r |H|H|HIIWH| 'fi ‘ __ _— -, —_ .— LIBRARY Michigan Sm: U' . This is to certify that the thesis entitled TEMPORALITY AND REPRESENTATION: A STUDY IN PSYCHOLOGICAL SEMANTICS presented by Stuart L. Doneson has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for M— degree in M% 1 W Major professor Date @143 /J:/I/2Z/ 0-7639 ‘llllllllllllmlllllll “ ’ 00666 0645 0 0 L3. lit: 3 g“; 3994) TEMPORALITY AND REPRESENTATION: A STUDY IN PSYCHOLOGICAL SEMANTICS By Stuart L. Doneson A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Department of Psychology 1978 ABSTRACT TEMPORALITY AND REPRESENTATION: A STUDY IN PSYCHOLOGICAL SEMANTICS By Stuart L. Doneson This thesis presents a semantic approach to the problem of con- ceptualizing basic theoretical terms in psychology, in this case "temporality" and "representation". More specifically, a brief his- tory of the theoretical treatment of temporal experience pointed to the intimate connection between representation as cognitive structure and function, and temporality as a condition of articulated experience. The fate of this "intimate connection" in the course of psychological theorizing was traced by schematizing the basic dimensions of repre- sentation, viz., motivational, formal, modal, and temporal. This schema of basic distinctions was then used to successively isolate different aspects of representing, thereby raising questions concerning the temporalizing potentials of different modes of representation. With this background, the epilogue attempted to sketch a psychoanalytic action language approach to temporality, as well as to indicate the possibility of reconceptualizing the relations between primary and secondary processes as figurative and literal modes of representation. For Susan, Daniel and David. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to thank Dr. Albert Rabin for giving me the time and space I needed to follow the bent of my curiosity; Dr. Griffith Freed for his unflagging interest in my conceptual excursions; and Dr. Bertram Karon for sharing his points of view. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page INTRODUCTION ..................................................... 1 Statement of Purpose ........................................ l METAPSYCHOLOGICAL ORIENTATION: THE SEMANTICS 0F TEMPORALITY ...... 5 On the Temporal Organization of Experience .................. 7 Temporality and Representation .............................. 8 PSYCHOLOGICAL ORIENTATIONS ....................................... ll 0N MAJOR THEORIES 0F REPRESENTATION: WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO THE QUESTION OF MODE ................... l4 CONCEPTUAL REORIENTATIONS: THE SEMANTICS 0F REPRESENTATION ...... 19 ON THE TEMPORAL DIMENSION OF REPRESENTATION ...................... 27 SUMMARY .......................................................... 32 EPILOGUE- RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT ................................ 35 On the Temporal Structure of Action ......................... 4l On the Temporal Structure of Motives ........................ 42 On the Temporal Structure of the Formal and Modal Dimensions of Representation ............................. 46 Conclusion: The Representation of Representation ........... 49 FOOTNOTES ........................................................ 52 APPENDIX ........................................................ 53 BIBLIOGRAPHY ..................................................... 56 iv INTRODUCTION Statement of Purpose Like every inquiry, the psychological investigation of temporality and representation requires an orientation to the phenomenon in ques- tion, a way of talking about the subject matter that enables us to identify relevant instances and to organize them into a domain of actual and possible facts. These ways of talking are inextricably bound to the implicit or explicit terms and terminologies we employ. Consequently, our access to the phenomena that interest us is governed by the resources of the set of concepts and methods we use to take hold of them and which inform the questions we ask and the answers we seek and find acceptable. Thus, we proceed with the realization that there is no single way of pointing to what we're talking about when we speak of temporality or representation. Instead we are confronted by a chorus of different and competing voices, each claiming to organize and unify the deliverances of experience, and each providing a language to talk authoritatively about a selected range of facts. However, the existence of this basic ambiguity of psychological theorizing raises a set of questions which delineates a fundamental (and often neglected) task for psychologists, viz. the removal of the ambiguities which surround basic terms by l spelling out their relevant meanings and regions of application as these are developed by the semantic resources of a particular theory. (cf. Carnap, R. l950). By proceeding in this manner, "temporality" and "representation" become thgmg§_which hold the diverse theoretical voices together as so many variations. Moreover, such an approach to a psychological question is not empirical, but "pre-empirical". It asks the prior question about what we think with_when we inquire abgut_these things. Thus, we shall seek to elucidate these tools of inquiry by examining the scope and limits of the leading frameworks and languages that govern contemporary approaches to temporality and representation. The subject matter and meaning of statements about "temporality"-- what temporality is and what one discusses when one discusses it-- will be discovered by examining the terms in which the theories are stated. The ambiguity of statements made and the manifoldness of things des- ignated can be brought into coherence as they are arranged according to systematic principles. Consequently, the discussion of temporality begins with a history which traces the implications of deriving terms and principles from "things", from "thought", and from "language and action". With beginning points drawn from "things", discussions of time are physically and metaphysically oriented; with beginning points drawn from "thought", discussions of time are epistemologically orient- ed; with beginning points drawn from "language and action", discussions of time are symbolically and semiotically oriented. Intimately linked to the fate of "temporality", the treatment of "representation" moves though a similar sequence. In particular, the focus on the relation between representation a§_cognitive structure, and representation as symbolic vehicle, provides a way of mapping out the continuities and discontinuities of much contemporary theorizing in this area. Close attention to the shifts in the basic terms of the leading theories reveals the likenesses and differences in subject matter. Although the wgrg_"representation" remains the same,different te§m§_ pick out and focus upon different aspects. Inevitably, particular theories and families of theories select one set of facts out of all possible facts and one set of languages out of the many available. From this review of theories a four dimensional semantic schema was constructed (see Appendixll) as a device for specifying the terms and aspects taken as basic in approaching "representation? viz., motiva- tional, formal, modal, temporal. The schema was used to clarify the complicated relations between different theories and findings by demonstrating how the basic dimensions of representing are transformed in different theories. With the construction of the schema and the locating of temporality as a dimension of representation, the work of the main body of the essay drew to a close. The preliminary tasks of psychological semantics had been achieved: (1) By a kind of concep- tual housecleaning, order was restored to the chaotic chorus of theoretical voices; (2) By showing the relevant sense and the appro- priate region of their application, wherein the same ambiguous word is used by different theories to develop different solutions to diff- erent questions, the angry Babel of critical refutation and counter refutation was replaced by a pluralistic (not syncretistic or rela- tivistic!) conversation. In an extended Epilogue, an attempt was made to indicate the major conceptual impediments to a serious and whole-hearted approach to temporality. Not merely the reign of S-R psychology and behavior— istics, but the underlying committment to motion language, and ex- planations in terms of antecedent causes and elements, tend to obscure the role of temporality in the construction of wish, desire, intention, purpose, will, etc. Consequently, the epilogue attempts to situate in a preliminary way the dimensions of the semantic schema within a descriptive or "action language" (Schafer, l976) context with temporal terms taken as architechtonic of the schematism. In effect, this amounts to a reappraisal of psychoanalysis as the archeology and teleology of desire (cf. Ricouer, 1970). Consequently, the figure of the Janus-faced structure of representation as projected backward and forward in time is articulated. Finally, the epilogue sketches the need for an adequate theory of sublimation, and more fundamentally, of the relations between primary and secondary processes reconceptual- ized as the relations between analogical and univocal terms, between figurative and literal modes of representation. But this is another problem and the task for another inquiry, e.g., a dissertation on the role of literal and figurative modes of representation in the construc- tion of temporal perspectives. METAPSYCHOLOGICAL ORIENTATION: THE SEMANTICS OF TEMPORALITY] The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and fa- miliarity. (One is unable to notice something because it is always before one's eyes). -Wittgenstein- The history of psychology bears witness to an inveterate tendency to conceptualize psychological processes by means of spatialized terms and metaphors. Aviaries, telephone switchboards, computers--not to mention Freud's hydroelectric power plants, icebergs, and buried cities --are only more blatant instances of this ubiquitous habit of thought. Less graphic perhaps, but even more profoundly ramifying, is the in- evitable use of one or more of the following contraries in mapping out the structure and function of personality: "internal-external", "sur- face-depth", "boundary-core", "part-whole". Needless to say, these terms help mark off crucial distinctions, without which theory and practice would be greatly impoverished. It is precisely this massive theoretical importance--reflecting as it does the spatial conditions of life--that threatens to obscure, conceal, or distort the signifi- cance of time, of temporality in human experience. Indeed, psycholo- gists would be well advised to reflect on Kant's contention that while space is the form of our "outer experience", time is the form of our "inner experience" (Kant, l965). Developmentally, the differentiation of inside and outside is an event only equalled in importance by the differentiation of before and after. There is no minimizing the profound and vertiginous conceptual reorientation entailed by interpreting the organizing principles of psychological processes in terms of time; that "psychic structures", the "inner world", the "stream of thought", etc., are fundamentally temporal rather than spatial in nature. Indeed, the history of psych- ological theorizing may be productively viewed as the periodic rise and fall of the predominance of spatial versus temporal root metaphors. Thus, for the fourth century Greeks, the twelfth century Scholastics, and the seventeenth century Rationalists, thought was oriented meta- physically, i.e., things were taken as the measure of thought. Being was represented by a spatially visualized and ordered cosmos. As a result, time was viewed as transitory succession, mere becoming as opposed to permanent, eternal Being. The task of both theory and practice--of philosophy and religion--was to keep men attuned to eternal things. Treatises on psychology sharply distinguished between reason and imagination, one oriented to Being, the other to Becoming. For the Stoics and Epicureans, for St. Augustine in the fifth