives if we understand individuals as being both constrained and free to reinterpret meaning.
In some ways, I have decided that what I am working on is best expressed in what is at
stake for me (at an embodied level). It was not easy to focus so narrowly on my own experi-
ences, centering on phenomena that are high stakes for me specifically, insofar as this kind of
selfish approach strongly diverges from the philosophical tradition in which I have been trained.
But I have found that a universal approach to philosophy does not work so well when theorizing
particularity.
Therefore, I find myself in a situation where I hope to bring to light certain truths about
the world and about my experience within it, that have the potential for broader application; that
can be picked up and played with by people different from me in order to bring their own truth to
light. So I focus on my own hopes and experiences for two purposes: to avoid speaking for oth-
ers, and to offer something true about myself that might have purchases on a larger endeavor to
create theory that has liberatory potential.
A. So what is at stake for me in this investigation?
1. Possibilities for empowerment. Simply put, I want power and I want my agency validated and
appreciated. Popular narratives about sexuality, especially women’s sexuality, do little to offer
possibilities for empowerment, and often reify women’s powerlessness. I find this to be in-
genuous and misrepresentative of my experience. While I sometimes feel acted upon by forces
I have little control over, this is not my dominant mode of existence. There is more to the ne-
gotiations of women under oppressive structures than oppression. Women exhibit power and
intelligence, and their negotiations bring to light under-appreciated knowledge about the
!4
world. I also think there is something poetic about emphasizing power in the actions that peo-
ple claim disempower you.
2. Disrupting narratives of 1) shame and 2) adaptive preferences by honing in on the rough
ground of women’s experiences. I hope to present viable alternative narratives for employing
sexualization in everyday interactions and reclaim existing narratives of eroticism and desire
so that they benefit women rather than sexist superstructures. Narratives create and constrain
possibilities, and I think there are benefits to both changing existing narratives as well as cre-
ating new ones. Often changing old ones requires an attentiveness to the texture of experience,
which is why I am taking such a personal, self-reflective approach in this investigation. I be-
lieve that by paying attention to the particularities of my experience, and the tensions and fric-
tions that arise when my experience diverges from available narratives, I can find a starting
point for creating more accurate descriptions of the phenomena in question in this investiga-
tion.
3. Personal safety. The dominant ways of analyzing sexuality/eroticism often victim-blames the
eroticized subject in ways that perpetuates a rape-culture ideology. In concrete terms, I have a
lot of fear stemming from my existence as sexualized, based in the promises of sexual vio-
lence that I experience on a regular basis. I am truly, honestly, terrified of being raped. It is
something that I spend a lot of time and energy avoiding, while simultaneously recognizing
that I have limited control over what happens to my body. There is a very specific powerless-
ness that comes from being a woman, and sexualized, in a world hostile to women, and I be-
lieve it deserves critical attention. Bringing attention to the kinds of threats faced by sexual-
ized subjects in a sexist system may help uncover assumptions and dynamics that are impera-
!5
tive for creating a more just understanding of sexuality, one that disrupts common narratives
about the inevitability of sexual violence.
4. Highlighting pleasure. I believe pleasure has intrinsic and extrinsic value and is part of a well-
lived life. Audre Lorde’s “Uses of the Erotic” is the foundational text for my investigation be-
cause it invests importance in the erotic and the sensual as fundamental aspects of living well.
I reject the notion that pleasure is a gratuitous or un-philosophical subject matter, and believe
that it is imperative that we include pleasure in any discussion of sexual politics as something
that is a necessary part of lived experience.
These four elements represent the motivations for this dissertation and shape my com-
mitments and purpose. This also means, as a matter of consequence, that there is quite a bit miss-
ing from this discussion. Depending significantly on personal narrative, this project is therefore
limited by the kinds of sexualized experiences that plague me specifically, which are defined by
a certain intersection of power relations that I am situated in as a white, heterosexual woman liv-
ing in the United States. The narratives that are available and accessible to me are also limited by
these factors, as are the assumptions and expectations that I carry with me. And while I hope to
use my positionality to explore issues of identity throughout the paper, it will not be my main
focus, for I am not trying to create a conclusive account of sexual politics, femininity, beauty or
desire, although these are all important components of this discussion. Therefore, I go into this
investigation acknowledging that my experience does not reflect women as a whole, and will not
speak to all women. This is a reality I am comfortable with, as it would be inappropriate to ex-
pect that I could speak to all the different manifestations of sexual politics that women experi-
ence. There is therefore a truly selfish component to this discussion, as it focuses on my needs
!6
and desires, although I hope that it does so with an acknowledgement that there exist other needs
and desires that may complement, and sometimes contradict, my own.
B. Road Map
In Chapter 1, I hone in on the phenomenological structure of sexualization by providing a de-
scriptive account of what it feels like to be sexualized and what I have learned about myself and
the world from these finite experiences. Starting with a phenomenology is useful in that it allows
us to bracket some of the normative assumptions about eroticism (these normative values will be
reintroduced throughout the rest of the dissertation). Phenomenology also allows us to explore
the things we take for granted about the world and look into them deeper — find underlying
structures that present us with a particular picture of the world that can help clarify the situation
that we are in. With my phenomenology of sexualization, I hope to come up with a description of
sexual desire that is neither phallocentric nor beholden to a master-slave dialectic (of dominance/
submission). I will also challenge certain existing erotic phenomenologies (overwhelmingly writ-
ten from the male perspective), while attempting to create an account of sexualization that is dis-
tinctive and resists a narrative of victimization.
In Chapter 2, I explore existing narratives/tropes for understanding myself as a sexual
subject involved in power relations by investigating the figure of the femme fatale. I chose to
look at the femme fatale trope because it is such a visible and iconic example of female sexual
politics. I use the femme fatale narrative to explore the implicit claim that erotic or sexualized
existence is necessarily harmful to the subject. I draw this assumption from popular descriptions
of erotic desire as being something to fear or suspect because of the way it limits autonomy, and
the way it further stigmatizes women in a sexist system. By drawing upon philosophy of lan-
!7
guage and narrative theory, I will examine how the language we use and the language games we
play will impact our ability to see sexual agency as subversive, and argue that we have a choice
to make in how we interpret the actions of women invested in sexualization as a way to navigate
interpersonal relationships.
In Chapter 3, I will argue that women have something to gain by paying attention to the
kind of theorizing done by black women around the question of sexuality and pleasure. Pleasure
politics looks at the advantages and disadvantages of eroticism by centering the black female
subject and the importance of pleasure. I find this specific discourse extremely helpful when the-
orizing desire because of the unique way it navigates between hyper-structural accounts that
foreclose agency, and certain liberal accounts that focus too narrowly on individual rights. The
strategy of showing how constructs generated within problematic power relations can be negoti-
ated and redefined is essential to rethinking the political value of eroticism. I believe that Plea-
sure Politics shows us explicitly how re-describing existing erotic narratives and sexual identities
can come from “within” rather than without. I will offer a political methodological engagement
with a set of theories that are not about me, but may offer me life tools, and ways of re-conceiv-
ing the world that can position me differently in the world as a result.
And finally, in Chapter 4, I will argue that the charge of false consciousness (also referred
to as ‘adaptive preference’ or ‘oppression by choice’) is often used to deny women autonomy, the
ability to interpret their own experience, and the ability to generate their own meaning-making
and production of knowledge. Through the charge of false consciousness, people’s self-expres-
sions become simply the manifestation of a pathological process of self-perpetuated oppression. I
am skeptical of the quickness with which false consciousness is brought up in discussions about
!8
the relationship between women’s experience of erotic desire and their agency and self-defini-
tion, and advise caution when theorizing the ways in which women participate in, or are respon-
sible for, their own oppression.
In many ways, this dissertation is the culmination of my academic philosophical training,
both in terms of subject matter and motivation. It seems a fitting conclusion to my studies, as it
captures the questions that have consumed me and the theories that have had the deepest impacts
on my work. It is also an opportunity to be honest and deliberate with my theorizing, and to take
the time to delve into the issues that have the strongest impacts on my everyday experience. Sex,
desire, pleasure, abuse, rape and pain make up a rather large portion of my cognitive phenomena,
due in large part to my daily experience, but probably also in response to my temperament and
personality. I recognize that a lot of people don’t care about these issues to the extent that I do,
and won’t agree with how I articulate the themes included. And even in the circles where these
topics are valued and pursued, there will be disagreement with my world-building, which is only
to be expected. If there is one thing that I walk away from my studies with, it is the inevitability
of my inadequacy in articulating and creating in ways that no one will find problematic, or offen-
sive. And so I invite you to learn something from me, because I do think there is something valu-
able about my perspective, however limited it may be. And I welcome challenges to the frame-
works that I propose, for I surely have created something that is insufficient as a stand-alone
model. All that being said, I hope this investigation offers something valuable to anyone who is
interested in reclaiming the sexual and the erotic as something critical, vital and vibrant, a source
of knowledge and power that resonates throughout our experiences, and allows us to live a full
and flourishing life.
!9
Citrus Salad
I bought a new dress.
Its striped like citrus salad, with off the shoulder sleeves that keep me from raising my arms all
the way if I want to keep the lines straight. Oh well, beauty is pain, right?
I feel like summertime, I feel like light. The teal next to the lime is the best thing I’ve ever seen,
except the clementine down at the bottom is even better. And don’t get me started on that lemony
stripe of sunshine wrapped around my breasts. This is the dress I’ve been waiting for.
I put on my strappy wedges, the ones with the skinny blush straps and the woven heels that blend
into my skin. They turn my short legs into skyscrapers, stretching for miles up to the white band-
ed hem that rests at the top of my thighs.
I look delicious. Delectable. Sweet but just a little tart.
My hair goes down, messy curls winding around each other all the way to my back. Its soft, but
deadly. No brush can forge a path through these curls. I like it like that. I’m not here to be
touched.
Lips get painted peach, highlight on the cupid’s bow gleams bright. Lashes stretch into wide
eyed wonder under arched brows that take no shit, and I am ready.
Living alone has been a revelation. I do what I want, when I want. I eat snacks all day and take
long walks on the beach at sunset. I wear short clothes that make me look like Barbie because
you aren’t here to claim it all for yourself. I miss you in theory, but I’ve been growing, unfolding,
since you left. I don’t think I’ll be the same when you come back.
Today is just another day in Summerland, and I’ve dressed for the occasion. Music in my ears,
my steps take on a rhythm that makes my body flow. The sun beats down. The ocean breeze
wraps around me. My hips sway from side to side, a hypnotizing beat that pushes me forward
without interruption.
Each step is a dare, and I’ve never been more ready.
Look at me. I dare you.
Watch how I move. I dare you.
Feel the power of my feet on the earth.
See how strong and unashamed I can be?
This is life in summertime.
I stop for no one. Does a cyclone stop its path to satisfy someone else’s curiosity? I am mine.
!10
Bitch
I was eighteen and on the elliptical the first time a man called me a bitch. He wanted my phone
number, I didn’t want to give it. He left, but then came back. I should have gone, I knew better,
but I wanted to finish my workout and so I stood there, trapped, my feet sliding back and forth
on the machine, moving endlessly to nowhere, when he reacted to my final rejection: “You know,
you don’t need to be such a bitch.”
It was surprisingly numbing. Bitch. B-i-t-c-h. Of course, I’d been called a bitch before, but not in
that way. Not for that reason. I’d been a “bitch” for making a rude comment to a friend, or taking
the last spot, or calling someone an asshole. Now, I was a bitch for telling him no. I was a bitch
for making him a failure. I was a bitch for denying him his right. I learned something new.
A few years later, I dated a man who called me his bitch. At first, I liked it. It was edgy, harsh, a
little bit dirty. It was exciting. But after a while, I noticed that when he chose to use it, I became a
little less. I was his bitch, but he was my man. Unequal. From his lips, “You my bitch” was a de-
claration of ownership instead of just a turn of phrase. It reflected the tenor of our relationship.
These days, I notice that men treat me like a bitch, in the literal sense. Honest to god, I walk
around feeling like I must be a god damned female dog. I knew men saw me as an easy target,
but now I know they think I’m dumb as dirt, too. Seriously, just a couple weeks ago, a man
snapped at me to get my attention as I was walking by him. He put out his hand and snapped,
like I would race over to him and see if he had a treat for me. Another stepped into my path to
block my way, I guess thinking I would prance up to him, sniffing his hands, ready to be pet.
Once, a man in line behind me at 7-11 ordered me to wait for him outside while he finished
checking out. It wasn’t a request, but a command: “Go wait for me there,” he pointed, while
looking at my tits. What was he planning on doing to me, out in front of the parking lot? Snap a
collar on me and take me home? I didn’t wait to find out.
I get the sense that being alone in public must just look wrong, like seeing a dog walking around
on its own with no leash. What was I thinking? Silly girl. Someone needs to own me, before I get
myself in trouble.
!11
Chapter 1: Phenomenology of Sexualization
In this chapter I will attempt to describe the phenomenon of sexualization as I experience
it. The following is therefore primarily a personal narrative about what sexualization is, and how
it feels. I am calling this a phenomenology of sexualization because it investigates the pertinent
conscious phenomena from a first person perspective. By starting from this standpoint, I am able
to narrow in on the particularities of what it means to exist as a sexualized being, and provide an
account that is sensitive to the embodied nature of relevant phenomena, including desire, lust,
entitlement and eroticism.
This will mean, by necessity, that my account of sexualization is situated within the par-
ticularity of my life, flavored by my distinctive mix of identities — by my background or hori-
zon. I want to be as clear as possible that my account is therefore partial and limited, and cannot
be said to expose the Truth of sexualization, as if there were such a thing. Rather, I hope that crit-
ically organizing my particular experiences will uncover structures that may be helpful when un-
derstanding how sexualization can function in women’s lives and how it might impact their iden-
tity formation and sense of well-being.
I am also taking a narrative approach because it seems a more natural (at least for me)
way to approach this topic, which is so deeply personal. It is intimate in a way that resists the
clean cuts of clinical philosophical inquiry because it involves aspects which are visceral, mater-
ial, and that at times seem unreasonable. It is not the type of thing that can be understood in a
vacuum, divorced from the feelings it engenders. And to be fair to myself as narrator, it is not a
simple task to organize all the various aspects and nuances of sexualized existence. Sexuality and
sexual desire are complicated and messy phenomena that are at work in a complicated and messy
!12
world. They are also phenomena with rich historical legacies that inform how we think, the lan-
guage we use, and the way we understand ourselves. I find myself, in life as well as in this dis-
sertation, consistently negotiating between the influences of many different forces, some of
which are contradictory to my goals.
This is not to say that philosophical inquiry is inappropriate for this investigation, but
rather that we ought to exhibit a certain amount of flexibility when attempting to theorize the ac-
tivity and experience of being sexualized. For these reasons, I find phenomenological methodol-
ogy, understood here as descriptive accounts of structures of consciousness as experienced from
the first-person point of view, or even more simply as the study of structures of experience, or
consciousness, particularly well suited for investigating this type of account. That being said,
1
this is not a true phenomenology in the Husserlian sense, especially as I shift from a descriptive
to an explanatory framework in the latter half of this chapter, and I take a certain amount of artis-
tic license in describing it as such. Rather, it is a way to introduce broad-scale phenomena with-
out overgeneralizing, or making universal claims about the state of the world. This chapter is also
titled a phenomenology as an homage to Sandra Bartky’s “Towards a Phenomenology of Femi-
nist Consciousness,” which is a beautiful account of an individual’s intentionality might take on
2
a feminist flavor. In this vein, my “Phenomenology of Sexualization” documents how an indi-
vidual’s intentionality might incorporate an awareness of the structures of sexualization.
Before we begin, I would also like to address the question of novelty. Sexual politics is
certainly a topic that is at the forefront of feminist philosophy, and the modern feminist political
Smith, David Woodruff. “Phenomenology.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition),
1
Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .
Bartky, Sandra Lee. "Toward A Phenomenology Of Feminist Consciousness." Social Theory and Practice 3, no. 4
2
(1975). http://www.jstor.org/stable/23557163.
!13
platform. We avidly talk about the effects of objectification on young girl’s development, we ar-
gue about whether or not pornography is hate speech, and we catalogue the wide spectrum of
sexual harassment and sexual violence that women all over the world face. In fact, I do many of
these things in this chapter. And yet, I still believe that these are topics that for one reason or an-
other, do not receive enough critical attention, which has allowed the philosophical discipline to
maintain a certain willfully ignorant standpoint when it comes to the messy and often contradic-
tory nature of sexualized experience. Which is not to say that eroticism has not garnered philo-
sophical attention. Theorists like Levinas, Sartre, and Foucault (among others) have taken up the
question of sexual desire. But to be perfectly honest, in my opinion these accounts leave a lot to
be desired (no pun intended). Levinas’s account of Eros manipulates the ethical relationship
3
with gendered tropes to create a non-ethical erotic relation, and stereotypically objectifies
Woman as unknowable, mysterious, and dark. Sartre’s account of sexual desire is frustratingly
4
individualistic and antagonistic, as sexual relations become just another example of existential
conflict between persons. Foucault’s account of sexuality as a historical phenomenon is certain
5
-
ly valuable in how it tracks the growth and changes of sexual paradigms over time, but it never-
theless misses vital embodied aspects of being sexualized. Not to mention that most of the avail-
able philosophical accounts of sexuality and sexual desire take a male perspective for granted,
one imbued with phallocentrism, penetration, and possession. It has long been my desire to push
back against the masculine assumptions that are so prevalent in academic accounts of eroticism,
Levinas, Emmanuel. “Phenomenology of Eros.” In: Totality and Infinity. Martinus Nijhoff Philosophy Texts, vol 1.
3
Springer, Dordrecht, 1991.
Sartre, Jean Paul. Being And Nothingness: An Essay In Phenomenological Ontology. Secaucus, N.J. : Citadel
4
Press, [1964], c1956.
Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality. OKS Print. New York: Pantheon Books, 1978.
5
!14
and center a female, though not universal, perspective — someone with unapologetic sexuality,
invested in a paradigm of pleasure rather than shame. As these are topics that inform so much of
the treatment directed towards women, I believe that this investigation is not only necessary, but
ethically imperative.
And finally, I would like to address, in advance, some of the conflicts inherent in this dis-
cussion. I make a pointed effort to resist a narrative of victimization, one which observes the im-
pacts of sexualization largely in terms of harm. But, as you will see, the first half of this account
does indeed emphasize the ways in which being sexualized has placed me in a position to be
harmed in specific ways. I grapple with the tension between my desire to develop an account of
sexuality as something pleasurable and empowering, and my experiences of sexuality as a source
of pain and fear. I believe both of these are accurate representations of what it means to be sexu-
alized, and I will account for both in this specific discussion.
1. Discovering oneself as sexualized
What does it mean to have a consciousness as a sexualized being? Largely speaking, it
means an awareness that you are fuckable. It is the recognition that you remind people of sex,
that when they look at you they see the possibility of sexual activity as strongly present. As sexu-
alized, your function as a being, and sometimes as an object, changes from what it might be in a
normal social interaction. It becomes narrowed, focused on the pleasure assumed potential in
you. The awareness of your embodiment becomes exaggerated, central to your value and purpose
in the world. The force of this awareness becomes a tangible state of affairs between you and
others. You are made flesh, flesh that demands attention as flesh, whether you wished it or not.
!15
To be conscious of one’s sexualization is to understand that your very meaning as a per-
son has changed. Your existence is now predicated on your ability to function as an object of
sexual pleasure, instigating an instantaneous symbolic transformation. This manifests in subtle
shifts in how your body is received and acknowledged: your breasts become tits, your butt be-
comes an ass, and your vagina becomes a pussy. These spaces take on central and exaggerated
6
importance, because they are now spaces imbued with a specific type of meaning. They are the
places that take on a new light as covetable, but also as morally suspect, because they remind
people that you can be fucked. They become signs that you are being treated as you were made
to be treated — as penetrable, as space predetermined for seeking out pleasure. Your meaning
and purpose in the world shifts, centering primarily upon your ability to summon these feelings
and images in those observing you. You have been put in your place, and that place is specifical-
ly to be the representation and incarnation of sexual desire and permissibility.
At twenty-eight years of age, I have long since developed a consciousness as a sexualized
being, but this was not always the way I understood myself. This consciousness developed over
years of experience, learned through practice as I came to recognize the specific types of expec-
tations and values that I represent to the public. And of course, sexualization became more ag-
gressively prevalent as I began to take on the qualities coded as sexual and sexually desirable.
My specific introduction into the dynamics of sexualization began with my experiences
as a pretty child. For as long as I can remember, people complimented my parents on my looks,
as if I were truly an object of their creation — a living doll. They said that I was going to be a
beauty, that I would drive the boys wild, that my parents would have to put me under lock and
This description takes for granted a normative female body, although it is certainly possible for male and gender
6
non-conforming bodies to be sexualized, as well.
!16
key. There were so many elements that people would hone in on, bringing to light things that I
had never felt a need to pay attention to, that I did not intend, or even see myself. People com-
mented on the clarity of my skin, and the darkness of my features, my silky hair, my dramatic
brows, my high cheekbones and my dimpled smile. My attention was consistently and systemati-
cally brought back to how I looked, as I learned that there were so many details that people
would invest with value.
This attention made me far too aware of my physical appearance from a very young age.
In many ways this would foreshadow the atomization of self that often accompanies sexualiza-
tion, as I learned to inspect and dissect my body into pieces, neatly organized into what was
valuable or not. My eyes were brown (bad), but lustrous (good), almost glowing from within. My
nose was too big for classic beauty (bad), but my arched brows gave me an exotic flair (good).
My hair was dark (bad), but my skin was clear and fair (good). And as I grew older I lived up to
the expectations of those around me, my appearance garnering always more attention. For this
reason, my experiences of sexualization are intimately intertwined with standards of beauty. This
is not to say that sexualization or sexual desirability is dependent on beauty standards, but rather
that the two often become convoluted in my own experience. I emphasize this for the dual pur-
pose of, again, recognizing that the account provided here is limited and finite, and acknowledg-
ing that the attention paid to my physical appearance has been a constant in my life and that this
attention cannot always be systematically organized by cause. I cannot neatly separate the expe-
riences that are based in sexual desire from those based in standards of beauty, and together they
become what I understand to be the focus of attention paid to me.
!17
2. Breasts
Up to my early teen years, I was still firmly childlike in my interactions with the public,
even if those interactions were often framed through an objectifying lens. And then the summer
before I turned thirteen, I grew breasts. This marked a turning point as the attention I received
spread beyond my face to the rest of my body. It was almost as if the emergence of breasts creat-
ed a spectacle of my body, and enabled attention to spread south of my neckline. People contin-
ued to talk about me, in front of me, but not really to me, as if they understood that discussing
my body would become unseemly if they acknowledged my personhood (after all, it is objective-
ly inappropriate to comment on how a 12-year old girl’s body is filling out, and how she is de-
veloping a “figure”). Through this new kind of scrutiny, I learned that there were even more
standards that I would be judged against when it came to my body. This attention, coupled with a
growing discomfort with my changing body, exacerbated feelings of shame and regret as I con-
tinued to develop and take up more space, while simultaneously garnering more and more public
attention.
In school, I learned from my peers that my breasts were one of my dominant features, one
of my assets. They became a salient feature in my identification, and I found out that when peo-
ple thought about me, my breasts became an automatic rejoinder. To the adolescent mind, Sophia
suddenly equaled Big Boobs, a metamorphosis based in new flesh. They were startling on my
adolescent frame, better suited to the likes of the lingerie models and actresses that graced the
pages of Cosmo and GQ. I often felt that my breasts took on a life of their own, endowed with
special powers to demand attention, entering into spaces in front of me, announcing my pres-
ence. They turned me into something different, and while I didn't quite know what to do with
!18
them, I felt the pressure to own them before someone else did. There was a sense of urgency, as
if I could feel the countdown ticking away my last moments of anonymity.
Growing breasts marked the first time I really experienced sexualization, and it ushered
in a shift in how people interacted with me. Boys started looking at my chest more than my face.
I got frequent comments about the visibility of my nipples through my shirts. Even my friends
commented on my new breasts, joking about how I should be in wet t-shirt contests, teasing me
about how they jiggled and bounced, capturing the attention of those around me. A classmate re-
ferred to me as “his type” while cupping his hands in front of his chest to indicate that what in-
terested him about me. My history teacher handed me an oversized t-shirt in the middle of class
and told me to put it on because my dress was dipping too low in front as I was hunched over my
desk working. It became clear that I was hyper-visible. I developed a tense relationship to the
flesh that brought me so much attention, in the form of desire, discomfort, vulgarization and
shame.
3. Growing up sexualized
Puberty and the subsequent changes to my body altered the way I was treated by the gen-
eral public. It was during this time that I began to have my life interrupted by grown men. Not
only the boys I went to school with, but men anywhere from one to six decades older than me.
They stopped me at the grocery store to tell me that I had a beautiful body, or while I was shop-
ping to ask if we could see each other again. They yelled at me and catcalled from their cars as I
was walking by. They often thought I was older than I was, regardless of my baby fat and chubby
cheeks, and I started to realize how vulnerable and unstable my protected status as a minor was.
Being a child did not matter to people who saw my body as being that of an adult. And because I
!19
could now attract adults, I also became responsible for avoiding them. I had to tell them that I
was too young, that no they couldn't have my number, that no we couldn't have coffee and chat. I
was told by “well-meaning” and “concerned” individuals that I shouldn't dress in ways that made
me look older and more mature if I didn't want that kind of attention. From both directions — of
desire or blame — I learned that I was now responsible for the treatment I received, and that I no
longer could expect to be recognized as protected, untouchable, or “too young.”
As a child, I had almost fetishized the idea of becoming an adult, and the freedom that
adult agency and autonomy would offer. But this status was manipulated into something alto-
gether unexpected, as I was denied adulthood and instead ushered into a lesser category. It was in
my early twenties that I realized that I did not have the privilege of being just an adult, of being a
grown human being. Instead, I was immediately placed in the category of Woman as it became
apparent to everyone around me that I was distinctly female, fuckable, and therefore vulnerable. 7
And this vulnerability was made tangible to me in particularly explicit ways. I started to get
stalked by faceless men in cars, who trailed behind me as I walked around. Men who had once
only catcalled now approached, aggressive and predatory. They made explicit comments about
my body and what they would do to it. Some grabbed me around the waist, or reached out and
touched my arms, my hair, or played with my clothes, as if considering undressing me right
there. I was followed home and cornered at the gate to my apartment complex. Men trapped me
in small spaces, like my car, elevators, and hallways, pressing close enough that I could smell
their scent as their eyes lingered slowly over my body.
These are not the only characteristics of the social category of Woman, but the ones that were predominant in my
7
experience and understanding of myself as gendered.
!20
Although I knew, objectively, that these were not experiences that were unique to my sit-
uation, I nevertheless felt isolated and alone, not knowing how to process these newer, more
dangerous events that had been introduced into my life. And this sense of isolation was only en-
hanced by the reactions of those closest to me. My partner at the time grew sensitive to the atten-
tion I received, and began blaming me whenever men displayed too much interest. He comment-
ed on the clothes I put on, the way I smiled at people, accusing me of asking for it when I com-
plained about the treatment I received. Female authority figures that I went to for advice and
wisdom dismissed my experiences with suggestions that I dress differently. Again I was remind-
ed that it was my responsibility, and therefore my fault, when others sexualized me. I was as-
sumed complicit in not only the ways that I was perceived, but also the ways I was treated. This
new attention exacerbated my natural tendencies towards shyness, as it became harder and harder
to fade into the background. I learned to fear being seen not only because it made me uncomfort-
able, but in order to avoid the judgmental voices that accused me of seeking out the very atten-
tion that caused me anxiety.
Needless to say, I learned quickly what it meant to be a woman in this world, or at least
what it meant to be the specific kind of woman that I am. I was reminded so often that I began to
see almost every social interaction through a lens of sexual predation or judgment, depending on
whom I was interacting with. While perhaps unfair — after all, NOT ALL MEN — having had
the persistent threat disclosed, I felt I had a moral license to treat future encounters in this way.
Or maybe it was simply for the sake of survival that I started to become jaded. An ever-present
cloud of threat hung over me, heavy on my body as I moved through space. Whatever the reason,
it was quickly evident to me that the available interpretations for these new experiences were not
!21
only limited, but that my safety hinged upon choosing the right one. It behooved me to become
suspicious of people’s intentions, if only to limit the chance of harm. Even so, the terrain I found
myself navigating was often ambiguous and confusing, making it hard to feel prepared for what
were quickly becoming inevitable interactions.
I had been prepared for these experiences to a certain extent, from stories about not walk-
ing alone at night to off-the-cuff remarks about how “men are dogs,” and yet I was still ill
equipped to deal with the messiness of my circumstances. See, the thing is that the men who let
me know in no uncertain terms what I had become, they were not always malicious with their
attentions. I say this not to excuse their behavior, or cater to their masculinity, but to address the
complexity of navigating the sexual arena. Some of them clearly were after the power play —
they wanted to see me demeaned and belittled in front of them. They wanted to put me in my
place so that they could assert theirs. And they did this with their explicit and unsolicited refer-
ences to my body, making sure I knew that it was publicly available for their consumption. Or by
shrugging off my attempts to dismiss them, asserting that they alone had a say in the interaction
we were having, and when/how it could end. They laughed at my discomfort and fear, enjoying
the ‘game’ that we were playing, regardless of the fact that it was not a game to me.
But often, the men who approached me did so almost as if they couldn't help themselves.
They would look at me upon receiving my attention as if they hadn’t planned that far, and had no
idea what to do. They would look at me like all their plans had gone up in smoke, or as if they
hadn't even been thinking at all as they approached me. This planted within me a seed of deep
discomfort and distrust of men, and reinforced the lesson that I would be uniquely responsible
for what men did to me, because they were not in control at all. Their eyes, when they looked at
!22
me, were bewildered, perplexed, and uncertain. They looked nervous, fidgety and almost desper-
ate, which made possible a unique kind of existential threat, for which I was not prepared.
