__THS ,I—FOJ/t‘ IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII IIIIII IL I LIBRARY I Michigan Shh Unlurslty This is to certify that the thesis entitled THE PERSECUTION OF THE PHILISTINES: THE AUTHORITY OF W. SOMERSET MAUGHAM presented by Rosemary Erickson Pierce has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for the M.A. degree in English WIN... A {M Major professor Date—iehWO 0-7639 MS U is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution — PLACE IN RETURN BOX to removofthls checkout from your record. TO AVOID FINES return on or batons date duo. DATE DUE DATE DUE DATE DUE __......_._._...._I IL__ MSU Is An Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institmion em“: THE PERSECUTION OF THE PHILISTINES: THE AUTHORITY OF W. SOMERSET MAUGHAM BY Rosemary Erickson Pierce A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Department of English 1990 ABSTRACT THE PERSECUTION OF THE PHILISTINES: THE AUTHORITY OF W} SOMERSET MAUGHAM By Rosemary Erickson Pierce Somerset Maugham's preoccupations have often been disparaged as philistine: yet Maugham is rarely consulted as an expert on philistinism or, more precisely, philis- tine disparaging as a stereotype of persecution. After tracing the gathering force of the term philistine as an accusation in the nineteenth century, and the charge of philistinism brought against Maugham throughout his career, this thesis reevaluates Maugham by emphasizing his understanding of philistine disparaging as a system of accusation. Texts used are Qahes_an§_51g, Qfi_flgman Bondage, and Ing_narrgg_ggzner, and René Girard's Mensgnge WW- Dedicated to Steven Nelson Pierce iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My first thanks must go to Rob Scott, who recommended Maugham's work to me, and thanks also to Paul Schellinger, who "went through a Maugham phase." I am grateful to Professor Victor Paananen, who contributed significantly to my decision to do graduate work in English. I sincerely appreciate the time given to this project by Professor M. Teresa Tavormina, to whose insights and suggestions I have not done justice. Professor William Johnsen, as my thesis advisor, gave many hours to this project. Without his assistance, this thesis could not have been written. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 Maugham's Critics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 Maugham and the Philistines . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Looking Forward . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 Notes . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 73 works Cited 0 O O O O I O O O O O O O O O I O I O O 7 8 INTRODUCTION In Eifi2_H9rKe_2f_Bnglish_Literatnre_fle_£guld_Qo Without, the reader of Somerset Maugham novels learns that the best that can be said of Ihg_nggn_gn§ Sixpence and, for that matter, of Maugham’s entire oeuvre, is that it is admirable middle- brow stuff, ideally geared to the demands of the stockbroker who likes to parade his literacy but has no taste for literature. (127) Those who scorn Maugham and his "cynical pot-boiling" (125) would probably find this assessment of his work amusing; for those who value Maugham’s work, however, it is an extremely annoying categorization. It is annoying not because it is valid, but because it echoes the charge so often found in Maugham criticism: Maugham is a philistine, he writes for the philistines, and only a philistine would appreciate his work. This charge is a particularly insidious one, for what literary person would want to align himself with that stockbroker? Call Maugham a philistine or label yourself one--that is the simple choice such criticism offers. But what does it mean to be called a philistine? What is a philistine? And having reached some kind of answer to that question, how can we put our understanding of this slander to use? Might it not illuminate Maugham’s work and help us understand his critical reception? Philistine conjures up images of blasts from Matthew Arnold, of Victorian respectability, of the bourgeois. Turning to the QED, however, one learns that originally the name referred to the people who lived along the southern coast of Palestine. That is straightforward enough to avoid confusion about who these people are, even if there are strong negative connotations arising from the philistines' unhappy relations with the Israelites. From the end of the sixteenth century, when the word turned into a general purpose term for one’s enemies, the philis- tine became increasingly difficult to define. Your enemy, after all, may not be the same as mine. The word’s meaning began to approach our sense of it through a nineteenth-century borrowing from German. anilistg; was what German students called those not attending a university, and the Victorians gleefully borrowed it for those "deficient in liberal culture and enlightenment, whose interests are chiefly bounded by material and commonplace things" (932 2, 2153). The term is a very useful one, for the difficulty of judging someone by these slippery criteria makes defense against an accusation of philistinism virtually impossible. As the 939 notes, the word is "often applied contemptuously by connoisseurs of any particular art or department of learning to one who has no knowledge or appreciation of it; [it is] sometimes a mere term of dislike for those whom the speaker considers 'bourgeois'” (2, 2153). Notice the multiplication of "tests" for philistinism implied by this ever broadening definition: it becomes ever easier to say that someone has failed your particular philistine litmus test and has therefore been proven ”guilty." Philistine is clearly a very handy label to keep about, ready for use. Turning to Matthew Arnold, the high priest of the philistine despisers, one finds that philistine gives the notion of something particularly stiff-necked and perverse in the resistance to light and its children; and therein it specially suits our middle class, who not only do not pursue sweetness and light, but who even prefer to them that sort of machinery of business, chapels, tea-meetings, and addresses from Mr. Murphy, which makes up the dismal and illiberal life on which I have so often touched. (206) Arnold links business activities and personal interests, and he evidently does so in order to set up an opposi- tional relationship between the "dismal and illiberal life” of the philistines and the life of those who "pursue sweetness and light." Between the confusion caused by the first trick and the vague language used in the second, however, he clarifies our definition of the philistine very little. (After all, how does one devote one's life to pursuing sweetness and light? What is required by such a calling?) This kind of defining, while it may not clear the matter up, does intensify it; it adds a sense of urgency to the search for a definition. There is a sense of indignation evident in Arnold's words, almost as if the philistines had offended some moral or religious prin- ciple. The reader senses the horror of being "stiff- necked and perverse in the resistance to light and its children" and winces to think of actually prejgxzing that "sort of machinery of business," etc., to cultural pursuits. There are several essential observations that can be made about the term philistine, observations which can bring us closer to a clearer definition and, at the same time, to an improved understanding of how the word functions. A necessary prerequisite to understanding "the philistine" is recognizing that the word does more than denote a particular social and economic class of person. Hidden beneath the surface is a whole accusational system. The idea of the philistine and its multitudinous connotations became so firmly entrenched in our literary culture that it seemed a black and white matter of us against them, with the philistine always filling the role of "them.” Recent critical and cultural theory has allowed us to see that "philistinism" is a cultural term open to debate, but withdrawing the accusation is easier than eliminating its effects on Maugham's work. Those who have achieved sophistication in critical theory are still able to overlook or condemn Maugham as a philistine: understanding the phenomenon in the largest sense does not preclude (ab)using it in specific cases like Maugham's.1 HAUGHAH'S CRITICS Maugham's novels ought to be required reading not only as reparation for the damage done him as an accused "philistine,"2 but also because his work rewards attention paid to it; for not only is philistinism a subject on which he provides a lot of insight in his literary works, his fate as a writer also reveals a great deal about the workings of philistine disparagement as a system of accusation. To approach a more complete definition of the philistine, one can look at Maugham criticism, for much of the criticism relies on the terminology of anti- philistinism. Those who wish to denigrate Maugham often do so by accusing him of being a philistine: those who wish to support Maugham often fall back on defenses against these charges of philistinism. His passionately condemnatory critics are what first focused my attention seriously on Maugham. If Maugham is "an author whose works brought fame and riches but never respect and honor" (Higdon 710), why do critics spend so much time and energy beating Maugham down? It is easy to think of twentieth-century writers whose works have sold well and made lots of money; it is even fairly simple to name members of that group who have claimed literary status, yet literary critics are not writing articles berating these writers. Maugham's case is clearly more complicated than this. One indication of the intensity of the anti-Maugham critics is the way negative remarks about Maugham creep in where no remarks about Maugham's work are necessary. Margaret Drabble, in her review of Ted Morgan's 1980 biography of Maugham, could not resist the temptation to take pot shots at Maugham while criticizing Morgan's work: "like Maugham, Mr. Morgan is no stylist: he writes inelegantly, relays apocryphal jokes, quotes gossip as though it were fact, is immensely repetitive and loves to explain the obvious" (l, 24). David Higdon similarly indulges in gratuitous Maugham bashing in his review of Morgan's book: "the biography consists of surfaces with little depth beneath them. In other words, it resembles a Maugham novel” (709). Neither of these reviews made any positive reference to Maugham's work, and Higdon suggests that what makes Maugham worthy of a biography is not his writing, but the fact that he is "perhaps one of our best representatives of the Edwardian compromises" (709). Any survey of the criticism of Maugham's work, even if only intended to reconfirm its hostility, must situate the sheer repetition of class-bound complaints. Maugham criticism is remarkably consistent, and thus looking at only a selection of work3 forces the reader of Maugham to conclude that what is "wrong" with Maugham is that he is a philistine. Consider, for example, the language that 21ft24flgrk§ uses to discuss Maugham. He "lacks intellec- tual imagination" (126): he ”can observe, but he cannot create" (126). What is most telling here is the class- bound name calling: Maugham "has a window dresser's idea of elegance, and a shop assistant's concept of romance. When he writes of Tahiti his language is that of a travel agent" (127), and "at his best he was a good reporter" (126). Window dresser, shop assistant, travel agent, reporter--deliver the authors of £1fi;y_flggh§ from the philistines!4 There is also a noticeable financial element in Maugham criticism. Before "popular writer” and "serious writer" came to be viewed as two mutually exclusive categories, it reflected well on a writer to sell a lot of books.5 In the twentieth century, however, selling well has become suspect. When Graham Greene laments that Maugham "his been misled . . . by his own [financial] success" (201), we sense that Maugham is being mildly chastised. It is an unfortunate time for literature, Greene suggests when he says that Writers belonging to a less easily appreciated school than the anecdotal, who depend for their market on the intellectual magazine, are lucky if they can earn twenty pounds by a short story, while the writer who fits the taste of the popular magazine may well earn ten times that sum. It is seldom that financial worry is a condition for the best work. (201-02) This opposition is familiar to us--the intellectual and the popular. We are to believe that the "intellectual" writer, who is poorly paid, deserves our sympathy and admiration for struggling on in spite of financial difficulty: it is considered a given that this "intel- lectual" writing is valuable. 