century, as well as for the great thinkers of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the skeptical and critical question of "how we know?" took precedence over "what?", and epistemology superceded metaphysics as the archetectonic discipline. It is no accident that many of the greatest psychologists appeared during these epochs. Not only Epictetus in Antiquity, and St. Augustine, but the emergence of psych- ology as a scientific discipline in the nineteenth century, bear wit- ness to the refocusing of inquiry from the modes of things and being to the modes of thought and the psychological conditions underlying knowing, doing and making. It is under this epistemological dispensation that the role of time in human psychology, (and correlatively, of history in human affairs at large), became manifest. No longer just objective, cosmic time--time as the general scheme of serial order and succession comprising all events--but the time of experience, of consciousness, of the human subject, became the locus of new questions and new dis- coveries. Theorizing about psychic time was gradually freed of dis- torting spatial analogies, (such as the image of a flowing river, or a line moving ineluctably from past to future through a succession of points existing one after the other), and was replaced by a psychologi- cal appreciation of the active relation between past, present, and future as grounded in the special distinction that the cognitive ca- pacities of memory and anticipation confer on human existence. On the Temporal Organization of Experience "Le present est chargé du passé, et gros de l'avenir" -Leibniz- It was St. Augustine who recognized that man lived and moved and had his being in time; that memory held the key to the structure of temporality--and therewith to the continuity of identity as the basis nu h ——w V'W‘v of selfhood (St. Augustine, 1962). More precisely, Augustine dis- tinguishes three actions of the mind: memory, attention, and an- ticipation; all of which exist as present actions. In this way, past, present and future co-exist in the present. The past is the present memory of the past; the present is present attention to the present; and the future is present anticipation of the future. What is novel about this approach is that it entails active relations between the temporal modes in codetermining the articulation of experience. By virtue of memory and anticipation our experience becomes connected; "before", "now", and "after" linked into the particular continuity of individual lives. From this perspective, memory and anticipation are viewed as active and pervasive mental operations which organize present experience by comparing it with what has been and with what might be. In the broad, ambiguous sense, these activities establish and link-- or by virtue of repression, fail to establish and link--past, present and future into an interpenetrating continuity which lays the founda- tion for the meaningful articulation of the experience of identity and reality, of the self and the object world. Temporality and Representation "All our knowledge is thus finally subject to time, the formal condition of inner sense... This is a general observation which, through- out what follows, must be borne in mind as being quite fundamental." -Kant, Critique of Pure Reason- As Rabin (Rabin, l976, p.3) has reminded us, "temporality, the conception of and awareness of the passage of time--past, present, and future--is a uniquely human characteristic which is closely re- lated to a series of complex psychological aspects of persons". The human capacity to transcend the present field of experience calls attention to the epistemologically fundamental act of representing - re present ing- experience. 0r put more strongly, the power of representation is constitutive of man's human way of being. Thus understood as the active process of making present-of re-presenting or recreating the presence of something absent, representation comes to light as "the common but to us unknown root" (Kant, l965) of human cognition. Indeed, recollection and anticipation presuppose the poss- ibility of distinguishing the present now from past or future "nows" while bringing them both simultaneously to awareness (cf. Wm. James, l950; Rabin, l974). Thus, the capacity to distinguish this now from others, i.e., the capacity to render or re-present a present in gen- eral--provides the principle for integrating experience. If we had no way of knowing that what we think is the same as what we thought before, we would be damned perpetually to Heracleitean purgatory in which we could not step in the same river twice--or even once!, for there would be no basis for referring to the river as the "same”. As Cassirer wisely notes: "Everything that we call the identity of concepts and significations, or the constancy of things and attri- butes is rooted in this fundamental act of finding again. Thus it is a common function which makes poss- ible on the one hand language and on the other hand the specific articulation of the intuitive world." (Cassirer, l957, p. ll4) 10 Presentation and representation-~the capacities to "have" pre- sent and absent objects--are basic to recollection and anticipation, the processes which make past and future present. 'Moreover, because it binds before, now, and after into the experience of ongoing duration rather than instantaneous present points, representation is inextricably involved with temporality. As an example, even the simplest perception presupposes a time spread by which the chair that I see is perceived as one chair "enduring" across several eyeblinks-- and which includes my own "enduring" as well. Thus, it is increasingly apparent that the capacity of representation to rise up and go beyond, to transcend, immediacy creates the possibility for the continuity o the object as well as the subject, for the epigenesis of self and object. The linking and ordering of "separate" perceptions, the maintenance of continuity which is termed "object constancy", is grounded in acts of representing the past and the future in relation to the present which make recollection and anticipation possible. A summary of this argument might be put as follows: the formal structure of representation presupposes temporality as an experiential time-field in which the differentiation of past, present, and future makes possible the concurrent appearance of subject and object en- during through change. PSYCHOLOGICAL ORIENTATIONS Thus far, the discussion of temporality has hinged on the re- alignment of theorizing made possible by those recurring revolutionary shifts in the history of thought away from the primacy of metaphysical categories to the primacy of episemological categories. Kant's “Copernican revolution" has been singled out as paradigmatic of this shift from the modes of things and being to the modes of thought and knowing. By virtue of this change of focus, the centrality of the psychological dimensions of time comes into view. After Kant, dis- cussions of time were no longer dominated by considerations of space and motion. Instead the human time of duration and temporality re- ceive vigorous attention in their own right. (Bergson and Proust are probably the premiere embodiments of this development). Consequently the codetermination of self and other, subject and object, was dis- cussed in terms of the essential temporalizing function--the creation of a time field--intrinsic to the act of representation. At this juncture we are once again confronted by a fundamental question. Just as metaphysics gave way to epistemology under the assault of the question "How do we know?"; the potential for spinning abstruse, autistic fantasies renders epistemological analysis vulner- able to the question "How do we know that we know?" This question, when taken seriously, results in a third and equally fundamental ll l2 realignment of the terms of inquiry. Instead of categories drawn from the modes of things and Being as in metaphysics, or from the modes of thought and knowing as in epistemology, this question marks the shift to the primacy of the categories of Expression, the modes of language and action. For speaking broadly and ambiguously, the answer to the question, “How do we know that we know?, is in terms of words and deeds. It is surely no accident that the twentieth century has witnessed the appearance of the architectonics of language and action. Consider the creation and veneration of such disciplines of language as: lin- guistics, general semantics, symbolic logic, ordinary language philosophy, communications, media studies, symbolic forms, "the new criticism", and psychoanalysis, "the talking cure"; as well as such disciplines of action as: pragmatism, Marxism, Existentialism, action painting, operationalism, behaviorism and behavior modification, the "action cure". Indeed, scientific experimentation itself, which makes possible the basis of objectivity in the consensual validation of trained observers-scientific communities--turns on the philosophical importance of the public visibility of language and action. In light of these considerations, the epistemologically oriented interpretation of representation and temporality remains merely formal unless complemented by a discussion of the vehicles or modes through which representation is expressed. For representation is only given as expression, as embodied or materialized in a specific modality. This fact cannot be overemphasized. In an important sense it marks the transition from metapsychology to psychology. The theoretical l3 skeleton that has been developed to understand the cognitive sig- nificance of temporal experience raises a new set of questions which cannot be solved by speculation and theory alone. Rather, an answer is required from nature via empirical investigation. Thus, even if representation is the mental activity that is presupposed in the con- struction of temporal orientation and perspective, (and the human psychological world in general), there remain open questions about the kinds of representations--or representational systems--that the organism has available for mediating these cognitive processes. Hence, claims about the character of internal representations are empirical in the sense that empirical data would tend toward confirmation or disconfirmation. That representation occupies the core of human mental life is a thesis acknowledged by most cognitive, developmental, and psycho- analytic theories. Yet the significance of this acknowledgement seems to be more honored in the breech than in the commission of detailed analysis of its implications. Thus, while representation is explicit or implicit in virtually every explanation advanced by these psych- ologists, the fact that representing presupposes a medium in which to represent is not always made explicit. Perhaps more seriously, the vital questions to which this assumption leads--e.g., what properties does a system 0f representations have?, in what ways do different media affect the process of representing?,--are rarely made explicit and taken as the focus of sustained research. ON THE MAJOR THEORIES OF REPRESENTATION : WITH SPECIAL REFERENCE TO THE QUESTION OF MODE In spite of the manifest differences in terminology, principles, and methods, there is a surprising formal similarity in the model of representation presupposed by many of the leading theories in the area. With certain notable exceptions to be discussed below, the major theo- retical approaches posit a two-tier structure of representation based on an underlying organization or coding process which may be manifested phenomenally, with varying degrees of distortion, by different media. Thus, in the psychoanalytic tradition, Beres and Joseph, (1970), dis- tinguish representation as "unconscious psychic organization" from such conscious derivativees as "symbol, image, fantasy, thought, affect or action" (1970, p.2). From the organismic-developmental per- spective, Werner and Kaplan (1964), treat representation in terms of the "intentional act of a human being and not in the material which is utilized qua vehicle" (1964, p.333). The act of representing, or symbol formation which is a synonym in this terminology, is