I learned to be terrified of those expressions because men’s uncertainty tinged with des-
peration presented a special type of danger. By this I mean that people who have historically
been allowed to act upon their whims, and are celebrated or excused for their actions simply be-
cause they are men, are people who represent a tangible threat because they are not held ac-
countable for said actions. The lack of control that they exhibited showed me that I literally did
not know what they might do to me in those moments. I didn't know if they just wanted a smile
and a polite thank you, if they wanted an opportunity to test their pick-up skills, if they would let
me walk away, if they would grab me, if they would insist upon my participation in a situation
they had forced me into. This uncertainty, coupled with the knowledge of what men are capable
of doing to women, learned over a lifetime of cautionary tales, left me feeling particularly pow-
erless. It didn't matter so much that this particular man in this particular instance did not harm
me, because the fear remained that the next one might very well do so. It seemed almost in-
evitable.
4. Rape threat
Rape became a persistent worry in my mind, and something that I actively strove to avoid
on a daily basis. Rape was brought into my life as a tangible threat, as it is in the life of so many
women, because of how men treated me. They treated me like an object for the taking, and ap-
proached me with entitlement that left me feeling small, vulnerable and violable. The licked lips
and roaming eyes, the lingering hands and invasive posturing made it clear that I was not granted
things like choice, autonomy and agency as a sexualized subject. At best, I was left with the abil-
!23
ity to gate-keep my sexual availability, which is a dubious power, because it persists in the as-
sumption that my body is there for some man’s sexual pleasure, its just my choice to safeguard it
for that ‘special’ man. Gate-keeping also perpetuates the idea that women are responsible for
men’s actions, that we must be the moral standard that keeps men in line, that our strength in pu-
rity and chastity must stand firm in the face of men’s voracious sexual appetites. And so, al
8
-
though I missed the official declaration, it became quickly obvious that it was open season on
Sophia, and I was never more aware that life had changed for me as when I recognized that one
of the seemingly inevitable consequences of being sexualized was the claiming of my body as a
prize.
And it was not only the treatment of men that enforced upon me the truth of my own vio-
lability. From (primarily) women I learned that I would be blamed if something did happen to
me, that I would deserve it because of how I looked/dressed/behaved. The judgment of my fe-
male peers and authority figures taught me that there would be little compassion for the treat-
ment I received under the guise of sexualization. The snide comments about my clothing, body,
and the attention that I received exacerbated an already tense state of affairs. Even empathetic
friends would subtly remind me that I was different, other than them. They would respond to my
complaints with pitying expressions, and ask me, in the gentle tones of one talking to a child who
ought to know better, “What did you expect?” This blind acceptance made me feel crazy for
thinking that things could be otherwise. It made me feel that my insistence on being treated with
dignity and respect was unreasonable, the idealistic dreams of a naive girl. And so, in a variety of
Its almost funny how women’s strength is only assumed/allowed when it comes to enabling men’s weakness.
8
!24
ways, I was taught that I deserved the treatment I received, or that at best, it was simply my lot in
life.
In some ways, this was simply a practical acceptance of what had become normal. Wish-
ing that things were different, or believing I deserved better had no tangible effect on my daily
experience. And so, I had to make compromises to stay safe. Real life does not always allow you
to act on principle and ideal. I learned, by necessity rather than desire, to navigate the sexual
landscape as prey. I learned how to accept compliments graciously: “well thank you, that’s so
sweet,” “how nice of you to say so,” “I appreciate it,” “you’re too kind.” These lies flowed off
my tongue like honey, with just the right amount of appreciation to appear suitably grateful for a
man’s attention without implying that I sought more. I learned that slightly-disinterested polite-
ness was the quickest way to extricate myself from an uncomfortable situation, because it catered
just enough to men’s egos to (usually) satisfy their expectations without manifesting their anger
or further efforts. This careful negotiation came from a recognition that men are fragile creatures,
easily lost to turmoil and identity crises when faced with a woman’s dismissal. They do not like
their “efforts” to go unrewarded.
And so I smiled, I laughed, I shook hands, I introduced myself and accepted introduc-
tions, I gave fake names — I catered. I catered because it was easier and safer than being called a
bitch or a slut, being yelled at, having someone follow me home, and getting cornered and forced
to accept their attention. I stopped trying to explain that it didn't matter if I already had a
boyfriend or not, and started taking the easy way out of claiming that yes, unfortunately another
man already owned me, and no, he wasn't into sharing. I learned to give fake names and take
!25
men’s phone numbers down in notes on my phone, deleting them as soon as I was out of sight.
These were my survival strategies.
5. Sexual advances
Rape threat creates a particular way of being in the world that I now call ‘constant vigi-
lance.’ Of course, at the time, I simply understood the need to be constantly aware, even hyper-
aware, of my surroundings. I could no longer lose myself in window shopping while walking
around the mall, or whatever book I was reading at a coffee shop, but instead had to always have
one eye out to see who was around me, who had noticed me, or even who might notice me. I
learned that the second I took for granted that I could be present in a public space without reper-
cussion, I would get punished. While seemingly dramatic rhetoric to some, the idea of punish-
ment captures the force of the spectrum of reminders that I was not safe when in public, that
ranged from small, like being interrupted during a task, to truly threatening, like being pushed
against a car in the mall parking lot with no one else around.
Of course, constant vigilance is not a phenomenon that I alone experience, or even one
that women alone experience. It is arguable that any group that faces targeted threats of violence
will experience this type of awareness. I think there is, however, a particular flavor to the kind of
paranoia that manifests from women’s experience as public beings, one that I believe is a direct
product of rape threat. It is almost like rape is the promise of a heteropatriarchal world (both het-
eronormativity and patriarchy are important here) — “be careful or you could get raped” is
whispered on the wind, or more realistically, in the hushed tones of girls speaking to other girls
about what happened to her. Women learn fear at the hands of men; it is a part of our socializa-
tion into the category of woman — the knowledge that we can be raped. But rape threat is not
!26
performed solely, or even primarily, by direct promises of sexual assault. More covertly, it is in-
sinuated through a myriad of actions that bring me to my next topic: the category of sexual ad-
vances.
This transition from rape threat to sexual advances might seem jarring, but I would ask
the reader to bear with me, as it accurately depicts the way in which rape is persistently brought
to the forefront of my experience. After all, rarely has someone actually verbally indicated that
they want to rape me, although this has, sadly, happened. And yet, even without explicit refer-
ence, I am overwhelmingly aware that rape is a very possible part of my future, a reality which
weighs heavily on my shoulders. It is a future so tangible and thick that I can almost feel my
power being leached away, in preparation of the violation that I fear so much. This fear, I argue,
is revealed and reinforced by a range of sexual advances, because they manifest as an extension
of our heteronormative sexual politics, one in which rape becomes the inevitable conclusion of a
patriarchal system.
Sexual advances are something I have become familiar, if not comfortable, with. For the
purposes of this discussion, I consider ‘sexual advances’ to be an umbrella term covering a range
of interactions including flirtation, propositioning, hitting on, harassment, and even assault. I
propose that sexual advances are some of the most common reminders of sexualization, as they
are different phenomena motivated by the same things: namely, sexual desire and power. They
present different levels of invasiveness and potential threat, and may be welcome or unwelcome
in different ways by different women. I say all this just to be clear that I am trying to avoid mak-
ing hasty generalizations by grouping these different phenomena together. I understand that by
bringing these diverse phenomena together under the banner of “sexual advances,” I am using
!27
this term differently than how it is often used colloquially. However, I think it is appropriate to
establish the connection between interactions that are obviously violent and ones that are more
subtly so, because it underlines the way in which our heterosexual interactions are often founded
upon harmful norms. In other words, I am trying to draw attention to the ways in which these
different ways of interacting, some harmful and some not, are related, in order to establish a
spectrum which organizes the frequency of sexual predation and aggression towards women.
For my purposes, I hold that flirting implies a mutual interaction in which both/all parties
involved consent to the interaction. I consider propositioning to be a direct request with an ulti-
mate aim of engaging in sexual activity: “Can I take you home tonight?” Harassment is unwant-
ed attention that interferes with one’s well-being by implicitly or explicitly threatening harm.
When harassment turns physical, e.g., groping or grabbing, I would consider this in the realm of
assault. All of these function as sexual advances, i.e., verbal and physical expressions of sexual
desire. Certain of these also function as power plays, and deployment of masculinity, etc. By tak-
ing on the social role of ‘woman,’ I have experienced the entire range of sexual advances. In fact,
these experiences in many ways constitute my understanding of what it means to be a woman. 9
But while all of these interactions are pertinent to this discussion, I want to focus specifically on
the experience of getting hit on, because it is arguably one of the most common sexual advances.
Getting hit on is a particularly predominant manifestation of sexual politics in women’s
lives, by which I mean it is easily one of the most common ways in which women learn what it
means to be a woman qua sexualized,
and encounter the power structures of sex and gender. In
10
This may not be the case for all those who identify as women.
9
There are, of course, other ways in which women learn what it means to be a woman. I happen to be focusing on
10
women’s experiences of sexualization specifically, which I consider to be a particularly dominant way in which
women are trained into the social category.
!28
fact, its so common that we regularly overlook it when considering manifestations of sexist so-
cial structures in favor of the more dramatic examples of sexual politics, e.g. harassment and as-
sault. But I think that this kind of routine interaction is part and parcel with the more blatant ex-
amples of sexual entitlement that feeds sexual violence towards women and deserves critical at-
tention to better understand the demands placed on sexualized female bodies. I say this because
in my own experience, getting hit on often feels threatening, even if it is not explicitly so. There
is something unsettling and destabilizing about someone with greater social power willfully in-
terrupting your life to demand recognition on the basis of their desire for you.
While colloquial, “getting hit on” is actually a fairly descriptive term that identifies a
somewhat ambiguous, grey-zone phenomena. “Hitting on” refers to unsolicited interactions
when someone, usually a stranger, attempts to create a personal connection in order to introduce
the possibility of sexual desire. It is the suggestion — sometimes covert, and often overt — that
more is desired. Usually, it is the precursor to conquest. When this type of behavior is welcome
and reciprocated by the subject, I would put this in the realm of flirting. So perhaps I could call
getting hit on unsolicited, and potentially invasive, initiation of flirtatious interactions.
The unprompted nature of hitting on someone is part of why it can quickly pass into un-
pleasant harassment and invasion of personal space, especially when the other person actively
indicates with body language or speech that they are not interested and the interaction continues
nonetheless. Being engaged in any form of conversation without it being solicited can be frus-
trating and unpleasant. This discomfort is magnified when based in sexual desire because of the
long-standing assumptions that women owe men sexual attention and gratification. And so, in
my own experience, men commonly assume that I am as interested in conversing with them as
!29
they are with me, and rarely, if ever, do they ask for permission. In fact, they usually keep talking
incessantly so that I do not have an opportunity to exit the un-asked for conversation, like a tele-
marketer who doesn't pause so that you can’t politely decline the call, leaving someone trying to
avoid instigating fragile masculinity in an awkward position.
There exists a pervasive idea that getting hit on is flattering. And this idea is perpetuated
by both men and women. We’ve turned aggressive behavior into a normal interaction between
individuals that women must accept, otherwise be labelled as ungrateful. People tell you that it is
flattering, and complimentary, to have your life interrupted by someone demanding your atten-
tion as they try to force an intimate connection on you. They say that you’ll appreciate it when
you’re older, because in a society where women’s value is largely determined by their sexual de-
sirability, these reminders can be seen as validating. Men are taught that they must actively pur-
sue women they find attractive, that ‘scoring’ with her adds to their masculinity, while her rejec-
tion deteriorates it, and women are taught to play along lest they make a man feel inadequate.
These gendered presuppositions are part of what complicates a clear understanding of how these
states of affairs really impact women’s health and well-being.
Personally, there are times when I feel that I can’t walk outside of my house without hav-
ing my life interrupted by a man who just has to have some of my attention. I often adjust my
schedule so that I do not have to go out alone, preferring to have the safety of a male accompa-
niment, even for everyday tasks. It is a persistent reminder of my powerlessness, and that this
world was not made for me to thrive. These constant demands upon my person remind me that I
am not allowed to simply exist, and feeds into the hyper-vigilant paranoia. Men continuously ap-
proach me as if their desire gives them permission to interrupt my life. And they do interrupt my
!30
life — while I am working, eating, talking on the phone, grocery shopping, exercising, reading
for pleasure, and generally pursuing my own goals. In fact, never am I simply sitting somewhere
expectantly, making myself available to strangers, and yet I get treated as if the purpose of my
existence is to be an opportunity.
6. The trouble with fantasy
As I became the target of sexual advances, I started to recognize that often preceding
these interactions was the existence of fantasy. Fantasy, as I am using it here, is the narrative
manifestation of possible states of affairs that are seen as desirable. Being fantasized about is of-
ten understood as a non-violent private act that has no purchase on the “real world.” If someone
casts me in their fantasy, it does not concern me in any tangible way precisely because it is
make-believe. But I find that in practice, this is not necessarily true. Fantasies speak to our hopes
for reality, our vision of a perfect world, and therefore creates expectations that have tangible
impacts on how we interact with others.
Being the object of fantasy can be dangerous in a heteropatriarchal context, because to be
cast in someone’s fantasy, particularly a sexual fantasy, often requires being flattened and reified.
When someone casts you into their fantasy, they build expectations about who you are and how
you will behave. They make choices for you, insofar as they assume your consent within their
fantasy. And the dynamic of patriarchy being what it is, the assumed consent within a fantasy
scenario often translates into an assumed consent in reality. Sexist social systems teach men that
it is appropriate to assume women’s consent, especially when we are sexualized, or worse, that
consent is not necessary when it comes to women.
!31
The male imaginary, in terms of the masculinity developed in a sexist social system, is
one in which fantasy is the first step towards actualizing a certain state of affairs. It goes: I want
something, I get it because I deserve it. Or alternatively: I want sex, I deserve sex because I am a
man, therefore women owe me sex. Male entitlement is precisely the expectation that fantasy
desires can and will be actualized on women’s bodies. And so, being the object of a man's fan-
tasies often feels like violence as I am placed in an untenable position where I am already cast
into a role that I am then forced to play out. When approached with their fantasy in mind, it be-
came that much harder to assert myself as independent and my choices and actions as not condi-
tioned by their expectations. This is part of why I hate being hit on — I am being presented with
a fantasy scenario in which it is assumed that I am a willing participant, therefore, there is rarely
if ever an actual inquiry into whether I want to engage back. And the verbal and non-verbal cues
that I do not welcome the interaction are often ignored because they do not fit into the fantasy
scenario of having a connection with a stranger that validates a man’s sexual interest and prow-
ess.
The thing about being cast into someone's fantasy is that it has little to do with the actual
state of the world. The Sophia that stars in men’s fantasies is not me, which is obvious because,
for the most part, these fantasies come from people who do not know me, or know me on a pure-
ly superficial level. They see me as their sexy teacher, the slutty nerd, the secret nympho, the
cute bookworm studying at the neighborhood coffee shop, or the dumb white girl with a fat ass.
These are roles that I do not get to choose for myself, and unsurprisingly place me in less-than-
powerful positions, ones in which I am often at the mercy of a man’s attraction and desire. They
tend to curtail my available options for responding or altering such fantasies, and easily place me
!32
in a position to be acted upon rather than act. This is deeply dehumanizing, as it is a reminder
that as sexualized I am no longer quite human, deserving of dignity and respect, but rather some-
thing sub-human, my existence and purpose predicated on my ability to fulfill men’s desires.
So the stranger who looks my body up and down, declaring that he “has to take you out
for dinner,” doesn't seem to consider the possibility that I have no interest in joining him for any
meal, instead assuming that his interest is tantamount to my acceptance. In fact, my very pres-
ence becomes an allowance. And this leaves me a distinctly powerless position, because the in-
teraction has been defined with the assumption that our positions are not equal, and that we do
not have equal say in the outcome of the interaction. To assert my own desires, which are namely
to say no, is then more than just a rejection of his offer, but also a rejection of the basis of the in-
teraction. It is a rejection of the assumption that I am an object to be acquired through a prede-
termined ritual. It is a rejection of a legacy about women’s purpose and the meaning of women’s
bodies. This becomes a much more complicated endeavor because my actions are more likely to
be misinterpreted to fit into the assumed state of affairs. My ‘no’ can be taken as coy, playful,
just part of the role that I have been assigned.
Similarly, the person who assumes that my main priority is securing male attention flat-
tens all aspect of my being to that shallow intention. In fact, it is so generally assumed that
women prioritize male attention in all of their decision making that I start to wonder if we have
overlooked two important realities: how incredibly easy it is to secure men’s attention and how
incredibly threatening that attention can be. It is hardly the boon that people imply it is, and yet
many persist in seeing my choices through the lens of seeking male approval. And so, for in-
stance, those who judge me as ‘slutty’ or ‘indecent’ for the way I dress and comport myself at-
!33
tempt to determine the meaning of my appearance for me — in ways that foreclose the possibili-
ty that I just like this outfit, that this is my style, or that I feel comfortable like this, etc. And peo-
ple feel incredibly entitled in assuming that my main purpose in life is getting male attention, to
the point that they obscure any alternative motivations that may exist for my actions.
Through sexualization, my body becomes not only a space for men to play out their de-
sires and fantasies, but also a space for acting out tropes of respectability and reputation. I have
learned that in a variety of ways, being sexualized is tantamount to being dehumanized, whether
it is used to deny my agency, erase my access to choose otherwise, or limit my personhood. It
can be challenging to see beyond how the body is co-opted by other’s desires and use-values, and
to frame the value of one’s physical being outside of those external judgments. This, in my expe-
rience, has been one of the most pernicious aspects of sexualization. It is simply too easy to fall
into the trap of blaming oneself for treatment received on the basis of being sexualized.
It is also easy to feel complicit in the ways in which you are evaluated by others. After
all, there I am, moving through space with my various parts. People assume things about me —
my availability, reputation, respectability, and value — based on the visual I present. Even if it is
not my intention, I still actively participate in this performance. Coming to terms with this reality
is challenging, not only when faced with accusations from outside: that I should know better,
“what do you expect when you look like that,” “well maybe you should have thought about it
more before you decided to wear that,” etc — but also when faced with internal stress and disap-
pointment. It wears on me, makes me second guess my own judgment, makes me doubt the legit-
imacy of my access to indignation and frustration because maybe, just maybe, people are right.
!34
That little voice in my head tempts me with my own culpability: Maybe I really should have
known better, and maybe I really did want it just a little bit.
There is no easy answer to these charges. Even today, I find myself continuously forced
to reconcile the fear and frustration of a world in which I am unsafe with my own participation in
that world, even if my participation is largely based on nothing more than my physical presence.
Being sexualized makes people feel justified in using you for their own purposes, emphasizing
the public component of how sexualization functions, e.g. that your sexualized body functions as
a spectacle for others to impose meaning on for their own use. This can be an incredibly demean-
ing position, one that I still struggle to deal with effectively. No matter how much of a feminist
consciousness I’ve developed, I often find myself frozen and startled in situations where others
attempt to control the meaning of my body while simultaneously denying my ability to determine
those meanings for myself. It is disarming to be confronted with the limits of one’s power to ar-
ticulate one’s own purpose.
7. Power
At the beginning of this chapter, I said that this would not be a victim narrative, flat and
typical. But to envision a way out requires an explicit accounting of things as they are. Therefore,
it made sense to start by emphasizing how stifling and complicated sexual power dynamics are in
practice because this reflects the chronology of my own experience. It is often painful, scary, and
frustrating to be sexualized in this world. It is the thing that makes me feel the most threatened,
that most impacts the decisions I make and what I do in my daily life. It is also my biggest
source of insecurity, both in a physical and existential sense. Of course, I recognize that this
speaks volumes about the relative security and privilege that I live in, and I want to be clear that I
!35
am not arguing that sexual stigmatization is the worst type of discrimination that people can ex-
perience. I simply want to articulate the precise ways in which my life is impacted by sexual pol-
itics, and to emphasize the harms inherent in the way that the practices of sexualization are cur-
rently enacted.
The way I see it, I have a few — limited — options. I can become what people tell me I
am, and see myself as less than because I look a certain way and inspire certain desires. I can
swallow the bitter pill of only being good for one thing, and allow my function to be diminished
to the pleasure derivable from my body. In contrast, I can resist and attempt to become the oppo-
site. I can reject the role I have been given by denying the parts of me that cause me pain. While
limited in scope, there is still much I could do to change my body specifically to make it less de-
sirable, or even less attention grabbing. Of course, this may mean sacrificing aspects of myself
that bring me joy, or make me feel good. It also keeps me subordinate to others’ perception of my
being and calls into question the autonomy of my choices. Or, as a third alternative, I can negoti-
ate something different — something that feels right, that is comfortable and happy, at least most
of the time (let’s be realistic).
I have worked to negotiate with the cards I was dealt because I refuse to settle for a way
of life in which I am devalued. I simply can’t accept that option, not after years of letting myself
be denigrated for no good reason. In no uncertain terms, my survival depends on it. And the thing
is, no matter what corners people have tried to back me into, I still maintain a capacity for mean-
ing-making that is perhaps my greatest strength, because it allows me to navigate the epistemic
landscape critically, rather than obediently. It just so happens that a majority of the messages I
received about myself as sexualized taught me to feel shame and accept a dehumanized status.
!36
But, while certainly culturally dominant, this is not a necessary state of affairs. I may have been
trained to feel powerless, but there is a depth of knowledge at the core of my being that reminds
me that I am worth more than how I have been treated. My life has become a work of resisting,
with greater and lesser degrees of success, the types of meanings imposed on my body by forces
that would see me disempowered.
As I mentioned earlier, sexuality is performative and intersubjective, and so how I have
come to understand myself as sexualized is derived from the continuous interactions between
myself and others. It is through these social interactions that I have learned, or been taught, that I
am sexy, desirable, and beautiful, but also that I am simultaneously inappropriate, shameful and
distasteful. These are not things I would come to know without being told. And so in this way,
identifying as easily sexualized is something that has been forced upon me without my explicit
consent. It isn't a character trait that I introduced into my life, or something that I sought out with
any particular intent. Nevertheless, I know that it is a salient aspect of my being, present to the
most superficial inspection. So while perhaps not intentional, being easily sexualized has become
an important part of my personal identity. And, despite my explicit enumeration of the harms
prompted by this identity, I have learned to appreciate it rather than be resigned to it. I would
even go so far as to say that I have learned to enjoy it, although not necessarily for the reasons
that people might assume.
At some point, I realized it was okay to be the way I was; that I could continue being just
who I was without shame or regret. Harassment and policing did not obligate me to become
something different if I did not wish to be changed. I would describe this internal shift — the
recognition that I need not relegate my sexual identity to the norms and scriptures of society —
!37
as a process of unfolding. The labels and judgments and shame that wrapped around me, slowly
loosened their grip on my consciousness until I could step out of their folds. And without these
constraints, I unfurled, stretched out for the first time, testing my new limits. It was a revelation,
a moment of wonder, as I realized that I was not a pet, or a doll, or an animal. I was not a thing to
be owned, or a creature to be tamed. I was not a canvas upon which the public could lay out their
desires and judgments and fantasies. I was just me, and I could find joy in that fact.
For so much of my life, I had been uncomfortable with the fleshiness of my body, with
the jiggling and the rolls and the curves that garnered so much attention. But I decided instead to
feel strong and proud of my presence, luxuriating in the bounce of my body with each step of my
strut. Instead of hiding for fear of being seen, I went out in the world and appreciated what it
meant to be tangible — to feel the pressure of the ground beneath my feet, the wind flowing
around my body and the sun beating down against my skin. Materiality was a joy, because it let
me feel. Sensation grounded me, provided me with a foundation from which to build myself
anew. And so I settled into the tactile, the sensual, and found purpose and value in my body, in
my very physicality, outside of anything it could provide for others, by honing in on what it pro-
vided me. These small acts were the start of something new for me, something exciting and
thrilling and bold. The shift was subtle, especially from the outside. But internally, my inner
compass suddenly had a new north, and it was infinitely better because it directed me towards
my own satisfaction.
I also developed a new orientation to pleasure, luxuriated in the feeling of my body com-
ing into being, and I learned to appreciate that desire could also work in my favor. Sexual plea-
sure was a highlight, something bright and beautiful, against a backdrop of fear, that I decided to
!38
fight for because it made me feel good, a rarity in my life. Feeling good, though simple, was
something that I invested heavily in because it confronted a lifetime of experiences that had
taught me that suffering was normal and to be expected. Women do not get taught to experience
pleasure for themselves, but always as a function of men’s enjoyment. I found myself no longer
willing to take the role of prop, used as a screen to act out some fantasy. I wanted more —
recognition of my being and appreciation of my desires. Instead of feeling resigned to the fact
that I was a woman, I decided to find joy in it. It became something I actively appreciated instead
of bemoaned, something that made me feel powerful and strong instead of small and weak. I
chose joy, in the way I dressed, the way I moved through the world, the things I did. Sexual or
not, this internal shift changed how I addressed so many aspects of my being. It translated into a
wide spectrum of acts that reinforced self-acceptance and the joy of pleasure.
These experiences, on the one hand of developing a strong sexual and erotic identity, and
on the other hand of being targeted for my assumed sexual potential, created a certain friction or
tension that captured my attention. Honing in on that tension, I started to see how the very things
that I was beginning to love and cherish were also consistently under siege by others, how they
were twisted and used against me. There was a battle happening, as the world sought to make me
drop the reins of my pleasure and my passion, and hand them over to be used and controlled by
others. And there I saw power — power at play, and power at stake. And the question, the temp-
tation, arose as I started asking myself: Could this power be mine?
This question continues to preoccupy my mind and my imagination, and I have since ac-
cepted it as centrally important to my well-being in this world. I have tasted power — in the
pleasure I can give myself, and the joy of consensual and respectful coming-togethers. There is
!39
unmistakable power in the awareness that I garner from others, in my apparent ability to capti-
vate and claim attention with nothing more than my presence. Of course, this source of power is
deeply loaded and attempting to mobilize it is a challenging task, one that I am not assured to be
safe or successful in. I have seen that being sexually desirable is both a benefit and a curse, de-
pending on my ability to consent and control a situation. But power is hard to ignore, and when it
comes into being in a visceral way, regularly rearing its pointed face in my daily life, I think it
deserves attention. In fact, I find I must pay attention to it, because it is perhaps the most perva-
sive example of power in my life — it is nearly ever-present, and follows me throughout just
about any space I inhabit, whether it be personal or professional, private or public.
Desire is a messy and complicated power, one often at stake of being a double-edged
sword. It can be tenuous and changeable. Even so, sexualization has come to be not only a con-
straint on my body and available actions, but a way in which I have come to know myself that
brings me joy and pleasure. In a most basic sense, sex makes me grateful to have a body, a rarity
in a world that punishes women for their materiality. Of course, I don't mean to imply that sex
and sexualization are the same things, but insofar as sexualization is the state of being recognized
as a sexual being, sexualization becomes important for sexual activity. They are intimately tied
together, and the pleasure and gratification I receive from engaging in sexual activity make me
recognize some of the more positive aspects of being sexualized. And there are aspects of sexu-
alization that I have come to realize are generative, fun, enjoyable and exciting. It is important to
me that these aspects be emphasized in this discussion because it would hurt to relegate sexual-
ization to the realm of patriarchal enforcement, to allow sexist structures to take ownership and
control of a salient aspect of my identity.
!40
In a perfect world (whatever that means) perhaps I would choose to derive power from a
different source, one less rooted in my oppression, one that does not flirt with the reason that I
can’t walk alone at night, that I have to stay constantly vigilant, that I am polite when I would
like to tell people to fuck off. But these hypothetical scenarios of a different world do little to
help me understand and hone the power that I have access to now. And to be perfectly blunt, I
want the power that I can get. And I want the negotiations and moves that I make to be recog-
nized as attempts not only for survival, but as actions that subvert commonly held assumptions
about the purpose of female sexuality. I am more than the product of a sexually repressive and
oppressive culture, and I have learned to see beyond the lens of our hegemonic sexual ideology. I
hope others will see it too.
And so I emphasize the range of different experiences pertinent to my eroticized exis-
tence in order to avoid creating an account of my sexual identification that rests solely in victim-
ization. I cannot, or will not, be reduced to a victim, even though I have been harmed by my pub-
lic recognition as a sexual being. This matters, because it is all too easy to collapse women’s ex-
periences of sexualization until they are nothing but another way in which we are harmed, anoth-
er instance of a sexist, misogynistic system. I use myself as an example to show that it is always
more complicated than that, and I demand a fuller recognition of my humanity and of my agency
— not only from those who would seek to reduce me to my sexual use-value, but also from those
who would seek to reduce my actions and motivations to nothing more than the products of a
sexist society, with special terms like “adaptive preferences” and “false consciousness.” My so-
called allies that insist on defining me by the abuse I endure, and interpreting everything about
me — from the way I dress, to the way I move, to my sexual activities and the things I desire —
!41
as little more than knee-jerk unreflective reactions to a hostile world, harm me in ways that are
parallel to the men who see me as little more than a sex doll. Both agree that the ways in which I
am sexualized define me, and judge me accordingly.
I stand by the declaration that I can both participate in and subvert an oppressive system.
And I must persist with this conviction because I have little control over the way in which I am
encountered. This lack of control problematizes assumptions made about women’s bodies and
their consent to sexual objectification. My curves have always been exaggerated, obvious. The
way my body takes up space does not provide the option of hiding it. No matter how high the
neckline, how long my skirt, how loose my dress, I cannot avoid being noticed as long as my
body remains the way it is. And I won’t be pushed into denying that I sometimes find satisfaction
is walking through the world and capturing attention. Attention seeking is not a moral flaw, un-
like the construction of masculinity that condones the abuse and mistreatment of women who
capture attention.