0n the other hand, the work of the "writer who fits the taste of the popular magazine" is "easily appreciated" so we mark ourselves as common if we appreciate it too.6 Perhaps the best known piece of Maugham criticism is Edmund Wilson's "The Apotheosis of Somerset Maugham." This piece, first printed in 1946, blasts Maugham from beginning to end, and in some important ways it has become the standard for anti-Maugham criticism. In it a reader can discern the seeds of the casual condemnations tossed off by sources as diverse as Margaret Drabble and fifty Work§--in a sense, Wilson made it fashionable to pan Maugham. He certainly helped set the terms for subsequent debate. 10 One of the key points of Wilson's article is that an appreciation for Maugham's work marks a decline in literary standards: appreciate Maugham, Wilson warns, and mark yourself a part of this lamentable decline. Maugham, Wilson asserts, is on a level completely different (lower) from that of "real” writers like Joyce, James, and Yeats. Furthermore, Wilson claims, Maugham recognizes this fact and resents it even while he does not understand what it is that makes these ”real" writers great: We get the impression of a malcontent eye cocked up from the brackish waters of the ggsmgpglitan magazine, and a peevish and insistent grumbling. There is something going on, on the higher ground, that halfway compels his respect, but he does not quite understand what it is, and in any case he can never get up there. (324) The message here is not subtle, but just in case we missed it, Wilson spells it out for us one more time: Maugham is for our time "what Bulwer-Lytton was for Dickens's: a half-trashy novelist, who writes badly, but is patronized by half-serious readers, who do not care much about writing" (326). Wilson's description of Maugham's readers as philistines (his remarks bring to mind our stockbroker friend in Eifty_flgrk§) sets up the choice mentioned earlier: malign Maugham or share in his guilt. In other words, you must join Wilson's group of those who prove 11 themselves not to be philistines by condemning the philistine among them or you inescapably mark yourself as a new target. Claiming that you value Maugham's work but are no; a philistine has little effect: since philistine is never used in a complimentary manner, no one is likely to describe himself as one, and assertions of "innocence" are therefore automatically suspect. In any case, you have been forced into defending yourself on the terms that Wilson has laid out. Once the issue of philistinism has been raised, you must use its terminology whether you choose to agree or disagree with the accuser. Wilson, like most of the Maugham bashers who follow him, reverts to name calling. He constructs an extended metaphor of Maugham as schoolboy, through which he denigrates Maugham for poor grammar, cliches, banal language, and unrhythmic prose (319-21). Not only is Maugham a schoolboy, but he is not an especially competent one: his handling of "a promising subject" suggests "one of the less brilliant contributions to a prep-school magazine" (321). Maugham does, however, have some advantages over our mythical schoolboy. He has more knowledge of the world than a schoolboy would have been likely to acquire, but that schoolboy, grown-up and much travelled, having somehow been diverted from his normal career of 12 law, medicine, diplomacy or parliament, might have produced such a novel as Then_and_flgw [the particular occasion for this review]: did, in fact produce it. (322-23) This, I feel, is the heart of Wilson’s dislike for Maugham: he is a member of the bourgeoisie, he comes from a family of lawyers, he has medical training. Maugham's class precludes his being a "real" writer. Instead of trying to write, Maugham should be practicing law or medicine. Wilson does offer some consolation, however: if one defines things carefully it is almost possible to make Maugham disappear: Maugham "is not, in the sense of {having the metier,’ really a writer at all" (319). What is most discouraging about this attack on Maugham is the lack of foundation for these conclusions. Because there are so many tests for philistinism, and because the meaning is so extended, a critic may fault Maugham for philistinism on scant grounds. At the time he wrote this review Edmund Wilson had read very little by Maugham. He says that he swore to read Then_anfi_figw completely "if only in order to be able to say that I had read a book of Maugham's through" (320), and he admits that he had not read any of Maugham's short stories. If he has not read a complete novel or a single short story, how is it that he has ”never been able to convince myself that [Maugham] was anything but second rate" (319)? 13 Critics are far more careful than this with other writers: it is hard, for example, to imagine a critic dismissing Dickens having read only bits and pieces of A_th1§;ma§ Carol and ngyig_ggppgzfi1g1§. In fact, the rule seems inverted for Maugham criticism: it is better to have up; read than to bag; read his work. Wilson is proud of having not read Maugham, and he seems to present this weakness as one of his credentials: he wins agreement from his readers by suggesting that ’of course he does not read Maugham.’ There have, of course, been critics who found praiseworthy qualities in Maugham's work. Theodore Dreiser’s review of Maugham's work was occasioned by the publication of Q£_flgman_figng§gg, so it precedes Edmund Wilson's review by over thirty years. Even in 1915, however, there were condemnatory reviewers and critics. Dreiser mentions his "surprise to find that the English reviews were almost uniformly contemptuous and critical" (203), and he scans some of the adverse American criti- cism, the standard hyperbolic fare, which he sums up as "too trite" (203). Dreiser nonetheless asserts the novel’s value firmly: "Despite these dissonant voices it is still a book of the utmost import" (203): it is "a novel or biography or autobiography or social transcript of the utmost importance" (202). 14 Dreiser heaps praise on Qf_flnnan_flgndage much as other critics heap scorn upon it. It is a near perfect piece of fiction: ”In viewing it one finds nothing to criticise or to regret. The thing sings, it has color. It has rapture. You wonder at the loving patient care which has evolved it" (202). Dreiser says that Maugham's descriptions are very apt, whether of the life of English clerks or of the particular characters who populate the novel. The novel contains "material . . . for many novels and indeed several philosophies, and even a religion or stoic hope" (202), and it is throughout "a gorgeous weave, as interesting and valuable at the beginning as at the end" (202). The language Dreiser uses to describe the novel indicates the unreserved nature of his approval. After Dreiser dismisses the anti-philistine criticisms of the book with ”too trite," he ignores them and writes about Maugham and Qf_fluman_fign§age on his own terms. And what does he see in it once he is not distracted by the philistine disparagers? For Dreiser, not only is Qfi_fluman_ngngagg a great book, but Maugham is a great writer. In fact, Dreiser twice calls him a genius, and he compares this novel to works in other art forms--it is like a symphony by Beethoven or a portrait by Rembrandt. Maugham has suffered, and he has "an immense capacity for 15 understanding and pity” (203). What is particularly noteworthy for Dreiser is Maugham's honesty: ”no situation, however crude or embarrassing, has been shirked” (203). The result of this honesty is not sensational or immoral, but 'unmoral' (202). This, to my mind, is one of Maugham’s most valuable characteristics, one that few other writers share. Me neither advocates the establishment morality nor does he impose an alternative anti-establishment morality on his readers. This, however, leaves him open to misinterpretation and condemnation by bgth points of view. Twenty years later, Graham Greene’s mixed comments on Maugham echoed some of Dreiser’s praises. In particular, he made explicit Dreiser's praise of Maugham's honesty and expanded on that theme. For Greene, honesty is Maugham’s most noteworthy attribute, and he sees it coloring many aspects of Maugham's work, from his subject matter to his writing style. He emphasizes the often-overlooked value of honesty when he refers to "Maugham’s honest unenthusi- astic mind. I do not mean pedantic or unimaginative. Honesty is a form of sensitivity" (198). Maugham's style is informed by this honesty as well: Greene discusses Maugham's "hard-won style at its best, clear, colloquial, honest" (203), and he says that the "quality of honest experience . . . gives his style such vividness” (198). This plain honesty that Greene praises seems to be another 16 way of talking about the unmoral nature of Maugham's work. "The characteristic most evident" in Maugham's best work, Greene tells us, ”is honesty" (197). Boiling Maugham down to his essence, Greene finds honesty, and this seems fitting praise. If Greene remembers it as an "unhappy honesty" (205) because it lacks Christian spirituality, that need not negate our positive view of it. Before looking at what Maugham has to say about the philistine and our culture's use of the word, I would like to consider what this survey of important Maugham criticism has added to our definition. Looking at the elements of this criticism, we can see more clearly what "philistine” means in a literary context. From the negative criticism we can see that a philistine who writes comes from the middle classes and might more appropriately be pursuing a career in law or something similar. Because he comes from the middle classes, he writes for them (the stockbrokers, those who read half-seriously): because he writes for them, he writes badly (inelegantly, repeti- tively, ungrammatically, banally, unrhythmically, super- ficially, and with lots of cliches and a very heavy hand). His middle-class past is continually getting in his way by causing him to see things through the eyes of a shop assistant rather than those of an artist. He lacks 17 creativity and imagination: he does not really have the calling of a writer: and he cannot even grasp what it is that serious writers do. Because his work is so philis- tine, however, he sells a great many books and enjoys considerable financial success. This portrait fits quite well with our intuitive sense of the philistine. The positive commentary by Dreiser and Greene, however, shows us other ways in which this portrait might be delineated. The "philistine" as a writer is a keen observer and a frank writer. These attributes allow him to create accurate and enduring social/cultural records. Because the literary philistine is unmoral, the reader is not forced to take any particular stand but is free to enjoy the text and the cultural commentary. Finally, his prose is "clear, colloquial, honest" (Greene 203) prose written in a vivid style, and this makes his work eminently readable.7 If it is legitimate to label a writer philistine on the strength of the negative portrait sketched out above, surely it ought to be equally legitimate to