exhibited more or less adequately in different media, with imagery a poor relation of language. Thus "it is only at levels of Tinguistic codi- fication that one observes a progression towards the attainment of full-fledged means for the differential articulation of the various aspects of an event" (p. 498). In a similar fashion, Piaget views 14 15 the development of thought as the underlying process which he calls ”representational intelligence", or representation "in its broader sense" (1945). In the narrower sense, representation is restricted to mental imagery. Although Piaget's treatment of imagery (Piaget and Inhelder, 1971), is sensitive to the developmental possibilities of the medium, these changes in the direction of greater abstraction are attributed to the development of underlying operative structures. As a result, imagery is viewed as essentially designative, figurative, personalized, and preconceptual, whereas language is the medium in which the potentialities of intelligence may ultimately reach fruition. Notwithstanding other basic differences, the same pattern of ex- planation may be detected in the work of cognitive experimental psych- ologists and psycholinguists. Thus, in an influencial review article, Plyshyn (1973), strenuously argues that "the need to postulate a more abstract representation--one which resembles neither pictures nor words, and is not accessible to subjective experience--is unavoidable. As long as we recognize that people can go from mental pictures to mental words and vice versa, we are forced to conclude that there must be a representation (which is more abstract and not available to con- scious experience) which encompasses both. There must be, in other words, some common format or interlingua" (1973, p.5). Plyshyn's view is echoed by other experimentalists who have fallen under the spell of computer models. For computer simulations of artificial in- telligence require an abstract coding base or programming language. Also consonant with these approaches is Chomsky's view of language learning as based on some innately specified system of language uni- versals which is instantiated in the grammars of the different natural 16 languages. Indeed, there seems to be a pre-established harmony between these views. What is common to these admittedly diverse theories is a pattern of interpretation in which representation as phenomena (as given in appearance and statement) derive their character from a structure assumed to underlie or transcend phenomena or statements. Moreover, this underlying structure of representation achieves its fullest realization in language--with imagery and action at best regarded as privative cases. Against the background of this conceptual unanimity, it is not surprising to discover that the bulk of the research generated from these theoretical positions has chiefly been focused on questions con- cerning how adequately the surface expresses (or represses) the depth, how the vehicles of representation reveal or conceal the underlying structure of representation. Consider, for example, the psycho- analysts' attempt to move from remote conscious derivatives to the unconscious representation. In a like manner, Werner and Kaplan study imagery and non-verbal media in order to shed light on "the genetical- ly early stages of symbolization....that eventually culminate in the autonomous symbol-systems of speech" (1964, p.355). In contrast to the unitary or monistic model of representation, which assumes a single underlying cognitive process expressed more or less adequately in different media, a smaller number of theorists opt for dualistic and even trinitarian approaches. Thus, in experimental psychology, Paivio (especially 1971) has emerged as a prolific and influential advocate of the "dual coding approach" to mental represen- tation. He assumes that verbal and non-verbal information are l7 represented and processed in two distinct but interconnected symbolic systems which are functionally independent (Paivio, 1974). Fur- thermore, he regards the non-verbal or imagery system as specialized for representing non-verbal information--concrete objects and events-- in an analog fashion via imagery. Whereas the verbal system is specialized for dealing with linguistic units and generating speech. From a psychoanalytically oriented perspective, Reyher's recent analysis of the two incommensurate modes of information processing based on the functional lateralization of the brain also develops a dualistic approach to representation. Reyher distinguished two unique modes of representation: the semantic-syntaxic and the analogic- synthetic. The former finds expression in language, the latter in imagery (Reyher, l976, pp.l4-l5). In his most recent theorizing about daydreaming, Jerome Singer also adopts a dual coding point of view (Singer, 1974). Finally, there is the trinitarian approach to mental representa- tion of Jerome Bruner and his coworkers in developmental psychology (Bruner et al., 1964, 1966); an approach which has also been used by Mardi Horowitz (1970, 1971), to rethink certain aspects of the psycho- analytical theory of cognition. These authors distinguish three sep- arable subsystems of processing information by which humans construct models of their world: through action, through imagery, and through language (Bruner, 1964, 1966). In Bruner's view, action--the enactive mode of representation--is highly concrete, being under the immediate control of particular environmental stimuli. Imagery--the iconic mode-- is seen as a somewhat more flexible and abstract system that is l8 relatively independent of action. At the same time, it is tied to the "surface of things". Consequently, imagery is regarded as rela- tively concrete and static, leaving only language--the symbolic mode of representation--as capable of achieving the full range of cate- gorical and hierarchical organization which produces the requisite freedom for treating abstract problems and concepts. In Bruner's rather vivid image, language is ”an extraordinary swift system in con- trast to action and imagery, the two rather sluggish modes of rep- resentation" (1966, p.40). Finally, for Bruner, action represents "past events through appropriate motor responses", (1964, p.2); images represent by "standing for" perceptual events; whereas language represents by "design features" that include displacement and arbi- trariness. The existence of monistic, dualistic, and pluralistic theories of representation testifies to the presence of serious ambiguities, not to mention contradictions, surrounding the use of basic terms. Typi- cally ambiguities and contradictions are dealt with in one of two ways: they are eliminated by selecting one of several meanings of an ambiguous term and by then showing the others to be ridiculous or inappropriate; or they are used by discriminating different senses or aspects of a term and the appropriate regions and limits of their application. While the former approach tends to develop controversial oppositions, the latter lends itself to more irenic resolutions. In any event, the present discussion is offered as no more than a prolegomenon to a proper conceptual analysis of the different principles and methods that Contribute to the fertility as well as the productive ambiguity and the need for conceptual housecleaning that characterize this field. CONCEPTUAL REORIENTATIONS: THE SEMANTICS 0F REPRESENTATION In psychology there are experimental methods and conceptual confusion. -Wittgenstein- In order to introduce some order into the Babel of competing voices, of overlapping and contradictory theories that characterize the discussion of mental representation, it is essential to find a means of productively comparing the similarities and differences of the various approaches. Since the activity of comparison involves clarifying the respect or respects of comparison, it is possible to exploit the resources of ambiguity surrounding the term 'representation' in order to delineate a set of respects, of dis- tinctions, by which to schematize the parameters of a more rounded approach. Such a procedure will facilitate the review of the confus- ing array of predicates assigned to 'representation' in the context of different theories, as well as their coordination based on a multi- dimensional conceptual analysis. For in themselves differences and ambiguities are not pernicious, but the tendenctho interpret them as real contradictions is. That path leads to dogmatism and fanaticism, relativism and nihilism; surely the Four Horsemen of the Apocalypse 19 20 as far as science is concerned. Since 'representation' can be addressed theoretically only to the extent that the terms of discussion permit, every discussion is rela- tive to its formulation. Consequently, attention to the aspects of representation that are selected by different theories, provides the starting point for this discussion. Thus, it has already been noted that Bruner, Paivio, Reyher, Horowitz, and Singer have revitalized the discussion of representation by making the media of representation their basic consideration. By focusing attention on the potentiali- ties of the media, these authors have argued that the different ve- hicles have different intrinsic organizational tendencies. Perhaps the crucial distinction is the one drawn between the sequential organ- ization of information of verbal representations as contrasted with the simultaneous arrangement of information of imagery representations. Consequently, the structural features of the former system have a special capacity for transforming abstract properties of linguistic units and hierarchies, whereas the latter is better suited for trans- forming information concerning the figural properties of concrete events (cf. Paivio, 1975, p.635). Moreover, the spatial 'format' of imagery representations would seem to allow simultaneous (or at least very rapid), access to information, while the linear format of verbal representations seems to permit a more sequentially ordered, discur- sive access to information. It is apparent from this discussion that although the modal_gj; mension, (the media or vehicle) of representation is taken as basic, other aspects of representation were brought in as derivative terms 21 to complete the analysis. Thus, in Paivio and Bruner the f2!flél.§i: mension of 'concrete—abstract' was subordinated to the characteristics of the modes. Nevertheless, Paivio goes on to elaborate the modes in terms of three formal "levels of transformation or coding....these levels of meaning reactions will be described here as (a) the 222227 sentational process (or representational meaning), (b) referential associative reactions (or referential meaning), and (c) associative chains or structures (or associative meaning)....This feature of the model relates it closely to the abstractness-concreteness dimension of stimulus meaning" (1971, p.52-53). Similarly, Reyher (1963, 1976), Horowitz (1971), and Singer (1965, 1975), treat the motivational dimension of representation in terms of the relative proximity of imagery and language to affect and drive systems. Further, Reyher introduces the formal dimension by distinguishing the indirect, refer- ential "gradients of structural, functional, and qualitative similar- ity" (1976, p.13) of "imagoic-depictive vehicles" from the semantic representation of conceptual-verbal vehicles. A realignment of like magnitude is seen when the formal dimension --which might be called the level of processing dimension--is taken as the basic term of analysis. Thus, both Werner and Piaget treat the act of representing in terms of the "orthogenetic principle" of in- creasing differentiation (Werner and Kaplan, p.40), or of the formali- zation of operations (Piaget and Inhelder, 1969, pp.152 ff.). From this perspective, Werner and Kaplan view the modal dimension as hier- archically ordered, with imagery the lisping anticipation of verbal symbolization. By contrast, Piaget was able to demonstrate that the 22 formal dimension is operative even within the medium of imagery (as well as the medium of language); that imagery also moves from con- crete to abstract--from reproductive to anticipatory and transforma- tional--in