8. Conclusion
I am hardly alone in lacking the power to control when and where I am sexualized. And
to be sure, while my sexualization is by far a product of my shape and features, for others it is
also a product of skin color, heritage and class. These things deserve critical attention because
there are many reasons why someone may be incapable of truly controlling how they are viewed
and what is assumed about their character because of how they look. The idea that women can
choose to be recognized as simply human, that they can control by whom they are sexualized —
these assumptions perpetuate a victim-blaming narrative that exacerbates the shame and disgust
that many women feel about their bodies. It also leads to women feeling like their bodies are
!42
against them, that their bodies are to blame for their pain and stigmatization, and that it is their
fault that they are targeted in these ways.
I’ve come to the conclusion that I cannot avoid being sexualized; it is a state of reception
that I cannot escape. But this assertion does not mean:
1. That I am claiming that everyone is attracted to me. Being sexualized and being sexually de-
sired are not exactly the same thing. Being sexualized is, in its barest form, just the percep-
tion of sexual traits or characteristics. It is the reminder of sex, in some capacity, whether it is
a focus or awareness of sexually coded body parts — like breasts and hips — or the general
association of sex to one’s being. Plenty of people sexualize me and make a point that I am
unappealing because of it.
2. That I am claiming that everyone, at all times, is sexualizing me. People often attempt to
downplay my experiences by implying that I am cherry picking events in order to craft a par-
ticular narrative. They accuse me of exaggerating, insisting that sexualization is something I
choose to perceive. And, of course I have interactions with people in which I do not feel ob-
jectified, or reduced to base biological capacities. The thing is, I don't need everyone to sexu-
alize me to feel persistently sexualized. I just need enough people to do it that it becomes a
constant reminder.
3. That I am creating an exclusive and definitive account of femininity, womanhood, or sexuali-
ty. This phenomenology is not an attempt to define what it means to be a woman, or what the
qualifications of womanhood are. Rather, I am trying to bring to light an aspect of being a
woman that is highly significant to my own experience, and that I believe is shared by many,
although certainly not all, people who identify as women. The category of ‘woman’ is not
!43
one that is easily defined, or delimited, due in large part to it being a socially constructed, and
therefore unstable, category. There are some prevalent phenomena associated, although not
universally, with the label, one of which I think is sexualization. The way I see it, this phe-
nomenology is just one patch in a quilt, and some of my ideas may be supported by the expe-
riences of others, while others may be more limited in scope. I may see things differently
than other people, and certainly have blindspots that listening to others will bring to light,
including individuals who were not socialized into womanhood from the beginning. I do not
use my experiences of being gendered and sexualized to deny the experiences of others who
also identify as women, and I recognize that gender manifests on a broad spectrum. I am not
particularly invested in a binary gender system, nor use this phenomenology to legitimize a
gender binary — rather, I describe heterosexual dynamics because of how they impact my
life, and in order to critique the heteronormative performances that we take for granted. My
life would be better, and safer, if we did away with our current narrow understanding of gen-
der, even if that meant I would lose out on some of the privileges I now access.
This phenomenology is just the beginning of this story. While anecdotal, I have pointed
to structures at play when it comes to sexualization. These phenomena offer a backdrop, a sense
of the horizon of my inquiry, and will be elaborated on in the following chapters. I hope readers
will keep in mind the complex and contradictory nature of sexual agency. It is not a straightfor-
ward state of affairs, and so our conversations will have to allow for certain amounts of ambigui-
ty. This is not a failing, but an acknowledgement of the realities of sexual politics as they mani-
fest in real women’s lives.
!44
Samson
You are my sweetest downfall
I loved you first, I loved you first
Beneath the sheets of paper lies my truth
I have to go, I have to go
Your hair was long when we first met
Samson went back to bed
Not much hair left on his head
He ate a slice of wonder bread, and went right back to bed
And history books forgot about us and the Bible didn't mention us
And the Bible didn't mention us, not even once
You are my sweetest downfall
I loved you first, I loved you first
Beneath the stars came fallin' on our heads
But they're just old light, they're just old light
Your hair was long when we first met
Samson came to my bed
Told me that my hair was red
Told me I was beautiful, and came into my bed
Oh, I cut his hair myself one night
A pair of dull scissors in the yellow light
And he told me that I'd done alright
And kissed me till the mornin' light, the mornin' light
And he kissed me till the mornin' light
Samson went back to bed
Not much hair left on his head
He ate a slice of wonder bread, and went right back to bed
Oh, we couldn't bring the columns down
Yeah, we couldn't destroy a single one
And history books forgot about us
And the Bible didn't mention us, not even once
You are my sweetest downfall
I loved you first
11
Regina Spektor. “Samson.”
11
!45
Chapter 2: Love a Man Dead
I care about sexual politics because I see it as a fundamental way in which my life is
shaped by social and political forces. I understand sexuality and the power dynamics encoded
within it as deeply defining the ways in which I am identified, how I identify, and the treatment I
receive in everyday interactions. Because I delve deeply into the sexual landscape, as I describe
in my previous chapter, it has become apparent to me how much sexual power dynamics struc-
ture my lived experience and that of countless women. I have also noticed that these dynamics
are largely described in ways that victimize women, and reinforces our lack of power. I find this
to be (at times) contradictory to the rough ground of my experience, and therefore fundamentally
restrictive — allowing for very little space to create new definitions and descriptions that better
represent what it means to be a sexualized subject. In order to bring to light alternative possibili-
ties that widen our understanding of sexual politics and how women can be situated within it, I
would now like to turn to narratives that exist about highly sexualized women, in order to see if
they offer possibilities to someone interested in liberatory sexual politics — i.e. an understanding
of sexuality that is not beholden to a patriarchal narrative, but has the potential to subvert it.
To accomplish this task, I will be investigating the trope of the Femme Fatale, an iconic
example of both female sexual agency and objectification. While there is no single definition of
the femme fatale, she is commonly portrayed as an agent who uses physical attractiveness to ma-
nipulate and dominate others, specifically (though not necessarily) men. Often morally ambigu-
ous, the femme fatale is also portrayed as duplicitous, dangerous and mysterious, and is alterna-
tively referred to as an enchantress, witch, spider woman or succubus. The femme fatale motif,
and its many different iterations, is arguably ubiquitous, and according to William Jankowiak and
!46
Angela Ramsey, exists nearly universally across cultures,
12
demonstrating a widespread and en
-
during fascination with women who are powerful and threatening insofar as they are desirable.
This preoccupation is often tinged with a certain amount of fear, reinforcing the femme fatale’s
position as a dangerous woman. And while there are many tropes that place women as objects of
sexual desire, the femme fatale is distinct in the threat that she embodies and her ability to en-
gender chaos and death.
Arguably an iconic example of powerful female agency, the femme fatale is nevertheless
a controversial figure insofar as she inhabits multiple, contradictory positions – that of sex object
and sex agent, that of supporting cast and master of her own fate. Rather than overdetermine her
with descriptions,
13
I hope to draw your attention to the power that the femme fatale trope un
-
covers as well as how that power is constituted, in order to explore the ambiguous themes of
sexual agency and eroticism in patriarchal contexts. For the purposes of this discussion, I am in-
terested in exploring the concept of the femme fatale in order to see if it can be read as a narra-
tive of subversive agency that is useful for someone engaged in liberatory sexual politics. By this
I mean: does the femme fatale represent a way of being in the world that showcases agentic
structures that can be recognized as disruptive in a sexist power structure?
My personal interest in the femme fatale follows from a fascination with powerful female
characters used and misused in storytelling — the jealous sidepiece, spurned lover, beautiful in-
nocent, morally suspect sorceress — cast as instruments and, less often, as manipulators of fate. I
am particularly interested in how sexualization is featured in these narratives, especially for the
Jankowiak ,William and Angela Ramsey. “Femme fatale and status fatale: a cross-cultural perspective.” Cross-
12
Cultural Research Vol 34, Issue 1, (2000). Pg. 62.
13
As Cressida Heyes argues, specificity is not always to our advantage.
!47
purposes of vilifying and dehumanizing what should be complex and multi-dimensional charac-
ters. The femme fatale, as a narrative trope, in some ways encompasses all of these varied char-
acters, or rather, all of these characters can be described as having characteristics of a femme fa-
tale insofar as their desirability to men makes them a force to reckon with.
Of course, these stories, as traditionally told and written (by men), often minimize these
women’s agency by casting them as either too stupid or too evil to be responsible for their own
impacts. And it is true that desirability is not the most active of roles, as exemplified by the term
sex object. We tend to minimize women’s claims to their own appeal, instead finding ways for
men to take ownership of women through their desire. However, I believe we shouldn’t be so
quick to dismiss the femme fatale and instead should investigate the sexual, social and ideologi-
cal unrest that she represents, as well as possible motivations for deliberately devaluing or eras-
ing this type of agency. Insofar as the femme fatale represents power derived from sexualization,
I hope to show that sexual agency and eroticism can be acts of subversion or resistance, in order
to complicate the traditional narrative that such acts only perpetuate women’s oppression.
1. What does it mean to re-appropriate?
For the purposes of this chapter, I am interested in the question of whether women can
choose to create and play more liberatory language games even if they are not completely dis-
tinct from sexist language games that we also participate in, and if therefore we can describe the
practices of women as sexual agents as actually subverting oppressive norms. While I have cen-
tered the figure of the femme fatale in this discussion, this chapter is not meant to be literary or
cinematic criticism but rather a philosophical exploration of a particular manifestation of sexual
agency. For the purposes of this chapter, my intent is not to label the femme fatale as a role mod-
!48
el, or make her aspirational in any significant way, as much as call upon an iconic example of a
woman whose power is tied up in her desirability. And with an attentiveness to language, we can
articulate the femme fatale not so much as a character or personality type, but rather as a descrip-
tion of certain practices. These practices are most commonly articulated in two main ways: one
situated in a “sexist” language game, and the other in a “subversive” language game.
I use
14
these labels to set up a contrast as well as draw attention to the material realities of the femme
fatale in each language-game, but it is important to note that these language-games are not mutu-
ally exclusive, but exist in relation to one another. Indeed, most of us participate in both of these
language-games, among many others.
To better articulate how tropes and narrative exploration can be helpful for this type of
investigation, I will briefly turn to the philosophy of language of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Accord-
ing to Wittgenstein, to acquire the sense of a concept we must “examine it within the complex
form of life that is revealed in the way speakers live and act.” For Wittgenstein, meaning re
15
-
sides in social use, and so to know the meaning of a concept is not simply a matter of being able
to define it, but of knowing how to use it. In order to show understanding of a term or concept, it
is necessary to make the appropriate connections between the concept and the language-game
within which it is deployed. Language-games, according to Wittgenstein, link a particular em-
ployment of language with the “actions into which it is woven,” and are therefore the setting
16
I leave open the possibility that there may be other articulations/language games available for understanding the
14
Femme Fatale that are not included in this discussion.
Marie McGinn, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations (1997)
15
71., quoted in Leader-Elliott, Ian, and Ngaire Naffine. “Wittgenstein, Rape Law and the Language Games of Con-
sent.” Monash University Law Review 26 (2000). Pg. 52, emphasis mine.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, and G. E. M. Anscombe. Philosophical Investigations. Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 1997: Pg.
16
77.
!49
within which our terms find meaning. I believe this conceptualization of language is particularly
useful for our investigation because it allows us to take a practical approach to understanding our
world, one in which we come to know something by doing it. It also recognizes that those who
participate in a language game have access to shared meaning, for we come to know through our
participation in a shared world.
Because language is social, there is no possibility of a private language, meaning that in
this investigation I cannot make Femme Fatale represent just anything to suit my purposes.
Things as they are in the world constrain the possibilities of our imagining, and of our language.
One can’t invent meaning out of nothing — therefore, even if language is arbitrary insofar as it is
contingent, meaning must come from something publicly available. Hilde Lindemann showcases
this dilemma with what she calls the “Humpty Dumpty theory of language,” using the following
excerpt from Alice in Wonderland:
“But ‘glory’ doesn’t mean ‘a nice knockdown argument,’” Alice
objected.
“When I use a word,” Humpty Dumpty said, in rather a scornful
tone, “it means just what I choose it to mean – neither more nor
less.”
“The question is,” said Alice, “whether you can make words mean
so many different things.”
“The question is,” said Humpty Dumpty, “which is to be master –
that’s all.” 17
Alice and Humpty Dumpty present us with a philosophical question: Is language master, or do
we master language? This question is somewhat deceptive because although we create language,
it exerts force upon us and our world. The legacies of our shared language-games create certain
Lindemann, Hilde. “Wittgenstein Meets ‘Woman’ in the Language-Game of Theorizing Feminism.” In Feminist
17
Interpretations of Wittgenstein. Ed. Naomi Scheman and Peg O’Connell. University Park: Penn State Press, 2002.
pg. 217.
!50
restrictions on how we may speak in the future. Private language or private meaning (what
Humpty Dumpty is claiming to have) is incoherent according to Wittgenstein because language
is by nature a public thing, insofar as meaning resides in social use.
‘Femme fatale,’ then, like any other term, “requires a grammar, a certain conventionally
determined positioning in the language,” as well as “criteria for application whose correctness
can be determined independently of the person wielding them.” That there are grammatical
18
constraints on ‘femme fatale,’ does not mean, according to Lindemann, that the concept cannot
be rescued from certain illicit usages, no matter how popular or entrenched they may be — the
reason being that language, like the forms of life in which it is embedded, always contains the
possibilities of challenge and change.
When a language game ceases to be useful, it loses its
19
force in the world and demands change for practical reasons — so that we may continue com-
municating and living in a shared world. Since we all participate in these language games, there
may come a time when they are no longer adequate, and the disruption may prove capable of not
only challenging what has generally been acceptable for communicating and understanding the
world and ourselves, but may provide the impetus to change it. With this in mind, let us further
contemplate the way in which the femme fatale is popularly understood, as well as the possibility
of addressing what I propose are inadequate language games.
2. Saving the femme fatale: an impossible task?
According to Lynne Tirrell, a story is “a narrative with a certain very specific syntactic
shape (beginning-middle-end or situation-transformation-situation) and with a subject matter
18
Ibid. 219
19
Ibid.
!51
which allows for or encourages the projection of human values upon this material.” Stories
20
arrange events into rationalized sequences which speak truth about the world, people and their
interactions. We use narrative structures to make sense of ourselves and to speak to the human
condition. We also tell stories to promote a certain way of understanding our environments and
to establish world paradigms. In telling a story, “one articulates what one thinks about a set of
events, a particular character, a set of characters, an issue, a problem, or whatever. One has one’s
say. In addition, one presents a perspective, a character, and a set of judgments which delimit
each.” Storytelling is therefore never purely objective, as it is always inscribed with a certain
21
position, whether this position is taken consciously or not.
As I alluded to in the introduction to this chapter, the idea of the seductively powerful
woman has been at play in our collective hermeneutical resources for millennia (just consider
Eve’s seduction of Adam, or Circe’s seduction of Odysseus), but the archetype of the femme fa-
tale especially flourished in contemporary pop culture with the introduction of film noir, the dark
and brooding style of cinema that came into prominence in the 1940s. The noir cinematic genre
is easily identified by its hyper-stylized visuals, depicting a world cast in monochromatic
grayscale, and steeped in shadows, often taking on a stark, almost prison-like aesthetic. Equally
as iconic as the dark visuals are the dark plot lines — thrillers and detective films imbued with an
overwhelming sense of cynical pessimism. This moodiness is reinforced by the stereotypically
disjointed and fragmented narration style, lending an almost confessional air to the story. All of
these elements — the desaturated and underexposed visuals mixed with melancholy voiceovers
Tirrell, Lynne. "Storytelling and Moral Agency." The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48, no. 2 (1990). Pg.
20
115.
21
Ibid. 116
!52
— serve to disorient the viewer, creating a sense of alienation and threat that lingers throughout
the storyline.
In the classic film noir plot, the (male) protagonist finds himself infiltrating a dark world
of corruption and intrigue, precipitated by a chance encounter with the femme fatale, who be-
comes the driving force of his downward spiral into darkness and criminality. And while their
meeting is coincidental — he knocks on her door to sell life insurance, like in Double Indemni-
ty — as Elisabeth Bronfen so wonderfully puts it, their meeting follows the fateful logic of love
22
at first sight,
23
although invariably the story is far from a typical romance. Indeed, the noir plot is
almost a subversion of the traditional love story, as the classic boy-meets-girl trope thrusts the
male protagonist into danger and criminality rather than heroism, and love-at-first-sight is im-
bued with deception and betrayal rather than the hope and purity of the fairy tales that provide
the most culturally prominent Happily Ever Afters. The male protagonist and the femme fatale
are partners in only the most superficial of ways, as there is a constant undercurrent of distrust in
their relationship, and neither truly fits the mold of the classic love interest, the femme fatale not
helpless enough, and the male hero not invincible enough.
In the vein of love stories gone awry, the classic femme fatale diverges dramatically from
more traditional love interests because she is not only sexually uninhibited, but also unabashedly
independent and ruthlessly ambitious.
24
She has no qualms about using her seductive charms and
her intelligence to liberate herself from an untenable situation, which in the noir narrative is often
22
Double Indemnity. Directed by Billy Wilder. Paramount Pictures, 1944.
Bronfen, Elisabeth. "Femme Fatale — Negotiations of Tragic Desire." New Literary History 35, no. 1 (2004). Pg.
23
105
24
Ibid.
!53
the imprisonment of an unfulfilling marriage. In fact, it is not so hard to imagine the femme fa-
tale as the cynical product of the famous fairy tale love stories that have captured our popular
consciousness, if these stories were to extend past riding into the sunset hand in hand with one’s
True Love. She is Cinderella after marrying Prince Charming, realizing that she has traded the
prison of servitude for that of matrimony. Or Snow White after being awakened by her True
Love’s Kiss, still valued primarily for her beauty and still in the service of men. While maintain-
ing a status of desirability, the femme fatale has lost the shiny veneer of purity, replacing it with a
brooding sensuality, obscured by a haze of cigarette smoke.
And so, “from the moment the hero catches sight of the femme fatale, both find them-
selves caught in a sequence of events which can go only one way” : intrigue, betrayal and ulti
-
25
mately death. In their chance meeting, the femme fatale recognizes the protagonist as a means of
escape, and pursues his complicity in her machinations in order to free herself from the static and
unsatisfying fate that she has been taught to welcome — namely, matrimony. She will seduce
him, he will be seduced, and subsequently duped into participating in her scheme to be free. As
this scheme usually involved the death of the femme fatale’s husband, the protagonist becomes
an accomplice to murder, and sometimes theft and extortion through life-insurance scams, as in
Double Indemnity. Her seduction is the launching point for his descent into criminality and de-
struction, which he can only escape through the inevitable death of the femme fatale, often at the
hands of the protagonist, thus absolving himself of her scheming, and any responsibility for their
shared actions. Nevertheless, his status as agent is forever called into question as the specter of
the femme fatale’s manipulations taints his autonomy and self-determination with a reminder of
25
Ibid. 105-6
!54
his fallibility. It is not a traditional happy ending, but one that lingers in the realm of ambivalence
as the hero comes face to face with the limits of his agency, and a reminder of his mortality.
This classic noir plot is compelling, not only because it delves deep into the dark side of
human nature, but because the same sequence of events can tell two very different stories. Since
any given story takes on a particular perspective, one meant to impact the audience in a certain
way, then we should ask ourselves what the noir narrative’s purpose is, who is telling it, and why
it matters. These factors will speak to the function of the language game within which it is de-
ployed. Delving into the femme fatale trope presented in film noir, we are confronted with multi-
ple levels of meaning-making: the author’s, or in our case the film-maker’s, intent, the meaning
of the film itself, and the wider social impacts of the film. These multiple levels of interpretation
are simultaneously at play, allowing the story to have a larger sphere of impact than perhaps in-
tended, and to reverberate through our social fabric and collective imagination. This is also why
the femme fatale story can speak to issues beyond the characters and events it portrays — and
can tell us something about our hopes, fears and beliefs, depending on the grammar and the lan-
guage game within which it is situated. I will now briefly contrast the femme fatale’s manifesta-
tion in the sexist language game and the subversive language game to elaborate on this point.
The femme fatale as she is constructed in the sexist language game takes on multiple
frames of reference: the trope carries sexist intentions, is told through sexist storytelling and has
sexist consequences/resonances in society. In other words, the femme fatale trope can be under-
stood as oppressive within the framework of the film, and it can also signify oppression outside
of the film. The femme fatale trope can be articulated as a product of sexist intentions in two
main ways: first, that the femme fatale is nothing more than male fantasy, highlighting the simul-
!55
taneous fascination with sexualized women with a fear of the power they may hold over men,
and second, that the femme fatale’s figurative purpose is to police women’s sexuality in order to
maintain the status quo. Within the film, the trope can be interpreted as a ritualistic performance
of male dominance over female agency. Outside the film, the trope validates the gendered social
order, and men’s patriarchal desires, by suggesting that these social and legal orders exist to pre-
vent men from being taken advantage of or otherwise exploited by women. It serves not so much
to highlight women’s sexual agency (even a limited sense of agency) but rather serves to rein-
force men’s desires to silence women through the problematic concept that men must safeguard
not only their masculinity, but also ensure that women’s sexuality is constantly policed, in order
to maintain male hegemony.
The subversive language game challenges the primacy of the sexist language game by
providing alternative interpretations of the femme fatale’s meaning, both within the framework
of film noir, recognizing that the femme fatale trope within the context of film noir can be under-
stood in a variety of ways, but also in the wider social context of sexual politics writ large, rec-
ognizing that the femme fatale trope may offer insight into the politics of sexualization as a so-
cial phenomenon. Having access to an alternative interpretation allows the subversive language
game to articulate a femme fatale that is not beholden to harmful norms in a way that perpetuates
the marginalization of women as nothing more than sex objects, thus providing a novel way of
understanding the impact of the noir plot. It also provides us the opportunity to reconceptualize a
classic account of female sexual agency that is widely available, and thus accessible. The subver-
sive language game generates possibilities for understanding gender and sexuality as constructs
that are malleable rather than fixed. Indeed, what is subversive about the subversive language
!56
game is that it challenges the authority of sexist knowledge production, calling into question the
internal logic of patriarchal world-building and meaning-making.
A. Sexual Agency
I would like to look at these different levels of interpretation first by looking at how fe-
male sexual agency is interpreted in the sexist language game in contrast to the subversive lan-
guage game. Generally speaking, in the sexist language game, the femme fatale’s sexual agency
is nothing more than a mechanism for policing women’s sexuality. In the subversive language
game, the femme fatale’s sexual agency is used for the sake of securing independence and free-
dom.
The sexist language game presents us with a femme fatale who acts as a mirror for het-
eropatriarchal paranoia used to reinforce hegemonic norms of appropriate female sexuality. In
this game, she is primarily the manifestation of male fantasy, revealing both a fascination with
sexually aggressive and uninhibited women, while simultaneously revealing fears of feminine
domination.
These contradictory preoccupations speak to the ways in which female sexuality is
26
established and policed within a sexist system. In fact, the policing of female sexuality depends
upon a paradoxical construction — where women will be simultaneously reviled and desired for
their sexuality. Women are put in their place, so to speak, by creating conditions for successful
existence that are impossible to meet. Female sexuality is further constrained by being placed in
contrast to respectability, so that sexual aggression in the femme fatale, while desirable, also be-
comes a reason to find her morally suspect. This is because sexually aggressive behavior repre-
sents a transgression of feminine norms, insofar as women are supposed to be sexually passive in
26
Ibid. 106
!57
order to maintain a tenuous respectability. And yet, patriarchal systems continuously promote
representations of women as hyper-sexual, creating a consumerist culture of women as sexually
available objects. In effect, women are both rewarded and punished for transgressing these sexist
feminine norms, which is reflected in the distrust that the femme fatale encounters in the noir
plot.
The significance of female sexual desirability in the noir narrative also reinforces certain
assumptions about the use value of female sexuality. The femme fatale’s power, grounded as it is
in her existential eroticism — her existence as beauty and sex object
27
— is easily implicated in
perpetuating, rather than subverting, oppressive social conventions designed to keep women in a
subservient position. After all, sex object — even sex icon — is a status designated by men in a
sexist superstructure, and therefore seems to be constrained by its source — one that is struc-
turally opposed to female agency. It is certainly true that if we accept that women’s lived experi-
ence as and through sexual desirability forecloses their autonomy,
28
then focusing too narrowly
on the femme fatale’s sexual agency could cause us to overlook that her sexuality (and any pow-
er therein) is simply derivative of heteropatriarchal norms. In other words, her desirability seems
to allow her some sort of power only because it was granted by men, and so it is a power con-
strained by men’s use for women’s sexuality. As Maddy Coy and Maria Garner argue, “such ex-
change-use of femininity… is shaped by restrictions created by structural factors, legitimated
only by masculinity and therefore unable to claim power of its own.” The femme fatale, insofar
29
Welch, Shay. Existential Eroticism: A Feminist Approach to Understanding Women's Oppression-Perpetuating
27
Choices. Lexington Books, 2015: 35.
28
Ibid.
Coy, Maddy & Garner, Maria. “Glamour modelling and the marketing of self-sexualization: Critical reflections.”
29
International Journal of Cultural Studies. 13. (2010). Pg. 660.
!58
as she is implicated in a politics of male-defined female sexuality, arguably fails to challenge the
material realities of continuing gender-based oppression. Without challenging material realities,
it can be difficult to envision how she might effectuate any meaningful change to power dynam-
ics.
This type of critique is frequently raised within the confines of the sexist language game,
and should be taken seriously, because we ought to avoid perpetuating, or otherwise becoming
complicit in, our own oppression. It is therefore a complicated terrain to navigate, particularly if
we accept that the source of power has determination over its use and influence. But it is worth
noting that this assumption boils down to a question of whether the source of a force in the world
(like sexualization, or even sexual desire) is mastered by where it manifests. While I am not sure
that all powers are completely indebted to their source, this is a frequent worry of feminist criti-
cal projects, and we ought to be attentive to the ways in which legacy can impact possibility. It is
certainly the case that in a language game like the sexist language game, there is no possibility of
female sexual performance serving any interests but men’s. Personally, I find this highly unsatis-
fying, and believe there is a need for alternative interpretations of female sexual agency that are
less deterministic.
Turning to the subversive language game, we find an account of sexual agency that offers
subtle but significant differences to the sexist language game. In this second interpretation, the
femme fatale is more than simply a symptom of the hero’s fantasy realm. While she may be the
object of the hero’s desires, her meaning goes beyond that which is prescribed to her from the
male gaze. The femme fatale therefore represents an alternative to traditional gender roles by of-
fering a practice of eroticism that is not entirely reducible to patriarchal constructs — insofar as
!59
its purpose is primarily for her own self-advancement, and her sexuality is only instrumentally
for the purposes of male desire. She will use male desire to get what she wants or where she
wants, but her end game is not male gratification, or even the exercise of being desirable —
rather these things are a means to an end. This is a subtle but significant distinction; the femme
fatale may gain power over the noir hero by nourishing his sexual fantasies, but her own interests
remain only superficially erotic.
30
Considering the sequence of events that lead to the femme fa
-
tale’s seduction of the protagonist, this interpretation offers a challenge to the sexist language
game’s assumptions that female sexual desirability can only serve men’s purposes.
Within the subversive language game, we are offered an opportunity to recognize the
femme fatale’s agency within the confines of her situation. It is arguable that the femme fatale
recognizes the role that she has been cast into by the protagonist, and uses her position as prey
“in order to introject her own scenario into his romantic one.” In effect, she uses the sexist lan
31
-
guage game’s blind spots to dupe the hero and manipulate the situation to her own ends, for the
male protagonist could never recognize her as his equal. This presents an internal critique that
showcases the limits of the sexist language game’s ability to accurately represent the state of
gender dynamics. Therefore, the threat of the femme fatale to the status quo manifests primarily
in how she affects the social dynamic through her performance as an object and subject of desire
— her willingness and ability to express herself in sexualized terms for her own benefit. The
femme fatale creates a tension or resistance to the heteronormative model by using desire to as-
sert her own power and assert control over social interactions, “largely abjur[ing] traditional ro-
30
Bronfen, “Femme Fatale,” 106.
31
Ibid. 108
!60
mance and passive domesticity.” I believe this presents an alternative to the view that women’s
32
sexuality as desirability is shaped and limited to the model of gender as dominance.
33
It shows
that the sexist language game, or the patriarchal grammar it is encoded with, is not essential or
necessary. And while most likely not the noir author’s intent, the narrative nevertheless shows an
attentive viewer that pleasure and power are not always in the purview of the man, nor are they
beholden to male structures of dominance. Rather, power is so to speak malleable, and the same
set of actions may be deployed to very different ends.
B. Purpose of the Femme Fatale
Next, I would like to look at the femme fatale’s purpose in the sexist language game in
contrast to the subversive language game. In the sexist language game, the femme fatale is posi-
tioned as a tool for perpetuating male power and maintaining masculine hegemony and female
oppression. Within this fits an articulation of the femme fatale as static and un-agentic sex object.
In the subversive language game, the femme fatale challenges heteropatriarchal assumptions to
show that there is an excess of meaning that cannot be consumed by sexist structures — an ex-
cess of meaning that points us to the existence of alternative epistemic resources for understand-
ing women's experiences of sexual agency.
Part of what makes the femme fatale so compelling is that she seems rife with contradic-
tions. Bronfen argues that within the sexist language game, film noir itself can be read as a “male
fantasy” with a poignant contradiction:
Even while it offers a stage for the dangerous woman, it also re-
lentlessly plays through her demise. This is because “the myth of
Boozer, Jack. “The Lethal Femme Fatale in the Noir Tradition.” Journal of Film and Video. Vol. 51, No. 3/4.
32
(1999): Pg. 20.
33
Welch, Existential Eroticism.
!61
the strong, sexually aggressive woman first allows sensuous ex-
pression of her dangerous power and its frightening results, and
then destroys it, thus expressing repressed concerns of the female
threat to male dominance.
34
While intentional or not, the destruction of the femme fatale takes on an inevitability that speaks
to the role that sexualized women are given within a sexist system — namely, as something to be
dominated. This is because the femme fatale poses an existential threat to the male protagonist
specifically, and also men in general, by calling into question the construction of masculinity.