call him a philistine based on the positive one as well. Before we can do this, however, we need to adjust our perception of what a philistine is: in order to see the need to make that adjustment, we need to understand how the word philistine has turned into a whole system of accusation. Maugham's novels can help us see what is going on. MAUGHAM AND THE PHILISTINES The original title of Rene Girard's peggit,_pg§1;gL W18 W. and the difference between the two titles seems to me an important one, for the French title simultaneously suggests what is wrong with Maugham criticism and what is right about Maugham’s work: the Romantic preconceptions of the critics lead them to brand his work philistine, but that work nonetheless rewards with special insight the reader who can loosen the grip of those preconceptions and read Maugham as he should be read. Maugham's work can go a long way in explaining our thriving accusational system of philistine disparagement, but he can do this only if we can rescue him from the claustrophobic grip of the Romantic readings we usually give him. This is not easy. As Girard explains, "Nous portons en nous une hiérarchie du superficiel et du profond, de l’essentiel et de l'accessoire, que nous appliquons instinctivement a l'oeuvre romanesque. Cette hierarchie, d’inspiration <>, <> et <> nous cache certains aspects essentiels de la creation artistique" (M323 308). This, I believe, is relevant for 18 19 Maugham studies, for once we can read Maugham without letting such instinctive judgments get in the way, we are amply rewarded. Another immediate difficulty many readers encounter in reading Maugham is his strong presence as narrator. This strong presence is often perceived as a failing: ‘21:;y_flgzk§, to cite just one example, says that Maugham's characters in one novel "are the same extensions of his own personality who litter the pages of his other novels" (126-27). However, as Anthony Burgess points out the personality of the novelist is important to us--the personality as revealed in his work and not in his private life. . . . The author is present with us on every page, sometimes, as with Somerset Maugham, as an idealised portrait ranking as a character--rational, tolerant, travelled--though more often as the man whose heavy breathing we can hear as he puts his words together. (18) Once we accept that all authors are "with us on every page," Maugham's "crime" becomes insignificant. He simply makes little pretense of being removed from the novel, of "seeking the anonymity of the divine creator" (18) in Burgess's terms. So what can we learn from his novelistic voice, his "rational, tolerant, travelled" voice? Among other things, we can learn a great deal about how 20 philistine disparagement functions, how it has become systematized. The primary rule for use of the word philistine is that the (acc)user never means anything good by it. In 9; Hgman_figndage, Maugham has presented us with a stereotypi- cal philistine in the character of Watson. Maugham reflects the exclusively negative meaning for philistine when he says that "while [Philip] looked upon Watson as a Philistine he could not help admiring him" (162), for it is clear from this that to admire a philistine is an awkward surprise, a reaction that ought to be resisted. When Maugham describes the "philistine" Watson, the reader instinctively sympathizes with Maugham and Philip. As soon as we learn that Watson is "’a son of Watson, Crag, and Thompson--you know--the brewers'" (158) he is marked a philistine, and Maugham does not disappoint our expectation. Watson is wealthy, sharply dressed, and very self-confident, the antithesis of Philip. Upon meeting him, Philip is somewhat overpowered by the young gentleman's condescension. At Blackstable they had always looked upon brewing with civil contempt, the Vicar made little jokes about the beerage, and it was a surprising experience for Philip to 21 discover that Watson was such an important and magnificent fellow. (159) We are implicated in this labelling of Watson, for we, the readers, would no doubt join in the laughter at those "little jokes about the beerage." Watson is further marked by being unable to appreciate Philip's hard-won cultural achievements, and he, like their boss in the accounting office, talks too much about his own status as a gentleman: "Philip was overwhelmed by so much gentleman- liness: in East Anglia they knew who were gentlemen and who weren't but the gentlemen didn't talk about it" (160). Who can help but see Watson as a philistine? We grant superiority to the East Anglian system of gentlemanliness almost instinctively, and those who fly in the face of its rules are philistines. Because we have become so habituated to philistine disparaging, the absence of any positive implications may seem obvious and unobjectionable. This absence is not altogether surprising, because we despise the philistine and our hate transforms him, our enemy: "La haine . . . ecrit chaque jour pour nous de la vie de nos ennemis le roman le plus faux. Elle leur suppose, au lieu d'un mediocre bonheur humain, traversé de peines communes qui viendraient remuer en nous de douces sympathies, une joie insolente qui s’offre irritante pour 22 notre rage. Elle transfigure autant que le désir et comme lui nous assoiffe de sang humain.” (Proust in M313 46-47) This image of writing "le roman le plus faux” is an especially pertinent one for readers of Maugham, since "readers" like Edmund Wilson have, in a sense, IEEIILIED Maugham's work in order to cast him out as a philistine. It is essential that we ignore those rewritings and read Maugham ourselves to find the truths in what he wrote. As Girard points out, we must see the philistine in black and white terms: he is not allowed to have any good qualities because our hate will not allow this. Unsurprising does not, however, mean just, and beneath the surface of our picture of a philistine rest many worthwhile attributes. Maugham gives us characters who are to be considered philistines, but even as he shows us that judgment on them he is careful to reveal that those we consider philistine often behave far better than we are prepared to admit. That consummate philistine Watson has, after all, some very redeeming qualities. New to London, hampered by shyness and his physical handicap, Philip is very lonely. Watson is unpretentious and kind hearted enough to invite Philip out, even though Watson has plenty of friends (male and female) to spend his time with. That their friendship does not develop very far is more a reflection on Philip than it is on Watson: Watson has gone out of his way to be 23 friendly, and Philip is too reserved and offended by Watson’s lack of ”culture" to meet him halfway. We see this phenomenon again when Philip's concern for Cronshaw's health elicits a scornful reaction: Cronshaw gives Philip "the quizzical look with which he reproved the admonitions of common sense" (404) and looks at him "in the way which had formerly had the power of making him feel incredibly narrow" (404). Cronshaw undervalues, as we might, the accused philistine's concern for him. Philip's concern is genuine, and it goes far beyond a polite inquiry: he takes on the burden of sharing his own lodgings with the dying Cronshaw. The exclusively negative implications of being a philistine can also be seen in the way philistines are often defined in opposition to things which we value. Because "1e snobisme commence a l’egalité . . . [et] les distinctions réelles et concretes de ces classes n'ont rien a voir avec les distinctions abstraites du snobisme" (£313 75), we have to define ourselves by eegepliehing differences to take the place of the real differences that have been lost. In Girard’s historical model, these differences have been lost through the processes of Western democratization which have levelled classes formerly anchored in birth-connected status. In order to establish these differences, the qualities of the 24 philistine must be seen as having no connection to those which we possess: they must in fact represent the oppo- sites of ours. Since the philistine is "bad" he is credited with the contrary of each of our cherished "good" qualities. Accordingly, Matthew Arnold described philis- tinism as a contrast to "sweetness and light," and the philistine is held to be actively against all things cul- tural, unappreciative of them, or just plain ignorant about them. This philistine opposition to cultural pursuits is one of our most basic pieces of dogma about philistinism. Equally basic is our belief in the financial ruthlessness of the philistine: we understand that the philistine is a materialist who will do whatever he can to make more money so that he may spend it on displays of wealth. While Maugham’s work reflects that side of the issue, he also reveals the financial maneuverings of those who disparage the philistines. The sense of moral superiority that accompanies philistine despising allows the despiser to feel simultaneously free of financial responsibility and assured of the accused philistine's responsibility to take care of him. In The_Ne;;eg_QQ;ner, Dr. Saunders, who seems particularly knowledgeable about philistine disparaging, understands how this works: [Idealists] were apt to look down upon those who were occupied with practical matters but not 25 averse from profiting by their industry. Like the lilies of the field they neither toiled nor spun, but took it as a right that others should perform for them these menial offices. (116) George Frith is one of these "lilies of the field." Educated to be a schoolteacher, he ended up on a remote island after a long period of drifting from one job to another, finally marrying into the Swan family and its plantation. His father-in-law is scornful of Frith because of his inability to keep a job or to get anything constructive done, but Frith considers himself above such complaints. He feels that it is "absurd to hurl such charges at a man who had spent twenty years in the study of the highly metaphysical thought of the Hindus and in whom in all probability dwelt the spirit of a celebrated Portuguese poet" (3; 129). This is surely no more absurd than the rationales of other philistine scorners, but Maugham has made it seem so by changing the perspective. We see Frith through the eyes of a detached (Maugham-like) observer and not through his own, which makes an enormous difference to our perception of him. Perhaps more importantly, though, Maugham has substituted for cultural pursuits to which we grant legitimacy--like painting or writing philosophy--some we do not. This substitution makes Frith seem merely ridiculous. 