the course of cognitive development (Piaget and Inhelder, 1967). Thus, it is not enough to claim that humans have access to a variety of media for representing events; even when it is added that the media of imagery and language have differing cognitive and emotive assets and liabilities. For in addition to the media, it has been advanced that humans also have access to a variety of formal levels of processing, of representing information. To put it much too simply, the media of representation may be viewed as coding input into words or images, whereas processing events establish the formal level of representing, particularly the conscious context or level of awareness which regulates attentional processes and the field of consciousness, (and presumably the underlying microstructural organization of brain assemblies as well (cf. Globus, 1973; Schafer, 1967). Common exper- ience, as well as controlled observation, recognizes a continuum of awareness running from dreaming to hypervigilance, with such inter- mediaries as hypnosis, sensory deprivation, free association, relaxa- tion, meditation, etc. Various theoretical languages have been de- veloped to call attention to and further differentiate the formal level of processing dimension of representation. Freud's discrimina- tion of the primary and secondary processes remains the most famous as well as the seminal analysis of this phenomenon (Freud, 1900; Noy, 1969). In Werner's terminology, levels of differentiation and de- differentiation cover similar ground (Werner, 1947). While Piaget 23 seems to get at the same process in terms of the relative primacy of assimilation and accomodation (Piaget and Inhelder, 1969). With ex- plicit acknowledgement of Freud's contribution, the cognitive psych- ologist Neisser (1963) distinguishes multiple and sequential informa- tion processing based on analogies borrowed from computer programming. Finally, Sperry et a1. (See especially Levy-Agresti and Sperry, 1968) may have provided the neurophysiological basis of this distinction by calling attention to the hemispheric differences in the modes of in- formation processing. It is interesting to note that those theories which make the formal level of representing the basic dimension of analysis tend to treat other aspects of representing as derivative. Thus, Werner and Kaplan consider issues of media insofar as they reflect different levels of symbolic differentiation. While Piaget detects the pro- gressive formal development reflected in the media themselves, from concrete to formal operations. Similarly, in his major "revision of the psychoanalytic theory of the primary process", Pinchas Noy (Noy, 1969), traces the continuum of psychic organization from primary process to secondary process as reflected in the shift from "thing representations" (images) to "word representations" (p.169 and passim). In this way, the psychoanalytic theory of cognition is recast from the formal level of processing point of view. Furthermore, these theories tend also to subordinate motivational considerations to formal ones. Piaget argues for a "functional parallelism" whereby the development of affectivity--the "energetics of behavior"--mirrors the form of cognitive development (Piaget and Inhelder, 1969, p.158). In a similar 24 move, Noy as well as Schafer refer to Rapaport's "drive organization of memory" and "conceptual organization of memory" as constituting the progressive formalization of motivational structures from pri- mary to secondary process (Noy, 1969, p.166; Schafer, 1967). These comparisons of the diverse aspects of representation high- lighted by the different theoretical frameworks may be thought of as supplying the 'vertical' dimension (formal levels of processing), which complements the previously discussed 'horizontal' dimension (media) of representation. Against this background the character of representation may be viewed as codetermined by modal and formal dimensions. However, even this double aspect approach does not ex- haust the dimensions of representation that have been taken as basic in psychological theorizing. On more than one occasion, reference has been made to the motivational dimension of representation. Piaget captures this aspect very neatly in his recognition that affectivity is an "irreducible" aspect of behavior, providing the "energetics of behavior patterns whose cognitive aspect refers to the structures alone. There is no behavior, however intellectual, which does not involve affective factors as motives" (Piaget and Inhelder, 1969, p.158). Perhaps nowhere is the motivational aspect of representation more fully articulated than in psychoanalytic theory. Indeed, for thevfl‘ classical position as developed by Fenichel, mental representation originates out of the frustrated drive state of the organism as an "hallucinatory wish fulfillment“ (Fenichel, 1945, p.47, ff). Rep- resentations come into being as vehicles for the satisfaction of wishes--psychic representatives of the instincts manifested as hallu- cination, image, fantasy, and gradually sUblimated into the higher 25 forms of symbolic functioning. To the extent that the economic and dynamic points of view provide the 'natural base' of the theory, the other points of view may be seen as cultural elaborations of these starting points in the direction of the reality principle and adapta- tion. Without getting too involved in the finer points, it is sufficient to call attention to the motivational basis of representa- tion in psychoanalytic theory and to indicate its priority to other aspects. Thus, contrary to the "formal" interpretation of Noy, Schafer, Gill, and Holt, the distinction between primary and secondary process originally referred to "modes of discharge of psychic energy and not the manifestations of these discharge processes--thoughts, dreams, fantasies, neurotic symptoms or motor acts" (Beres, 1960, p.259. But compare Noy, 1969; Gill, 1967; and Holt, 1967). It is the energic and dynamic vicissitudes that determine the "formal" level of rep- resentation. As Freud pointed out early in his investigations, "nothing but a wish can set our mental apparatus at work" (Freud, 1900, p.567). Consequently, "the urge to fulfillment of the wish is the motivating force in human psychic activity or motor response" (Beres, 1960, p.258). Primary processes are regulated by the immediate discharge of the wish; secondary processes by delay of discharge. Similarly, the various modes of representation are classified in accordance with how they serve primary or secondary process discharge. Tradi- tionally, imagery--"plastic representation"--is viewed as the special province of primary process (cf. Freud, 1915). For present purposes, (and notwithstanding the fact that the recent work of the ego analysts Hartmann (1964), Arlow (1960), Beres (1960, 1961), Singer (1965), etc., have attempted to redress this one-sided emphasis by demonstrating the role of imagery in secondary process thinking). classical 26 psychoanalytic theory remains the foremost example of the establish- ment of the motivational dimension of representation as fundamental, while formal and modal aspects are treated as derivatives of motiva- tional consideratibns. ON THE TEMPORAL DIMENSION OF REPRESENTATION By sifting through the sometimes bewilderingly inconsistent theoretical statements and experimental yield, three irreducible aspects of representation were found to be presupposed in every treatment of the topic. For all their ambiguity, the differences between representation as modal, as formal, and as motivational run through each discussion, and are still operative in generating theo- retical and empirical problems. Indeed, so salient are these dimen- sions in current controversy that they tend to overshadow the aspect of representing set forth at the beginning of this study, viz., rep- resenting as temporalizing. In spite of, or perhaps because of, its very obscurity, the temporalizing function of representation lays claim to a status equal to the other dimensions; therewith turning the trio of basic aspects into a quartet: modal, formal, motivational, temporal. Moreover, it can be argued that the temporal dimension might properly be regarded as first among equals. As stated earlier §g_present ing is interpreted as the active process of creating or recreating presence; of making and keeping present, time past and time future, things known and things unknown. Representation presupposes the presence of what is absent: the "what has been" or the "what is not yet". Furthermore, representing brings the nonactual (past or future) into the present, thereby 'binding' time together; where the 27 28 nature of the 'binding' in any particular case depends, at least in part, on the purposive orientation of the subject. Needless to say, 'purposing' itself--the "feedforward that structures all activity" (Richards, l955)--is fundamentally temporal, constituting the syn- thesis of the temporal field in the light of future representations. It is this process of binding the presently possible future with the presently recollected past into a unified field of experience, that led Kant and Heidegger to regard the temporal dimension of representa- tion as the ground of the purposive structure of experience. In a more circumscribed usage, the term 'temporal orientation' "refers to the preferential tendency discovered in individuals with respect to past, present, and future" (Rabin, 1976, p.7). Thus, if the shifting fields of our experience are structured in terms of dominant interests and purposes at the moment, it might be expected that different classes of purposing will presuppose different forms of temporal orientation and perspective. More will be said about this intriguing possibility when the other dimensions are reintroduced to further articulate this aspect of representing. It is interesting to note that while the three previously ob- served dimensions of representation--modal, formal, motivational-- have vociferous champions on the present North American psychological scene, the fourth dimension remains mutely and ingloriously obscure. This is not to say that the other theories disregard time. On the contrary, every theory makes some provision for temporality. Thus, Piaget has written a complete book on the subject, as well as several extended discussions scattered through the remainder of his works. 29 Werner and Kaplan also devotes several chapters to the subject. With- in the purview of research on the functional laterality of the brain, Efron has demonstrated in a series of articles that time concepts tend to be mediated by the left hemisphere (Efron, 1963a, 1963b). While Freud's remarks on time-~and timelessness!