This threat can only be contained through the destruction or domestication of the femme fatale,
forcefully reasserting the primacy of masculinity, which is evidenced in the routine way in which
noir film ends with the femme fatale either dead or married.
The logic of the sexist language
35
game, therefore, requires that the femme fatale be destroyed in order to maintain the status quo
of gender politics, because she “functions as a symptom of the noir hero’s fatal enjoyment in
such a way that, by destroying her he hopes to purify himself of the desire she inspired and the
guilt this entailed.” The femme fatale’s body becomes the screen upon which the male protago
-
36
nist plays out his fantasies, distances his failures, and reasserts his independence and position of
power. This speaks to a cultural backdrop of sexism and misogyny, where women are simultane-
ously devalued and feared, fetishized for the pleasure they manifest and used to reaffirm the log-
ic of patriarchy.
Film noir therefore rather explicitly showcases the destructive repercussions of attempt-
ing to cross the boundaries set in place by sexist structures of power. The femme fatale, charac-
34
35
Bronfen, “Femme Fatale,” 113.
Boozer, “The Lethal Femme Fatale,” 22.
36
Bronfen, “Femme Fatale,” 107.
!62
terized by uninhibited and aggressive sexuality, is set up to fail precisely because she refuses to
conform to appropriate modes of feminine existence. Her demands to be a player in the game, to
assert her independence and use rather than be used, all turn her into the type of being that does
not easily fit the sexist model. Jack Boozer argues that the frequency and similarity of the femme
fatale’s incarnations in classic noir films “clearly points to a mass market demand to see these
demonstratively ambitious and dangerous women put back in their domestic ‘place.’” In this
37
way, the femme fatale’s ritualistic destruction at the end of her story offers a cathartic solution to
a society plagued with fears and anxieties about women’s sexual and economic liberation. In or-
der to reinstate the status quo, the femme fatale has to pay for transgressing social norms, espe-
cially for being a sexual agent — perhaps even more so for being a sexual agent than for the oth-
er crimes she commits.
Within this sexist framework, where the femme fatale’s only use-value is to police the
behavior of women in order to reinforce the practices of appropriate femininity and desirability,
the viewer might ask why the femme fatale would even attempt to free herself when her destruc-
tion seems almost pre-ordained, particularly if we conceptualize sexist gender politics as a kind
of omnipotent “higher power.” Bronfen claims that Double Indemnity offers us a possible answer
to this question in a brief, but arresting, exchange between Walter (the male protagonist) and
Phyllis (the femme fatale). In the scene, Walter tells Phyllis about a woman who ended up in
prison after killing her husband when his life insurance claim was investigated, a situation eerily
similar to the one Phyllis finds herself in. The camera closes in on Marlene Deitrich’s face, the
actress playing Phyllis, as she replies quietly, talking more to herself than Walter, “Perhaps it was
37
Boozer, “The Lethal Femme Fatale,” 22.
!63
worth it to her.” This brief moment provides rare insight into the femme fatale’s interiority, and a
glimpse at the high stakes of her actions. While Walter cannot fathom why the woman had at-
tempted to commit what he only sees as insurance fraud and murder, Phyllis obviously em-
pathizes with the woman’s motivations, and her willingness to risk getting caught in her scheme.
The gap between the two character’s assessment speaks to the space separating them, both in
terms of their motivation, but also in terms of their logic and grammar. As Bronfen argues, this
rupture renders visible the incompatibility of their two fantasy scenarios, and offers the viewer a
choice: “will we privilege Walter Neff’s misogynistic description of the femme fatale in his voice
over narrative, or recognize her as a separate human being, exceeding his appropriation of her,
and in doing so, exhibiting an agency of her own?” This choice encapsulates the possibility of
38
switching between language games by offering a moment of disruption in which the viewer is
offered the opportunity to choose one interpretation over the other.
The juxtaposition of the femme fatale’s experience of her life as deeply unsatisfying with
the trappings of a successful existence (for a woman) i.e. money, clothes, and wedded bliss, cre-
ates a tension that, to the outsider, may seem minimal. But for the femme fatale, it becomes un-
bearable, precisely because this tension illuminates what the femme fatale lacks — freedom and
independence. She has nothing that is her own; even her value is dependent upon others around
her, and specifically the husband she seeks to escape. So given the opportunity, or the chance en-
counter, the femme fatale decides to put to use that which she is used for, in order to achieve
what she really wants: independence. While this is often framed as selfishness, it can equally be
recognized as an act of desperation. The femme fatale needs to escape her situation, which takes
38
Bronfen, “Femme Fatale,” 112.
!64
on an all-encompassing and oppressive flavor that sets the stage for her seduction of the protago-
nist. Her motives are not particularly pure, nor good in an unambiguous way. She toes, and usu-
ally crosses, the ethical line, navigating through the murky space to the side of morality, because
for her, it is a matter of survival. And so, in her seduction and manipulations, she takes on a mer-
cenary characteristic which foreshadows her inevitable destruction. She is fighting a losing battle
because her aim is more than just money — it is something that destabilizes norms of femininity
and sexual difference in a way that threatens the security of masculine power.
The subversive language game provides us with the resources to acknowledge the femme
fatale as a subject of her own actions, and an opportunity to
No longer be[] blind to the way she is anything but a screen for
male fantasy. It also means overcoming a critical prejudice,
which, by treating her as a symptom of masculine anxieties and
not as a subject of female agency, allows us as critics to avoid the
tragic message she relentlessly embodies.
39
The femme fatale’s desperation can be overlooked if we persist in interpreting her as mercurial,
selfish and intent on petty destruction. But a deeper look unveils a figure who feels trapped, de-
spairs her fate, and is willing to do almost anything to set herself free. Rather than simply being
blindly destructive, the femme fatale has reason behind her actions. She may be ruthless, even
merciless or cruel, but that ruthlessness serves a purpose. To limit her impact to only perpetuat-
ing patriarchal interests does a disservice to the femme fatale by turning her into a caricature, and
obscuring the realities that she faces. It also shields us from the moral obligation that comes from
recognizing that a harm has been done. It is far easier to “avoid the tragic message” that the
39
Ibid. 115
!65
femme fatale embodies in favor of seeing her as foolish, flat, and nothing more than the manifes-
tation of masculine suspicion and distrust of women.
C. Broader Cultural Context
Finally, underlying both interpretations of the femme fatale’s sexual agency and narrative
purpose, we see that the treatment of the femme fatale within the context of film noir speaks to a
broader social context.
In the sexist language game, the femme fatale trope speaks to a larger fear of women be-
coming more financially and personally independent, and therefore less beholden to men for sur-
vival. Noir narratives found cultural resonance in the social instability of the 40’s and 50's,
as
40
traditional gender norms and roles were called into question in what would later be recognized as
the very beginnings of the women’s liberation movement. The iconic darkness and cynicism of
film noir capture the hegemonic response to the unstable social and economic conditions follow-
ing the second world war, including the newly found economic independence of women who had
entered the workforce by necessity only to be pushed out again when their men came home from
war.
41
Once offered the opportunity to provide for themselves, and have their labor compensated,
even if not at the same level as men could expect, many women were understandably resistant to
the idea of being forced back into unpaid domestic labor.
In response to these cultural shifts, the classic noir plot speaks to the insecurities of men
encountering new practices of feminine independence and self-sufficiency that destabilized es-
tablished social norms. The femme fatale, who plots to take her husband’s money, becomes a foil
40
Boozer, “The Lethal Femme Fatale,” 22.
41
Ibid.
!66
for the threat of women usurping what rightfully belonged to men — particularly the ability to
make money and partake in capitalist enterprise. Not only does the femme fatale try to accumu-
late wealth for herself, bypassing the need for a man to provide her with economic security, she
does so using manipulation and deception. The implication is that women are not capable of
earning their own capital without engaging in some sort of underhanded or criminal endeavor,
and that any woman who is independent has gained that status through some kind of deception
and therefore cannot be trusted. In effect, female independence becomes a signal for criminal
behavior, which justifies the femme fatale’s demise.
In the subversive language game, the femme fatale speaks more broadly to a shift in gen-
dered power relations. It is commonly assumed that women profit from oppressive norms simply
for the sake of profiting — in this case for the sake of being seen as desirable or fitting the pre-
scribed model of a valuable woman. But the femme fatale shows an alternative to this model in-
sofar as desirability is merely instrumental to what she hopes to achieve. Part of my own fascina-
tion with the femme fatale stems from how she uses that which is so often used against her for
her own benefit. She turns the table on traditional dynamics of desire and attraction. And when
you walk away from her story, whatever else you may think of her, it is hard to deny that she is
strong, conniving, intelligent, and strategic. And yes, she is beautiful, but her beauty is an active
thing rather than static and reifying — her beauty is but a starting point for her activity. She has
depth; she is more than just a reflective surface for men’s fantasies. She circumvents traditional
roles to create new pathways, and her existence troubles the kinds of meaning-making that tradi-
tionally surrounds women.
!67
Beauty, in a sexist system, often renders women powerless, because it becomes the de-
termining factor of their fate. To be beautiful is to be targeted as prey, to be hunted down and rei-
fied as some status object, a living trophy. Beauty gets you trapped in loveless marriages,
bartered as a good for trade, treated as property to be used for status and pleasure. A subversive
reading of the femme fatale recognizes the limitations of valuing beauty as a thing in itself.
Which is not to say that beauty has no intrinsic value, for there is arguably pleasure and joy to be
found in the presence of beauty. Beauty adds something essential, something necessary, to our
world, and participating in it brings a sense of satisfaction that is undeniable. In my more fanciful
moments, I like to imagine myself as a flower of some kind, whose very presence adds some-
thing special to its environment and draws the eye, providing a moment to pause and reflect on
the wonder of nature and an appreciation for color, texture and lines. I like being beautiful, not
even primarily because of what it can get me, or its use-value, but because it is nice to participate
in a good. I don’t even mind when people tell me I’m beautiful, unless their intent is to turn me
into a possession. But this is an unfortunate reality within a sexist language game, wherein beau-
ty as a good is constrained.
I offer the femme fatale trope as a critique of beauty, not because we ought to reject its
intrinsic value, but rather to showcase the mistaken assumptions made about the extent to which
beauty positively impacts women’s lives. The femme fatale recognizes that simply being beauti-
ful does not give her the life she wants. This idea, that beauty is not by itself a satisfying life for a
woman, contests deeply rooted assumptions about women’s values and desires, especially the
tacit assumption that beauty is an end point for women, and that to be beautiful is to have
reached a coveted status that satisfies in and of itself. Which is not to say that beauty isn't covet-
!68
ed, and that it doesn't impart a certain status even within the subversive language game. Rather, it
is often a highly unsatisfying status, one that fulfills limited needs, and does not impart much in
the way of survival. While perhaps a minute point, or even a mere technicality to some, this shift
acknowledges a hermeneutical lacuna that further justifies the need to see otherwise.
The femme fatale’s power and agency are also highlighted when contrasted with the pas-
sivity and helplessness she causes in those she engages with. Phenomenologically speaking, in
the narrative of the femme fatale, desire and lust overwhelm the protagonist’s attention, holding
him "captive," so to speak, even if only for a brief moment. I argue that the femme fatale recog-
nizes that this ability to engender desire potentially gives her the upper hand, insofar as it enables
her to frame a social interaction. In film noir, this can be seen in her ability to entrance and hyp-
notize her victim; hence, the femme fatale today is still often described as having a power akin to
an enchantress, witch, or demon.
While captivated by the femme fatale, traditionally active
42
players (like men) become passive and malleable, allowing the femme fatale the opportunity to
manipulate states of affairs to her advantage. In this way, I believe the femme fatale manifests
new practices and description of what it means for a woman to actively encourage being encoun-
tered as a sexualized being.
Through the subversive language game, we therefore are presented with a new concept of
the erotic, one which inverts the sexist language-game’s understanding of eroticism, in which
eroticism can have no ultimate end other than male approval. The grammar of the sexist lan-
guage game forecloses the femme fatale's type of sexual agency, and arguably does her a disser-
vice by misinterpreting or misrepresenting the rough ground of her being. Which is not to say
42
Ridge, George Ross. "The "Femme Fatale" in French Decadence." The French Review 34, no. 4 (1961): Pg. 352.
!69
that the subversive language game should be considered the end-all-be-all of female sexual
agency. Even understood as subversive, the femme fatale’s eroticism is not ideal or unproblemat-
ic. But it also does not have to be to show marked improvement over the sexist language game’s
articulation of female sexuality.
3. The dialectic
By emphasizing Wittgenstein’s conceptualization of language as a public shared activity,
one that is always stemming from and relating to practices, we can see that the sexist and subver-
sive interpretations are both valid insofar as they are part of different language game – respec-
tively creating and foreclosing the possibility of subversive sexual agency. If we accept that both
of these language games exist simultaneously, then the opportunity arises to make a choice. I be-
lieve that directing our attention to the existence of different language games – tied to different
descriptions of practices, can create a starting point to advocate for one conception over the oth-
er. From a political standpoint, one interpretation clearly presents opportunities for empower-
ment that the other does not, and ultimately in this investigation I am most concerned with how
ideas play out in people’s lives. If agency is constituted by the norms and discourses made avail-
able to us, then I argue that it is especially important to reconceptualize tropes like the femme
fatale.
Narratives/stories and pictures are often how people are placed in hierarchies, “how so-
cial stratification is made to seem inevitable and right, how feelings of inferiority and superiority
are engendered, and how indifference to violence against those on the bottom is rationalized and
normalized.” According to Wittgenstein, we are often held captive by a picture, a picture that
43
Langton, Rae and Caroline West. “Scorekeeping in a Pornographic Language Game,” Australasian Journal of
43
Philosophy, Vol 77, No 3. (1999): Pg. 305.
!70
can be misleading as it shows the world (and us) in a misrepresentative way.
44
Cressida Heyes
argues that to the extent that we are held captive or entranced by such a picture, we are unfree,
especially if that picture does not fit our “ethical commitments, or if it limits our agency and pos-
sibilities.” Beholden to an image, people can fail to see otherwise, to recognize alternatives that
45
already exist. We can also be blind to the material realities of people’s lives and actions. The
practices that create differences in privilege and marginalization are thus deeply intertwined with
our language-games, and one cannot be changed without the other. In order to “see the world dif-
ferently,” we must “revisit the history of our own self-image, to see whether we might construct
an alternative genealogy.” Constructing these alternative genealogies becomes an essential
46
strategy for those wishing to introduce alternative ways of speaking and being.
Looking at the different practices of female existential eroticism that we have been pre-
sented with, we can see on the one hand an argument that the femme fatale exists solely to sup-
port men's sexual and social identities, and on the other hand that the femme fatale is an erotic
being in her own right, rather than simply a derivative of patriarchal norms. Of course, being an
erotic being in her own right does not automatically qualify the femme fatale as a radical being,
but it does present an essential flaw in the patriarchal narrative. After all, this narrative requires
the femme fatale to serve the promotion of sexist ideology, indeed to perpetuate the very status
quo that undermines her access to agency. If we can find evidence that she disrupts this status
quo, then not only are we faced with critical weaknesses in the sexist narrative, but we are forced
Heyes, Cressida J. “Pictures of the Self: Wittgenstein and Foucault on Thinking Ourselves Differently,” in Self-
44
Transformations: Foucault, Ethics, and Normalized Bodies. Oxford University Press., 2007: Pg. 16.
45
Ibid.
46
Ibid.
!71
to reconsider the narrative force of the femme fatale trope. Such a disruption of established
meaning introduces the possibility of seeing otherwise, illuminating deception and mistruths that
have clouded our ability to recognize alternative possibilities, and it opens the door to ask: how
might we understand how sexual agency operates in a way that is not beholden to these sexist
structures?
This introduces a moment of possibility that is striking to someone dissatisfied with con-
ventional approaches to understanding and categorizing sexual agency. I find myself truly excit-
ed by the possibility of creatively producing, through imaginative thinking, alternatives that al-
low for novelty. It is in this pursuit of understanding otherwise that I find myself looking for
more in the femme fatale’s story than appears at first glance. There persists an unresolved tension
between her actions and the traditional interpretations that demands a certain accountability from
the viewer, and if one pays attention, the predictable assumptions about the femme fatale be-
come, to my mind, unsatisfactory, as she is revealed to represent so much more.
So although noir films present the viewer with an image of the strong, unrepressed
woman, then attempt to contain her subversive sexuality by destroying her (through her murder
at the hands of the hero) or converting her to traditional womanhood (through marriage),
it is
47
debatable whether the femme fatale can be made to serve the status quo so easily. In fact, the rit-
ualized destruction of the femme fatale as an attempt to foreclose the possibility of female sexual
agency often seems artificial or forced, heavy handed. It seems precisely like someone trying to
make a point, rather than the inevitable conclusion of her actions. As Bronfen argues,
Even though, in the course of each cinematic narrative, the
femme fatale loses her power both on the diegetic level (she dies)
47
See Boozer, “The Lethal Femme Fatale” and Bronfen, “Femme Fatale.”
!72
and on the visual level (she falls into shadows, diminishes in size,
has no voice-over of her own), the disturbing power she embod-
ies remains through the end… Her transgressions against mascu-
line authority — killing her husband, cheating the insurance
company, bringing about the demise of her disloyal lover — is
what tarries in our memory.
48
There is something about the femme fatale, some sort of je ne sais quoi, that stays with us, even
after she is eliminated as a threat. She forces the recognition of power, destructive or manipula-
tive though it may be, and this power is not easily dismissed. Patriarchal language games may
attempt to foreclose her agency, making her an object in someone else’s narrative, reducing her
value to her sexual objectivity, or otherwise minimizing her agency, but she arguably remains an
example of female independence and a threat to the existing distribution of power in a patriarchal
society.
The femme fatale trope continues to exert force on our collective imaginations precisely
because she shines a light on hegemonic structures, forcing us to confront the social construction
of power and question the extent to which these constructions remain stable. She directs our at-
tention to the rough ground of experience, that excess of meaning that cannot be contained even
by the most ingrained legacies of oppression. There is something undeniably compelling about
the story of the femme fatale, something that captures our attention and forces us to look closer.
Superficial interpretations, while abundant, are unsatisfying precisely because she triggers a
recognition that there is more to be said. The femme fatale perplexes, confuses, and otherwise
obfuscates; “the meaning she assumes in any given text refuses to be fixed.” To greater or less
49
-
er extents, we know that women are not just objects to be acted upon. We know that a woman’s
48
Bronfen, “Femme Fatale,” 113.
49
Ibid. 113
!73
ambition is more than a desire for irrational destruction. The femme fatale demands recognition
as a person — complex and dimensional — despite the attempts to flatten and reify. She is nec-
essarily more than a Jessica Rabbit who was “drawn this way.”
So perhaps the question we must ask ourselves is: Are there insurmountable constraints
on seeing the femme fatale as subversive and agentic? Luce Irigaray argues that the main prob-
lem for women has been the lack of a language of their own or at least the impossibility of
speaking of women’s experience within the hegemony of masculine linguistic structures.
50
She
argues that women both exist and yet are excluded from a male dominated society and language.
They play the dominant language game, often conversing fluently in the language that demeans
them, the language built to support sexist practices and ways of life that are inherently harmful to
women. And while women also play alternative language games, these are often precluded from
uptake, meaning that the experiences and practices not recognized by dominant language can
have no purchase. One cannot speak what one does not have the language to voice. In this way,
women have been denied the possibility of introducing new meaning into the popular context.
Rae Langton and Caroline West argue that there are some illocutionary moves that
women cannot make in certain contexts.
51
Our use of language is limited by the popular gram
-
mar, by the accepted rules of what counts as meaning. Women, therefore, often find themselves
“unable to alter the score of language games in the ways that they intend – and find themselves
altering the score in ways they did not intend.”`
52
In hostile contexts, women’s words are often
Davidson, Joyce, and Mick Smith. "Wittgenstein and Irigaray: Gender and Philosophy in a Language (Game) of
50
Difference." Hypatia 14, no. 2 (1999).
51
Langton, Rae and Caroline West, “Scorekeeping,” 313.
52
Ibid. 314
!74
used against them — they do not have the illocutionary force intended, or are received as mean-
ingless by others. Only think of how often women are trapped by the rules of consent as config-
ured in a sexist language game. A ‘no’ from a woman is often heard as a ‘yes’ from a listener, if it
is even heard at all, begging the question of whether women really have access to consent in the
first place. Indeed, the practice of entitlement towards women’s bodies often precludes the possi-
bility of women having an option, emphasizing the public construction of language. While this
may seem to trap us in a perpetual loop, Wittgenstein reminds us that “the language-game is so to
say something unpredictable.” He states that “certain events would put me into a position in
53
which I could not go on with the old language-game any further. In which I was torn away from
the sureness of the game.” We can see, then, that language and meaning are not fixed, given
54
once and for all, “but new types of language, new language-games, as we may say, come into
existence and others become obsolete and forgotten.” In other words, while our use of language
55
has inertia, it can be shifted to swing in another direction with enough force.
I submit that the reason we cannot go on anymore with our current use of language is be-
cause of its inability to articulate the practice of sexual agency as anything other than complicit
in patriarchal norms. If we recognize that demeaning sexual agency is itself an oppressive act,
insofar as it silences women’s alternative practices and relegates them to being responsible for
the harms done to them in the name of desire, then we should begin to build a new way of speak-
ing that accounts alternative conceptualizations of sexual practices. The material consequences
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, G. E. M. Anscombe, and G. H. von Wright. On Certainty. Oxford, UK: Blackwell,1972. §§
53
559
54
Ibid. §§ 617
55
Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, 23.
!75
of seeing figures like the femme fatale as perpetuating patriarchy – a charge often found in femi-
nist analyses of self-sexualization and other uses of desire/lust for personal gain, creates condi-
tions that belittle individuals for being eroticized – something that is not always within one’s
power to control. That we persist with a grammar and language that insists on a traumatizing and
hostile account of sexual politics is unacceptable especially because we can already imagine al-
ternative possibilities.
4. Conclusion
In this chapter, I look at stories because the stories we tell matter. Stories create new
routes for lives to travel through — like water eroding through rock, engraving grooves and riv-
ets that guide the droplets that follow. We follow the paths that people have taken before us, fun-
neled in by the routes often traveled, and the deeper they are, the easier they become to slip into
and perpetuate. In other words, the stories we weave have inertia, and they create expectations
for how the world works. In some ways, we become our stories, and we force others to conform
to the narratives that we entertain. And yet, that network of lifelines carved in the bedrock — the
stories that structure our lived experience and expectations, the narratives that we are trained to
see as true/natural/inescapable — if you were to take a new perspective and look down upon it,
you might notice that there is much empty space waiting to be inscribed with new stories. If we
can bring that negative space to the foreground, in high relief, we can start to see the possibility
for something new/novel/other. All it takes is a drop to diverge, to take a left turn into uncharted
territory, to pick the road less traveled. In this way, new networks of possibility can come into
being.
!76
Of course, so many of the stories available to women are sexist and unpalatable. This is
hardly a surprise, as we live in a world long structured by systems of gender-based oppression.
Like any good tyranny, patriarchy will use the ideological tools at its disposal to reinforce the
spaces in which women are allowed to exist — and these spaces are by and large powerless, de-
humanizing and victimizing. Which might beg the question: does diverging from these stories
make a difference? Even if we go off the beaten track, is that space corrupted in a way that will
not allow for the type of novelty that has potential to destabilize oppressive structures and inject
a feminist consciousness? I believe these are the questions that lead people interested in libera-
tion to argue that the only option is a radical rejection of what currently exists — by declaring
the only option is the opposite of what we contest.
I find this strategy to have its own flaws. After all, this type of move takes the same start-
ing point as the sexist narrative, and is therefore framed by what it fights against. Which is not to
say that rejection is not a viable strategy. Sometimes what has been is so very wrong, that to do
the opposite provides the best opportunity for resistance. But it seems to me that the mechanisms
and impacts of sexism are not often so black and white, and the ambiguity of those boundaries
between what is sexist and what is liberating can be convoluted, messy and fraught with tension.
I believe that, rather than being seen as an impediment for liberatory action, this should be seen
as an asset — for we have possibilities for feminist praxis present right now with the way things
are, no matter how imperfect they appear. I firmly believe that those interested in dismantling
systems of oppression need to be flexible and open-minded about what liberation can look like.
This is in particular true of feminists, who may dismiss something like sexualization or objectifi-
!77
cation out of hand because it has been used to harm women, but in doing so foreclose the possi-
bility for women to take on those aspects of life willingly and without threat of victimization.
The way I see it, we have a couple of (inclusive) choices: we can reject the stories that we
are told and create new ones, or we can retell the stories that we have inherited in new ways. I
think both strategies are important, and in this chapter I am especially interested in the latter
strategy and the possibility of recuperating or renegotiating the meanings of existing narratives
about sexualized women. I find this to be a worthwhile and compelling project for several rea-
sons. First, there’s something special about taking a story meant to belittle and dehumanize, to
put you in your place, and inscribing it with truth and agency. Second, stories that we are familiar
with have the advantage of already participating in our collective hermeneutical resources. And
third, by retelling stories we do the double work of both rejecting a particular popular interpreta-
tion that we judge to be inadequate and harmful, and replacing it with one that is more honest
and representative of a certain truth that has been hidden/denied.
I believe that there is great potential in the practice of recuperating historically maligned
or notorious female figures through storytelling — whether it is Lilith, or Delilah, or any other
incarnation of a femme fatale. There’s just something irresistible about the idea that there is more
to a well known figure than has been told — that there is a story behind the story — because al-
though women are often placed front and center in folklore and mythology, they are seldom pre-
sented as complex and compelling characters. Instead, they are often figures acted upon, used as
plot points or motivations for their more active male counterparts. Not only are women confined
to sexist or otherwise unpalatable roles, they seldom have a voice of their own.
!78
When retold from the perspective of the heroine, well-known events, like the Trojan War,
or Camelot, uncover women trapped by circumstance, struggling to assert agency in states of af-
fairs brought about by the actions of gods and men. And while these stories are often tragic, be-
cause even in our imagination women are often placed in un-winnable situations, the outcome is
not what is most important about a retelling — its the excavation of otherness. It is the process of
raising a voice that may not have been intended by the original author, but that is viable because
the character has been brought into being through storytelling, and because we can imagine it. So
even though Helen of Troy’s purpose was to be the “face that launched a thousand ships,” Homer
nevertheless brought into our collective imaginings a woman whose existence shook the world.
To recover a character for her own purposes showcases the incredible power that narrative has to
open possibilities for understanding women’s actions and motivations in ways that are complex
and resist stereotypical interpretations.
Certain language games currently only allow women to be defined in terms of their utility
for male identity and heteropatriarchal norms. We are all responsible for the insistence upon this
particular form of life. I (fairly uncontroversially) charge these language games with being inad-
equate and poorly representing the complexities of sexual agency. Changing the way that sexual-
ized women are conceptualized, and introducing descriptions and practices into hegemonic lan-
guage-games so that women can be valued as sexual agents in their own right and not solely, or
even primarily, for the benefit of patriarchal systems, will require a large scale communal
project. Indeed, it will require altering the grammar of our shared culture.
56
56
Davidson, Joyce and Mick Smith, “Wittgenstein and Irigaray,” 87.
!79
The femme fatale presents us with the opportunity to theorize what it would mean to
imagine sexualized women otherwise. To see their actions in a new way — one that may open
doors for interpreting women differently — provide us with a new paradigm, one more attentive
to the rough ground, so that we may play a new language game. Do I want to make the femme
fatale a heroine? Not really. Its more about using her to understand how tropes often carry inher-
ent contradictions, that they can be read in different ways to uncover new, more subversive, nar-
ratives that might offer us possibilities for seeing the world in new ways, and highlighting the
systematic way in which sexual power has been denied from women and rewritten to go back to
men.
Irigaray argues that feminist praxis is necessary in order to address the circuitous rela-
tionship between language-games and oppressive norms, and believes that this is the only way a
feminist language game can have a chance to develop.
57
This feminist praxis, I believe, must in
part be the act of redescribing traditionally heteronormative subjects or mythologies in a way that
brings to light a subversive agency that exists but has been overlooked. So although the trope of
the femme fatale may in part have been the sexist hegemony’s way of attempting to restrict the
possibility of women’s agency in a way that could be co-opted to fit in and reinforce the het-
eropatriarchal initiatives and norms, as Lindemann says, “The original need not and should not
be thought of as essential.” So while debate continues over whether figures like the femme fa
58
-
tale represent “a liberatory loosening of constraints or the mainstreaming of subordination for
women,” I would like to leave open the possibility that feminist praxis may allow women to
59
57
Ibid.
58
Lindemann, “Wittgenstein meets Woman,” 230.
59
Coy, Maddy and Maria Garner, “Glamour modeling,” 659.
!80
elaborate and constitute their own erotic identities, ones that do not have to be completely di-
vorced from the language-games in which they have participated, and that they not be held re-
sponsible for someone else’s language game.
!81
Goodies
I bet you want the goodies.
Bet you thought about it.
Got you all hot and bothered.
Maybe ‘cause I talk about it.
Looking for the goodies
60
Keep on lookin’ ‘cause they stay in the jar.
60
Ciara, “Goodies”
!82
Chapter 3: The Power of Pleasure
In the previous chapter, I argue that narratives have power, both to maintain the status
quo, but also to create new realities. I believe that we ought to attend to narratives that describe
and articulate the dynamics of sexualization and eroticism, because they speak to issues that
many women find themselves embroiled in, and can serve as a starting point to create new defin-
itions that are more suitable for women engaged in practices of critique and liberation. I have
been particularly interested in women's sexual narratives, and the ways in which eroticism, desire
and sexualization intertwine in their daily lived experiences. I find these experiences to speak
loudly to how women show strength and resilience in the face of harmful structures of power. It
also showcases the flexibility and practical intelligence of women, as they navigate states of af-
fairs meant to harm and oppress.