26 This particular lily of the field is also not an appealing character because he has managed to survive only because his wife "’ran the estate and looked after things and made both ends meet'" (139). She accepts the superiority of his value system, even though she can do so only at her own expense: she was pleased to "'think of Frith sitting in his den with his books, reading and writing and making notes. She thought him a genius. She thought everything she did for him was only his due’" (139). Her agreement with this hierarchy of values does not make us respect Frith more: instead, it suggests that Frith probably treated her as if everything she did was "only his due." Upjohn's funeral plans (in Qflfl), discussed more fully below, are another example of this phenomenon. He never considers making a financial contribution, but he still feels assured of his right to belittle Philip's arrange- ments and to offer improbable suggestions. He is enamored of his plan for a grand funeral and seems to find nothing odd in half-expecting Philip to pay for its implementa- tion. Cronshaw also exhibits this same kind of financial presumptuousness. While he is grateful for what Philip's money is providing him with, he still reserves the right to belittle Philip's philistinism on intellectual grounds. He complains to Upjohn of Philip's behavior and he gently 27 mocks Philip's sense of responsibility, but he allows Philip to house and feed him. Edward Driffield is another Maugham character who allows the philistines to serve him, although his situation is more complex than the others. He does not denigrate the philistines as Frith, Upjohn, and Cronshaw do, but he does seem to take pleasure in needling them, and he certainly manipulates them effectively. When Ashenden is a child, Driffield arranges for their brass- rubbing outing by playing on the philistine elements in the vicar's personality: he lets Mrs. Barton Trafford forward his career without reciprocating with the sense of obligation to her she expects (he even marries someone else surreptitiously): and he benefits in many ways from his judicious handling of his second wife's philistinism. Even though Amy Driffield seems a bit officious, the reader should not overlook the fact that she does devote a great deal of time to taking excellent care of old Driffield. The benefits that she receives are consid- erable, but they do not negate what she does for Driffield. He gains the benefits of philistinism while leaving himself in a morally superior position: she receives the scorn of Ashenden and the reader while he profits from her labors but escapes the scorn. Through these lilies of the field, Maugham shows us that profiting from the philistine's resources-- 28 intellectual, physical, emotional, and especially financial--does not make the philistine disparager lose any of his sense of superiority. As it is hardly credible that these people are unaware of what they gain from the philistines, it seems that they are not above basic financial planning: they merely approach their financial ends by means more surreptitious than those employed by the philistine. Part of Maugham's development of the oppositionally defined philistine (that is, the philistine who is identified by what he does neg do, believe, understand) takes place in the context of Driffield’s work, and this context will get us closer to the character of the philistine in literature. Driffield's novels, Ashenden tells us, are anti-philistine. This necessarily implies that they are literary: ”to admire Ine_§gp_efi_L1fie became a mark of aesthetic acumen: to be shocked by it was to confess yourself a philistine" (157). Associated with the literary, and therefore in opposition to the philistine, are several features of Driffield’s work: "though his books sold but little, and one or two were banned by the libraries, it was very much a mark of culture to admire him. He was thought boldly realistic. He was a very good stick to beat the Philistines with" (93). By describing 29 Driffield's work in anti-philistine terms, Maugham has given us an implicit sketch of the philistine: to see what a literary philistine is, we need only invert the description of Driffield's work. By doing so we learn that the literary philistine's books fail to meet legitimate aesthetic standards, sell very well, are the ultimate in respectability (and thus are appropriate for conscientious lending libraries), and are not "boldly realistic." Q§£§§_AEQ_Al§ contains a fully drawn picture of the author who would produce books such as these. The novelist and multipurpose writer Alroy Kear is the epitome of the literary philistine. Kear, we are told, approaches literature pragmatically rather than artistically: in fact, to borrow Edmund Wilson's phrase, one could say that Rear "is not, in the sense of 'having the metier,’ really a writer at all" (319). Kear has achieved success by giving the public what it wants: he is a "popular" writer with little substance. Notably, much of what critics say about Maugham echoes what Ashenden says about Kear. Maugham's narrator even begins to sound like Edmund Wilson, sixteen years before Wilson wrote his review of Maugham’s Ihen_eng_ueg, as when Ashenden says of Rear: ”though I have finished few of his novels, I have begun a good many" (18). 3O Maugham, however, moves beyond the place his critics are content to rest and shows us how this philistine labelling works. As the narrator portrays him, Rear is always aware of what is current, and he makes a concerted effort to follow the trends, both literary and extra- literary. Rear "published his first novel at the period when men of letters, to show their virility, drank beer and played cricket, and for some years there was seldom a literary eleven in which his name did not figure" (12). When cricket goes out, those who remain cricketers ”find difficulty in placing their articles" (13) but Hear has ”ceased playing cricket a good many years ago, and he has developed a fine taste for claret" (13). He moved on at the right time, and because this judicious switch from cricket to claret helped his literary career, it seems unadmirable to us. What motivates Kear, however, is no different than what motivates those still playing cricket and those who never took it up at all: Kear is simply playing smarter than the competition, proving his masculinity and furthering his career at the same time. Kear is an excellent guest, just the sort of author hostesses desired for their tea parties, and he joined all the right clubs. He has "a pretty gift for after-dinner speaking" (13) which further enhances his value. He can sense who is "in" as well as he can tell what is "in," and since Ashenden's reputation had been experiencing a 31 downturn, he had not seen Rear for some time before Kear's proposal about the Driffield biography. The great success of his literary career comes in part from these astute decisions--he is not an extra- ordinarily gifted writer, but he is well aware of the political rules governing literature. He is careful and conscientious: ”Roy was very modest about his first novel. It was short, neatly written, and, as is everything he has produced since, in perfect taste. He sent it with a pleasant letter to all the leading writers of the day, and in this he told each one how greatly he admired his works" (13), etc., etc. He maintained the same attitude for his second novel: "he took great pains with it and he profited by the advice his elders in the craft had given him" (14). This novel repeated his initial success, but not to such a degree that it alienated his supporters. Instead, "it confirmed them in their suspicions that he would never set the Thames on fire" (14), and so they were happy to continue helping him out, confident that he posed no threat to them. Kear, however, played the game so well that he rose above many of his benefactors. As the narrator tells us, "I know some who smile bitterly now when they reflect on the mistake they made" (14). Rear has not done anything disgraceful--any beginning writer would be grateful for whatever help others were willing to 32 provide. If anything, the sincerity of their "help" is more suspect than the sincerity of Kear's intentions, for they clearly intended to assist him only within some decidedly circumscribed limits. Hear is an excellent self-evaluator: he knows what his strengths are and he maximizes them. Furthermore, he knows his place in literature and does not aspire to Wilson’s "higher ground": ”'I know I'm not a great novelist,’ he will tell you. 'When I compare myself with the giants I simply don't exist. . . . I do my best. I do work. I never let anything slipshod get past me. I think I can tell a good story and I can create characters that ring true’" (14). After all is said and done, he knows he has achieved a success that no one can take away from him: "'after all, the proof of the pudding is in the eating: Ih§_E¥§_Q£_§h2_E§§§l§ sold thirty-five thousand in England and eighty thousand in America, and for the serial rights of my next book I’ve got the biggest terms I've ever had yet'" (14). Maugham shares more of what he knows about this particular system of accusation by making us a part of it. Our narrator accuses Rear of philistinism, and we immediately chime in. But what exactly is it that makes us despise Hear and dismiss him as a novelist? Looking back over what we are told about him, and thinking rather than accusing, it becomes evident that we despise him 33 because he is just like us. All of his transgressions are ones that we too are guilty of, and some represent accomplishments many of us have not yet achieved (like benefiting from good advice). So why are we so scornful? I suspect that our scorn springs from resentment: if we wrote novels, we are secretly convinced, they would be nothing less than brilliant. Alroy Hear (and Somerset Maugham?) achieved more success with lesser talents than we have, we grumble to ourselves. Maugham’s reflection of this accusatory system, because he lays it out for us to examine, demonstrates its inherent unreasonableness. Why should we expect writers to be different from us, to be above the concerns that constitute our lives, to be antisocial and completely unconcerned about others’ opinions? How can we expect them to do the impossible? The simple fact of publication makes indifference an impossible demand. As Girard points out, "cette dialectique de l’appel qui se nie en tant qu’appel se retrouve dans la littérature contemporaine. Ecrire, et surtout publier un ouvrage c’est en appeler au public, c’est rompre, par un geste unilateral, 1a relation d’indifférence entre 801 et les Autres" (£313 263). Those writers who meet with our instinctive philistine-despising standards, then, have set themselves the unusual (not to mention impossible) task of trying to sell us something 34 while maintaining that they are uninterested in our purchase: as Girard puts it, "on ecrit pour prouver au lecteur qu’on se moque de ses suffrages' (M313 264). Maugham gives us an example of this paradox in Cronshaw: he never published his poetry, but once death is approaching, he decides to do it. After all, he believes, there is "something fine in keeping to himself these treasures of beauty all his life and giving them to the world disdainfully when, he and the world parting company, he had no further use for them" (933 406). And yet what finally brings him to England to arrange the publication is the publisher’s offer of "ten pounds in advance of royalties" (407), royalties which will exist only if the buying public likes Cronshaw’s work. In his enthusiasm, Cronshaw puffs up thinking of his money being "’in advance of royalties, mind you . . . Milton only got ten pounds down’" (407). His disdain for the world has fled in the face of an opportunity to sell his work to it. Maugham also gives us a writer who is a self- professed anti-philistine, 933’s Leonard Upjohn, and his interactions with the philistines tell us even more about philistine disparaging. Upjohn is part of an interesting triangular relationship (Cronshaw and Philip constituting the rest of the triangle) that revolves around the philistine-despising system. In this triangle, Upjohn’s 35 position is clear--he loudly and repeatedly accuses Philip of philistinism. He romanticizes Cronshaw as a great, dying poet: he deplores Philip’s practicality, especially when money is an issue. Philip’s position seems to be a moderate one: he sees its limitations, but believes that it is essentially an honorable one. He recognizes that Upjohn considers him a philistine, but he does not agree with that assessment, something which does not, however, prevent him from judging others to be philistines. Cronshaw presides over this situation, apparently recognizing and accepting both Philip’s and Upjohn’s attitudes. His views on philistinism are, however, at least as complex as Philip’s. He realizes that Philip has changed his life for the better: he knows that Upjohn will "’do nothing more for [him] than write a pretty article about [him] after [his] death’" (414-15). This awareness notwithstanding, he complains incessantly about Philip to Upjohn, and when the situation reaches a breaking point, he