--are justly famous (Freud, 1953). Finally, and perhaps most strikingly, it is seldom appreciated that the distinction between the simultaneous organization of imagery processing versus the sequential organization of verbal processing, which figures so centrally in the work of Paivio, Neisser, Reyher, and Singer, is clearly based on time, on two ways of repre- senting temporality. Lest this discussion leave the impression that time has been given its due, it is important to recognize that in every instance temporality is considered in terms of other distinc- tions taken as more fundamental. It is hardly an exaggeration to assert that the treatment of the temporal dimension of representation is conspicuous by its absence in current debates--if it was even recalled that temporality constituted a dimension at all! In this regard, Loewald's work deserves special mention precisely because it exhibits in an exceptionally vivid way the new problems and the new perspectives that are brought to light when temporality is taken as the keystone of a theory of representation. More than anyone else, Loewald appreciates the central role of temporality in psychoanalytic theory and practice. Here are some of the temporal phenomena and concepts that most obviously are of importance in psychoanalysis: Mem- ory, forgetting, regression, repetition, anticipation, presentation, representation; the influence of the past on the present in thought, feeling, and behavior; delay of gratification and action; sleep-wakerIHeSS and other 3O rhythmicities in mental life; variations and abnormal- ities in the subjective sense of elapsed time; the so called timelessness of the id; the role of imagination and fantasy in structuring the future; values, stan- dards, ideals as future oriented categories; concepts such as object constancy and self identity; not to mention the important factor of time in the psycho— analytic situation itself, in technical aspects, appointments, length of hour, etc. (Loewald, 1973, p.402). Indeed, when viewed from this perspective, psychoanalysis offers perhaps the most sustained consideration of the multi-leveled temporality of human existence. While this is not the place for an extended analysis of Loewald's position, it is interesting to observe how the other dimensions of representation are recast by taking temporality as the starting point, the principle of explanation. As a result, motivational aspects are viewed as "primitive" propelling forces of the past, as in early id psychology, or as the pull of future possibilities and purposes as in ego psychology and object relations theory. While this is clearly not a case of either -or, it does allow Loewald to reconceptualize the relations between the so called life and death instincts as marking the motivational oscillation between future and past time orientations (Loewald, 1973, p.404). Consider also the hypothesis that structural- ization--the development of psychic structures--is not spatial but temporal in organization. As Loewald phrases the issue: "it might well be useful to explore further not only the superego in its rela- tions to the temporal mode future, but also the time dimension of id and ego and their relations to the temporal modes past and present" (Loewald, 1962, p.502). In this way, the formal dimension of rep- resentation is accounted for by assimilating it to the progressive 31 or regressive temporal differentiation of present experience (Loewald, 1962b; p.268; but cf. also 1972, p.407). Finally, Loewald addresses the modal dimension of representation by distinguishing the uncon- scious primary enactive memory system from the conscious secondary representational memory system (Loewald, 1975, pp. 318-319). This can be loosely described as a continuum from unconscious transferen- tial acting out of the past--in which past isn't distinguished from present (cf. Bruner and Horowitz on enactive representation)-- to the "higher forms" of memorial activity of "thing presentation and word presentation", i.e., of imagery and verbal modes (321 ff.). SUMMARY Even if any given terminology is a reflection of reality, by its very nature as terminology it must be a selection of reality; and to this extent it must function also as a deflection of reality. -Kenneth Burke- The impetus for reexamining the meaning of 'representation' came from recognizing the possibly under-appreciated fact that psychologi- cal theorists do not mean the same thing when talking about 'repre- sentation'---and most other basic terms for that matter. In order to explore in some detail the different meanings, relations, and impli- cations that have been assigned to the common term 'representation', a four dimensional schema was constructed and employed as a device to specify basic aspects of 'representing'. Consequently, it has been possible to trace the way in which an initially ambiguous term is given different meanings within the context of different theoretical languages. This process occurs by establishing one dimension as basic in terms of which the others are interpreted; and by further elabo- rating that dimension in the context of the specific terminological and methodological resources available in a given theory. Ambiguities initially arise in the attempt to assimilate the other three dimen- sions to the one taken as basic. The schema helps clarify the comp- licated relations between different theories and findings by 32 33 demonstrating how the basic dimensions of representing are transformed in different theories. Thus, theories such as Freud's and Fenichel's, which take the motivational dimension of representing as primary, endeavor to show how representation is constructed out of elements of the 'representable', viz., the unconscious structure of instincts. Whereas theories such as Piaget's and Werner's, which take the formal dimension of representing as basic, attempt to assimilate the other dimensions--motivationa1 (or the 'representable'), modal (or the rep- resented), temporal (or the 'representer')--to the formal level of representation (See Appendix.A fbr an attempt to graphically depict these various schematizations of 'representing'). In a like manner, Bruner, Paivio, Reyher, Horowitz, and Singer highlight the modal dimension or vehicle (the represented), in terms of which they treat the other aspects. Finally, theories such as Loewald's, that em- phasize the temporal dimension of representing, discriminate the other dimension as the products of the temporalizing activity of the representer (cf. also Kant, 1965, Husserl, 1962, Heidegger, 1962). The advantages of such a schematic device are twofold. On the one hand, by revealing the different references, the different ques- tions and meanings concealed behind a common term, apparent incon- sistencies and contradictions are minimized; therewith undermining the grounds for dogmatism and skepticism. Thus, in showing the proper senses of a given usage of a term, it becomes apparent that different theories focus on acceptibility obvious and different aspects of the multivalent phenomenon of representation. On the other hand, the schema of basic distinctions, by isolating different aspects of representing, can articulate the four dimensions in 34 various ways, thereby raising new questions and new perspectives. If there is any moral to be drawn from this semantic approach to the ambiguities of 'representation', it lies in the recognition that the multiplicity of theoretical languages-~0f subject matters and systems of inference--faci1itates the differentiation of the complex and richly diversified meaning of this fundamental concept. That different terminologies direct attention to distinguishable major aspects of the phenomenon of representing, precludes the necessity for choosing one language and banishing all others--as if salvation rested on the proper declaration of faith. Rather, the different theoretical languages are more modestly and usefully viewed as so many tools of the trade, each with its own assets and liabil- ities for solving distinct kinds of problems. By the same token, the fourfold dimensionalization of 'representation' constitutes yet another analytical device, another tool of inquiry that will have to prove its mettle in the only relevant arena: that working with it produces positive and verifiable results concerning the questions that interest us. EPILOGUE - RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT A retrospective look at the movement of this preceding discussion reveals the joints, the transition points of the argument, and inti- mates the direction of its further elaboration. By puzzling about the place of time in psychology we attempted to trace a kind of recurring historical cycle, wherein time is treated first in terms of "things", as the universal context of motion, then in terms of "thought", as the formal structure of the knower; and finally, in terms of "language" and "action", as the temporal structure of rep- resenting. Thus, 'context', 'agent' and 'act' provided different perspectives on the meaning of time and its placement in psychological theory; and we had occasion to note that the temptation of using models of time derived from the perspective of things tended to ob- scure vital aspects of temporal experience; (but more about this later). Thus, after passing from the psychological statu§_of temporality to the agt_of temporalizing, we sought a new perspective by playing with a pun on the grammar of the term "representing" (as re presenting). Following a suggestion of Kant's, we hoped to find the "unknown root" of temporality by digging into the "ground" of representation. 35 36 After a brief detour through selected philosophers as a way of getting oriented to the complicated connections between temporality and representation, we turned to the major psychological theorists of representation, in the anticipation of finding there the conceptual resources to make Kant's suggestion pay off; or, to change the metaphor, sensing the "catch" that would justify the fishing expe- dition. Surprisingly, the catch was neither fish nor fowl, but good red herring. To begin with, the literature on representation is rife with ambiguities-~if not downright contradictions. Further, and in spite of the almost unanimous agreement that "representation" func- tions as a pivotal concept, there are virtually no careful conceptual analyses of the term to be found, certainly none that go beyond the somewhat parochial boundaries of different schools. In order to fill this vacuum, we attempted a provisional semantics of psychological theorizing, focusing on the vicissitudes of meaning assigned to the term "representation". Three basic terms were found to be featured in the different theories: representation as formal, representation as mgd_al_, and representation as motivational. Each of these terms pro- vided a perspective on representing in which the other terms played a secondary or derivative role. But while this finding was not without intrinsic interest and implication, it failed to shed the desired light on representing as the foundation of temporality. Sometimes the failure to find what is expected can be more illumi- nating than success. Rather than pass too hastily over the absence of discussions linking time and representation, we might take heart from the example of another student of representation, and above all, mis- representation. In this, as in so many other things, Sherlock Holmes 37 points the way. When Holmes observed that the dog's barking held the key to the mystery of The Hound of the Baskervilles, Watson protested that the dog did not bark that night. And that, of course, was the point. And that may be our point as well. The absence of discussions of time in the context of theories of representation may not be adven- titious, but instead prove to be the most revealing clue of all; drawing attention away from the quarry of temporal experience, and to the devices we have fashioned, the terminological nets and net- works we use in taking hold of it. From this vantage point, the theoretical obliviousness to time as temporal experience may be traced to committments to concepts and methods which dictate the acceptable categories of explanation (in- cluding the criteria and rules for what counts as elements, facts, and relationships), which in turn render certain kinds of evidence inex— pressible in its terms. Needless to say, such considerations touch on profound and controversial issues in epistomology and the.philosophy of science. With respect to the question at hand, we are witnessing certain local effects of the more general decision about the nature of science as it bears on the study of human behavior. The policy of substituting "how" questions for "why"; of treating humans as "objects" explicable by mechanisms and processes; the banishment of final causes and the sovereignty of efficient causes, all point to the triumph of "natural science“ methods of approaching and organizing the domain of psychology. The purpose of mentioning this is not to detract from the hard earned successes of this approach in its proper place, but rather it is, in the words of Whitehead, "to draw attention to the mass of evidence...which is simply ignored in the prevalent scientific 38 doctrine. The conduct of human affairs is entirely dominated by our recognition of foresight determining purpose, and purpose issuing on conduct. Almost every sentence we utter and every judgement we form, presuppose our unfailing experience of this element in life. The evidence is so everwhelming, the belief so unquestioning, the evidence of language so decisive, that it is difficult to know where to begin demonstrating it" (Whitehead, 1966, p.13). In short, we are proposing