The ways in which women maneuver and navigate our social fabric deserves attention
and admiration, for it uncovers realities that deny malicious untruths about women’s capacities,
or lack thereof. But so often, women’s actions are trivialized or diminished the point that their
agency is discounted, or not perceived at all. I believe this is an egregious oversight, one that
perpetuates the intent to marginalize women’s production of knowledge. In doing so, we keep
women in the position of perpetual victims of a legacy they did not create, and overlook the work
that has been done to slowly come out from the shadow of that legacy. Women are left to con-
front histories of abuse, often without recognition that they maintain the basic capacities of per-
sonhood. Even when this personhood is acknowledged, women often find themselves faced with
standards for agency that are both unrealistic and unfair, as if constraints on available actions
necessarily devalue the choices that people make.
!83
I find this to be particularly true when issues of sexuality are considered. Perhaps this is
because sexuality is such a highly charged topic, with a seemingly endless legacy of violence
against women, leading us to collectively confront the ways in which sexuality has long been a
linchpin of women’s oppression, and a mechanism through which their humanity has been de-
nied. It has been the focus of many feminist critiques, which expound on how sexuality has been
used to harm and victimize women, across centuries and cultures. And rightly so — after all,
gender-based oppression rooted in sexual difference is arguably one of the more ubiquitous
forms of oppression at work across time and cultures. While all of this is true, I have often been
uncomfortable with how persistently feminist theory has insisted upon women’s position as vic-
tim, and pursued an understanding of sexuality and eroticism as almost inherently oppressive to
women. As something to suspect, to view with suspicion and distrust. To someone whose identity
is invested in these categories, it can be extremely demoralizing to over and over again read the
words of one’s allies and see that they disparage the qualities and characteristics that you find
meaningful, that have come to be an integral part of how you understand yourself.
This is why, in the last few years, I have tried to develop a personal sexual politics that
better reflects how I employ sexuality, desirability, and pleasure in ways that destabilize com-
monly held assumptions about women’s value and purpose, and potentially loosen the hold of
ideological constraints associated with the sexist worldview. To combat the cycle of fear, shame
and self-blame that I discussed in Chapter 1, I believe a need exists for feminist engagement with
how, as Treva B. Lindsey puts it, different women carve out spaces for authoring self-actualized
!84
sexual selves,
61
in order to widen our scope of “acceptable” sexuality. A need exists for a sexual
politics that works for women situated in diverse ways, and takes seriously the different ways
that women experience and understand themselves as sexual agents. While it is true that I have
been focusing rather narrowly on certain particular manifestations of sexual agency throughout
this dissertation, I recognize that an effective sexual politics requires the space for all different
kinds of sexual performances to rise to the level of legitimate. Otherwise, we simply replace one
constrictive paradigm with another.
For the purposes of this chapter, I look to the work of women who are already engaged in
this type of endeavor, because their work has been such a source of inspiration to me throughout
my doctoral program. It is, therefore, no exaggeration to say that this dissertation is deeply in-
debted to the writings of theorists like Audre Lorde, Joan Morgan, Mireille Miller-Young, Jessica
Marie Johnson, and Treva B. Lindsey, because their work speaks to my hopes of destigmatizing
and reinvisioning what it means to be a sexual subject. Of course, it is worth pointing out that
none of these women are writing to me, or have me in mind in the worlds they are creating, and
so putting this chapter together has been a delicate process, so to speak. There are parts of these
works that I simply don’t have access to, or the training required to truly understand, and so I
have repeatedly made mistakes based in fundamental cultural differences. But I could not write
this dissertation without this chapter, because these authors created something that gives me hope
and direction, both personally and professionally. They also offer philosophical guidance for a
problem that I am deeply invested in solving.
Lindsey, Treva B. “Complicated crossroads: black feminisms, sex positivism, and popular culture.” African and
61
Black Diaspora: An International Journal, 6, 1 (2013): 56.
!85
Which is not to say that the authors included always agree with one another, or even have
obvious methodological compatibility. In weaving together these diverse theories, there are mo-
ments of tension that I do my best to appreciate, and I try to avoid collapsing these different theo-
retical frameworks on the assumption that these thinkers ought to have similar views because
they share a common community. And so while at first glance, the theorists included in this chap-
ter may seem to have only superficial commonalities, I believe that by bringing these disparate
theories together in a dialectic, a more comprehensive and practical picture of the erotic and sex-
ual agency can come to light. I begin with Lorde because she provides a backdrop, a way of un-
derstanding the sensual, the erotic, as an integral part of humanity, one that should not be shied
away from, but embraced. Lorde’s theory of the erotic justifies the attempts I have made to argue
that sexuality, pleasure and desire are essential capacities for identity formation and deserve
philosophical consideration. I then turn to Morgan, whose paradigm of Pleasure Politics address-
es some of the gaps of Lorde’s conception of the erotic by providing grounded and practical re-
sources for women looking for an alternative to theories of sexuality and eroticism that reinforce
victim-status or creates dichotomies of good/bad sex. Lindsey and Miller-Young provide con-
crete examples of Morgan’s theory at work, in the music industry and the porn industry, respec-
tively.
I have done my best to respect the context that these theorists speak from, and their focus
on black women’s sexualities and embodiment in order to maintain the integrity of their frame-
works. The works mentioned here explore sexuality (and explicitly black female sexuality) in
ways that are novel, not because they draw on new histories and experiences, but because they
look at those histories and experiences and find new paradigms for understanding sexuality, sex-
!86
ualization, eroticism, desire and sexual politics. These paradigms create the possibility for allow-
ing women to exist as they are, without shame, by asking the viewer to reconsider the hermeneu-
tical resources they draw on to understand and interpret women’s actions and choices, in effect
placing the burden on the viewer to understand women differently, rather than expecting women
to be different in order to deserve recognition. I find this approach refreshing insofar as it legit-
imizes ways of being that are often dismissed.
1. Audre Lorde
In “Uses of the Erotic,” Audre Lorde articulates a conception of the erotic that is much
broader than I have been using throughout this project. She positions the erotic as a kind of pow-
er, but one that has been traditionally under-recognized. However, she points out that this lack of
recognition is not accidental — rather it goes hand in hand with a tradition of the subjugation of
women. Lorde describes it as a mechanism of women's oppression: “In order to perpetuate itself,
every oppression must corrupt or distort those various sources of power within the culture of the
oppressed that can provide energy for change. For women, this has meant a suppression of the
erotic as a considered source of power and information within our lives.” This idea speaks to
62
the ways in which the erotic has been trivialized and diminished, both as a matter of critique, and
as a consideration for personhood.
Of course, a suppression of power is some kind of recognition, but it is one that attempts
to negate. For the erotic, this negation has taken the shape of suspicion and shame, as women
have been “taught to suspect this resource, vilified, abused, and devalued within Western
62
Lorde, Audre. “Uses of the Erotic,” in Sister Outsider. Brooklyn, N.Y.: Out & Out Book, 1978. Pg. 53.
!87
society.” This trivialization has led many to the false belief that “only by the suppression of the
63
erotic within our lives and consciousness can women be truly strong.” And yet, paradoxically,
64
the superficially erotic has been simultaneously encouraged, but only as a sign of women’s infe-
rior status.
This has created an untenable state of affairs in which the erotic is both recognized
65
and ignored, encouraged and suppressed, valued and feared. Ultimately, it creates a system in
which women are bound to lose, because the game is set up so that it is impossible for them to
play. Therefore, Lorde shows us that patriarchal models of power are constructed in such a way
that will not allow women to succeed, no matter what they do.
But Lorde argues that “the erotic offers a well of replenishing and provocative force to
the woman who does not fear its revelation.” To the woman who recognizes that this power has
66
been twisted and used for the pleasure and service of men, purposefully devalued and trivialized,
there emerges the possibility of uncovering and dismantling these lies that have enabled a certain
ignorance. As I mentioned before, Lorde makes it clear that the erotic has been twisted to serve
male systems of power, which in itself establishes a weak point in the ideology of male suprema-
cy — a point of tension that reveals a deeper truth — that the erotic, that deep feeling which
Lorde describes, is powerful and valuable enough to be possessed. Therefore, it is not merely a
product of patriarchy, or a sign of women’s demeaned status, but something that predates patri-
archy — chronologically and metaphysically.
63
Ibid.
64
Ibid.
65
Ibid.
66
Ibid. 54
!88
Although Lorde describes the erotic in depth, she does not necessarily define it as an in-
dependent concept, but rather, as is her style, as a poetic construct and a practice in our lives. She
explains what it does for the woman who does not fear it, and how it impacts life. She describes
the erotic as “a measure between the beginning of our sense of self and the chaos of our strongest
feelings,” and as an “internal sense of satisfaction to which, once we have experience with it, we
know we can aspire,” that allows us to demand more from ourselves, our lives and our work.
67
The erotic is an “internal requirement towards excellence” and it guides us not only in our ac-
tions, but in “how acutely and fully we can feel in the doing.” The erotic becomes a way to
68
measure the quality of our various life endeavors, a state to achieve in our doings, our labor. By
embracing the erotic in all of our endeavors, our work becomes a “conscious decision — a
longed for bed which I enter gratefully and from which I rise up empowered.” The erotic estab
69
-
lishes something authentic, true and basic. I would, upon reading Lorde, even consider the erotic
as a kind of intuition — or intuitive awareness of what is right, good and real — that makes our
work meaningful by attending to human need.
The erotic is also something universal and accessible — a feeling that is not limited to a
certain group nor does it require a particular status. In my own life, I have felt this depth of sen-
sation when reading something truly beautiful — philosophy that makes me feel alive, that rush-
es through my body as if awakening every nerve. That tingling, tightening sensation, that accom-
panies the reading of theory that is more than simply an exercise in critique or cleverness, but an
effort of love that speaks to my hopes and passions — it reminds me what theory can do in the
67
Ibid.
68
Ibid.
69
Ibid. 55
!89
person and the world if its full potential is unleashed. And it is the same kind of feeling I get
when I take a walk in the sunshine, or help someone see something differently, or lean into my
partner’s arms and breath him in deep. These are the moments, where I see the richness and pos-
sibility of life, the feeling of fullness and satisfaction, that (I think) I understand what Lorde
refers to when she speaks of the erotic. Once attuned to the sensation, it becomes a sign of the
‘rightness’ of a particular choice, the validation of a chosen path. These are everyday experi-
ences, unexceptional in appearance, and yet integral to a healthy development of self.
There is an unmistakably intersubjective aspect to the erotic, a recognition of otherness
that guides the deepest feeling that Lorde speaks of — whether that otherness is the world in
which you are one piece, or a person whose presence feeds the erotic within you. There would be
no erotic in a vacuum, or a world alone. I believe this is why Lorde emphasizes the act of sharing
when she discusses the erotic. One obvious example of this type of sharing is sex. Sex can con-
nect us to another person in a moment of undisguised joy, from which stems a unique knowledge
of ourselves and our capacity for pleasure. This type of pleasure is certainly part of Lorde’s erot-
ic, although the concept as a whole is not reducible to sexual pleasure. Rather, sex is the way in
which we are most comfortable, or accustomed to thinking about the erotic within us. It is there-
fore a useful model for the type of deep feeling and sharing of joy that Lorde articulates, even if
the erotic is not reducible to sex.
Of course, not all sex meets Lorde’s criteria for the erotic, which she makes clear with her
distinction between eroticism and pornography. Lorde describes these two contrasts as “diamet-
rically opposed uses of the sexual.” Pornography, according to Lorde, is some kind of distortive
70
70
Ibid.
!90
reduction of the deep feeling that characterizes the erotic, transformed into “the confused, the
trivial, the psychotic, the plasticized sensation.” Lorde describes pornography as the opposite
71
of the erotic — sensation without feeling. It is a “direct denial of the power of the erotic, for it
represents the suppression of true feeling.” Pornography makes a mockery of the erotic, and
72
turns it into something shallow, erasing the depth of feeling that comes with sensation, leaving
only the most superficial of impressions.
Since Lorde describes the erotic as the “lifeforce of women,” one can conclude that the
73
pornographic is an attempt to usurp that life force, to use women for their power and sensation.
Lorde claims that patriarchy attempts to erase women’s capacity for joy and obstructs access to
their deepest knowledge. And although “deepest knowledge” seems to be a deliberately vague
term, one that implies philosophically contentious concepts like an access to Truth, with the im-
plication that there is an actual truth and some kind of essentialized meaning — by deep knowl-
edge, Lorde in fact refers to knowledge that is dark and ancient and prior to both understanding
and language. This deep knowledge is a guide, an undercurrent to reason. For Lorde, saying that
something “feels right to me,” rather than being simply a turn of phrase, “acknowledges the
strength of the erotic into a true knowledge, for what that means is the first and most powerful
guiding light towards any understanding.” Deep knowledge is therefore that which is deepest
74
within ourselves,
75
and by linking the erotic to deep knowledge, Lorde grounds the erotic in a
71
Ibid. 54
72
Ibid.
73
Ibid. 55
74
Ibid. 56
75
Ibid. 102
!91
before space of awareness that is not given to language and is not privy to understanding. She
describes the erotic as the “nurturer or nursemaid of all our deepest knowledge,” our under
76
-
standing of which is only the “handmaiden which [] wait[s] upon, or clarify, that knowledge,
deeply born.” 77
This deep knowledge is erased by the kinds of systematic male dominance that hold
women captive, distorting the erotic into something empty and shallow. Which is why Lorde ar-
gues that “the erotic has been used against us, even the word itself, so often, that we have been
taught to suspect what is deepest within ourselves, against our feelings.” Patriarchy has suc
78
-
ceeded, to a great extent, in making the erotic something dirty, shameful and small — a source of
shame rather than strength. And so, for Lorde the pornographic (a shallow distortion of what the
erotic really is) becomes a tool of patriarchal systems to deny the power of the erotic, and simul-
taneously attempt to sustain it is such a way that it forecloses women's access to deep knowledge
while maintaining sensation in the most superficial of ways. After all, the “male world” that we
live in “values this depth of feeling enough to keep women around in order to exercise it in the
service of men, but which fears this same depth too much to examine the possibility of it within
themselves.” Therefore, the pornographic allows women to be “maintained at a distant/inferior
79
position to be psychically milked;” to be used for their power while maintaining male suprema
80
-
cy and the fiction of women’s devalued status.
76
Ibid. 56
77
Ibid.
78
Ibid. 102
79
Ibid. 53-54
80
Ibid. 54
!92
As Lorde emphasizes throughout “Uses of the Erotic,” empowered women are dangerous
because they can demand more — and the erotic is what allows them to recognize that more is
both possible and desirable. As the nursemaid to “that deep and irreplaceable knowledge of my
capacity for joy,” the erotic “comes to demand from all of my life that it be lived within the
knowledge that such satisfaction is possible.” The dangerous truths that the erotic reveals,
81
makes me unwilling to accept the lies and distortions that lead to the feelings of powerlessness
and resignation: “In touch with the erotic, I become less willing to accept powerlessness, or those
other supplied states of being which are not native to me, such as resignation, despair, self-ef-
facement, depression and denial.” I no longer need to be compliant with a way of life that is
82
fundamentally unsatisfactory when I realize that so much more is not only possible, but within
my grasp. But of course, this type of awakening threatens the fabric of male supremacy, and
therefore cannot come into existence without a struggle. Like any power, sexism will fight to
maintain itself by twisting and manipulating the truth to its advantage. And so women “are taught
to separate the erotic demands from most vital areas of our lives other than sex,” in order to
83
hide the latent power waiting in the shadows. Women are taught that we are nothing more than
the sensation others can get from our bodies, that we are there to be used so that others might
profit from us. We are taught that sex is our realm, and yet Lorde argues that even this space is
carefully circumscribed to make sure that we do not find true satisfaction in ourselves and our
81
Ibid. 57
82
Ibid. 58
83
Ibid. 55
!93
work, lest we begin to demand more from other aspects of our lives. And so even sex loses its
erotic value, becoming merely pornographic without the value and fulfillment of the erotic.
84
But I am not so sure the by “pornographic” Lorde refers to actual pornography. I am in-
clined to think that this erotic/pornographic distinction is more of an illustrative concept to
showcase the twisting and derivitization of those deep feelings until they are plastic, hollow and
superficial — rather than referring to the tangible practice of pornography. Of course, I hardly
claim access to the “true meaning” of Lorde’s words, and her poetic philosophical prose does
lead to certain ambiguities that have exacerbated rifts within feminist accounts of sexuality. It is
no surprise that feminist theory has a long-held tradition of demonizing pornography, and partic-
ularly the pornography industry, as a symbol of women’s oppression. Some have even (mis)used
Lorde’s own framework to create normative sexual binaries that implicate certain kinds of sexual
practices as harmful. For example, Patricia Hill Collins contrasts the erotic with sex/fucking,
85
mirroring the erotic/pornographic dichotomy that Lorde articulates.
Nevertheless, I believe that Lorde, in invoking the pornographic like she does, is talking
about its conception rather than its practice. The contrast between these two ways of understand-
ing the erotic can be challenging to discern, especially if one subscribes to the Wittgensteinian
theory of language proposed in Chapter 2, where the practice simply is the concept. Neverthe-
less, I do not think Lorde herself would ascribe to that type of theory, and so it seems reasonable
to recognize that for her, the erotic as practice and the erotic as concept are related, but they are
not the same. Therefore, I believe it is arguable that when Lorde speaks of the “pornographic,”
84
Ibid.
Hill Collins, Patricia. Black Sexual Politics : African Americans, Gender, and the New Racism. New York :Rout
85
ledge, 2005. Pg. 298
-
!94
she referring to a concept within an idealized space, rather than specific tangible manifestations.
That being said, it does leave quite a bit of space for interpretation, showcased by the wide range
of interpretations of Lorde’s text.
So while Lorde’s erotic/pornographic distinction may seem to imply that pornography, as
a practice, is something we should distrust and demonize, I believe we ought to take care before
we read her as developing binaries of good vs. bad sex. Of course, many feminists understand
Lorde in this way, and I do not have the experience and knowledge to claim authority on the mat-
ter. My hesitation stems mostly from my suspicion that Lorde would not want her words used to
shame actual women, whether or not they engage in activities that reflect her concept of the
pornographic. But the fact that her words have been used to defend the defamation of women’s
choices to participate in certain activities should give us pause — not necessarily to critique
Lorde’s work itself, but to ask ourselves why we may jump at the opportunity to condemn
women. Instead, I find it fruitful to ask what other interpretations might exist that would allow us
to understand Lorde’s words in a way that does not perpetuate the association of shame with sex.
I think that this is a point where more materially grounded theory is necessary in order to
investigate these questions that are messy, convoluted and rarely straight forward. There are per-
haps limits to the type of theory that Lorde provides, and while it is beautiful, hopeful and poetic,
it leaves us with many questions as to how to actualize her words — how to bring the positive
changes she describes into reality. I believe Lorde’s “Uses of the Erotic” is consistent with my
commitment to destigmatizing women’s existence as erotic subjects, but this will involve a will-
ingness to get messy, so to speak. It will involve recognition that when theorizing about material
realities like sexual politics, eroticism and pleasure, things will not always appear as we think
!95
they ought to, and this is not necessarily a sign of failure. We should not allow our theoretical
commitments to make us blind or deaf to the realities of real women. And to claim otherwise is
to be dangerously out of touch with the daily negotiations of sexuality and pleasure that are
commonplace in the lives of many women.
There is something to be said for practicality — for theory that toes the line between ide-
alism and realism. For theory that acknowledges that things need not be perfect to be worthy of
our critical attention and respect. It is also worth noting that ideal theory may have to shift and
change when applied to specific contexts, and that situating our goals/desires in a particular set-
ting may demand adjustments to what we think things ought to look like. Like Lorde, Joan Mor-
gan seeks “a framing of the erotic that is both deliberative and expansive.” However, she is
86
quick to point out that she does not condone a reading of the erotic that is opposed to the sexual,
or that “implies that the erotic can only be achieved by a transcendence of mere sex, or by es-
chewing sex that isn't regulated to the realms of romantic love or the spiritual.” Instead, Mor
-
87
gan offers an account of erotic agency that is realistic and practical, that resists binaries and “de-
mands space be made for honest bodies that like to also fuck,” rejecting the notion that sex
88
must be legitimized in order to be defensible. Her work is not necessarily a natural counterpoint
to Lorde’s, and so I would like to be clear that I am not setting up a genealogy, as they have both
methodological and phenomenological differences that are significant in scope. That being said, I
think these works complement one another, particularly as we investigate what new erotic para-
Morgan, Joan. “Why We Get Off: Moving Towards a Black Feminist Politics of Pleasure." The Black Scholar 45,
86
4. (2015): 39.
87
Ibid.
88
Ibid. 40
!96
digms might look like in practice in our ever changing world. Morgan’s work offers necessary
insight for someone invested in an account of the erotic which defies sexist mythology.
2. Joan Morgan’s Pleasure Politics 89
Joan Morgan proposes pleasure politics as a liberatory black feminist project that “ele-
vates the need for sexual autonomy and erotic agency without shame to the level of black femi-
nist imperative.” She recognizes that the black feminist agenda has commonly engaged in dis
90
-
puting a wide and often contradictory spectrum of deeply entrenched stereotypes around black
91
women’s sexualities that have led to the “creation of a black feminist master narrative in which
black women’s damaged sexuality takes center-stage as a site of reoccurring trauma.” In ac
92
-
knowledging this theoretical tradition, Morgan worries that BFT has become overly reliant on
paradigms that reinforce how black women have been harmed by the sexual identities placed
upon them,
93
and argues that by overstating the violence done to black women in the name of
desire, black feminist theory has shown a “mulish inattentiveness to black women's engagements
with pleasure — the complex, messy, sticky, and even joyous negotiations of agency and desire
that are irrevocably twinned with our pain.” Black women’s experience of pleasure is more
94
complicated than many theories would imply by honing in on victim narratives at the exclusion
of alternative depictions. She argues that disregarding the importance of pleasure and a healthy
89
A term I am borrowing from Joan Morgan.
90
Ibid. 39
91
Ibid. 36
92
Ibid.
Morgan specifically mentions “the field's most trenchant theories — specifically Kimberle Crenshaw's "intersec
-
93
tionality", Patricia Collin's "controlling images", Audre Lorde's deployment of the erotic, Higginbotham's "re-
spectability politics", Hine's "cultural dissemblance.”” (Morgan 38).
94
Ibid. 46
!97
erotic serves to “discount[] black female interiority — i.e. the broad range of feelings, desires,
yearning (erotic and otherwise) that were once deemed necessarily private by the politics of si-
lence.” In other words, there is much of black women's experience that is under-theorized, and
95
therefore discredited.
Morgan therefore presents an alternative to theories of respectability that advocate or
conclude in shame and victimization, showing that these are not the only options available to
black women. She argues that pleasure is an “under-theorized resistance strategy for black
women” and that to actively emphasize pleasure as a viable theoretical paradigm:
96
Encourages recognition of black women's pleasure (sexual and otherwise)
as not only an integral part of fully realized humanity, but one that under-
stands that a politics of pleasure is capable of intersecting, challenging,
and redefining dominant narratives about race, beauty, health and sex in
ways that are generative and necessary.
97
This speaks to the discursively generative potential of pleasure — it has purchase in many dy-
namics of power that structure black women’s embodied experience, and can speak to many dif-
ferent aspects of their lives. Morgan recognizes that pleasure, insofar as it relates to black
women’s engagements, commitments and desires, can be a site for challenging and subverting
hegemonic norms.
Although Morgan most explicitly defines the value of pleasure in her philosophical inves-
tigations of black women’s agency, I believe that Treva B. Lindsey and Mireille Miller-Young
echo her commitments by showing “real-world” examples of Morgan’s theory already at play.
95
Ibid 37
96
Ibid. 44
97
Ibid.
!98
For example, Mireille Miller-Young asks: “what if pleasure is one of the most radical tools black
women can mobilize to intervene in their oppression?” And while I am highly sympathetic to
98
their similar goal of emphasizing the importance of the erotic and pleasure in black women’s
lives, it is not necessarily clear that black women’s sexuality is socially constructed in such a
way that centering black women’s assertions of sexual subjectivity has the impact these theorists
propose. This is because the (often contradictory) controlling images of black female sexuality
present particular challenges for subverting the harmful sexual tropes attributed to black women.
However, I believe that the theorists in this chapter are attentive to these issues and describe how
black women already engage with their sexualities in ways that provide both discursive and ma-
terial possibilities to contest norms and definitions and create new ones. They also show why it is
important to explore the complicated and sometimes uncomfortable spaces of explicitly sexual
imagery, behavior and narratives that black women engage in because of their generative poten-
tial for disrupting popular conceptions of black women’s value and eroticism.
3. Treva B. Lindsey
In “Complicated Crossroads,” Treva B. Lindsey looks at the sexualized performances of
black women in the entertainment industry, noting the burden of a unique historical legacy that
“continues to affect contemporary popular representations of the black female body.” This
99
unique historical legacy — one rife with dehumanization, exploitation and hypersexualization
that has identified black women as “deviant, dysfunctional, inferior, and ‘other-ed’”
100
— con
-
Miller-Young, Mireille. A Taste For Brown Sugar: Black Women in Pornography. Duke University Press Books,
98
2014: Pg. 280
99
Lindsey, “Complicated Crossroads,” 55.
100
Ibid. 56
!99
fronts black women entertainers with a social imaginary of fascination, desire and fear of black
female bodies.
101
Lindsey frames her discussion within this legacy to show how black women’s
bodies are always already subjected to discourses that place black female entertainers in a start-
ing position invested in particular images of black womanhood. In other words, the standards
that black women are measured up against are hardly built to allow for subversive readings of
black women engaging with the policing tactics directed at their bodies, because the position
they start from is one that confronts seemingly endless assumptions and stereotypes about their
value, character and sexuality.
However, Lindsey argues that the historical legacy of dehumanizing and exploitative im-
ages of black women in popular culture does not foreclose the possibilities for black female
artists claiming pro-sex standpoints. She believes that music videos, as dynamic narrative spaces,
provide black music artists with the space to “challenge and manipulate racial, gender, and class
specific historical entanglements,”
102
and allow them an “opportunity to function as authorial
figures in the creation and dissemination of representations of African-American female
bodies.”
103
She specifically references the performances of Kelly Rowland and Ciara, both of
whom she argues “embrace sexual desire and expressivity in their videos and claim leading and
authorial roles in determining the sexualized components and parameters of their music
videos.”
104
For Lindsey, this signals a subversion and arguably, an “outright rejection of gen
-
101
Ibid.
102
Ibid 58
103
Ibid.
104
Ibid. 56
!100
dered racial and sexual stereotypes about black women.”
105
In other words, there is something
special about the way in which these women employ their sexuality in the public eye that pushes
back against commonly accepted norms and scriptures associated with black female sexuality.
I admit that this is a point of Lindsey’s argument that I had a hard time processing at
first. While I agree that asserting the value of pleasure and a healthy erotic are important tools for
liberation from oppressive sexual norms, Lindsey is less clear how, or when exactly these contes-
tations will start to subvert norms in a way that is noticeable to particular individuals out in the
world. But she nevertheless claims that the black female artists she cites “compel black femi-
nists, particularly those invested in representations of black women, to theorize the transgressive
possibilities of black women’s bodies within contemporary popular music performance.”
106
For
Lindsey, there is something significant about the sexual performances of women like Ciara and
Rowland that “illustrate a dynamic and complicated response” to the deeply embedded histories
of devaluation that frame black women’s sexualities.
In order to address these concerns, I would like to take a moment to unpack Lindsey’s
argument to better understand how the strategies she mentions might work for women. Central to
Lindsey’s argument is the idea that narrative spaces offer transgressive possibilities for black fe-
male performers/artists because they allow these women to author their own sexual identities.
This identity negotiation — “women making decisions about their sexual selves and self-identi-
fications based upon their desires to engage or not engage in sexual activity”
107
— is for Lindsey
a mechanism that destabilizes harmful stereotypes. Lindsey argues that artists can contest tropes
105
Ibid.
106
Ibid.
107
Ibid. 58
!101
of black female sexuality by taking authorial roles in their sexual representation, and that these
authorial roles allow them to challenge popular narratives by giving them the publicly available
space to create and perform their own identities. This is arguably subversive because it resists
determination from the outside. It demands recognition of autonomy and agency, both of which
are systematically denied to women and black women in particular. In other words, the assertion
of the “right to the explicitly sexual within potentially objectifying spaces such as music videos
signals a subversion and/or outright rejection of gendered racial stereotypes that police the public
behavior of African-American women,”
108
because they create alternatives for black women’s
sexual realities that can begin to infiltrate our collective hermeneutical resources and hopefully
become accessible to all women.
Demanding multiple possibilities for sexual expressivity, particularly for bodies con-
fronting “stultifying stigmas” rooted in racist/heterosexist/patriarchal discourses, forces us to re-
consider our most basic reactions to women’s sexual expressivity — ranging from “fear to dis-
gust to fetishization to desire.”
109
As Lindsey notes, because their movements are so sexual, for
many, figures like Ciara and Kelly Rowland (and more contemporary figures like Beyonce and
Rihanna) become symbols of the changing-same
110
with regards to representations of black
women in popular culture, i.e. the more things change the more they stay the same. This accusa-
tion reflects “a perpetual discomfort with explicit sexuality forming part of black women’s sexu-
al identities,”
111
a discomfort that is pertinent because of the harm done to black women in the
108
Ibid.
109
Ibid. 56
110
Ibid. 60
111
Ibid.
!102
name of their sexuality. Similarities in appearance, especially superficial similarities, can be read
as perpetuating a long history of oppression, and erase transgressive possibilities. But discomfort
is not license for dismissal, and performing sexuality publicly should be recognized as more than
the changing-same insofar as it demands recognition of autonomy, self-definition and self-own-
ership.
Lindsey argues that despite the potential for objectification, which is always present in
visual imagery, the “lyrical narrative coupled with the moving visual provides [these women]
with a space to control and manipulate how the audience gazes upon [their] bod[ies].”