simply laughs the matter off. It is not made clear whether he views Philip as a philistine, for when Philip renewed their friendship in London by sending a note to Cronshaw, he replied that he would be very glad to see Philip. His reply read, ”I am a stranger in a strange city and I am buffeted by the philistines" (403), a statement which would seem to confer upon Philip the same 36 high moral position Cronshaw has staked out for himself. When they do meet, however, Cronshaw behaves as if Philip were a philistine, mocking Philip’s concern for his health and living accommodations. In any case, when Philip and Cronshaw do get together in London, Cronshaw is preparing his manuscript for publication, as arranged by Upjohn. Cronshaw is dying from cirrhosis of the liver, and his financial situation has forced him into miserable lodgings in Soho. Philip, as mentioned previously, moves Cronshaw in with him. Upjohn visits Cronshaw at Philip’s two or three times a week, and Philip becomes the main target for his insistent philistine disparaging. He belittles what Philip has provided for Cronshaw on the grounds of its philistinism: "’I wish you had left him in Soho. There was a touch of romance in that sordid attic. I could bear it if it were Wapping or Shoreditch, but the respectability of Kenning- ton! What a place for a poet to die!’" (413). Upjohn is so resolutely anti-philistine that he evidently believes it is better for Cronshaw to starve in a sordid but romantic attic than to live fairly comfortably in a philistine stronghold. Sordid but romantic is not, of course, a standard by which he chooses to live his own life. The philistine/anti-philistine conflict between Philip and Upjohn reaches a climax after Cronshaw dies and 37 a funeral must be arranged. As Cronshaw has no relatives to take care of this, Philip goes to an undertaker to make some arrangements himself. Because he is a student, he has virtually no extra money, but he wants Cronshaw to have some sort of funeral. Once Upjohn hears that Philip has arranged for a funeral, he voices grandiose plans: ”I hope you’ve spared no expense. I should like the hearse to be followed by a long string of empty coaches, and I should like the horses to wear tall nodding plumes, and there should be a vast number of mutes with long streamers on their hats. I like the thought of all those empty coaches." (418) When Philip points out that without financial assistance his limited means oblige him to make moderate arrange- ments, Upjohn responds with this suggestion: "’ But, my dear fellow, in that case, why didn’t you get him a pauper’s funeral? There would have been something poetic in that. You have an unerring instinct for mediocrity’" (418). Philip has chosen a middle course, and this allows Upjohn to fault him twice--once for not choosing the high extreme and again for not choosing the low extreme. Romanticism requires sublimity, and scornfully rejects all middle ground. Thus, the middle position has some pecu- liar disadvantages to it, as Maugham not only shows in his work but also demonstrates through his fate with the 38 critics. By refusing to buy into either the establishment morality or the anti-establishment, intellectual "moral- ity," he sets himself up for abuse from all quarters. An interesting feature of the disagreement over the funeral is that Upjohn exhibits acute concern for appear- ances. He does not feel that the funeral is inconsequent and that Philip is a philistine because he is concerned with such vulgar trappings: rather, the basis for his complaint is that Philip’s arrangements do not make a proper showing. The funeral that Philip has chosen and paid for is worthy only of contempt because it will not look good enough, good being either showy or romantic, depending on which of Upjohn’s plans is providing the contrast. Upjohn’s scorn for the philistines does not preclude him from exhibiting the same concern for appear- ances he despises them for having: the standards applied may be different, but the essential concern for appear- ances is the same. On the way home from the funeral, our philistine- despising poet begins to plan the article he will write about Cronshaw, and his planning reflects a practicality even a philistine would admire. In fact, he demonstrates a more determined practicality than that which he earlier had mocked Philip for possessing. He speculates on the most sensible timing for publication: "’It’s rather lucky the poems haven’t come out yet. I think we’d better hold 39 them back a bit and I’ll write a preface’" (419). He is concerned about ”whittling away" his copy, so he decides that it would make more (practical) sense to write an article for a review which he can later reprint as a preface to Cronshaw’s book. In no way will Upjohn, suddenly very businesslike, waste any time or compromise any dramatic value by doing an article and preface on Cronshaw in an inefficient manner. Ultimately the article comes out, and it is a complete triumph: "Leonard Upjohn had never written anything better. It was a miracle of grace, charm, and pity. . . . He was thenceforth a critic to be reckoned with. He had seemed before a little aloof: but there was a warm humanity about this article which was infinitely attractive" (420). The article, a mix of half truths, poetic pronouncements, and aspersions on Philip, was written so astutely that it virtually wiped out Cronshaw’s little book. Upjohn printed the best of Cronshaw’s poetry in the article, so when the book of poetry finally came out, ”much of its point was gone” (420). It takes a very clever "poet" to pull off this amazing feat: Upjohn drew upon and praised Cronshaw’s work in such a way that it forwarded his own reputation considerably while doing little good, even some actual damage, to Cronshaw. In his article, Upjohn describes his own ”efforts to transport 40 the poet to some cottage embowered with honeysuckle amid a flowering orchard" (419), and this and other similar half truths (or outright falsehoods, depending upon the reader’s charitability) serve the purpose of making Upjohn seem very noble. In contrast to this nobility is the picture Upjohn gives of Philip and the good but misguided intentions that prompted Philip to move Cronshaw into such a philistine neighborhood: “it reminded Leonard Upjohn of Christ among the Pharisees, and the analogy gave him opportunity for an exquisite passage" (419). Appropri- ately, Upjohn reserves the final word for "the middle- class, ordinary, prosaic funeral of him who should have been buried like a prince or like a pauper. It was the crown-buffet, the final victory of Philistia over art, beauty and immaterial things" (420). It would be very difficult to deny that Upjohn is, at the very least, a hypocrite. What is so striking about his hypocrisy is that Maugham has shown it to be a special brand, that of the philistine disparager. One of the commonly accepted pieces of dogma about the philistines is that they are hypocritical: Arnold’s philistines talked a lot about helping the poor, for example, when all they really wanted were more people to attend their church meetings and opportunities for self-congratulation. Maugham reveals that whatever the verdict on the philistines, those who are not philistines exhibit their 41 own kind of hypocrisy. we have already seen this in their willingness to benefit from the philistine’s resources, but Leonard Upjohn raises it to new heights. Upjohn never strays from his affirmations of anti- philistinism: but as he voices those affirmations, he simultaneously furthers his own interests at the expense of others. His interest in Cronshaw, for example, has little to do with a love of art. Upjohn is a literary critic, one who first made his reputation by plagiarizing, through uncredited translation, work done by French critics. He has attained by these means a reputation for originality, and he sees his bringing out of Cronshaw, this great but heretofore undiscovered poet, as the opportunity to really cement that reputation. What he thinks of Cronshaw’s poetry we do not know: we do know that it gives him a chance for advancement, prestige, and financial reward. We can see that he speaks on one level while operating on another. His anti-philistine, pro-art stance is, in the simplest terms, a coverup: Maugham exposes Leonard Upjohn as a representative of what he claims to despise. He is a philistine in disguise. This phenomenon is a natural consequence of the way in which philistine disparaging has become systematically accusational. The undervaluing of £11 philistine attri- butes makes it extremely undesirable to be considered a 42 philistine while at the same time, the automatic credibil- ity and subjective terms of the accusation make it a difficult one to discredit. The combination of these two facts makes everyone afraid of his own "philistinism.” The individual must find ways to hide its presence in himself from both Other and Self. As Girard explains, this self-conscious sense of isolation and inferiority is the inescapable result of the principle ”derriere toutes les doctrines occidentales qui se succedent depuis deux ou trois siecles. . . : Dieu est mort, c’est a 1’homme de prendre sa place" (3313 62). The promise is that we have become gods: the problem is that tous les individus découvrent dans la solitude de leur conscience que la promesse est mensongere mais personne n’est pas capable d’universaliser cette experience. La promesse reste vraie pour les Autres. Chacun se croit seul exclus de 1’héritage divin et s’efforce de cacher cette malédiction. . . . En un bref instant de lumiere le sujet voit 1e mensonge universel et 11 ne peut plus croire a sa durée: il lui semble que les hommes vont s’embrasser en pleurant. Mais cet espoir est vain et l’etre meme qu’il souleve redoute bientot d’avoir livré aux Autres son horrible secret. Il redoute 43 encore plus de se l’etre livré a lui-meme. (3323 63) Maugham reveals what this "false promise" does to our understanding of philistinism: it turns it into a system of accusation. The individual feels obligated to hide the traces of philistinism he finds in himself, and so he must refute for others the accusation he makes, consciously or unconsciously, of himself. He can refute this through his idealistic facade (the covert philistine) or he can draw attention away from his own philistinism by pointing out its presence in others (the accusing philistine). Dr. Saunders (HQ) understands the covert philistine, and he checks underneath the appearance of the self- professed idealist to see if he might be such a philis- tine. Fred Blake expresses unadulterated admiration for Erik Christessen and his enthusiasm for great literature, but Saunders is more cautious: he wondered idly if Erik was a good business man. He was not very fond of idealists. It was difficult for them in this workaday world to reconcile their prefessions with the exigencies of life, and it was disconcerting how often they managed to combine exalted notions with a keen eye to the main chance. (116) It would seem that the philistine is far better suited for life in our "workaday world," but we, the culturally 44 proud, resist that knowledge. It is that resistance to being just part of the masses which has resulted in our philistine-disparaging system, for we become unanimous in our attempts to be different: "La societe moderne n’est plus qu’une imitation negative et l’effort pour sortir des chemins battus fait invinciblement retomber tout le monde dans l’orniere' (3333 105). Those who choose to deny their own philistinism by means more active than the covert philistine’s silently above-it-all posture fall into the rut of philistine disparaging. There they have plenty of company, for the phenomenon of the philistine masquerading as a philistine despiser, what I call the accusational philistine, is a fairly common one. Just as we despise Alroy Rear for being like us, so the accusational philistine scorns