that the indifference to temporality stems from conceptual committ- ments (we almost said "occupational psychosis") to what might be called the project of replacing the "impure" language of intentional- ity by a purified language of causality; a project which promises to bestow the blessings of science on the heads of its practitioners. But since blessings are dialectically related to curses, it would be remiss to assume that this project is not without its cost, its shadow side. Or, to quote Whitehead once more: "Scientists animated by the purpose of proving that they are purposeless constitutes an interesting subject for study" (ibid., p.16). At the heart of this controversy, which is at least as old as Galileo's (if not Democritus') rejection of final causality, is what Roy Schafer (1976) has recently christened the debate between "action language" (or as George Klein (1976) calls it, psychoanalytic 'clin- ical theory') and "metapsychology" (construed as the translation of meaning into the underlying dynamics of energy). In their stronger, ontological form, action models presuppose the human body in con- scious or purposive motion, whereas motion models seek to reduce action to its antecedent internal or external causes. Thus, 39 behavioristic explanations seek to reduce or dissolve act and actor into conditioned responses to environmental stimuli, while dynamic explanations reduce act to actor who in turn is driven by motives which have their foundation in such natural mechanisms of motion as drive and instincts. Both internal (drives) and external (environ- mental) causes reduce action to concatenations of motion, sheer motion. (Consider such terminological strategies as 'instincts', 'drives', 'homeostatic regulators', 'information processors', etc.). Moreover, motion models rely on tracing chains of antecedent causes, thereby decomposing complex motions (behaviors) back to simpler motions (instincts or reflexes), ultimately, in their ontological forms, to the laws of chemistry and physics. In such theories, past present and future are stretched out in an (external) sequential and causally related order, with the explanatory power rooted in the past (e.g., biological continuity and learning histories). In its more cautious, semantic or "logological" forms (i.e., words about words), these models represent different policies about the kinds of terms or "languages" that are most relevant for an ade- quate psychological account of human behavior. Such policy decisions establish the criteria for singling out elements of experience, for classifying them into kinds based on relevant resemblances, and for systematizing the coherences and relationships among them. Different terms and languages will "feature" certain resemblances in certain respects and neglect other resemblances and other respects. From this angle, the paucity of attention to temporality takes on new significance. When employed as a way of classifying theories of representation, the "action-motion" dichotomy brings to light the 40 way different theories exploit the ambiguity in such terms as "beha- vior", "movement", "instinct", "program", "homeostasis","information processing" and even "representation“. For all these terms can mean either action or sheer motion. Such accounts acquire a certain plausibility by moving illicitly from one set of meanings to the other, by sliding from an ostensibly rigorous theoretical language of causes to the ordinary language of meaning and intention. These conceptual sleights of hand provide the best of both worlds: theo- rists can have their verisimilitude, and their scientific consciences too! Rather than giving a detailed account of the specific sins of each theorist, or ranking their sins in order of magnitude (for this, c.f., Schafer, l976), suffice it to say that the lure of causal ex- planations of representation directs attention to the influence of the past and therein obscures the radical way in which time enters into human life, the way in which action can be seen as a time-struc- ture that is intrinsically different from simple biological develop- ment. In this vein, we will attempt to detail the conceptual trans- formations entailed by extending the three dimensions of representa- tion--modal, formal, motivational--from their original matrix in various causal theories, and relocating them in an action model of representation that takes temporal representation and perspective as the semantic rock bottom of explanation. 41 On the Temporal Structure of Action This epilogue has moved beyond the essay's original aim of attempting to neutrally state the structure of different theories of representations as a way of discovering basic conceptual dimensions, and toward a restatement of those dimensions in an action language framework. But even this project must be approached with circum- spection lest it become merely the substitution of one set of crude abstractions for another. For the distinction between causal and intentional languages, and the action-motion polarity on which it is based, is not without its own ambiguities. Once the smooth surface is scratched, the concept of "action" seems to cover a multitude of sins, stretching over a series of graduated differences in meaning and shades of qualification. In this way our dramatic use of the action- motion dichotomy may actually blur further necessary distinctions, thereby becoming inadequate to the complexity of experience. With these caveats firmly in mind, it will be nonetheless contend- ed that time is implicit in the logic of the concept of action and action language; that in contrast to need driven conceptions, temporal perspective is a necessary condition of action. "Agtjggf presupposes an ggtgr_who acts in various contexts with intentions, plans, ur- pgsgs, foresight, etc., i.e., temporal perspective informed by the past and oriented to future projects (both long and short term). Thus time and temporal perspective become the fundamental dimension when explanatory strategies shift from "metapsychological", "economic", "drive discharge" constructs to those of an intentional, action language. Moreover, the concept of temporality expands to include not 42 only the past but the future as well, i.e., not only the "objective" literal history of environmental contingencies and antecedent causes but above all the figurative history of personal meaning (e.g., dreams, wishes, fantasies, symptoms--the "symbolics of desire"). Such a project, if carried out, would bring to fruition the high hopes with which we turned to 'representation' as a clue to under- standing temporality. Not only would this vindicate that theoretical gamble, but it would also proivde a satisfying symmetry to the argu- ment; completing the movement from"time' to 'representation' and back to 'time' again; but this time armed with the new perspectives ac- quired as a result of the expedition into representation. Specifically, it would require the coordination of the dimensions of representations into a differentiated temporal organization consistent with an explan- ation in terms of meanings, intentions and actions. Further, it would provide a preliminary glimpse at what "the native tongue of psycho- analysis" would look like if the spatial analogies in the service of explanatory mechanisms and causes were replaced by the temporal structuring of meanings and intentions. This would involve extend- ing the claims staked out in Loewald's work, as amplified by recon- ceptualizing the dimensions of representation as coordinate perspec- tives on temporality. On the Temporal Structure of Motives Etymologically, motives and motivation are concerned with the sources of human movement. It has been an abiding hope of scientifi- cally minded psychologists to explain human motives according to the 43 prestigious paradigms established by the classic science of motion viz. physics. As a result, it seems perfectly natural to find Piaget appealing to the "energetics" of behavior as the focus of motivation. Similarly, Freud's interest in the economics and dynamics of behavior was the legacy of his earliest speculations in the "project of a scientific psychology" (Freud, 1895). However, it is a tribute to Freud's genius that he used terms that could double as both move- ments and acts, causes and reasons. Thus, when he writes that it is "the wish that sets the mental apparatus in motion", he leaves himself the option of interpreting wishes as energies derived from instincts or in their more ordinary sense as representations of desire. (At this level of analysis, Freud joins up with that tradition of Western Psychology that regards Eros (Plato), appetition (Leibniz), conatus (Spinoza), i.e., desire, as definitive of human being). Treating the motivational dimension of representation in terms of the modalities of desire--rather than by adducing a more basic level of account in terms of the regular laws governing movement, i.e., metapsychology-- is not to postulate an occult faculty. Rather, it draws attention to the person wishing as engaged in the personal agt_par excellence. For the idea of an unhindered wish contains the notion of a spon- taneous disposition which comes from the agent rather than being im- posed by others (cf. Taylor, p.51). The "I wish" is the person act- ing and not being acted upon from outside; the person and not a faculty or an underlying instinct. In this fashion, wishing, as Freud wisely observed, is the principle, the origin; but not of motion but of action--the paradigm of self-generated action. 44 In this fundamental usage, wishing is not the antithesis of reality, but rather the basic act which relates the person to objects, to the world. Or, as Fenichel (1945) would have it, "the first signs of object representation must originate in the state of hunger" (p.35) which is merely the obverse of his telling remark: "if every need could be immediately taken care of, a conception of reality would probably never develop" (p.34). It is this conjunction of wishing, longing, frustration and satisfaction that enables Fenichel to state that "the origin of the ego and the origin of the sense of reality are but two aspects of one developmental step" (p.35). The existence of desire implies an absence, a lack in the one who desires. Thus desire testifies to the impossibility of the dream of self- sufficiency, of that special kind of timeless solipsism that Freud terms "primary narcissism". It is by virtue of desire and its aims and objects that man is situated in the world. Yet the infant's in- ability to satisfy his desires himself gives rise to "the most funda- mental anxiety" (p.44). This cleavage opened between desire and fulfillment is bridged by primitive forms of yearning and anticipa- tion which are the precursors of a sense of time. This transition from passive or reactive waiting to active anticipation marks the simultaneous appearance of (rudimentary) action and temporal per- spective (Hartocollis, 1974, p.299). Finally, in analytic theory, "the first signs of object representation must originate in the state of hunger" (Fenichel, 1972, p.35), which in turn presupposes memory oriented toward future fulfillment of frustration. Thus, even within psychoanalysis the priority of the future over the past 45 is acknowledged. In a paradoxical way which remains unthematized within psychoanalytic theory proper, memory is first manifested as anticipation of future satisfaction. The famous image of the "hal- lucinated breast" as the paradigm of mental representation embodies this bipolar temporal structure: presumably, the remembered repre- sentation is experienced as futural, is projected into the future as the satisfaction of desire. As a result, representing emerges as Janus-faced, turned to the past as "archeology" and to the future as "telelogy" (cf. Ricouer, 1970). Thus far, this attempt to trace the temporal conditions of motivation by reconceptualizing psychoanalytic theory in an "actional" vocabulary, focused on the constellation of interlocking terms that emerge from the "dialectics of desire" (Ricouer, 1970): satisfaction and frustration, representation and reality, timelessness and time. Focusing on the birth of desire out of an undifferentiated