112
It mat
-
ters that these women deliberately perform their sexualities, that they do so consciously and de-
cisively. This deliberate performance allows them to set the tone of their sexual expressivity, and
helps frame, although it cannot determine, the reception by the audience. In effect, she argues
that Rowland and Ciara, by deliberately portraying themselves as sexual agents, assert black fe-
male subjectivity in a way that does not sacrifice the erotic for respect. They push back against
the objectification of black women’s bodies by deliberately positioning themselves as agents.
And while it is true that any action is,
Always mediated through existing power structures such as
record companies and television networks as well as a popular
culture landscape in which sexism, misogyny, heterosexism,
racism, and patriarchy continue to flourish, it is important to
recognize that racial and sexual stereotypes should not preclude
possibilities for African-American female artists to author and
participate in sex-positive representations of African-American
womanhood.
113
112
Ibid. 58
113
Ibid.
!103
Lindsey expresses a reasonable concern that we not restrict black women’s access to meaningful
sexual performances on account of misrepresentations created to oppress. Holding these women
accountable to these racial and sexual stereotypes may serve to further marginalize their voices
and control their meaning-making capacities.
Instead of assuming that they are coerced into the way they represent themselves (often
with movements and clothing that fairly explicitly summon their sexuality), we should ask why
they choose to represent themselves in such a way. The answer could reveal an agentic stand-
point that subverts the generally accepted rationality that black women only behave in these
ways because they are victims of a sexist system. I take her to be saying that there is something
particular about black women’s experience that makes the assertion of sexual subjectivity espe-
cially important. Sometimes we must delve deeper in the things that have caused us historical
pain — that have dehumanized and terrorized — in order to find new ways of understanding our-
selves. Historical legacies can only be broken when we recognize an alternative to the story we
have been told. And those alternatives may take effort to bring into being — it may take practice
to become viable. New paradigms become relevant because we demand them, arguably in the
way that these women demand recognition of their sexual agency through their erotic perfor-
mances.
Lindsey recognizes that sexuality deserves critical attention, that it has under-acknowl-
edged generative and liberating capacities, and that it is something marginalized bodies can use
to their advantage. She also thinks that representing black female sexuality in such a way will
force black feminists to critically consider how the “‘gray area’ of black female sexuality and
!104
black female hypersexuality”
114
might offer possibilities and not only constraints on black
women’s agency and choices. While recognizing that these constraints exist, Lindsey puts for-
ward what looks like a cautionary tale to feminists, warning us to recognize that our current in-
terpretive frameworks can cause us to misread pro-sex black feminist performance, erase agentic
and self-authoring capacities, and consequently “imprison black female sexual expressivity.”
115
This is a lesson that is pertinent to all individuals engaging in feminist politics, as it is a reminder
of the role we all play in enforcing certain stereotypes that constrain our interpretive frameworks.
If we are serious about liberation, we need to be open to the ways in which women, including the
black female entertainers that Lindsey engages with, choose to represent themselves, regardless
of whether or not it fits our model of respectable womanhood. The discomfort that we may feel
is not license to dismiss a woman’s choices out of hand.
4. Mireille Miller-Young
In A Taste for Brown Sugar, Mireille Miller-Young looks at the American porn industry,
and specifically at the experiences of black female porn actresses. Her interest in the porn indus-
try as a context for investigating black women’s sexuality and erotic agency is in some ways
reminiscent of Catherine MacKinnon, insofar as they both conceive of pornography as reflecting
popular culture, and reproducing the values, fantasies and fears of society. However, unlike
MacKinnon,
116
Miller-Young thinks that pornography has positive creative potential for black
women. She argues that by bringing previously illicit subcultures, communities, and sexual prac-
114
Ibid 62
115
Ibid. 63
116
MacKinnon is particularly well-known for her firm anti-pornography stance.
!105
tices into the public eye and into other modes of culture,
117
pornography has made black
women’s sexualities more visible, and is therefore a space in which they can publicly manipulate
and define their sexuality (an argument reminiscent of Lindsey’s).
Making black women’s sexuality more visible has subversive potential in at least two
ways: it forces uptake and recognition of what is often hidden/ignored, and, coming from black
women, it allows for more authentic/truthful representations of the diversity of black women’s
experiences as sexual agents. Both of these destabilize commonly accepted norms and bring into
question the viability of the status quo. Harmful legacies cannot be contested if they remain un-
seen, and so there is something to be said for the public performance of sexuality. These perfor-
mances force us to confront our assumptions and beliefs, work through our discomforts and rec-
ognize the existence of other persons.
Like Lindsey, Miller-Young traces the nature of desire for, use of, and pleasure in black
women’s sexuality (in the United States context) to the sexual economy for black women’s bod-
ies under slavery. According to Miller-Young, the pervasiveness of the cultural mythologies as-
sociated with slavery has restricted black porn actresses’ access to various roles, often forcing
them into the position of reproducing denigrating stereotypes like the ‘ho’ if they want to make a
living. For Miller-Young, the ‘ho’ trope is a pejorative catch-all which describes “a class of
women who are perceived to represent multiple legitimacy crises — the ‘disappearing’ black
family, epidemics of teen pregnancy, HIV/AIDS, and even the materialism and consumerism of
black youth culture.”
118
Because of this, black women in porn face censure for participating in
117
Miller-Young, “A Taste For Brown Sugar,” 7.
118
Ibid. 163
!106
the very same cultural standards that undermine their value, and reinforce the inherent label of
deviance forced upon them by white supremacist cultures.
The apparent willingness with which these porn actresses play into harmful stereotypes
for the consumption of (mostly white) men arguably reinforces their role in the continued pro-
duction of negative tropes about black women, with the result that they are often considered irre-
deemably complicit and shameful. In many cases, feminists politically and ideologically distance
themselves from women in the sex industry because they are seen as too deeply invested in the
very structures that feminism contest, and this is particularly the case when it comes to black
women, who traditionally face harsher scrutiny and censure for their sexual habits. Miller-Young
argues that instead of turning away from women in porn in an effort to “recuperate ourselves
from myths and violence associated with black sexual deviance,”
119
we should work to recognize
that black women in the sex industry are much more than simply victims or puppets — they are
“active social agents” who use “alternative economies” to work within and against structural and
discursive constraints.
120
It is important to recognize that working within and against are not mu
-
tually exclusive possibilities, and that participation in sex work writ large does not invalidate a
woman’s claim to agency. These sorts of restrictions serve only to further erase these women’s
testimony.
Miller-Young presents an alternative interpretation of black women working in the porn
industry. She argues that these women use their sexualities strategically for both social mobility
as well as everyday survival, in effect having both long and short-term goals. Referring to this as
119
Ibid. 145
120
Ibid. 7
!107
a trick-off, a game, or hustle,
121
Miller-Young argues that black women in porn have learned to
capitalize on their sexual performances,
122
in order to attempt to exceed the limits of their often
devalued roles.
123
In doing so, these women bring to light the often concealed fact that “while
black women may be characterized as valueless hoes, in fact both white and black men benefit a
great deal from commodifying black women’s sexualities.”
124
An under appreciated reality is the
substantial amount of money made from exploiting black women’s bodies and sexuality, and yet
very little of it benefits the women themselves, effectively reinforcing their “value-less” status.
Uncovering the ways in which men invest in black women’s sexuality while simultaneously dis-
crediting it helps to contest the assumed non-value of black women’s sexuality. This, in turn, cre-
ates the space for black women in porn to “employ, repel, or rework those images, reshaping rep-
resentation”
125
in order to provide more complex meanings for black female sexualities — mean
-
ings not limited to those created specifically to reinforce an exploitative state of affairs.
This idea that black women put hypersexuality to work in strategic ways
126
may seem
paradoxical, but Miller-Young argues that this speaks to the inadequacy of our interpretive
frameworks rather than the impossibility of black women’s potentiality. Because self-commodi-
fication and investment in sexualized performance are equated with objectification rather than
subjectivity in many feminist frameworks, sex workers (understood broadly) are often treated as
121
Ibid. 11, 49
122
Ibid. 176-7
123
Ibid. 146
124
Ibid.
125
Ibid.
126
Ibid. 11
!108
flat and undynamic caricatures that are denied the complexity given to other kinds of workers,
127
regardless of the magnitude of their labor. But black women in porn are in fact engaged in com-
plex negotiations between “contestation of and consent to damaging images that constantly
evolve and take on a life of their own.”
128
As Miller-Young argues, these harmful and demeaning
tropes are not static but historical and evolving, and women actively infuse these narratives with
new meanings through their “illicit eroticism”
plain below.
129
and “erotic sovereignty,”
130
terms that I will ex
-
Miller-Young described erotic sovereignty, which she also calls sexual dissent,
131
as a
process, rather than a state of being,
Wherein sexual subjects aspire and move toward self-rule and col-
lective affiliation and intimacy, and against the territorializing
power of the disciplining state and social corpus. It is part of an
ongoing ontological process that uses racialized sexuality to assert
complex subjecthood, inside of the overwhelming constraints of
social stigma, stereotype, structural inequality, policing, divest-
132
ment, segregation, and exploitation under the neoliberal state.
By emphasizing complex subjectivity, erotic sovereignty disrupts deeply entrenched discourses
of “sexual responsibility, gendered propriety, and racial loyalty.”
133
The recognition that people
are complex, that their commitments may at times contradict one another, and that the deploy-
ment of sexuality is not determined by established norms, creates the opportunity to reconfigure
127
Ibid. 178
128
Ibid. 165
129
Ibid. 11
130
Ibid. 16
131
Ibid. 203
132
Ibid. 16
133
Ibid. 203
!109
the erotic negotiations of black women in pornography. And while these women make up a very
small portion of women in general, the power dynamics they navigate mirror those of many
women, as the sex industry is in many ways a microcosm of our collective sexual politics. There-
fore, it behooves us to pay attention to the mechanisms and strategies that these women have de-
veloped, consciously or otherwise, to not only survive in an arena built to exploit them, but to
thrive.
Miller-Young argues that by using their sexualities strategically, black women in pornog-
raphy aspire to material survival and security, but also to define their own sexual needs and de-
sires outside of everyday exploitation.
134
In this way erotic sovereignty, or sexual dissent, “priori
-
tizes, or at least aims toward, an autonomous, independent, and self-defining sexuality, while
also acknowledging the forms of affiliation, relation, and responsibility that sexual subjects have
to one another.”
135
Erotic sovereignty is not an excuse to disregard our intersubjective commit
-
ments, or place self-interests before our community responsibilities. Rather it is a mechanism
through which these highly stigmatized women bracket the judgments and assumptions aimed
towards their bodies in order to articulate sexual identities that have practical value. The recogni-
tion of the inadequate existing sexual narratives is already subverting popular conceptions of
black women, if only we can change our frame of reference to better see it.
Our second term, illicit eroticism, gives us the background for erotic sovereignty by
“provid[ing] a framework to understand the ways in which black women put hypersexuality to
use.”
136
It is a term used by Miller-Young in two slightly different contexts: first, to identify a
134
Ibid. 146
135
Ibid. 203
136
Ibid. 11
!110
repertoire unique to the realm of sexual and sexualized labor; and second, to describe how black
women use, manipulate, and deploy their sexualities within the economic sphere.
137
According to
Miller-Young, the tactics of illicit eroticism are threefold:
First, black women in pornography use illicit eroticism to inter-
vene in the realm of representation, working around, against, and
through often-stereotypical roles to produce illicit erotic images of
black female sexuality. Second, black female porn performers use
illicit eroticism in the realm of personal development and explo-
ration, using erotic performance as an opportunity to have new
sexual experiences, and presenting themselves and their biographi-
cal experiences as courageous, groundbreaking, and transcendent,
not exploited or victimized. Finally, illicit eroticism is useful to
black women navigating the field of pornography as an industry.
The industrial tactics of illicit eroticism include black women’s use
of their sexual capital for material survival, the ways in which their
participation in the industry may provide space for future actresses
to enter, and their ability to take control of the means of produc-
tion.
138
Miller-Young uses ‘illicit eroticism’ to describe tactics available to those whose sexualities have
been subject to a tradition of erasure, and have historically been identified as illicit, in order to
change the roles they have access to, develop an attitude of playfulness in exploring and develop-
ing new sexual identities, and impact the industry in which they work for immediate survival as
well as future change. Illicit eroticism therefore “conceptualizes how these actors use sexuality in
ways that necessarily confront and manipulate discourses about their sexual deviance while re-
maining tied to a system that produces them as marginalized sexual laborers.”
139
In other words,
black women in pornography can be seen to work within their industry with the intent of chang-
ing the ways in which they are perceived. The fact that they continue to rely on the pornographic
137
Ibid. 182
138
Ibid. 266 (emphasis mine)
139
Ibid. 16
!111
industry, which is deeply invested in racist and sexist structures, for material survival does not
foreclose their ability to overcome their exploited or victimized status. In fact, many of the
women that Miller-Young speaks to deliberately use their sexual capital, and commodify their
sexualities, as part of the strategic and tactical labor they use in capitalist economies.
140
This type of strategic labor recognizes that “consumer demand for one’s sexuality, includ-
ing (but not limited to) the unspeakable, taboo desire for racialized erotic fantasy that dominates
most markets for black-oriented adult entertainment,”
141
provides a starting point to assert one’s
value in a realm that reinforces black women’s valueless-ness. By deploying their “sex, sexuality,
and eroticism in ways that promote one’s human capital, survival, and self-care in the face of
enormous impediments,”
142
black women in porn are able to “navigate a sexist, racist, and clas
-
sist society by using their embodied, or corporeal, resources for material survival.”
143
They en
-
gage meaningfully with the power dynamics that they are embroiled in, both resisting and acqui-
escing at different times and in different ways.
5. Discussion
Both Lindsey and Miller-Young engage in commendable efforts to excavate and establish
positive and empowering sexual identities and practices for black women in a contemporary con-
text. They work to show how black women make sense of their sexual lives, take seriously the
testimony of black women who engage in sexual politics, and witness the ways in which black
women refuse to be shamed into accepting a starting position of sexual victimization. They also
140
Ibid. 182
141
Ibid. 183
142
Ibid.
143
Ibid. 182
!112
outspokenly contest the suspicion and dismissal of black women’s claims to agency, and their
complex deployment of sexuality for their own benefit and pleasure.
Of course, it is important to reflect upon whether the examples mentioned in their work
— of porn actresses and pop stars — are translate-able. Will they impact representations in a way
that can be later picked up and manipulated by all women? Do they serve as a model for what
women can do if they desire to? I believe as prominent and visible examples of women deeply
invested in sexuality, they at the very least have a right to be heard. Their experiences and testi-
mony of the way sexuality works for them should be recognized — and I am included narrative
and theatrical representations (like music videos) — as constituting a kind of testimony here. It is
also important to recognize who Lindsey and Miller-Young look to for insight into the workings
of sexual politics — namely, women engaged in these politics in concrete and explicit ways. If
we stay true to our commitment to reframe existing narratives about female sexuality, then it
would seem especially important to listen to the ways in which differently situated women al-
ready do this work.
In “Why We Get Off” Morgan states that the project of pleasure politics asks two impor-
tant questions: “What possibilities can a politics of pleasure offer for black feminist futures?”
and, “Specifically, how can deepening our understanding of the multivalent ways black women
produce, read and participate in pleasure complicate our understanding of black female subjec-
tivities in ways that invigorate, inform and sharpen a black feminist agenda?”
144
I obviously can
-
not speak to some of the specificities of these questions as a white woman. But, as I have tried to
show in this chapter, there is much to learn from these discussions, and it is worth attending to
144
Morgan, “Why We Get Off,” 46.
!113
the specific spaces that these theorists work in. By engaging with these various works, I hope to
promote a more communal understanding of sexual politics, one which takes seriously the diver-
sity of approaches that women take to understanding and acting out their sexual identities. It be-
hooves me to listen to women who are different than me, not only because I owe it to them to
pay attention to their experiences, but also because I can learn something valuable by paying at-
tention.
The paradigms and practices of eroticism proposed by these different authors deserve at-
tention and bear witnessing because they present important possibilities. I am particularly recep-
tive to the idea of centering pleasure and satisfaction in our sexual paradigms, as they provide a
necessary intervention to the stagnant tradition of victimizing narratives. That being said, I am
not sure that I can be explicit as to how these contestations will start to subvert norms in a way
that is noticeable to the general public, and therefore has an impact on the collective hermeneutic
resources used to understand women’s sexual agency. It will certainly depend on uptake, and
specifically, uptake by a significant enough portion of the public to be considered a valid posi-
tion. However, I also do not think that this is as difficult as it may seem at first glance. After all,
we witness the changing of meanings throughout our lives. It is a common experience, and one
in which we all take part. However, it does underscore our dependence on our communities to
create new life practices and ways of thinking.
It is important to pay attention to how both Miller-Young and Lindsey emphasize that we
must all actively participate in changing the ways that we interpret women’s actions and motives.
We need frameworks that better suit the types of sexual agency exhibited by women, and we
need to actively push these frameworks into mainstream understanding. As Miller-Young argues,
!114
agency, even if it goes to work within larger embedded relations of subordination, should be rec-
ognized as a dialectical capacity “for progressive change as well as everyday survival.”
145
There
is a give and take when it comes to matters of agency, and our ability to impact our environments
in the ways we wish. Sometimes, what will help us survive another day is not entirely compatible
with what will help us succeed in the long run. A successful politics of sexuality must recognize
this dialectical capacity between making moves for now and for later, for oneself and one’s
community, and for survival as well as change. Moving forward, we should consider how we can
shift the conversation from that of adaptive preferences, or complicity in oppression, to what
Lindsey describes as the excavation and establishment of female-authored sites of sexual expres-
sivity.
146
We must grow to be receptive to the work that women do to liberate themselves, even if
it presents contradictions or tensions.
Which is not to say that public performances of sexuality are never problematic. Rather,
“problematic” is not a death sentence. Problematic does not invalidate a position in and of itself,
and if we are willing to bracket “problematic” we may come to learn something important from
the experiences of women that we tend to disregard. By listening to the testimony of women en-
gaged in these dynamics, I believe we will find perspectives and strategies that are vital to de-
stigmatizing women’s existence as erotic beings.
The varied accounts presented in this chapter all have something to say about how we
ought to re-envision the erotic in order to release women from the stranglehold of sexist, and
racist, structures. And while each author understands the practice and conception of the erotic in
145
Miller-Young, “A Taste for Brown Sugar,” 17.
146
Lindsey, “Complicated Crossroads,” 60.
!115
different ways, they all have something valuable to offer the person interested in liberation.
Lorde provides a way of articulating the erotic as an integral aspect of a life worth living, one
which validates the erotic as something primal and indispensable — and therefore worth the time
and energy necessary to recover it from illegitimate usages. By tying the erotic to deep knowl-
edge, to something prior to understanding, Lorde also shows that it is something prior to the ma-
nipulations of sexism and racism. Morgan provides a targeted and textured account of contempo-
rary black women’s sexual identities that is grounded in specific interventions. Hers is an impor-
tant counterpoint to Lorde’s, one that does not rest on any sort of dichotomous conceptualiza-
tions of sex and sexuality. Lindsey offers us a more nuanced look into some very visible exam-
ples of black female sexuality at work in public spaces, and warns us not to underestimate the
power of authoring one’s own sexuality. Finally, Miller-Young offers a look into the lives and
labor of women deeply invested in eroticism, in order to problematize some of the assumptions
made about these women, and showcase their creativity and strength in developing strategies for
both short and longterm survival.
6. Conclusion
In this dissertation, especially with the goal I have in mind of articulating a sexual politics
for women invested in sexualization that nevertheless has liberatory potential without impossible
standards, I find myself limited insofar as my performance and exhibition of sexuality are, in
comparison to many other women, protected if not respected. It is not enough to talk about how
life might be better for me if the world learned new sexual paradigms that don't dehumanize and
derivatize women, because I am not the only one impacted by these dynamics. In other words,
while this project is certainly self-interested, its importance is not solely on account of potential
!116
improvements to my life, as I cannot change the world for myself without changing it for others
too. Nor would I want to. The experiences I have of being sexualized are rooted in structures of
power that are necessarily intersubjective, as they put me in relation to other people. Therefore,
my struggles and fears and hopes are intimately tied with those of many other people, and I de-
sire to work for them at the same time as I would ask them to work for me.
While this desire is perhaps commendable, I’ve not always gone about this the right way.
Like many other white women, I’ve fallen prey to the privilege that allows me to be incredibly
self-centered in my work, political goals and personal aspirations. And while I would consider
my studies, invested as they are in feminist theories of race, sexuality and power, as effective
training for knowing better, I have nevertheless faltered, and showcased the types of ignorance
inherent in the privilege from which I profit. This, I believe, has been particularly evident when
I’ve worked with black feminist theory and black feminist accounts of sexuality, perhaps because
my whiteness is deeply implicated in these accounts. It is not surprising then that I find myself
navigating the reality that while I want to be part of the solution, I am also part of the problem.
I have come to understand that solidarity requires a healthy dose of humility. I have
learned that “me too” is not always the right way to approach common ground.
147
At best, “me
too” misses the point of someone else’s experience, at worst, it does violence by attempting to
erase the particularities of another’s differences. And while I do not wish to be that type of per-
son, I do wish to learn from those who are different from me, and find truth and hope in their ex-
periences and knowledge. Figuring out how to do this in a respectful and appropriate manner is
not particularly simple, especially because philosophical methodology is not immune to co-opt-
Incidentally, I wrote this before the introduction of the “me too movement” into popular culture, and am not in
147
tending to direct any judgment towards that particular cultural phenomenon.
-
!117
ing the production of knowledge of marginalized groups. These conflicts mean that reading BFT
is not a carefree activity but one in which I work to actively remind myself that it is not about
me, and that my place is not at the center.
The women cited in this paper write beautiful, meaningful narratives that deserve to be
held up as examples of exceptional feminist theory. They present us with a particularly necessary
conversation to have if we are interested in liberatory sexual politics, i.e. ways of conceptualiz-
ing and acting out sexual politics that dismantle oppressive systems and create vibrant new pos-
sibilities for sexual subjects. And while it is not obvious how these narratives relate to my expe-
rience or offer something that I can use, considering my particular mix of identities, I think there
is value in working across difference. I also believe that coalition building, both in our theory
and activism, is vital for introducing real change. Of course, effective coalition building is
thwarted by the aforementioned privileged point of view, and so people like me need to actively
work to address the ways in which we make poor partners for change, and how we can be more
accountable in the future. In this vein, I have started weeding out certain terms from my vocabu-
lary, including borrowing, transferring, and translating, and replaced these with the idea of
thinking with. Thinking with requires thoughtful and active listening that is supportive and un-
selfish.
Perhaps I am simply repeating what Lorde and Morgan have already recognized: that this
ought to be a labor of love.
148
I hope to participate in imagining new erotic possibilities for
women, because I am dissatisfied with the limited options currently available. And these new
Morgan writes: “I share this piece as a reminder (to both the reader and myself) that inherent in the noble search
148
for new directions in BFT is the diffident, exciting, uncertainty of that new-new — that tricky, impolitic thing that
positions itself precariously on the firm foundation of black feminist intellectual labor and a destabilizing, clearly
crunk willingness to strip the house down to its structural beams, if necessary. Like all successful renovation
projects, it is driven by love…this is not a comfortable or easily habitable space.” (Morgan 40)
!118
possibilities ought to exhibit both fluidity and flexibility, in order to address the needs of “the
enslaved to the pop star to the sex worker.”
149
This will be a collective project, so that no group
assumes the position of ‘neutral,’ or the capacity to speak for others. And collectively, I believe
we can engage in sexual identity negotiations that constitute a project of accountability and heal-
ing.
149
Morgan, “Why We Get Off,” 38.
!119
Daddy
Is it that much worse than ‘baby’?
!120
Chapter 4: False Consciousness
Charges of false consciousness often accompany many of the topics covered in previous
chapters, particularly around sexuality, desire and the sexualization of women. False conscious-
ness strikes at the heart of the experiences that drive this entire project, because it is the most po-
tent theoretical obstacle to overcome in my pursuit of sexual paradigms that allow for more em-
powering and agentic erotic identities. It is a charge that has often been sent my way, along with
the implication that I am lacking in some critical capacity as evidenced by choices that I have
made, or just some aspect of myself. One could say it is therefore something I have not only aca-
demic, but personal, interest in. While I feel a great deal of affinity with many aspects of feminist
theory, false consciousness is a concept to which I have always been resistant, perhaps because it
threatens that which is not merely a professional preoccupation, but an effort of survival.
I have decided to finish this dissertation with a systematic account of false consciousness
in order to address the ways in which these accusations infringe upon women’s spheres of action,
and limit the ways in which they can cultivate a disruptive sexual identity. While I do not reject
the notion of false consciousness, I find it to be a loaded concept, easily misused and inappropri-
ately applied, particularly with the intent to demean or invalidate experience. Of course, I am not
the first person to cast a critical gaze on the purpose and function of false consciousness in femi-
nist theory/praxis, but I hope that my personal entanglements with the concept will elucidate the
caution that I would like to instill in our invocations of false consciousness when we address
women’s choices and actions.
!121
1. Genealogy of false consciousness
False consciousness, as a philosophical concept, can be traced back to Marxist theory on
capitalism. For Marx and Engels, false consciousness was a form of consciousness produced by
the life practices of capitalist society,
150
and therefore intimately tied to capitalist ideology. In
traditional Marxist theory, the “relation between false consciousness and ideology is conceived
of in terms of the relation between social existence and social consciousness, a relation between
who one is (objectively) and about what one (subjectively).”
151
For Marx and Engels, ideology
described the distorted beliefs held about a society while false consciousness described the ways
in which individuals were deluded about their own beliefs.
152
This idea of delusion — that peo
-
ple can be misguided about the source of their beliefs — is central to the organizing power of
false consciousness and ideology because it provides a mechanism for falsehoods to be propa-
gated as truth.
Marx and Engels also argued that false consciousness was the normal way of perceiving
and acting within capitalist society,
153
because the commodity relations of capitalism permeated
all spheres of society, and thus the logic of capitalism became part and parcel with people’s
everyday experiences. False consciousness therefore affected everyone’s perception and con-
struction of reality, whether they were bourgeois or proletariat, because their class position de-
manded a structural blindness to capitalism as a social system and cultural organizing force. In
this way, false consciousness is a necessary instrument in the domination of both the ruling bour-
150
Eyerman, Ron. "False Consciousness and Ideology in Marxist Theory." Acta Sociologica 24, no. 1/2 (1981): 44
151
Ibid.
152
Ibid.43
153
Ibid. 45
!122
geoisie and working class in the capitalist system,
154
bringing their disparate interests in line with
one another.
With this theoretical backdrop, we see that, generally speaking, false consciousness can
be described as the holding of beliefs that are contrary to one’s interests and which contribute to
the disadvantaged position that a person/group finds themselves in. False consciousness is neces-
sarily produced by an accompanying ideology — a way of thinking about the world that false
consciousness supports by ambiguating or otherwise distracting attention from certain truths. It
is, in essence, a way in which people lie to themselves that serves a system of power that they are
harmed by. False consciousness is an arguably necessary component of any exploitative system,
because it accounts for the participation of those who are oppressed. Without false conscious-
ness, it would be hard to explain why people choose to perpetuate systems in which they are
harmed. Therefore, false consciousness serves a distinct theoretical purpose in most conceptual-
izations of social power dynamics.
2. Feminist accounts of false consciousness
Within feminist theory, the notion of false consciousness is derived largely from Cather-
ine MacKinnon’s work on sex and consent.
155
MacKinnon argues that the social and cultural
conditions of patriarchy compel women to consent to states of affairs that “they do not authenti-
cally desire and that is often against their physical, dignitary and political interests.”
156
Not only
do women consent to these practices, they are also trained to desire, or otherwise willingly en-
154
Ibid.
See MacKinnon, Catharine A. "Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: An Agenda for Theory." Signs 7, no.
155
3 (1982): 515-44. and MacKinnon, Catharine A. Toward a feminist theory of the state. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard
University Press, 1989.
Wells, Shallyn. “Feminism, False Consciousness & Consent: A Third Way.” 18 Geo. J. Gender & L. 251 (2017):
156
254.
!123
gage in them. MacKinnon focuses particularly on how the system of patriarchy conditions
women’s sexual practices and expectations, especially as structured by heterosexual intercourse,
which she considers to be endemic to the devalued status of women in a sexist system. She ar-
gues that sex, in particular, is a space in which gendered power relations manifest and play out to
the detriment of women, because “sexuality is to feminism what work is to marxism,”
157
and is
therefore a space primed for false consciousness. According to Wells, for MacKinnon, women
are conditioned to patriarchal sexual practices in three ways:
1. Coercive social context — Women are conditioned to submit to sexual activity with
men for fear of the consequences of not submitting to sexual activity with men. This
fear of harm creates a social context that exerts pressure on women’s actions.
158
2. Habit formation — Women come to normalize a baseline of having sex that they do
not really want and that is often not in their interest, considering it to be normal.
3. Adopting patriarchal interests — Women submit to this type of sexual activity that is
not in their interest, and that they do not really want, because “they have come to de-
sire submission; degradation has become sexy; the threat has become foreplay.
Women have, under this theory, adopted the interests of patriarchy as their own de-
sires.”
159
160
It is this third level, wherein women come to desire the interests of the sexist system, that is regu-
larly referred to as false consciousness. In effect, by adopting patriarchal values, women invest in
the very ideological systems that are the basis of their oppression, allowing these harmful ide-
ologies to frame their identities and desires. Therefore, for someone like MacKinnon, in a move
strongly reminiscent of Marx and Engels’ theory of capitalism, if patriarchy is the ideology, then
“desiring sex that is physically and psychologically contrary to one’s interests is the false con-
157
MacKinnon, “Feminism, Marxism and Method,” 515.
158
Wells, “Feminism,” 254.
159
Ibid.
160
Ibid. 255
!124
sciousness.”
161
It is not simply the acceptance of, but the desire for, sex that is harmful and de
-
meaning which constitutes women’s false consciousness under patriarchy.