other philistines and makes sure he is quick and loud with his accusations of philistinism. He is afraid he will be spotted, and he believes that the best defense is a good offense. Leonard Upjohn, with his self-serving discourses on the errors of the philistine’s ways, is a representa- tive model of this form of refutation. What Girard says about the Proustian snob is equally applicable to an accusational philistine like Upjohn: L’indignation qu’excite en nous le snob est donc toujours la mesure de notre propre snobisme. . . . [Le snob] est douloureusement sensible aux 45 moindres manifestations de snobisme. . . . Entre l’indignation et la culpabilité i1 y a un rapport de nécessité. Et la penetration la plus aigué est au service de cette indignation. Seul le snob connait vraiment le snob puisqu’il Luise son désir, c’est-a-dire l’esence meme de son etre. . . . On se comprend entre snobs au premier coup d’oeil et on se hait presque aussi vite. (m 78) Knowing about the philistine and his disparagers is no guarantee that one will not accuse others of philistin- ism: indeed, Girard suggests that the more one knows about philistinism the more likely one is to make accusations. Saunders, one of Maugham’s most knowledgeable characters, provides an example of this. When Fred describes Sydney’s literary set--"’they’d talk a lot of tosh about books and then, before you knew where you were, they’d be wanting to pop into bed with you’"--Saunders says, "’the Philistine dots his i’s and crosses his t’s with a definiteness that is unbecoming, and when he sees a nail he hits it on the head’" (3; 114). In spite of his awareness of the com- plexities of identifying people as philistines, Saunders proves willing to use the label himself, casually label- ling Sydney’s literary set. Philip, often a target for philistine disparagers such as Leonard Upjohn, Hayward, and his fellow would-be 46 artists in Paris, shows himself similarly willing to accuse others of philistinism. When he is a young man, before he begins to understand the complexities of calling someone a philistine, we see him accuse Watson and the Americans he meets in Paris, among others, of philistin- ism. Even after he has learned not to accept such accusa- tions at face value and has felt how humiliating they are to the recipient, he continues to think of others as philistines. When he goes to the British Museum to view the groups from the Parthenon, for example, he finds that he cannot enjoy them because the philistines are viewing them too: There were too many people, provincials with foolish faces, foreigners poring over guide- books: their hideousness besmirched the everlasting masterpieces, their restlessness troubled the gods’ immortal repose. . . . their features were distorted with paltry desires, and you felt they were strange to any ideas of beauty. They had furtive eyes and weak chins. There was no wickedness in them, but only pettiness and vulgarity. (Q33 521) We can see that understanding the "philistine" is not enough to prevent use of it as an accusation. We already know what it is we despise the philistines for: it is what we are secretly afraid of finding in ourselves. "Les deux 47 cymbales qui font le plus de bruit sont pourtant celles qui se recouvrent le plus exactement' (M333 128), Girard says, and this is true of the philistine disparagers. The differences between the accused and the accuser, like the differences between those the snob pursues and those he scorns, represent a "chose fugitive, insaisissable et presque imperceptible si l’on n’est pas snob [or philis- tine] soi-meme” (M323 92). If refinements of our defini— tion are inadequate means for exploding the myth of "the other guy" as philistine, what can end the accusations? Understanding how the system functions can begin to do so. Once we recognize the quantity of baggage carried by the label "philistine," we are ready for the next step. fine; a philistine is (is not) becomes almost irrelevant: fine; heppene when the accusation is made represents the essen- tial concern. Maugham contributes significantly to our understand- ing of the system’s functioning by turning it inside out and showing us what philistine disparagement looks like from the other side, that of the accused rather than that of the accuser. What does it look like from the accused literary philistine’s end of the accusation? This is not a vantage point often represented in literature, for the precise reason that the institution of "literature" is one of the main forces behind the philistine-disparaging accusational system.8 48 To provide us with this unusual perspective, Maugham describes a writer’s evening with an old friend, a pre- success friend, and in that description we discover the accusation of philistinism coming directly at us, as we are addressed in the second person by the narrator. Maugham’s characterization of his "you" as a successful but philistine writer forces his readers to identify, at least for a time, with the role of the accused rather than that of the accuser. As Maugham explains: Of course it is grand to talk of the good old days when you shared a crust of bread in a garret together, but it is a little disconcert- ing when you reflect how near to a garret is the room you are sitting in. You don’t feel at ease when your friend tells you that his books don’t sell and that he can’t place his short stories: the managers won’t even read his plays, and when he compares them with some of the stuff that’s put on (here he fixes you with an accusing eye) it really does seem a bit hard. ‘You are embar- rassed and you look way. You exaggerate the failures you have had in order that he may realize that life has its hardships for you too. You refer to your work in the most disparaging way you can and are a trifle taken aback to find 49 that your host’s opinion of it is the same as yours. You speak of the fickleness of the public so that he may comfort himself by thinking that your popularity cannot last. (955 15-16) Since his work remains unappreciated by the buying public and the literary hierarchy alike while yours enjoys considerable success with both, he feels justified in nailing you (the reader) to the wall: your commercial success proves that you are a philistine. The nature of the philistine-disparaging accusational system requires that you go along with his rude behavior. You become self-effacing, even self-disparaging: you have chimed in with the system at your own expense. Your friend sees no reason to consider possible flaws in his own work because he is commercially unsuccessful: this same lack of public success allows him to discuss frankly the flaws in your work. He offers comments as gifts, comments that on any other subject would be considered unthinkable by both parties. He tells you, for example, that he hasn’t read your latest book, but he remembers being disappointed in its predecessor. Really, he says, your first book was your best: ”’you’ll never do anything so good as that,’ he says heartily, and you feel that your whole career has been a long decadence from that one happy hit. ’I always think you’ve never geiEe fulfilled the promise you showed 50 then’" (16). Intolerable rudeness finally disintegrates into a complete breakdown of sense: when your friend sees the nice car your literary success has paid for, he “looks at it with tolerant superiority" (16). Is there any good reason for which he should feel superior? This is an unusual vantage point Maugham has given us: representations of the philistine-disparaging system from the perspective of the accused are rare. It does more for the reader’s sense of superiority, his assurance of knowing more than the characters know, to give por- traits sympathetic to the accuser rather than to the accused. In a way, our literary sensibilities work against portraits of the accused, for our awareness of our own interests makes the figure accused of philistinism too close to be comfortable: "nous devinons quels phenomenes de contagion littéraire et sociale ont opéré sur lui. Nous voyons bien guels supports, toujours insuffisants, i1 se cherche dans l’histoire, l’esthétique et al poésie" (M313 81). Through the rare window that Maugham gives us, the philistine disparager looks quite a bit different. He is not noble, but petty and ill-mannered. It is he, not the philistine, who behaves disrespectfully and uncompassion- ately toward his friends. The philistine is the one put- upon, not the accuser. Above all, this vantage point that 51 Maugham has given us shows the essential unregegngpleneee, the iEIAIIQDALILY of the whole procedure. That the substance of the accusation is remarkably thin becomes clear, as does the pressing need to question it. No doubt those who dislike Maugham and support the philistine-disparaging system would like to dismiss this reversed-direction portrayal on the grounds that Maugham himself is a philistine, and so of course he makes the philistine disparager look bad. This would be an unfortunate error, for Maugham has matured beyond his readers in his understanding of philistinism, and therefore he can (and does) show the attractive egg the negative aspects of both positions. He has been actively involved in the system, and his participation is what allows him to tell us more than we already know: ”1e romancier qui revele 1e désir triangulaire ne peut pas etre snob mais il faut qu’il l’ait été. Il faut qu’il ait desire et qu’il ne desire plus" (M323 222). The novelist, like Maugham, who reveals the machinations of philistine disparaging appears to his critics to be searching in irrelevant places for truths that only the "intellectual" writers can uncover. He is, however, looking in the places precisely most relevant for modern culture, and if we are wiling to listen, we can learn a great deal from him: 52 En s’interrogeant sur le snobisme 1e romancier s’interroge, a sa facon, sur les ressorts caches de la mécanique sociale. Mais les savants haussent les epaules. La question est trop frivole pour eux. Si on les presse de répondre ils se déroberont. Ils pretendront que le romancier s’interesse au snobisme pour des raisons impures. Il est lui-meme un snob. Disons plutot qu’il l’était. C’est un fait: mais la question demeure. Qu’est-ce que le snobisme? (M323 222) This is a question that must be answered, in some way, by someone. While the scholars and savants are shrugging their shoulders at its frivolity, Maugham is pressing an answer upon us. We have already seen through his work much of what constitutes philistinism: further examination reveals more fully how philistine disparaging functions as a system of accusation. Referring to the participants in these instances of philistine bashing as the accused and the accuser may seem overly dramatic, but these are in fact very apt names. Part of their appropriateness stems from the complete incivility, even violence, on the part of the accusers, something which I have already commented on. Maugham does not want us to forget this: he knows it is an essential part of the confrontation, and so it is an element in all the philistine accusations he shows us. 53 While Philip is in Germany, he is anxious to learn as much as he can, and part of his education is listening to his friends discuss various topics. When Hayward and Weeks first venture into the subject of Greek tragedy, Hayward feels that his authority as the recipient of a pass degree from Cambridge entitles him to instruct the American. Once he has finished lecturing, however, Weeks "tore to pieces all that Hayward had said: with elaborate civility he displayed the superficiality of his attain- ments" (933 110). It turns out that Weeks is a scholar, that he has taught Greek literature at Harvard. This, of course, brands Weeks a philistine in Hayward’s eyes, and he feels no compunction about very rudely dismissing Weeks and all his learning: ”’I might have known it. Of course you read Greek like a schoolmaster,’ he said. ’I read it like a poet.’" (110). Hayward did not know what he was talking about, and his readings of Greek had been proven inaccurate. Hayward is undaunted: what does that matter? After all, Weeks is only a philistine. As Hayward explains to Philip, "the man’s a pedant. He has no real feeling for beauty. Accuracy is the virtue of clerks. It’s the spirit of the Greeks that we aim at" (110). Hayward finishes off his case against Weeks like this: "’Damned Yankee!’ That settled it. It was the perfect answer to an argument which had seemed unanswerable" 54 (111). How can one counter against a “perfect answer" such as this? There is never an adequate response to name calling: there is no answer Weeks could make that would cut Hayward down to his proper size. The mere fact that name calling is such an often seen feature in philistine belittling suggests that the accused/accuser terminology is appropriate, for name calling reflects all the accusa- tory impulses we try to hide. Hayward maintains this snide attitude toward Weeks, making remarks like ”I didn’t expect you to understand me. . . . you can only adopt the critical attitude. Emerson and all that sort of thing. But what is criti- cism? Criticism is purely destructive: anyone can destroy, but not everyone can build up. You are a pedant, my dear fellow. The important thing is to construct: I am constructive: I am a poet." (112-13) Maugham characters who say ”I am a poet" are always rather offensive, and no small part of their offensiveness is their self-righteous rudeness to those they perceive to be philistines. Cronshaw exhibits this same tendency of incivility to friends during Philip’s Paris stay when he tells Philip, "’you’re a tradesman, you want to invest life in consols so that it shall bring you a safe three per cent. I’m a 55 spendthrift, I run through my capital. I shall spend my last penny with my last heartbeat’" (245). It is, of course, that "tradesman” Philip who takes in the desti- tute, dying Cronshaw later in the book. Even at that time, as when he makes the tradesman accusation, Cronshaw has a sense of moral superiority: he knows he is no philistine. Because of their marked sense of moral superiority, philistine disparagers feel no need to observe the common- place social rules of civility when they are dealing with a philistine. At times it seems as if they feel it is incumbent upon them to be rude, that they are doing a service to society when they behave abominably to philis- tines. The pervasive rudeness of the philistine despiser is often an automatic response, as Upjohn’s knee-jerk references to Philip’s "middle-class mind" demonstrate. Financial matters are especially contentious, and a mere mention of them is enough to bring on some manifestation of rudeness. Upjohn is again a representative example: "whenever there was any question of money, Leonard Upjohn assumed a slightly disdainful expression. His sensitive temperament was offended by the reference" (414). The self-righteous rudeness of the accusers, combined with the serious implications of the accusation, requires either silence or defensiveness from the accused. The accused recognizes that he is under attack, and so if he 56 responds at all, he responds defensively. The defensive- ness of the accused’s reaction is exacerbated by the ill- defined terms of the attack which make it impossible to say anything adequate in one’s defense. When Hayward calls Weeks a “’damned Yankee’” (111), this is an accusa- tion of philistinism, something Weeks would recognize if he were there to hear the insult. When he tried to pin down Philip and Hayward on the definition of a gentleman (in Maugham’s work, the opposite of a philistine), he understands that ”’we may take it that only Englishmen are gentlemen’" (113), a statement even the anxious-to-please Philip dares not contradict. No matter that Weeks has superior intelligence, education, and social skills, he is an American and a philistine,9 and therefore dismissible. Faced with these accusations, Weeks chooses silence: he will ignore them, for he knows there is no way to make a dent on the complacency of the attacker. We can only guess at Weeks’ thoughts while he ignores the accusations: we are told what Philip’s are. When Cronshaw belittles Philip for his financial conservatism in the "tradesman" accusation, Philip recognizes the nature of the attack implicit in this, and he is frus- trated by his inability to assail the unassailable: ”the metaphor irritated Philip, because it assumed for the speaker a romantic attitude and cast a slur upon the position which Philip instinctively felt had more to say 57 for it than he could think of at the moment” (245). Through Philip, Maugham conveys perfectly the predicament shared by everyone accused of philistinism: he knows his position is far more honorable than the accuser admits, but he also knows there are no words which would convince the accuser of that. The narrator of gekee_gn§_31e gives us a demonstra- tion of the flustered defensiveness which is the accused’s only alternative to silence. The young Ashenden, used to Academy portraits, makes a horrible blunder when he first sees Lionel Hillier’s portrait of Rosie: he asks Hillier when it will be finished. Upon being told that it already is finished, he blushes in embarrassment. He senses the unspoken accusation of philistinism and concurs in that judgment: "’It’s awfully like,’ was all that then I could lamely say’" (134). When Hillier makes the accusation explicit, Ashenden becomes even more flustered: "’It’s not chocolate-boxy enough for you,’ said Hillier. ’I think it’s awfully good,’ I answered quickly, defending myself" (134). Nothing he can say will save the face he has lost by branding himself a philistine (and in an artist’s studio, no less) and anything he does say will only make his situation worse. This is in fact what happens, for when he tries to compliment Hillier on the portrait by asking if he intends to send it to the Academy, the 58 response is a horrified "’Good God, no!" (134): Ashenden has only dug the pit deeper. Someone accused of philistinism, then, has two choices: he can ignore the accusation or he can flounder about defensively. Having a choice only between these two ineffectual courses of action is a result of the foolproof nature of the accusational system, and the accuser’s sense of superiority is confirmed by the accused regardless of which option he chooses. Silence implies agreement, at the very least that the accused has nothing to say in his own defense, while the awkwardness caused by defensiveness completely undermines everything the accuser says. The accused cannot win: the accuser cannot lose. The philistine despisers share, as a direct result of being against this common enemy, the philistine, a sense of camaraderie. In this, they are like the residents of Proust’s Combray, who "se sentent solidaires et fraternels lorsgu’ils découvrent ce qui les oppose aux étrangers" (M323 198). Each individual feels this clubby atmosphere, although sometimes those who include themselves in the club would not be had at any price by the other "members," as Maugham shows in The_Me;:eg_ge:ner. When Captain Nichols and Dr. Saunders meet Erik Christessen, he is very pleased to see them for, as he explains, ”it’s always a pleasure to me to meet English gentlemen" (96). The 59 extremely disreputable Nichols is hardly Saunders’ idea of a gentleman, but Nichols nonetheless feels a kinship between them: "’intelligent chap, that. Knew we was gentlemen at once’" (96). Saunders suspects irony, but Nichols is perfectly serious. Nichols lives with the assumption that this class of men (the gentlemen, the non- philistines) exists and, furthermore, that its members can recognize each other: more to the point, he believes that he, Saunders, and Christessen all belong to it. Saunders shares Nichols’ assumptions, but he makes distinctions which differ from those of Nichols. When he meets Frith, he is pleased by his education and his manner. He identifies Frith specifically as a gentleman, and he enjoys that same feeling of camaraderie which Nichols earlier felt with him and Christessen. Saunders, however, excludes Nichols from the group: Frith "certainly did not belong to the same class as old Swan and Captain Nichols" (123). These differences indicate the falseness of the unity: like Proust’s Verdurin salon, this unity is "une simple facade" (M323 206). What unity there is comes from hatred and fear, which is a "fausse unite qui dissimule la duplicité et la multiplicité" (206) and not a true camaraderie. The kinship the philistine despisers feel is not real, and thus we see dramatically varying views of who is in (and therefore out) of the group. 60 The appropriateness of the accused/accuser terminology is further borne out by the fact that the philistine is not allowed to offer any criticisms of anyone, no matter how accurate or insightful they may be. Thus it is that Philip does not mind Hayward’s belittling of Weeks because Weeks is a philistine (and an American), but he loses his temper when Weeks makes some disparaging observations about Hayward. Philip insists to Weeks that Hayward is a poet, but Weeks’ judgments are far more astute than this: he points out to Philip that Hayward is in fact immature and irresponsible. Hayward is twenty- five years old and ”’does nothing but stay in pensions and write poetry’" (108), Weeks observes to Philip, prompting Philip to exclaim "’you don’t know him’" (108). This same phenomenon shapes the disagreement over Upjohn’s contribution to the formalities: the laurel wreath. He brings this wreath to Philip’s apartment before the funeral: "He was pleased with the idea of crowning the dead poet with this: and attempted, notwith- standing Philip’s disapproving silence, to fix it on the bald head: but the wreath fitted grotesquely. It looked like the brim of a hat worn by a low comedian in a music- hall" (933 418). Not to be deterred, Upjohn decides to put it over Cronshaw’s heart instead. When Philip points out that Upjohn has in fact put it on Cronshaw’s stomach, Upjohn smiles and dismisses Philip with, "’only a poet 61 knows where lies a poet’s heart’” (418). Those who belong to the philistine-bashing camp are willing to fly in the face of virtually any fact because they have artistic/ poetic souls and ”no one knows what’s in nature and what isn’t! The world sees nature through the eyes of the artist" (Q33 186). In the laurel wreath scene, Maugham gives us an example of the ridiculous results this can have: it is hard not to laugh imagining a laurel wreath on the stomach of the scrawny, pathetic Cronshaw, and Upjohn’s talk about poets’ hearts only heightens the ridiculousness. Accusations of philistinism have a curious way of drawing in bystanders. Those who witness the accusations, like the accused himself, often chime in right on cue: at the very least they appear to concur with silence. Philip, who protested against Weeks’ insightful criticisms of Hayward, "listened complacently to the abuse of a man who had gone out of his way to be kind to him" (933 108) when Hayward faults Weeks for everything from his moral values to the pants he wears. This results from the desire to be "right," as Maugham reveals when Philip takes Hayward to the art galleries in Paris. Under these circumstances, the two switch roles: "like most people who cultivate an interest in the arts, Hayward was extremely anxious to be right. He was dogmatic with those who did 62 not venture to assert themselves, but with the self- assertive he was very modest" (219). Perhaps the most significant implication of this is that anyone can provoke unanimity by making an accusation of philistinism. Philip’s Paris art friends make con- certed efforts to be unique, and they often disagree violently with each other. In spite of their ”original- ity," the subject of the Great Victorians (the ultimate stereotypical philistines) can by itself bring about unanimity: they threw themselves upon [the subject] with gusto. They were unanimous for once. They elaborated. Someone proposed a vast bonfire made out of the works of the Forty Academicians into which the Great Victorians might be hurled. (9113 186-87) Unanimity provided by an accusation of philistinism is important in Maugham’s novels: it is a crucial element in his literary career. His critics are unanimous because someone had the great idea of calling Maugham a philistine who is writing for the middlebrow. There is, however, an important corollary to this: if unanimity is provoked by an accusation, what happens if no accusation is made? The simplest answer, which is almost always the correct one, is that there can be no unanimity. 