state gives the impression that desire is prior to the other terms. Yet it must be borne in mind that such descriptions of origins, of genesis, are necessarily "mythological"--even when clothed in the respectable garb of the latest fashionable vocabulary. The point of using myths, of telling "likely stories" as Plato used to call them, is to "set in motion", to place in the temporal order of becoming, the timeless logical implications that inhere in the cycle of terms implicit in this concept of action. As Freud said in a different context: To be sure, this is only an hypothesis, like so many others with which archeologists endeavor to lighten the darkness of prehistorical times--a "Just-So story" as it was amusingly called by a not unkind critic (Kroeger); but I think it 46 is credible to risk a hypothesis if it proves able to bring coherence and understanding into more and more new regions. -Freud, 1960, p.69- In similar fashion, we have used the historical terminology of psycho- analysis' genetic point of view to state something about the "gssgn-. tigl" conditions of action, which may or may not have existed ab initio, but which do exist ggw. Thus, temporal perspective, as implicit in the Janus structure of representation, is the condition whereby appetite (tension) transcends the moment and is projected toward the future as desire and experimental action. On the Temporal Structure of the Formal and Modal Dimensions of Representation Taking the motivational dimension of representation as a starting point may have suggested that motives (as desire) are clearly sep- arable from the other dimensions. But this is only the case at the level of discourse. Our distinctions live in the words chosen to draw them. In actuality, the dimensions are given together. Representa- tion and action are seamless webs that are divided into dimensions only in our theoretical talk about them. And, as we have had ample occasion to observe, not only do we use words, but they also use us. Hence, some of the tangles, paradoxes and ambiguities that keep in- truding into the attempt to get clear about time and representation. Even in so called action language, the temporal structure of representation as the archeology and teleology of desire-~or less presumptuously as the varieties of wishing and planning and willing-- is always qualified adverbally by the "formal dimension", e.g., 47 "concretely" or "abstractly", "prudently" or "compulsively", etc; and by the "modal dimension", e.g., "imaginatively" or "verbally". To further thicken the plot, at the same time that they mediate motives, the formal and modal dimension cross classify each other as well. In his own way and for his own purposes, but without naming it as such, David Shapiro involves the dimensions of representation in his account of action: Conscious motives are generated by the experience of needs (our archeological pole of the motivational di- mension) in a mind that is aware of the possibilities of action (the telelogical pole of temporal perspec- tive). It is evident, then, that the particular form and conscious motive will depend not only on the nature of those needs but also on various other characteris- tics of that mind: the style of thinking (an aspect of our formal dimension), imagination (our modal dimension without the additional division between verbalizing and imaging), and anticipation (the temporal dimension again); relevant attitudes or points of view; and always, an existing context of other motives, including relatively stable ones such as long-range arms and intentions (temporal dimensions qualified by abstract pole of formal dimension). -Shapiro, 1970, p.336- Shapiro goes on to observe that in the course of development "it is no longer possible, even if it is desired, to act without imagination, anticipation, and awareness of the self acting" (p.336). The pro- jections of the self's action in the media of imagination become the possibilities which are deliberated about in the process of decision making. Shapiro has brilliantly delineated the formation and deforma- tion of the experience of volition as it is affected by different cognitive styles (Shapiro, 1966, 1970).2 48 From the perspective of the terminology developed in this essay, the logic of desire terms unfolds into the archeology and teleology of representations: with archeology as the genesis of the forms and figures of desire grounded on the legacy of past identifications and fixations; and teleology, as the transformation or sublimation of desire into long and short range temporal perspectives as acculturated plans, projects, goals and so forth. From the fgrmal_point of view, archeology is regressive, characterized by "primary process" modes of thought, while teleology is progressive characterized by the "sec- ondary processes". That the transformation of the infantile wishes from the primitive and the past, (with their repetition compulsions enacted transferentially), into the realm of culture and the future is a vastly complicated process goes without saying. An adequate accountflfi of the transformation of desire (and its aims and objects) from the base to the sublime would require a fully developed theory of sublima- tion, one grounded in the language of action rather than economics. _ Finally, the modal dimension cuts across the others, with action, images and words having inherently different temporalizing potentials which are in turn modified by the formal levels of regression or pro- gression. Since cultural experience is largely publicly codified in verbal forms, it is to be expected that the forms of language (literal and figurative) would mediate the development of both extended time perspective and sublimation of aims and objects. Images, by virtue of their greater privacy, appear to be in closer "proximity" to earlier wishes (cf. Flugel, 1953). (Surely, the manipulation of imagery to gain control of motivation has never been lost on those 49 who would control others: from Dostoevsky's grand inquisitor to Madison Avenue, and from Plato's Philosopher Kings to Wolpean desen- sitizers). But even here, care must be taken to distinguish the primitive wish fulfilling images of infancy from the sublime images of the "fine" arts and the high religions. It might be added that the goal of psychoanalysis (and linguistic analysis as well) can be described as breaking the blinding powers that certain pictures (images) and words (concepts, habits, thought models) have to in- fluence and distort our lives in the present. In this way the patient is freed from neurotic bondage to models formed in the past and has gained "the freedom to decide one way or another" (Freud, Standard Edition XIX, p.50) in light of imaginatively entertained possibilities of an open-ended future. Conclusion: The Representation of Representation In spite of the "imperialistic" tendency to present itself as an all encompassing theory, the present study has been explicitly con- cerned with exploring the psychological implications of the terms "representation" and "temporality". It goes without saying that any selection of terms is necessarily no more than a "point of view". And, while different theories of representation have been analyzed and reduced to a four dimensional semantic schema, this was never meant to provide a definition of representation or even to set forth a definitive doctrine of what representation "is" or what the word "representation" means. Likewise for "temporality". For as we have seen, representation and temporality are given together, codetermine each other. Both of these concepts have the character of elementary 50 notions, not to be explained by translation into other terms; but rather to be used themselves in any attempted explanation. Stated paradoxically, representation, at least the way the term is used here, is what makes language use possible; while at the same time, language is required to explicate the nature of representation. The very activity of explicating constitutes both an expression of and an amplification of the capacity for representing. Consequently, the different theories of representation are, when taken generically, representations of representation. In this they testify to an essential fact about human beings: man is that animal who can re- present his experience, and in turn, re-present his representations._,/ This reflexive or second-level character of representation of representations--including words about words, images of images, words about images, and images of words, etc.--opens onto a specifically human existence within the symbolic universe of cultural systems. As the "symbolic animal"--which is the modern version of Aristotle's "rational animal"--or "that being for whom being is in question" (Heidegger)--man is the creature who asks questions and invents theories about himself--as well as images, fictions, illusions, de- lusions, etc.--and then attempts to live in their light. Moreover, the term "symbolic animal" suggests that man is simultaneously the citizen of two realms: the sumbolic and the animal, each with its own source of motives and intentions. To make matters even more complex, the coexistence in the two realms suggests two kinds of explanations: 1) the reduction of the "animal" to bodily causes and ultimately to motions, and 2) the elaboration of the "symbolic" into 51 meaning and action. That this dual character of human life has been represented in terms belonging to each of these dimensions comes as no surprise at this stage of the game. The perennial squabbles be- tween mechanists and mentalists, behaviorists and cognitivists, causal concepts and intentional concepts, motion and action bears witness to the endless temptations of reducing one term to the other. And yet the idea of a "symbolic animal" puts both orders of ex- planation together. Similarly, the reflexivity of representation of representation--of which this essay is an example-~puts active and passive together, "representer representing" as cause, and "representer represented" as caused in a way that suggests a third kind of explan- ation, a mixed explanation wherein mechanism and meaning are dialecti- cally assimilated to the active and passive dimensions of representa- tion (cf. Ricouer and Whitehead). But be this as it may, these are matters of the greatest difficulty and obscurity. Suffice it to say that this study of representation and temporal- ity, by selecting the terminology it did, directed attention to cer- tain aspects of these phenomena--and inevitably away from others. In one sense, it had no other aim than the re-exploration of "represen- tation" and "time" without necessarily seeing them in the constella- tions imposed upon them by old habits of thinking and talking. That this new classification has its own limitations, its own blind spots, points once again, to the invincibly perspectival character of repre- sentation as both revealing and concealing. Consequently, there is u no danger that this study constitutes a final, synoptic perspective on perspectives, and no reason to believe that a definitive representa- tion of representation has been achieved. FOOTNOTES FOOTNOTES In more ways than it would be possible to document, the discussion which follows depends on the investigations of Augustine, Cassirer, Heidegger, Wittgenstein and the "Chicago 'Neo-Aristotelians'" in philosophy; and on Freud, James, Loewald, Paivio, Piaget, and Wer- ner in psychology. In our terminology, cognitive styles would be resolved into differ- ent ratios of temporal, formal, motivational and modal dimensions. Thus, the obsessive style would comprise a preponderance of the verbal mode experienced as a necessity "often accompanied by such phrases as 'I must', 'I should', 'I musn't', in inner speech" (Flu- gel, 1961, p.18). Whereas the "impulsive style" would consist in the primacy of wishful images (i.e., at the concretistic formal, motivational, modal ratio) with the attenuation of long range aims (temporal dimension) and the absence of a flexibly articulated yer: bal_value hierarchy, etc. It would appear that Shapiro's schema can be generated from the various ratios of dimensions. In prin- ciple, such a reduction would eliminate much of the ambiguity in Shapiro's treatment, while at the same time systematically high- lighting basic aspects of each style for further study. 