False consciousness is sometimes also referred to as “adaptive preferences,”
162
which is
the idea that women’s choices under patriarchy are not ‘real’ choices because they are in fact
prompted by the interests of a system which is structurally opposed to women’s dignity and
flourishing. They are choices ‘adapted’ to patriarchy, and thus conditioned by oppressive social
contexts to such an extent that they should be viewed with skepticism and suspicion. Wells ar-
gued that, for MacKinnon, within the context of heterosexual activity, and under the hegemonic
regime of patriarchy, “women’s desires are conditioned by the limited options made available to
them…these societal limitations are internalized as personal choices and desires, which in turn
inform how and when consent is given and desire is felt.”
163
According to this logic, women’s
access to authentic desire is blocked by patriarchal ideology to the point that their consent can
hardly be understood as such, since it is given within a context in which there is no adequate al-
ternative. In order to avoid confronting the reality of their lack of ability to choose for them-
selves when consent is given and when desire is felt, women learn to see that which is forced
upon them as a choice. In other words, women lie to themselves about their desires in order to
ignore their lack of choices, and therefore willingly participate in a system that demands they act
against their own physical, social, and political interests. Women’s desires and inclinations there-
fore take on a suspect quality that reinforces that women’s intentionality cannot be trusted, as
they become a benchmark of how ingrained patriarchy is in women’s everyday decision making
161
Ibid. 256
162
Ibid. 258
163
Ibid.
!125
processes. The logic of this type of feminism concludes that if women wish to be liberated, they
must then act against their felt desires, insofar as these desires are conditioned by patriarchy.
164
To summarize, arguments about the existence of false consciousness attempt to explain
behavior through which an oppressed group contributes to, or perpetuates, the patterns of its own
oppression. They do so by describing “such actions as being the product of internalization, by the
oppressed group, of essential elements of the dominant ideology,” and “describ[ing] this internal-
ization of and determination by ideology as occurring beyond the conscious comprehension of
the oppressed group.”
165
Both false consciousness and adaptive preferences can easily be pro
-
jected onto a wide spectrum of women’s experiences, including (but not limited to) women’s vot-
ing practices, clothing choices, grooming habits, and interpersonal relationships. It is a powerful
explanatory device with an incredibly large scope, because in many ways, all of women’s actions
and choices can be seen through a lens of patriarchal oppression, whether we look at it from a
perspective of language-games, or simply recognize the ubiquitous nature of patriarchy in our
social fabric.
3. Questioning the deployment of false consciousness
Of course, the purpose of this chapter is not to question the veracity of false conscious-
ness as a concept, but rather the way it is deployed. I have no intention of arguing that false con-
sciousness is a phenomenon that does not exist. It is well documented that oppressive structures
can obscure self-knowledge, and make us resistant to the truth of our own subordination in a va-
riety of ways. As Matsuda argues,
164
Ibid. 260
165
Abrams, Kathryn. “Ideology and Women’s Choices.” 24 Ga. L. Rev. (1989): 763.
!126
Various phenomena, such as working-class authoritarianism,
Asian-American homophobia, and Women’s internalization of pa-
triarchal body images, show how subordination can obscure as
well as illuminate self-knowledge. The long, cold history of subor-
dinated status generating subordinating impulses is well known to
both scholars and targets of recycled hate.
166
Not only does false consciousness identify a real phenomenon (this cycle of subordinated status
generating subordinating impulses), it is particularly useful for understanding how and why peo-
ple may willingly opt into systems that cause them harm. It is certainly more useful than simply
claiming that people are irrational, stupid or lack free will.
False consciousness, as a concept, is also useful insofar as it reinforces that oppression is
structural, and that any project with a goal of dismantling systems of subordination requires that
we look at the systems that inform individuals’ behaviors and beliefs. For issues of sexual poli-
tics, “a reading of theorists like MacKinnon is valuable because it reveals sexual hierarchy and
suggests theoretical structure,”
167
offering an account that highlights the mechanisms through
which ideology becomes reified and naturalized. It takes a bird’s eye view that shows the scaf-
folding of patriarchy, helping us bring together a wide spectrum of phenomena in one cohesive
narrative about the subordination of women.
By bringing together so many disparate experiences under one umbrella of sexual domi-
nation, Abrams argues that theorists like MacKinnon also prevent women from exempting them-
selves from her analysis.
168
False consciousness implicates all women because it shows that the
structures of patriarchy produce certain ways of thinking that we share in common by nature of
Matsuda, Mari J. “Pragmatism Modified and the False Consciousness Problem.” 63 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1763 (1990):
166
1777
167
Ibid. 1766
168
Abrams, “Ideology and Women’s Choices,” 775.
!127
existing in a shared society with a common language and grammar. In the most generous sense,
false consciousness articulates how gender hierarchy is perpetuated through our acceptance and
adherence to gender ideology — to the way in which we consume and live gender mythology.
Because the stories we tell about gender are so ubiquitous, impacting so many aspects of our
lives, it is, practically speaking, almost impossible to exist outside of them. Our social interac-
tions are predicated on ideas of male dominance and female submission, and women are forced
to participate in these gendered politics, voluntarily or not. To exist in our culture means accept-
ing, to some extent, existing gender hierarchies, although, of course, this acceptance does not
preclude one from attempting to dismantle them at the same time. Rather, it is important to rec-
ognize that we are all complicit in the systems in which we participate, simply on the basis of
that participation.
Abrams also argues that theorists like MacKinnon use concepts like false consciousness
to “turn up the volume” on feminist messages for strategic purposes.
169
There is no doubt that
declaring that (all) women participate in their own oppression is attention-grabbing, even sensa-
tionalizing. It is even more attention getting to argue that women may not even be aware the ex-
tent to which their everyday choices and actions are a result of their subordination as women in a
patriarchal system, because it calls into question the everyday motivations for our actions. If tak-
en seriously, these charges implicate everyone, from the housewife to the factory worker to the
feminist scholar. It also instills a sense of pressing importance, a weight and insistence that may
not be as easy to see in a less wholesale theory, one that does not incite a call to action, so to
speak.
169
Ibid. 776
!128
Nevertheless, it is certainly the case that arguments about how women are the victims of
false consciousness, and that “their choices are unconsciously determined by gender ideology,”
have been a long-standing source of disagreement and concern in feminist theory and politics.
170
I will now outline a few of the critiques of false consciousness that I believe are particularly per-
tinent to our discussion. This is by no means a conclusive account of the different positions that
theorists have taken, but rather the critiques most palpable in my own experience. It is also worth
noting that these critiques are closely tied together, and there is significant overlap between
them.
4. Critiques of false consciousness
Generally speaking, critiques of false consciousness attempt to showcase the limitations
of the concept. Often, particular issues that are called upon as evidence of false consciousness
are more nuanced and complicated than they may initially appear. In fact, many phenomena used
to support the viability of false consciousness resist a decisive account of how women are impli-
cated in gender hierarchies, calling into question the extent to which women are culpable for
their continuing oppression. These arguments also involve a judgment process that can be very
paternalistic and imply that women are less capable of understanding themselves than a more
“objective” outsider perspective. The rhetoric of false consciousness frequently overstates the
degree to which women should be held responsible for their own oppression.
4. a. Academic bias
False consciousness, particularly as it appears in academic theory, is often used to privi-
lege academic voices over those of non-academic lay persons. This seems to be a somewhat nat-
170
Ibid. 761
!129
ural consequence of claiming that some group, i.e. women, does not understand their own best
interests, but I, the academic/researcher, understand what they do not from my privileged stand-
point of superior knowledge. I think that this type of entitlement is somewhat indicative of the
field of philosophy, and the academy more generally, given that we invest particular importance
in our expertise, our methodologies and our general know-how. Of course, philosophy is not the
only field to perpetuate this type of paternalistic thinking. Matsuda, who works in legal theory,
articulates the type of academic bias inherent in claims of false consciousness within her profes-
sion:
When I have argued in the past that legal theorist should seek out
subordinated voices, I have heard in response a regiment of rea-
sons why this search would prove pointless, ranging from “we al-
ready know what they have to say,” to “it does them disservice to
romanticize their position,” to “their immersion in their own sub-
ordination taints their analysis.”
171
There are many different ways in which experts marginalize the voices of the oppressed, but they
largely boil down to an assumption that closeness causes blindness, or an inability to reflect criti-
cally on one’s experience. Instead of knowledge, it may simply be “the way things are”
172
to the
individuals in question. Which is why some might conclude that even if experts do go to the
trouble of identifying and reaching out to subordinated groups, there is no guarantee that the in-
dividuals in these groups have any valuable knowledge to share about their own subordination.
173
Instead, we are better off looking to the experts to speak to the experiences of women, rather than
171
172
Matsuda, “Pragmatism Modified,” 1777-8.
Ibid. 1777
173
Ibid.
!130
women themselves, who run the risk of being inarticulate and incapable of sharing what they
know.
The idea that women, as a group, are less capable of understanding and being able to ar-
ticulate their own experiences, rests on an assumption that they cannot be trusted to take a criti-
cal stance on their own positionality. This type of view is further justified by arguing that be-
cause the average woman participates in “ideologically infused acts which contribute to [her]
subordination,” women’s awareness and appreciation of their own experiences are less reliable
than an experts.’
174
But this does beg the question: are women in academia exempt from ideolog
-
ically infused acts? It is unclear why we should assume that experts are successfully impartial,
bestowed with a special objectivity that allows a better understanding of women’s situation than
women themselves. Rather, it would seem that these experts are also implicated in the systems in
question, and therefore are not necessarily better equipped to take an objective viewpoint. In fact,
this type of separation is exactly what theorists like MacKinnon deny — that any women could
consider herself exempt from the influence of patriarchal ideology. Even claims to expertise and
developing particular sensitivities to phenomena that others may be numb to, so to speak, cannot
really justify this type of move, which is not to say that this type of training is not valuable, but
rather that it does not automatically translate into action. Therefore, it is somewhat untenable to
claim that a woman is incapable of truly comprehending the motivation for her own actions, but
that a “feminist scholar’s explanations of her choices should be categorically preferred to the
woman’s own.”
175
174
Abrams, “Ideology and Choice," 765.
175
Ibid. 770
!131
It is also unclear how exactly being “ideologically infused” should make a particular act
or choice suspect. After all, it is hard to conceive of an action that is not ideologically infused in
some capacity. We all participate in these ideological systems, and no space is completely ex-
empt from them. I do not find this to be a flaw, but rather a recognition of the settings in which
we all live and work. Nor is it clear how being situated in ideological structures would make
something not a choice. The alternative, that actions only count as choice when they are radically
free of ideological influence, presents such a restrictive concept of agency as to be nonsensical. I
agree with Matsuda when she claims that,“My personal and unscientific suspicion is that there
can be false consciousness about false consciousness. There is a strong incentive for academics
to believe that poor and working people have little of value to say about law, social life, or poli-
tics.”
176
This incentive is arguably the maintenance of academic voices as superior, bestowing
them with authority and expertise to be respected and listened to. It is also worth pointing out
that although I am arguably one of these ‘experts,’ my testimony is frequently dismissed by my
peers, which begs the question of who is able to claim expertise and have that status recognized.
4.b. Demeaning to women
A second critique of false consciousness argues that it is a concept that is demeaning to
women, or regularly deployed in ways that demean women, specifically through the implication
“that women somehow lack sufficient agency to make and manage their own choices and by (of-
fensively) suggesting that they do not properly understand their own ‘real’ interests.”
177
This
idea, that women are in some way incapable of understanding themselves, and consistently make
176
Matsuda, “Pragmatism Modified,” 1778.
Gill Rosalind and Ngaire Donaghue. “As if Postfeminism Had Come True: The Turn to Agency in Cultural Stud
-
177
ies of ‘Sexualisation’.” In: Madhok S., Phillips A., Wilson K. (eds) Gender, Agency, and Coercion. Palgrave
Macmillan: London, (2013).
!132
choices against their perceived best interests because they simply cannot know better, is one used
to discredit women as agents and degrades them to the status of subjugated object-person. It is
also closely tied to our first critique, as this type of discrediting sets the stage for the privileging
of ‘expert’ voices.
The emphasis on women’s interests, often seen in these discussions, should give us pause
because it is a concept does not necessarily hold up to scrutiny as it is content-poor. While group
interests are not necessarily arbitrary or relative, they are also not particularly easy to articulate,
especially as you attempt to get into specifics. Of course, at a general level, it is easier to say
what is desirable for women — to be treated equally to men, or even to have equal social, eco-
nomic and political power and agency in our world. This may involve certain prescriptions about
changes that we need: dismantling rape culture, getting rid of the gender pay gap, easy and safe
access to abortions and birth control, and better representation in political institutions, among
many other things. There are clearly many things that we can think of when considering
women’s interests.
But it becomes more challenging to specify exactly what is in (or against) women’s best
interests as we attempt to hone in on specific practices and embodied phenomena. Many things
can be implicated in a system of oppression without being responsible for it. Focusing on peo-
ple’s individual actions, or even the practices of communities and groups, is often inadequate for
constructing hypotheses about what is helpful or harmful in a feminist context. Which explains
the frequent tension in feminist discourses about the appropriate theoretical and political posi-
tions to take on sexual practices and institutions like pornography, BDSM, slut walks, and strip-
ping, to name a few. All of these can easily be (and often are) called upon as evidence of false
!133
consciousness, and yet these arguments present an incomplete picture of what these activities
entail. Very few things are as cut and dry as being able to say that “x” practice is not in women’s
interests.
Perhaps particularly demeaning is the way in which false consciousness overly simplifies
the “complexity of women’s experiences, subjectivities or investments in particular cultural
forms or modes of femininity.”
178
Relegating women to the status of cultural dupe, unable to see
the real patriarchal forces at work in their social fabric and everyday interactions, further implies
that women’s agency can be wholly compromised by patriarchal forces. But this claim also
presents a certain amount of ambiguity. On the one hand, it is certainly true that structures of op-
pression will limit and constrain oppressed people in ways that those in power are not subject to.
Patriarchy creates important limitations on women’s choices by enforcing particular ways of life
that must be respected in order to survive. Take for example, the fact that I will seldom walk
alone at night — a product of my training in rape avoidance, which is a state of affairs that is a
direct product of the violence against women used as policing mechanism under patriarchy.
There are very tangible ways in which my daily choices are affected by the sexist structures that I
live in.
On the other hand, it does not necessarily follow that these constraints make me less ca-
pable of being recognized as agentic. While I am forced to move within specific parameters, the
ways in which I navigate those structures are still reflective of my capacity to deliberate, think
critically, and behave in ways that speak to my reflexive capacities. The question may be, how
significant are the barriers of patriarchy? This is not a simple question to answer, as it will de-
178
Gill and Donaghue, “As if Postfeminism had come true.”
!134
pend on myriad factors that complicate the possibility of coming to a universal answer. In other
words, the barriers of patriarchy will be customized to the women who face them, and so there is
no straightforward account of how exactly, and to what extent, sexist structures constrain
women.
Analyses dependent upon false consciousness bring to mind an image of women as
caged, trapped within the confines of patriarchal structures and incapable of escaping. With this
view in mind, it becomes more difficult to argue that agency exists, that choices matter, and that
women’s actions represent something generative and empowering. And yet, it is unclear as to
why we must relegate ourselves to this type of model. Perhaps it behooves us to recognize that
different women experience the restrictions of sexism in different ways, and while there is value
in hyper-restrictive accounts, relying too heavily on these may create a picture of women that
does not accurately reflect their autonomy, or their experience of being agents. I believe it is im-
portant for our theoretical constructs to meaningfully engage with women’s own sense of them-
selves.
Some theorists claim that critiques about the ways in which false consciousness as a theo-
ry undermines women's agency necessarily leads to moral relativism. Speaking to this specific
critique of false consciousness, Wells argues that,
Even recognizing what this argument assumes (that the feminists
deciding what is and is not false are condescending and paternal-
istic), the argument cannot stand without accepting some kind of
total moral relativism. However, in the context of, for example,
female genital mutilation, it becomes clear that this relativism has
its limitations. Surely even most feminist relativists believe there
is no cultural context that makes female genital mutilation moral-
ly permissible — even when women in that culture say it is…
Whatever the reason, to believe that there is no cultural context in
!135
which female genital mutilation is morally acceptable from a
feminist perspective, is to believe that women in that culture who
submit to, consent to, or desire this procedure are suffering from
false consciousness.
179
I find this line of argumentation problematic in a few ways, which I will discuss here. That being
said, I first would like to state that moral relativism ought to be avoided in feminist theory be-
cause, in a very basic sense, if things are “all relative,” it creates significant challenges for claim-
ing that sexism is bad. Feminists need to take a strong moral stance on sexism and patriarchy that
articulates these structures as objectively harmful, and therefore something we should actively
work to dismantle. However, I do not think that avoiding the charge of moral relativism requires
us to disregard the agentic potential of any and all possibly controversial acts. In other words, it
is not clear that arguing that women exhibit agency under patriarchal structures invites morally
relativistic accounts. Neither is it the case that taking on a position that certain claims of false
consciousness do not adequately account for women’s agency necessarily forces one to defend a
practice like female genital mutilation. It is also worth noting that female genital mutilation is an
extreme example that does not adequately capture more commonplace, if still controversial,
choices that women may make. There are many facets of sexist and misogynistic cultures that do
not exhibit such strongly objective harms to women, and female genital mutilation can hardly be
used as a model for this type of investigation.
Of course, I don't mean to imply that arguments in favor of the existence of false con-
sciousness necessarily claim that women do not have agency, but rather that they can restrict
women’s agency to the point where it becomes trivial. And to trivialize women’s agency under
patriarchy is not only demeaning, but harmful, for it assumes that women are not capable of act-
179
Wells, “Feminism, False Consciousness and Consent,” 256.
!136
ing in meaningful ways and mirror tropes about women’s irrationality that have been used for
centuries, if not millennia, to justify the dehumanization of women. Whether a result of the sys-
tematic oppression they face or not, it does condemn women to a diminished status that is com-
mensurate with that which women are assigned under patriarchy.
Some might argue that false consciousness is not a claim that women are not agents, but
rather an inquiry about the conditions necessary for women’s agency.
180
Feminist theory be
-
comes the space in which to determine what the necessary conditions for agency are; to deter-
mine which assumptions, beliefs, and practices are harmful to women, to determine how patriar-
chal ideology has been internalized by women, and to determine what practices and beliefs are
contrary to women’s best interests. But this again begs the question: who decides what is in
women’s best interests? Ideally, this is a collective project between women, but in practice this
has clearly rarely been the case. There is often a select group of women deciding what behaviors
and beliefs are “bad,” or “wrong,” or otherwise subvert women’s interests. But while some prac-
tices may be glaringly toxic to women — i.e. female genital mutilation — other, equally popular,
symbols of women’s oppression, are less straightforward.
4.c. Ignores intersectionality
A third critique of false consciousness is that it is a theory that does not adequately ac-
count for intersectionality. This is particularly apparent in arguments about the ideological de-
termination of women’s experiences as sexual subjects. While it may be the case, as MacKinnon
argues, that “all women live in sexual objectification the way fish live in water”,
181
there is still a
180
Ibid. 257
181
MacKinnon, Towards a feminist theory of the state, 149.
!137
spectrum of women’s experiences within objectification culture. In fact, you could substitute
“sexual objectification” for any manifestation of patriarchy, and it would still be the case that the
phenomenon in question exists within a spectrum of experience. This is why terms like “hyper-
sexualization” have been developed — to do the work of articulating that different kinds of
women experience the same sexist phenomena — i.e. sexualization — in different ways, and that
these differences can be crucially important for understanding how the intersection of identities
impacts women’s experiences.
It is important to attend to difference, even while invoking a commonality. Ideological
determination arguments, like those of false consciousness theory, often “neglect the crucially
diversifying influence of race, class, and sexual orientation,”
182
when attempting to develop a
coherent theory. It is simply the case that some groups may not be sensitive to the same ideologi-
cal constraints. For example, “the social construction of the sexuality of women of color has of-
ten differed radically from that of whites,”
183
and yet most feminist accounts of sexuality and
sexualization are overly reliant on white women’s accounts and experiences. As we saw in the
previous chapter, overlooking the differences between different groups of women can hinder our
ability to adequately theorize oppression, and may keep us from recognizing effective practices
of resistance. It can also obscure crucial areas of divergence between different populations, and
the types of ideological constraints that different women face.
This is of particular importance to my overarching focus on sexualization throughout this
dissertation. Theorists who utilize false consciousness theory to explain women’s oppression,
182
Abrams, “Ideology and Women’s Choices,” 768.
183
Ibid. 769
!138
often focus on sexuality and sexualization as a hallmark of women’s ideological indoctrination
into patriarchy to the exclusion of alternatives. For example, MacKinnon argues that women con-
tribute to their own subordination through the very act of engaging in heterosexual relations, and
that both the “choice and enjoyment of sex may themselves be shaped by the practices and the
ideology of male dominance.”
184
She argues that “some women eroticize dominance and submis
-
sion; it beats feeling forced,”
185
overlooking the possibility that sex can be playful, and that
women can approach dynamics of power within intimate spaces in ways that are creative and
imaginative. Since MacKinnon’s conception of false consciousness relies heavily on universal-
ization, this line of reasoning effectively:
Homogenizes, and ignor[es] differences and obscur[es] the fact
that different people are sexualized in different ways and with dif-
ferent meanings. Sexualization does not operate outside of pro-
cesses of gendering, racialization, and classing, and works within a
visual economy that remains profoundly agist, (dis)ablist and het-
eronormative.
186
By creating such a narrow framework, feminist accounts of false consciousness often contain
their own inherent weaknesses, because it becomes all too easy to find an alternative. When
building a theory of sexual politics, it is important to constantly confront the limitations that any
particular point of view will inevitably face. This is why, although I begin this project deeply
embedded in my own experience, I try to acknowledge that my experience, while valid, may not
reflect that of other women, even those similarly situated. There will be aspects of my work that
do not apply to other women, and may seem inaccessible, or impractical, which is only natural.
184
Ibid. 764
185
MacKinnon, Towards a feminist theory of the state, supra note 5, 172-83.
Gill, Rosalind. "Media, Empowerment and the 'Sexualization of Culture' Debates." Sex Roles 66.11-12 (2012):
186
741.
!139
That does not make this project less valuable, but rather circumscribes its possible impacts by
recognizing the diversity of perspectives and assumptions that exist, even about a topic like sex-
ual politics.
4. d. Ideological overdetermination
A fourth critique argues that false consciousness presents an overly deterministic account
of ideological influence, which leaves little room for alternative conceptions of how women in-
teract with oppressive structures. It also promotes a view of intellectual laziness that is arguably
unfair to large portions of the populations. This critique is intimately tied to the previous one
about intersectionality, because it emphasizes the importance of recognizing alternatives, and the
fact that even ubiquitous dynamics impact different people in different ways.
On a personal level, it can be deeply frustrating when trying to articulate how, as an indi-
vidual, I retain the capacity to encounter sexist power dynamics with cleverness, creativity and
awareness that provides the opportunity to make adjustments to the game. Being denied the op-
portunity to exist in ways that are not completely subsumed by deterministic accounts runs
counter to my own experience of navigating the complex terrain of gender politics. And it is not
a particularly good sign when theory about women directly contradicts, and even negates, their
own experience. False consciousness arguments based in ideological determination describe, at
best, “a woman who operates reflexively or at worst resignedly, while many women’s experi-
ences are more indicative of the tension and anxiety that accompany hard choices.”
187
Our inter
-
actions with gender politics are complex, often constituted by tension and conflict, rather than
coercion or force. We survive patriarchy “sometimes resisting, sometimes acquiescing, some-
187
Abrams, “Ideology and Women’s Choices,” 781.
!140
times knowing, sometimes deceiving” ourselves.
188
People deserve the benefit of the doubt that
their actions are more than knee-jerk reactions, even if this may not always be the case.
Ideological determination arguments may also be particularly unpalatable for women
who “have understood, or resisted, the pull of ideological influences.”
189
For someone who has
gone through consciousness raising practices, worked towards developing sensitivities to struc-
tures and manifestations of oppression, and otherwise developing a critical consciousness, it is
demeaning and belittling to be treated like a stagnant cog in a machine. Being viewed this way
may also keep women from becoming empowered in situations where exerting agency is particu-
larly important. Abram argues that ideological determinism may “cast doubt on women’s capaci-
ty for choice in contexts in which such doubts may be particularly costly; and they may, by pre-
senting women's choices as determined by one socially diffuse influence, impede remedial in-
quiry into the complex array of factors that shape women’s choices.”
190
If we accept that power
is dynamic, always adjusting and shifting in subtle ways, it does not seem appropriate to support
a theory that does not have space for women to operate reflectively.
Which is not to say that ideological determinism does not allow for a way out under any
circumstance, but rather that it makes the chances of transformation so rare as to become almost
nonexistent. MacKinnon, who fairly or not has become the poster child for this sort of position,
Does not rule out the possibility that an individual woman may
find herself within a crack in the system of gender inequality — a
rare experience which may transform her “choices” into choices
and make her “consensual” sex consensual — yet this is rarely the
way she responds to women’s reports of such experiences. She is
188
189
Matsuda, “Pragmatism Modified,” 1767.
Abrams 762
190
Ibid.
!141
more likely to ask, for example, whether lesbians who engage in
forms of behavior that resemble heterosexual relations “express the
male supremacist structure or subvert it” or to suggest that those
people, including women, who report consensual sex, want to be-
lieve they already have this more than they want to have it.
191
This type of totalizing account is unrealistic, and presents an overly simplistic portrayal of how
power organizes and informs action. It is also a decidedly top-down approach, not recognizing
the ways in which people may adjust or subvert power structures through meaning-making,
world-building, and other creative endeavors. And it re-emphasizes the bias mentioned previous-
ly — a prejudice towards theorists’ perceptions of women’s actions over women’s own articula-
tion of their experiences.
Gill and Donaghue argue that there exists a general “fatigue with what [are] understood
as totalizing feminist accounts in which women were always depicted as victims.”
192
This is con
-
sistent with the position I have advanced throughout this project. As Matsuda asks, “If woman is
defined as a victim, how will she be anything but that?”
193
Accounts that overemphasize victim
-
hood artificially restrict other stories that we can tell about women. And they place an unneces-
sary burden on women to prove that they aren't merely victims, forcing them to implicitly accept
a powerless status as a starting point. Personally, I admit that it is exhausting to be continually
reminded of how much of a victim I am by people who are supposedly my allies. Which is not to
say that I deny the strategic value of identifying as a victim in certain circumstances, but it is
something that I would rather self-identify as than be forced into.
191
Ibid. 765
192
Gill and Donaghue, “As if postfeminism had come true.”
193
Matsuda, ‘Pragmatism Modified,” 1775.
!142
4. e. Makes women shoulder the burden of their own oppression
And finally, it is arguable that false consciousness makes women shoulder the burden of
their own oppression by over-emphasizing “the limited role of women in perpetuating a system
of gender inequality that they did not create.”
194
Perhaps there is some strategic advantage to
turning our gaze inwards, and reflecting on how we participate in the very structures that cause
us harm. After all, how can we expect change if we ourselves are still beholden to the systems we
want to dismantle? And yet, to posit this as the most important step may place an undue burden
on an already subjugated population. It is akin to saying, “Here is this problem that you didn't
ask for, now figure out how to fix it and start with yourself.” We ought to consider how this push
to focus on one’s complicity may at times distract from the project of liberation itself, for if all of
our energy and attention is spent inwards, it is unclear what will be left over to change our world.
That being said, false consciousness is hardly a stand-alone theory, and is most common-
ly presented along with other feminist accounts in order to present a more complete picture of
how patriarchy functions. There is certainly benefit to this type of work, but we should be honest
and reflective about what the benefit is and what its limits are. Being able to articulate how
women participate in sexist structures is a necessary part of dismantling these systems of oppres-
sion, insofar as our participation further cements the states of affairs that harm us. Acknowledg-
ing the part we play is therefore important, especially if we maintain a sense of responsibility to
other women and our shared situation. This is particularly important for white women, whose
status is enabled by the further exploitation of women of color. Whiteness becomes a way for
white women to benefit from a patriarchal system, and therefore become particularly complicit in
194
Abrams, “Ideology and Women’s Choices,” 783.
!143
systems that oppress women as a whole. All this to say that of course false consciousness theory
has a place at the table. The question is, how much space should it take up? How much of our
attention should it receive? How effective is the concept of false consciousness at dismantling
patriarchy? What might it cover up, and what might it overemphasize? We ought to be careful
that our theory does not over-burden the very people it aims to liberate.
5. Structural vs. Personal
I want to now turn our focus to agency as it is not only a vital part of any type of liberato-
ry politics, it is also a point of contestation amongst feminist critics. Agency comes up often in
discussion about false consciousness because it seems to be the natural counterpoint to ideologi-
cal determinism. We are either free or we are determined; we can either act or we are acted upon.
Agency is also important in any discussion about oppression, because it is a vital mechanism for
altering the world in which we live: “The very possibility of social transformation of gender rela-
tions depends upon [agency]: in order to change the world we must act.”
195
One result of the debate about false consciousness and agency that I find particu-
larly interesting (and dangerous) is the emphasized dichotomy between structural and personal.
On the one hand, false consciousness as a theory would seem to support an understanding of
women as existing within structures, and being determined, to greater or lesser extents, by the
overarching social system in which they exist. This position has routinely been critiqued by turn-
ing to individualism and the ideal of personal empowerment. The tension between individual vs.
structural deserves our attention because it is foundational to the controversy surrounding false
consciousness and claims that women work against their own interests when their actions are
195
Gill and Donaghue, “As if Postfeminism had come true.”
!144
seemingly the products of a patriarchal system. Critiques and defenses often swing between the
two, setting them up as binaries that we cannot think around. While this juxtaposition is impor-
tant for illustrating how power influences us, it can also be misleading.
This negotiation between personal and structural is one that I personally come up against
in this project, for I am deeply invested in the idea that I have personal agency and some type of
autonomy, even if it is circumscribed by my responsibilities to others, and that I can use my in-
telligence and creativity to influence the world around me, and begin a shift in power. Some will
be uncomfortable with the emphasis that I place on individual agency, even if they share my
larger goal. I admittedly have fairly liberal convictions of what the good life consists of, and I
think these convictions are well placed. For instance, I believe in the importance of agency and
autonomy, especially within a context like sexualization, because it so often manifests as a denial
of my ability to choose for myself, to author my own experience and to testify. I also believe that
the underlying assumptions of individual agency do not restrict or foreclose the possibility of
supporting the liberation of others or having a more community oriented vision of liberation. Af-
ter all, I am both a subject, and an inter-subject, and I don’t necessarily need to privilege one
over the other in the grand scheme of things, although I think it is only natural that I sometimes
hone in on one depending on the type of experience I am exploring.
However, I do recognize that an over-dependency on these individualistic phenomena can
lead to theorizing that is too isolated to be effective. I want to avoid some common pitfalls, par-
ticularly those concerning certain forms of liberal feminism, by which I refer to feminist politics
that emphasize individualism, personal agency and autonomy at the exclusion of more collective
goods. Agency that is highly individualistic in this way can overlook collective struggles in favor
!145
of focusing on personal acts. And with such a narrow focus on the individual, this type of femi-
nism makes it easier to justify what might otherwise be controversial acts, while simultaneously
ignoring collective responsibility. This is often done by bracketing social context, as context in-
evitably complicates the significance of a particular act, and therefore emphasizing the value of a
woman’s choice rather than on “creating the conditions of possibility for all women to enjoy
safe, consensual and pleasurable sex.”
196
A common refrain goes something along the lines of “if its my choice, then its a feminist
choice,” highlighting the prioritization of personal agency above all else. And, to a certain extent,
the idea that “the point of feminism is that I, as a woman, get to choose for myself” is something
I agree with, insofar as feminism exists in part to break down the strictures of oppressive gender
roles, so that women are actually able to make choices for themselves. Only think of the pro-
abortion refrain: “my body, my choice,” or even the types of rules that exist about what women
can say, what they can wear, how they should speak, when they should speak, what professions
they should pursue, etc. In this vein, a liberal feminist might support a woman who strips on the
basis that women have the freedom to exploit their bodies to their own advantage, while some-
one like MacKinnon would probably see the same woman as perpetuating oppressive sexual
norms and the general subjugation of women as a class. As far as I am concerned, both of these
arguments are valid. We can’t ignore that strip clubs are, in many ways, a subjugating space for
women, where they sell the promise of sex to men who are literally able to control them with
money. And yet, I will never disparage a woman for using that which it is at their disposal, even
if it is her body. And I believe friends of mine who strip when they tell me that they have found
196
Gill, “Media,” 743.
!146
ways of becoming empowered in this type of work. So how do we negotiate between these two
positions? I think we ought to attend to women’s testimony, take seriously their claims of em-
powerment, and ask ourselves who bears the burden of responsibility for these sexist structures.
In this project, I have been interested in using personal testimony as a starting point for
investigating how a focus on agency, particularly in a context of sexualization, can be challenged
by proponents of false consciousness, and how we might reformulate the central arguments so
that we are not beholden to some of the inherent weaknesses of certain versions of liberalism,
197
particularly its potential to focus on the individual at the exclusion of the community. This is par-
ticularly pertinent in discussions on sexualization, an issue which has garnered so much attention
(in the form of anxiety and concern) that it has become a discursive space in which agency has
become a preeminent topic of concern. There is a tremendous amount at stake in these discus-
sions, as we decide what meaning will reign supreme, which interpretation will get more trac-
tion, and who will be able to define what it means to exist in a way that aligns with feminist poli-
tics. It is why I advocate for a kinder and more fluid sexual politics that is vital for the success of
feminist politics writ large. This will mean recognizing that there is no right way to be a woman,
and that while we may recognize that there are practices that perpetuate harms, it is not always
obvious how much of a burden rests on an individual woman’s shoulders to do or be otherwise.
Of course, this does not mean that women are not accountable to one another, and that we cannot
make demands of particular women. Rather, we ought to be circumspect when issuing charges,
like those of false consciousness, which can overestimate the responsibility of any single indi-
vidual, as well as the legitimacy of our censure.
I find it worth noting that ‘liberalism’ covers a wide range of political theory, and should not be rejected whole
197
sale.
-
!147
It is vitally important to articulate agency in a way that is more than simply rhetoric, in
order to recapture it from illicit usages that undermine what agency really stands for in these dis-
cussions. It is too important; there is too much at stake in the idea of my ability to think and act,
in spite of and within forces that are larger than me. Forces that organize both my thoughts and
actions but are not conclusive of my possibilities. I resist attempts to trivialize talk of agency, to
turn it into something shallow, a tool of the privileged to justify their choices. This discussion is
difficult for me, because it threatens things that are vital to my understanding of myself, to the
strategies that I have developed to survive and flourish in this world. It holds up my hopes to a
light that shines through and reveals the weaknesses inherent in the assumptions that I have
about my freedom, and the autonomy I take for granted, that I emphasize in order to feel more
powerful. Power matters when you are made powerless, and it is no wonder that some feminists
find ways to read power in moments that might otherwise be overlooked. I empathize with these
intentions, and yet I cannot ignore the force of critiques that argue that to call anything agency, to
read power in any act, no matter how small, can create an account of power that is not radical
enough to create change — that adds to the mortar between the bricks of sexism rather than
wearing it away. It can in effect create an account of agency that has no content, because it has
no limitations.
5. b. The problem with empowerment
As Gill argues, many activities that are seen as controversial can be defended, or even
celebrated, because they can be described as ‘empowering’
198
— usually by emphasizing person
-
al feelings of empowerment i.e., “Doing X makes me feel strong/powerful/good.” The problem
198
Gill, “Media,” 736.
!148
with empowerment as a justification for any given act taking on feminist meaning is that the lan-
guage of empowerment can trivialize systematic accounts of oppression. At its most insidious,
“empowerment is regarded merely as a cynical rhetoric, wrapping sexual objectification in a
shiny, feisty, post-feminist packaging that obscures the continued underlying sexism.”
199
As the
language of empowerment has been co-opted by mainstream culture, and especially consumerist
capitalism, it also runs the risk of been stripped of its subversive potential, to the extent to which
it can in fact actively contradict the purpose of empowering by adding additional (and unneces-
sary) demands for women to meet, i.e. that women need to be sexually adventurous, or that sexu-
al empowerment must conform to a very particular set of physical manifestations, to be con-
sumed by the public. When women are called on to perform their sexualities in specific ways,
they are again placed in a position of being told how to develop erotic identities, rather than be-
ing able to choose for themselves. This is exactly the opposite of what I hope for in advocating
for more fluid accounts of sexuality, that do not force women to participate in sexual politics in
any specific way, but that also do not punish women for participating in those particular ways
either.
I believe in the importance of rescuing empowerment from hegemonic cooptation be-
cause I have tasted the bitter, acrid taste of powerlessness — and worse than powerlessness, the
sting of disempowerment — of having my power wrested from me in order to turn me into
something less than human. And, akin to the picture I drew in chapter 1, I have learned to replace
moments of powerlessness with feelings of empowerment through a variety of strategies.
Though no strategy is foolproof, they are still tools in my toolbox, so to speak, that I will hang on
199
Ibid. 737
!149
to until I come across something better. One of those tools has been to alter my own interpreta-
tion of my actions, to see the things I do in new ways in order to find new meaning. And since
my disempowerment, because of who I am, centers in many ways around sexuality, I am preoc-
cupied with the conditions of sexual empowerment. This sometimes means, as Gill argues,
“opening up questions about what constitutes sexual empowerment, who has the right to decide
this, and, significantly, the nature of the relationship between subjective feelings of empower-
ment, and actually being empowered.”
200
I find this to be a particularly worthy inquiry because
there are many conflicting accounts of sexual empowerment, from ‘anything I choose to do is
empowering,’ to ‘no heterosexual activity can be empowering.’ Both of these extremes distract
us from exploring the space in between.
A common refrain is that feelings of empowerment do not empowerment make. In other
words, it is not enough that I feel empowered, if that feeling does not accurately reflect a state of
affairs in which I have actually taken on power that I previously did not have. Yet again, we enter
into the murky territory of interpretation, and attempt to anchor our actions to objective truths in
order to prove that something has shifted, that there has been a legitimate change in the alloca-
tion of power. The fin of false consciousness rises above the waters, as we learn to develop a
healthy skepticism of claims of empowerment. It is in this way that we encounter arguments like
the following: “Although they feel empowered, their sense of power is, in fact, a false con-
sciousness marketed to them by a sexualized advertising culture.”
201
These type of arguments
persist in portraying women as dupes, manipulated into desiring the very things that keep them
200
Ibid.
201
Ibid.
!150
oppressed. It also justifies a continued skepticism towards women’s own accounts of their ac-
tions and motivations, and gives the viewer the moral and epistemological high ground.
The issue at stake here is deciding how we are to interpret women’s actions as sexual
agents. When women act in ways that seem in accordance with hegemonic norms of female sex-
uality, does that relegate them to nothing more than the status of cultural dupe? While this line of
thinking makes little sense to me when accounting for the complexity of both women’s decision
making processes, as well as the sexual landscape, it is evident that I must defend against these
types of charges if I want to maintain the legitimacy of sexual agency within an oppressive sexu-
al landscape. Which is why I will state again that resemblance is not the same thing as culpabili-
ty, and discomfort is not license for dismissal. It is inappropriate to create additional require-
ments that women have to meet in order to account for the semblance of domination in their
choices.
All too often, we are faced with questions like Calogero’s: “Does compliance with the
system and the garnering of rewards for doing so constitute empowerment?”
202
This, of course,
assumes multiple things, including that women who behave in ways that fit hegemonic standards
are “complying” (where complying means to act in accordance to a wish or demand) for the sake
of complying rather than doing so for other strategic reasons. As we saw in previous chapters,
things are not always as they appear, including women’s motivations for their actions. Second, it
assumes that the rewards for complying are granted externally, the implication of course being,
by men. However, as we saw with the femme fatale, male approval may only be tangentially re-
Calogero, Rachel M. On objects and actions: Situating self-objectification in a system justification context. In:
202
Gervais, Sarah J., ed. Objectification and (De)Humanization: 60th Nebraska Symposium on Motivation. University
of Nebraska Press, 2013: 109.
!151
lated to a specific act. And finally, it assumes that empowerment is nothing more than receiving
the gratification of having behaved as one should, which in this case would be according to fem-
inine standards of desirability. Again, the problem with this is that it presents an unnecessarily
narrow view of the concepts that are pertinent to this discussion. Empowerment should not be
framed within the restrictive lens of hegemonic norms, especially considering that many of these
norms have been crafted with the intent of limiting access to power.
If we accept such a narrow view of sexual politics, then we find ourselves formulating
accounts of existential eroticism that portray women as short-sighted, misguided, and sub-
servient, leaving us with arguments like the following:
Clearly some women feel quite powerful by “controlling” or
“choosing” their sexualized appearance to capture the attention of
men. Yet, there is reason to be skeptical of the empowerment ve-
neer. First, the fact that some women report pleasure through their
own bodily objectification is not surprising when we consider that
the objectified lens through which they come to view themselves
emphasizes their value to men as sex objects. When their appear-
ance elicits attention and approval from men, many women view it
as flattering or validating, and therefore advantageous to them-
selves and their in-group and prefer to interact more with men who
sexually objectified.
203
The above account is too restrictive to be fair. First, it assumes that garnering male attention and
approval is the end goal of sexualized appearance. It also assumes that women can only get plea-
sure from emphasizing their materiality through the male gaze. And it implies that said male gaze
is the dominant lens through which women can view their bodies. It assumes that male attention
and approval is unconditionally desirable to women, and that it is both flattering and validating. I
will not attempt to speak for all women; mind reading is beyond my training, no matter how il-
203
Ibid. 108-9.
!152
lustrious academic philosophy is, and without engaging them in respectful and unscripted dia-
logue, I can hardly claim to know the truth of women’s motivations and goals. However, I am
privy to my own mind, and can confidently say that this interpretation does not do justice to the
complexity and tension that is endemic to my sexual performances. Nor does it account for my
motivations for choosing a sexualized appearance, or adequately capture my pleasure at eliciting
attention.
Of course, this does not necessarily relieve the issue of empowerment as an individual-
ized phenomenon, especially when the term is used indiscriminately without relating analytically
to issues of power, inequality, or oppression.
204
When empowerment appears as such a dislocat
-
ed, individualized, and atomized experience,
205
it presents challenges to feminist goals of dis
-
mantling systems of oppression because there is a disconnect between the personal and the polit-
ical. This disconnect can manifest in the creation of “insecure positions of power for some
women and prevents other women from ever gaining access at all.”
206
In other words, women’s
choices to feel empowered may be taking advantage of oppressive structures to profit momentar-
ily, if not long term.
This harkens back to the description of adaptive preferences, where ‘empowerment’ can
be used as a rhetorical device to justify making adaptive preferences (preferences adapted to an
oppressive context), without having to pass a critical glance at what kind of power is available
through a given (and assumedly sexist) act. It also focuses so intently on the individual that dis-
cussions of social intersubjectivity and relationality are not even broached. But this does bring to
204
Gill, “Media,” 741.
205
Ibid.
206
Calogero, On objects and actions, 109.
!153
light an important tension between individual women maneuvering to make the most of their
own lives, and the overarching goal of empowering women collectively. This is a tension that I
don't necessarily have an answer to, other than to say that it seems prudent to encourage women
to find ways in which to empower themselves on a regular basis, without assuming that their do-
ing so will harm women more generally. We must be sensitive to the need for women to feel like
they have influence over their lives, that they are capable of making moves that allow them to
create a life in which they can flourish as individuals.
Does this resolve any and all fears that the source of power can be necessarily corrupt?
Probably not to the satisfaction of someone beholden to ideological determinism, who might ask
something along the lines of “If women's outcomes are dependent on men's responses to their
appearance and sexual appeal, then do women actually hold the power?”
207
Again, we find our
-
selves looking for reductive answers for incredibly complicated situations. Although one might
argue that outcome dependency on men does not empower women collectively, it is still unclear
that women’s outcomes are actually entirely dependent on men’s responses in the way that we
generally assume. Of course, I can hardly argue that there are no questions raised by the use of
self-objectifying behaviors — behaviors that seem to enact exactly what women are “supposed
to do” or how they have been trained to behave. Not only do we get trained on how to act in a
way that bolsters patriarchal politics, our very expressions of femininity are conditioned to
soothe and please the construct that is masculinity. I’m supposed to wear short skirts and high
heels because they hamper my movements and make me easier to catch. I’m supposed to shave
my legs and my pussy so they resemble a prepubescent girl’s, and grow my hair out so it is un-
207
Ibid.
!154
necessarily and impractically long to attract attention to my “feminine” features. And since I
have large breasts and wide hips, I’m supposed to feature those assets without flaunting them
disgracefully, so that I both reveal and conceal at the same time. I am charged with both leaving
a little something to the (male) imagination while also taking on the responsibility of garnering
that attention in the first place. I have to smile and laugh, although not too loud or too openly,
and look appropriately interested in whatever man is talking at me.
It is true that there are so many ways in which my daily life is directed by male approval.
This is just what it means to be a girl in the world. So consciously or not, I have learned how to
get that approval. But just because I’m able to do so, does not mean that I always do, or that I do
so with the most obvious of intentions. In other words, that knowledge that allows me to curry
approval also provides me the opportunity to manipulate. When you learn the rules of the game,
then you can use them to your advantage, possible with the result of changing the game itself.
All this to say, often our worry about whether or not some given choice is acceptable is
maybe not the most appropriate use of our energy. It neither is or isn't acceptable purely based on
the action itself. Context matters. And it is too easy to come up with alternative accounts for any
given choice. Which again, brings us to a point at which we must choose which account we grant
greater epistemic value. Like with the femme fatale, we have a choice to make in how we portray
women. Are they dupes or heroines, objects or agents, cogs or wrenches? Well, to be perfectly
honest, women are neither, or perhaps they are all of the above. Which is to say, it’s complicated,
and at any time, all can be the case. These worries are ultimately a distraction as we spend more
time trying to either undercut or justify individual actions, and we forget that the issues at stake
are much larger.
!155
This is why I find arguments about false consciousness that center on self-sexualization,
dress choice and sexual behavior to be particularly frustrating. Too much attention is paid to
things that, while perhaps not trivial, are also not the linchpins of gender hierarchy. I believe that
the preeminent focus “on embodies practices such a wearing high heels, painting finger nails,
and participating enthusiastically in sexualized culture,”
208
serves more to constrain women, and
usher them into a cycle of shame and self-blame, than actively work against systematic gender
oppression.
Without denying the need for critical consciousness about these phenomena, I believe
that certain manifestations of patriarchal culture need not be seen as wholly negative, or evidence
of the victimization of women. Perhaps we would be better off admitting that some of the choic-
es we hone in on and invest with value are not that important. Or perhaps it is fairer to say that
they can have multiple meanings and we need not oversimplify. Rather than spend time articulat-
ing the reasons why women should not wear lipstick, wouldn’t our energy be better used to cre-
ate a world where it doesn't matter if a woman wears lipstick or not? This would seem to me to
be an ultimate goal of feminist praxis.
6. Conclusion
Facing the demands of radical feminist theory is not always simple or clear. I often find
myself wondering what aspects of myself I will have to change to appear/qualify as feminist
enough, to garner the support and defense of my peers. Of course, it is expected that our politics
will ask us to change ourselves at times. And liberation is an ongoing activity, with both external
and internal focuses. But all changes are not equal, or necessary. Which is why I urge caution in
208
Gill and Donaghue, “As if postfeminism had come true.”
!156
declaring the ways in which women must change themselves to exist legitimately, or so that they
do not take on the appearances of complicity with harmful hegemonic norms. I worry that this
train of thought leads to apathy towards certain women’s suffering, because they are viewed as
undeserving of support.
If the intent of feminist theory is liberation, it should not further justify the dehumaniza-
tion of women — by dehumanization I mean the implication that women cannot think for them-
selves, that they are easily misled and fooled, that they are uncritical. This type of thinking fol-
lows a long tradition of sexist theories of mind that posit women as non-rational, lesser than men
specifically because of their lack of capacity to think. This has been used to dehumanize women
for centuries, if not millennia, and we should be suspicious of theories, even/especially those
purported to help women, that perpetuate sexist stereotypes that have been used to justify the
subordination of women.
False consciousness can easily become another justification for demeaning women for
sexualizing themselves, or even for being sexualized in the first place. If we are not cautious in
our deployment of false consciousness, we can make women responsible for their own victimiza-
tion by claiming that they are acting in concert with patriarchal ideology, rather than allowing
that women may navigate oppressive structures in ways that are more nuanced and complicated
than simply being cultural dupes. Let those of us invested in feminist politics avoid overlooking
the resilience, negotiation, creativity, struggle that are daily occurrences in the lives of women.
!157
Conclusion
Feminism is an act of critique — it points out the ways in which our current state of affairs
is flawed. Feminism is also creative — it imagines new possibilities of how things could be. This
dissertation is an attempt to hone in on the creative potential of feminist philosophy by articulat-
ing the capacities we already have for building a world in which an endless spectrum of women
can thrive. Of course, I have focused specifically on highly-sexualized women, because it is a
state of affairs that speaks to my experiences, hopes and frustrations, and that I am therefore par-
ticularly interested in on a theoretical level. The limitations of this project are self-evident — this
is a partial account of femininity and womanhood, a taste of a bigger picture. I believe it is a
taste that speaks to larger structures of sexism and eroticism, and has value beyond just being an
account of myself. That being said, I have no intention of advocating that all women encounter
the world in the ways I do, but rather hope that we can open up our concepts to allow for more
fluid and flexible accounts of sexual politics and erotic identities; e.g. for accounts that build a
sense of eroticism that is open to innovation, playfulness and difference. There will be ways of
understanding eroticism and sexual performances that are not included in this account, and peo-
ple who are not represented therein. I will push for these alternative conceptualizations to be tak-
en seriously, the same way I advocate for my own.
Eroticism deserves critical attention because it so deeply impacts our interpersonal rela-
tionships as well as our broader social fabric. I encourage an understanding of the erotic that is
destigmatizing, so that more women will become comfortable with attending to the erotic in their
lives. Women deserve the opportunity to understand their erotic identities in ways that do not
force them deeper into cycles of shame and unhappiness, as is commonplace within our sexist
!158
social structures. It is past the time to address the ways in which eroticism has been, and contin-
ues to be, used as a mechanism of oppression. I hope that I have offered a glimpse into how this
may be the case, by showcasing why loosening our understanding of sexuality is an important
step in liberation. By this I mean that the wider our range of sexual performances becomes, the
more inclusive and open to difference we can be.
In many ways, this project has outlined my own personal politics, and the ways in which I
live my life. It has been developed over years of anger and frustration, love and joy, and trial and
error as I have attempted to construct an understanding of myself as an erotic subject that is both
empowering and honest. While there will always remain domains in which we are implicated in
certain structures of privilege and oppression, this reality does not mean it is unacceptable to be
an unapologetic sexual subject. In fact, the very idea that we have to apologize for our existence
as erotic beings shows the extent to which we allow these aspects of our lives to be vilified.
There is little logic to this type of vilification, other than to condone the types of violence that
women face as sexualized subjects.
By delving deep into the sexual landscape, I have attempted to articulate sexual phenomena
that are ubiquitous, and yet under-acknowledged. We cannot address issues that affect many
women’s lives if we are unwilling to spend the time and energy to settle into the themes taken up
in this project. It was my goal to open up the space to really consider what it means to be sexual-
ized, what it means to develop an erotic identity, and why someone might develop such an identi-
ty both for practical purposes, but also to live a fuller life. I have attempted to push back against
narratives of victimization, while also acknowledging the power of legacy, in order to create
more potent opportunities for the erotic to have positive potential in our lives.
!159
This dissertation is merely the start of a broader conversation about the power of the pussy,
about the dynamics of desire, and the stories we tell to make sense of sexual politics. There is so
much more to think about, and so many more directions in which this project can go. As a project
born of personal necessity, there are inherent limits to this discussion insofar as I am situated in
the world in a very specific way. I believe this creates an opportunity for different women (and
men) to take up the charge of engaging with liberatory sexual politics in ways that are cus-
tomized to their own situation, and speak to their own identities. And it need not take my experi-
ences as the basis for their own, but rather take up my intention in a way that creates possibilities
for their own lives. And if those other narratives contradict my own, I will be attentive to the ar-
eas of tension, and offer myself the opportunity to learn something new. This project is not meant
to circumscribe how individuals ought to go about the process of sexual liberation, but rather to
present an account of how I have formulated what a liberatory sexual politics might look like, in
order to provide a starting point for further discussion.
Given the time to expand this project myself, there are many topics that I would be inter-
ested in including. I believe that the phenomenon of rape fantasies, and the eroticization of pow-
er implied by these sexual narratives, is a potent example of creativity, playfulness, and the limits
of false consciousness as an explanatory mechanism. I am also deeply interested in the produc-
tion of pleasure through erotic literature, a field that is overwhelmingly dominated by women,
and overwhelmingly geared towards women. Both of these topics represent everyday engage-
ments with sexual politics in ways that are intimate, but also speak to common misconceptions
about how women, in particular, understand themselves as pleasure-seeking subjects.
!160
And so, as I wrap up this chapter of my life and prepare to exit the academy and go out into
the ‘real’ world, I find myself wondering how this will be received. I hope that, at the very least,
this project will offer an opportunity for critical reflection on the ways in which we all engage in
sexual politics, and the narratives that we hold on to when interpreting women’s actions as sexual
subjects. I know that people will take issue with not just my claims, but my presuppositions, and
the framing of my project. I recognize that I depend on certain concepts that are the subjects of
philosophical debates like a dependence on individual empowerment, autonomy, and personal
choice. I have done my best to be aware of the potential pitfalls of these positions, and yet I do
find them useful enough to warrant engagement with. I am, after all, a product of my own lan-
guage games, and fixate on certain aspects of freedom and pleasure that are particularly evident
to me, but may not be so evident to others. I say all this simply to acknowledge that I have much
to learn if I want to work in concert with others for the sake of creating a safer and more pleasur-
able world.
That being said, I believe that a strategic focus on individual agency is cohesive with a
larger focus of shifting power relations, which is by necessity a communal project. If we take
what I have created here as one patch in a quilt, then it becomes less of an individualistic narra-
tive, and more of a single thread in a tapestry of coalition (to mix metaphors). The tapestry is
large enough to allow for economic, cultural, social and political difference, for conflict and dis-
sension.
!161
WORKS CITED
!162
WORKS CITED
Abrams, Kathryn. “Ideology and Women’s Choices.” 24 Ga. L. Rev. (1989): 761-801.
Bartky, Sandra Lee. "Toward A Phenomenology Of Feminist Consciousness.” Social Theory and
Practice 3, no. 4 (1975): 425-39. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23557163.
Boozer, Jack. “The Lethal Femme Fatale in the Noir Tradition.” Journal of Film and Video. Vol.
51, No. 3/4 (1999): 20-35.
Bronfen, Elisabeth. "Femme Fatale — Negotiations of Tragic Desire." New Literary History 35,
no. 1 (2004): 103-116.
Calogero, Rachel M. On objects and actions: Situating self-objectification in a system justifica-
tion context. In: Gervais, Sarah J., ed. Objectification and (De)Humanization: 60th Nebraska
Symposium on Motivation. University of Nebraska Press, 2013: 97-126.
Coy, Maddy & Garner, Maria. “Glamour modelling and the marketing of self-sexualization: Crit-
ical reflections.” International Journal of Cultural Studies. 13. (2010): 657-675.
Davidson, Joyce, and Mick Smith. "Wittgenstein and Irigaray: Gender and Philosophy in a Lan-
guage (Game) of Difference." Hypatia 14, no. 2 (1999): 72-96.
Double Indemnity. Directed by Billy Wilder. Paramount Pictures, 1944.
Eyerman, Ron. "False Consciousness and Ideology in Marxist Theory." Acta Sociologica 24, no.
1/2 (1981): 43-56.
Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality. OKS Print. New York: Pantheon Books, 1978.
Gill, Rosalind. "Media, Empowerment and the 'Sexualization of Culture' Debates." Sex
Roles 66.11-12 (2012): 736-45.
Gill, Rosalind and Ngaire Donaghue. “As if Postfeminism Had Come True: The Turn to Agency
in Cultural Studies of ‘Sexualisation’.” In: Madhok S., Phillips A., Wilson K. (eds) Gender,
Agency, and Coercion. Thinking Gender in Transnational Times. Palgrave Macmillan: London,
(2013).
Heyes, Cressida J. “Pictures of the Self: Wittgenstein and Foucault on Thinking Ourselves Dif-
ferently,” in Self-Transformations: Foucault, Ethics, and Normalized Bodies. Oxford University
Press, 2007.
!163
Hill Collins, Patricia. Black Sexual Politics : African Americans, Gender, and the New Racism.
New York :Routledge, 2005.
Jankowiak ,William and Angela Ramsey. “Femme fatale and status fatale: a cross-cultural per-
spective.” Cross-Cultural Research Vol 34, Issue 1. (2000).
Langton, Rae and Caroline West. “Scorekeeping in a Pornographic Language Game,” Aus-
tralasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol 77, No 3. (1999): 303–319.
Leader-Elliott, Ian, and Ngaire Naffine. “Wittgenstein, Rape Law and the Language Games of
Consent.” Monash University Law Review 26 (2000): 48–71.
Levinas, Emmanuel. “Phenomenology of Eros.” In: Totality and Infinity. Martinus Nijhoff Phi-
losophy Texts, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht, 1991.
Lindemann, Hilde. “Wittgenstein Meets ‘Woman’ in the Language-Game of Theorizing Femi-
nism.” In Feminist Interpretations of Wittgenstein. Ed. Naomi Scheman and Peg O’Connell.
University Park: Penn State Press, 2002.
Lindsey, Treva B. “Complicated crossroads: black feminisms, sex positivism, and popular cul-
ture.” African and Black Diaspora: An International Journal, 6, 1 (2013): 55-65.
Lorde, Audre. “Uses of the Erotic,” in Sister Outsider. Brooklyn, N.Y.: Out & Out Book, 1978.
MacKinnon, Catharine A. "Feminism, Marxism, Method, and the State: An Agenda for Theory."
Signs 7, no. 3 (1982): 515-44.
MacKinnon, Catharine A. Toward a feminist theory of the state. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1989.
Matsuda, Mari J. “Pragmatism Modified and the False Consciousness Problem.” 63 S. Cal. L.
Rev. 1763 (1990).
Miller-Young, Mireille. A Taste For Brown Sugar: Black Women in Pornography. Duke Univer-
sity Press Books, 2014. Kindle Edition.
Morgan, Joan. “Why We Get Off: Moving Towards a Black Feminist Politics of Pleasure." The
Black Scholar 45, 4 (2015): 36-46.
Ridge, George Ross. "The "Femme Fatale" in French Decadence." The French Review 34, no. 4
(1961): 352-60.
!164
Sartre, Jean Paul. Being And Nothingness: An Essay In Phenomenological Ontology. Secaucus,
N.J. : Citadel Press, [1964], c1956.
Smith, David Woodruff. "Phenomenology." The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer
2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .
Tirrell, Lynne. "Storytelling and Moral Agency." The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48,
no. 2 (1990). Pg. 115.
Welch, Shay. Existential Eroticism: A Feminist Approach to Understanding Women's Oppres-
sion-Perpetuating Choices. Lexington Books, 2015: 227pp.
Wells, Shallyn. “Feminism, False Consciousness & Consent: A Third Way.” 18 Geo. J. Gender &
L. 251 (2017).
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, G. E. M. Anscombe, and G. H. von Wright. On Certainty. Oxford, UK:
Blackwell, 1972.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, and G. E. M. Anscombe. Philosophical investigations. Oxford, UK:
Blackwell, 1997.
!165