52 APPENDIX APPENDIX A 1. Schema of basic terms used to interpret 'representing'. Formal Level of Processing Dimension (Representation) Modal Dimension-4—-——-——Representing ;;Temporal Dimension (Represented) (Representer) Motivational Dimension (Representable) 53 54 APPENDIX A - continued 2. Transformations of schema of basic terms: a. Motivational terms as archetechtonic of schema; e.g., Freud and Fenichel. Representation (Formal Dimension) Represented Representer (Modal Dimension) (Temporal Dimension) Representable (Motivational Dimension) b. Formal terms as archetechtonic of schema; cf., Piaget, Werner, Noy. Representation (Formal Dimension) Represented Representer (Modal Dimension) (Temporal Dimension) 1 Representable (Motivational Dimension) BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY Arieti, S. The intrapsychic self. New York: Basic Books, 1967. Arieti, S. The structural and psychodynamic role of cognition in the human psyche. In S. Arieti (Ed.). The World Bienniel of Psychiatry and Psychotherapy, Vol. I., New York: Basic Book§jl97l. Arlow, J. Ego psychology and the study of mythology. Journal gf_thg_ American Psychoanalytic Association, 1961, 2, 371-393. Arlow, J. Fantasy, memory, and reality testing. Psychoanalytic Quar- ter12, 1969, 3_8_, 28-5]. Atwood, G. An experimental study of visual imagination and memory. Cognitive Psychology, 1971, 2, 290-299. , Bellak, L. Free association: The cornerstone of psychoanalytic tech- nique. The broad scope 9f Psychoanalysis, New York: Grune and Stratton,—1967. Berdach, E. Bod position and memory recall. Unpublished Master's thesis, Michigan State University, East Lansing, Michigan, 1965. Beres, D. The psychoanalytic psychology of imagination. Journal of. the American Psychoanalytic Association, 1960, 252-259. Beres, D. Perception, imagination, and reality. International Jour- nal_9j_Psychoanalysis, 1960, 327-334. Beres, D., and Joseph, E. The concept of mental representation. In; ternational Journal 9f_Psychoanalysis, 1970, 1-9. Bernstein, D., and Borkovec, T. Progressive relaxation training. Champaign, Illinois: Research Press, 1973. Bruner, J. The course of cognitive growth. American Psychologist, 1964, 19, 1-15. Bruner, J. Studies ig_cognitive growth. New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1966. 56 57 Bugelski, 8. Words and things and images. American Psychologist, 1970, §§, 1002-1012. Bugelski, B. The definition of the image. In S. Segal (Ed.). Imagery: Current cognitive approaches. New York: Academic Press, 1971. Carnap, R. Empiricism, semantics and ontology. Revue Internationale 1e philgsgphje, 1950, 11, 20-40. Cassirer, E. The philosophy pf_symbolic forms, Volume 1: Language. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970. Cassirer, E. The philosophy pf symbolic forms, Volume 3: ng_ppg- nomenology pf_knowledge. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1963. Cassirer, E. Ap_essay pp_mpp, New Haven: Yale University Press,l963. Efron, R. Effect of handedness on the perception of simultaneity and temporal order. Brain, 1963a, 86, 261-284. Efron R T m oral erce tion, a hasia and de'a vu. Brain, 1963b, pp, 403-323. D p p 3 —— Fenichel, O. The psychoanalytic theory pf_neurosis. New York: W.W. Norton, 1972. Flugel, J.C. Man, morals §_society:_A_psychoanalytic study. New York: Viking Press, 1961. Friedman, A., & Bourne, L. Encoding the levels of information in pic- tures and words. Journal pf_Experimental Psychology. 1976, 195, 169-190. Freud, A. The interpretation pf dreams. Standard Edition 4 & 5. London: Hogarth Press, 1953. Freud, S. Formulation of the two principles of mental fanctioning. Standard Edition, 1958, 1g, 218-226, London: Hogarth Press, Freud, S. The unconscious. Standard Edition, 1957, 14, 166-215. London: Hogarth Press. Freud, S. Repression. Standard Edition, 1957, 14, 146-158. London: Hogarth Press. Freud, S. Group psychology and the analysis pf_tpg_ggp, New York: Bantam Books, 1960. Furth, H. Piaget's theory of knowledge: The nature of representation and interiorization. Psychological Review, 1968, 15, 143-154. 58 Fraiberg, S. Libidinal object constancy and mental representation. The Psychoanalytic Study pf tpg_Child, 1969, 24, 9-48. Gill, M. The primary process. In R. Hold (Ed.) Motives and thought, New York: International Universities Press, 1967. Globus, G. The problem of consciousness. In Rubinstein (Ed.). Psychoanalysis and contem orar science, New York: International Universities Press, I975 Hartmann, H. Eassays pp_ggp_psychology. New York: International Universities Press, 1964. Hartocollis, P. The origins of time: A reconstruction of the onto- genetic development of the sense of time based an object relations theory. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 1974, 43, 243-261. Hebb, D. Concerning imagery. Psychological Review, 1968, 75, 466-477. Heidegger, M. Being_and time. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1962. Heidegger, M. Kant and the problem pj_metaphysics. New York: Harper, 1968. Heidegger, M. The way back into the ground of metaphysics. In W. Kaufmann (Ed.). Existentialism from Dostoevsky tp_Sartre, New York: Meridian Books, 1962. Holt, R. Imagery: The return of the ostracized. American Psych— ologist, 1964, 12, 254-264. Holt, R. The development of the primary process: A structural view. In R. Holt (Ed.). Motives and thought, New York: International Universities Press, 1967. Holt, R. 0n the nature and generality of mental imagery. In S. Sheehan (Ed.). The function and nature pf_jmagery, New York: Academic Press, T972. Horowitz, M. Image formation and cognition. New York: Appleton- Century-Crofts, 1970. Horowitz, M. Modes of representation of thought. Journal pf_tpg_ American Psychoanalytic Association, 1972, 793-819. Husserl, E. Ideas. New York: Collier Books, 1962. Jacobson, E. Progressive relaxation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1938. James, W. The principles pf psychology, Volume 1, Dover, 1950. 59 Kant, I. Critigue pf_pure reason. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965. Klein, G. Psychoanalytic theory. New York: International Uni- versity Press, 1976. Kosslyn, S. Information representation in visual images. Cognitive Psychology, 1975, Z, 341-370. Kosslyn, S., and Holyoak, K., and Huffman, C. A processing approach to the dual coding hypothesis. Journal pf_Experimental Psych- ology, 1976, 2, 223-233. Kroth, J. The analytic couch and response to free association. Psychotherapy: Theory, Research and Practice, 1970, 7, 206-208. Langer, S. 0n Cassirer's Theory of Language and Myth. In P. Schilpp (Ed.). The philosophy pf_Ernst Cassirer, Evanston: The Library of Living Philosophers, 1949. Langer, S. Philosophy 1p.g_ppy“2gy. New York: Mentor Books, 1962. Levy-Agresti, J., and Sperry, R. Differential perceptual capacities in major and minor hemispheres. Proceedings pj_the National Academy pf_Science, 1968, Q1, 1151. Loewald, H. Ego and reality. International Journal pj_Psych0- analysis, 1951, 22, 10-18. Loewald, H. Internalization, separation, mourning, and the super- ego. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 1962, 21, 483-504. Loewald, H. The superego and the ego ideal II: Superego and time International Journal ijPsychoanalysis, 1962, 42, 264-268. Loewald, H. The experience of time. The Psychoanalytic Studypf' tp§_Child, 1973, 401-411. Loewald, H. Perspectives on memory. In M. Gill, and P. Holzman, (eds.). Psychology versus metapsychology. Ps cholo ical Issues, IX, 4, New York: International Universities Fress, I976. Menninger, K., and Holzman, P. Theory pf_Psychoanalytic Technique. New York: Basic Books, 1973. Neisser, U. The multiplicity of thought. British Journal pf_Psych- Neisser, U. Cognitive psycholpgy, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1967. 6O Novey, S. The meaning of the concept of mental representation of objects. Psychoanalytic Quarterly, 1958, 22, 57-79. Noy, P. A revision of the psychoanalytic theory of the primary pgpcess. International Journal pf_Psychoanalysis, 1969, 42, - 78. Paivio, A. Mental imagery in associative learning and memory. Psychological Review, 1969, 22, 241-263. Paivio, A. Ima er and verbal processes. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1971. Paivio, A. Imagery and language. In S. Segal (Ed.). Imagery: Current Cognitive Approaches, New York: Academic Press, 1971. Paivio, A. A theoretical analysis of the role of imagery in learning and memory. In P. Sheehan (Ed.). The Function gpg Nature pf_ Imagery. New York: Academic Press, 1972. Paivio, A. Language and knowledge of the world. Educational Researcher, 1974, 22, 5-12. Paivio, A. Perceptual comparisons through the mind's eye. Memory and Cognition, 1975, 2, 635-647. Piaget, J., and Inhelder, B. Mental imageryjp_§pg_child. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1971. Piaget, J., and Inhelder, B. The psychology pj_§pg_child. New York: Basic Books, 1969. Plyshyn, Z. What the mind's eye tells the mind's brain: A critique of mental imagery. Psychological Bulletin, 1973, 29, 1-24. Rabin, A. On fantasy and imagination. Pre-publication draft. Rabin, A. Correlates of temporal experience. Introductory remarks at Psychology Colloquium, University of Utah, Feb. 14, 1974. Rabin, A. Temporal experience and personality. Paper delivered at the Third Conference of the International Society for the Study of Time, Alpach, Austria, July, 1976. Reyher, J. The presentation and representation of repressed strivings in awareness, the functional organization of the brain, psycho- pathology and psychotherapy. Chapter based on paper presented at the Downstate Series of Research in Psychiatry. Communicative Structures and Psychic Structures, State University of New York, Downstate Medical Center, January, 1976. 61 Reyher, J. Emergent uncovering: A method for producing and objecti- fying psychopathology, repression and other psychodynamic pro- cesses. Unpublished Manuscript. Richards, I. Speculative instruments. New York: A Harvest Book, 1955. Richardson, A. Mental imagery, New York: Springer, 1969. Ricouer, P. Freud 2_philosophy. New Haven: Yale University Press,l970. Sandler, J., and Rosenblatt, B. The concept of the representational world. The Psychoanalytic Study pf 2pg_Child, 1962, 11, 128-145. Schafer, R. Aspects pf_internalization. New York: International Universities Press, 1968. Schafer, R. A new 1an ua e for psychoanalysis. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1976. Shapiro, D. Neurotic styles. New York=Basic Books, 1965. Shapiro, D. Motivation and action in psychoanalytic psychiatry. Psychiatry, 1970, 22, 329-343. Sherover. C.M. (Ed.). The human experience pf_time. New York: New York University Press,ll975. Singer, J. Daydreaming, New York: Random House, 1966. Singer, J. Imagery and daydream methods in psychotherapy and behavior modification. New York: Academic Press, 1974. Singer, J. Navigating the stream of consciousness. American Psychologist, 1975, 727-738. St. Augustine. The confessions of Saint Augustine. New York: Wash- ington SquarE_Press, 1962. Stern, D. The uncovering properties pj_visua1 imagery, verbal association with eyes closed, and verbal association with eyes en: A comparative study. Unpublished Master's Thesis, Mic cfiigan State University, 1974. Stern, O. Si ens of anxiety during three verbal association conditions. Unpublis doctoral dissertation, Michigan State University .1975. Taylor, C. The explanation pj_behavior. London: Routledge & Kegan Paol, 1965. 62 Wallace, M. An investigation Lf future time perspective in schizo- phrenia. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Michigan— State University, 1954. Wallace, M., and Rabin, A. Temporal experience. Psychological Bulle- 313, 1960, 21, 213-236. Werner, H. Comparative psychology_Lf mental develgpment. New York: International Universities Press, 1973. Werner, H., and Kaplan, B. Symbol formation. New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1964. Whitehead, A.N. The function 9: reason. Boston: Beacon Press, 1966. Witkin, H., et a1. Psychological differentiation. New York: Wiley, 1962. Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan, 1970.