63 It seems to me that this is the true problem Maugham causes his critics: they operate under the assumption that all writing is interested, is ideologically motivated, and when faced with text which treats all sides of an issue fairly, they are thrown into confusion. Maugham has in fact produced some neutral text: in Girard’s terms, Maugham he§_heen a philistine but is one no longer. Maugham can show us both sides of the philistine- disparaging accusation system, and he does so. This does not mean, of course, that there are no moments in his work which reflect philistinism: his transcendence is not a constant presence. Girard recognizes that Cervantes, Stendhal, Proust, and Dostoyevski sometimes reflect and sometimes reveal triangular desire: the simple fact that they reveal at all makes them special sources of knowledge. So too with Maugham: he provides a unique educational opportunity, and the absence of a completely consistent transcendence should not be allowed to function as an excuse to ignore the insights that are present in his work. When Maugham’s work lacks a vested interest in the system on its own terms, it throws his critics into confusion and they respond by provoking their own kind of unanimity through an accusation of philistinism. Those who can get beyond the critics and their stone- throwing unanimity, however, can learn a great deal about 64 our thriving philistine-disparaging accusational system. Those readers who can do this, like Theodore Dreiser, can see what is really in Maugham’s work instead of what some critic, proud of not knowing Maugham’s work, 5325 is in Maugham’s work. This is why Maugham ought to be in university classrooms: students will not carry the same baggage their instructors do, and because they are unaware of what Edmund Wilson said about Maugham, they will not be automatically forced into agreement with him. English professors rarely (if ever) present the texts they are teaching as "middlebrow," and given the same opportunity canonized texts receive, Maugham’s work would prove its worth. On its own, it produces no unanimity: this might be initially uncomfortable for the instructor who chooses to teach it,10 but it would certainly be beneficial for the students and fair to Maugham’s work. LOOKING FORWARD My interest in Maugham, as I explained in the introduction to this work, began in anger: the novels themselves have since dispelled that anger. This is indicative of Maugham’s uniquely valuable perspective, for as Girard demonstrates, the novelist who successfully reveals rather than merely reflecting his subject has been there himself but ie_;neze_ne_19ngez. Maugham has been an active participant in the philistine-disparaging accusa- tional system: he has also been angry. Indeed, these are closely related: as Girard points out, our degree of indignation indicates our level of culpability. What this means for potential readers of Maugham is that he knows more than we do. We need to stop trying to demonstrate Maugham’s philistinism and start trying to learn from him about the accusational system that has grown up around the ”philistine.” This is the kind of learning Girard writes about in the introduction for T2_Denble_nusiness_fieund: our relationship with the works of mimetic revelation cannot be defined as ’critical’ in the usual sense. We have more to learn from them than they have to learn from us. . . . we 65 66 should try to divest ourselves of our misconcep- tions in order to reach the superior perspective they embody. (x-xi) It is clear from this that Maugham’s readers (and non- readers) need to make the necessary adjustments, that it is pointless to belittle Maugham when he knows more than we do. Philistinism and the philistine-accusing system provide one way to make a much-needed reevaluation of Maugham’s work. It is a way with a future, for it gets at the heart of the problems surrounding Maugham while suggesting how much readers miss if they slight Maugham based on his reputation. It is, however, only one way, and if it is to be explored further or if others are to be opened to inquiry, we need to get beyond Edmund Wilson and his epithet of ”half-trashy." We must convince ourselves that a high sales figure does not automatically preclude literary or cultural value. The warning of Anthony Burgess that "it is unwise to disparage the well-made popular" (74) would be well heeded. For the literary snob, "well-made popular” is as much an oxymoron as "literary philistine,” but Maugham shows us that neither phrase can accurately be called an oxymoron. While every kind of literary study has its pitfalls, even the limited scope of this project has shown me that 67 any academic (student or faculty) who wishes to do work on Maugham has to avoid more than the usual number. There is a lot of brush to be cleared away before the real work can begin. A great deal of the brush comes from the bushes of academic pretentiousness. Arrogance is a very real prob- lem for authors and scholars alike: as Girard notes, "la tentation de l’orgueil est eternelle mais elle devient irresistible a l’époque moderne car elle est orchestrée et amplifiée de facon inouie" (M323 62). Furthermore, we need to be prepared to look closely at philistines, snobs, and other non-Romantic types: we must avoid the impatient shoulder shrugging of the schol- ars and savants, and we have to ”dépasser l’irritation que nous cause le snobisme" (M323 81). In order to do this, we must first recognize the validity and appropriateness of Maugham’s "researches." The philistine and the gentle- man are not charming (or not so charming) Edwardian anach- ronisms, but the areas of study most relevant for our society. What might appear to be their frivolity should not lead us astray: it is an interesting paradox that "seuls les médiocres et les genies osent écrire: <> Le simple talent recule devant cette platitude humiliante ou cette supreme audace” (M323 230). Let no one say that Maugham belongs 68 to the mediocre faction until he has read Maugham carefully. In W. Girard pits the novelists of mimetic revelation squarely against the Romantic preconceptions of most readers and critics. This opposition is a very insightful one, and it helps us appreciate Maugham’s accomplishments. Maugham makes us realize that philistine disparaging has turned into a whole system of accusation, and he reflects and reveals its machinations. As he does so, he undermines much of the Romantic value we associate with the anti-philistine position. What he does, in essence, is reveal the complexities and dispel the romanticism of philistine disparaging. Those who cherish their romantic motivations for philistine bashing should be cowed by Maugham’s portrait of Leonard Upjohn, as well as by Maugham’s consistent exposure of the ludicrousness of the (supposedly superior) idealistic point of view. As the art master, Monsieur Foinet, observes to Philip: "I have nothing but contempt for the people who despise money. They are hypocrites or fools. . . . Without an adequate income half the possibilities of life are shut off. . . . You will hear people say that poverty is the best 69 spur to the artist. They have never felt the iron of it in their flesh. They do not know how mean it makes you. It exposes you to endless humiliation, it cuts your wings, it eats into your soul like a cancer." (933 248) Poverty is not romantic, it is degrading. Maugham’s message is clear: not only are such Romantic staples as the beauty of the starving artist inaccurate and reprehensible, but these myths are only put about by people who lack any direct knowledge of their subject. Not only does Maugham dispel the Romanticism attached to philistine disparaging, he also reveals the complexi- ties of that accusational system. It is simpler for us as readers if everything is black and white, and indeed, Romantic critics demand that we see novelistic heroes in black and white terms: we hate them totally or we admire them completely. These critics transform the heroes that meet their criteria into ”martyrs de ces Autres dont on ne nous laisse jamais ignorer, bien entendu, qu’ils sont tous uniformément intolerables” (M323 148). The truth is surely more complex than this, and in Maugham’s novels, it is. He shows readers what is admirable in those who are accused philistines, and he lays bare the hypocrisy of the accusers. Matters touching on the philistines and their disparagers tend to be very clear cut (the guys in the 70 white hats and those in the black), but Maugham’s novels indicate the subtleties other writers and critics often do not. He dees not allow the philistine disparagers to feel self-righteous because they have accused someone else of philistinism: they may claim to be better than the accused, but they really are not. Girard makes this same observation in the context of the nobility in an egalitar- ian culture: 'c’est parce qu’il a cesse d’etre distinct que l’aristocrate cherche a se distinguer. Et il y réussit parfaitement mais i1 n’est pas plus noble pour autant" (M323 128). So where does all of this leave us? First, we should realize what we do when we accuse someone of philistinism: once we understand that, we might be, speaking optimis- tically, far less likely to make the accusation. More specifically, we should recognize both the inadvisability and the inaccuracy of accusing Maugham of philistinism. Such an accusation is inadvisable in general terms: it is also an inappropriate charge to level at Maugham. After all, he has been where we are now: he knows more than we do. As a novelist, he is serenely above such accusations on our part--"le romancier se reconnait coupable du péché dont il accuse son médiateur" (M323 298)--and such accusa- tions are scarcely relevant and appropriate for Maugham as a literary figure. 71 As far as Maugham’s work is concerned, once we have left behind the irrelevant concern over his philistinism, we should come to his work prepared to value it, learn from it, and enjoy it. His accomplishment ought not to be overlooked, or dismissed by analogies with schoolboys and hacks. "Honesty is a form of sensitivity” (198), Graham Greene reminded his readers, and that is the kind of insight which we need to appreciate Maugham’s work. Even more than that, we should keep in mind Theodore Dreiser’s remark about Qfi_flgmen_3engege: "despite these dissonant voices it is still a book of the utmost import" (203). We can also learn from Maugham’s work, even if this requires abandoning the Romantic preconceptions about literature which are near and dear to us. If we have to adjust the critical terms a bit, it is worth it: we risk losing more by holding fast to our terminology and ignoring Maugham than we do by taking a chance with the terms in order to look intelligently at him and other writers who are slighted now. The novels ought to set the terms for the theory rather than the reverse. As Girard makes clear, "we must elaborate a language more faithful to the intuitions of the authors themselves” (333 x). Finally, we ought to enjoy Maugham’s work. While academics have been slighting his novels, other readers have been enjoying them: in the first half of this decade 72 alone, for example, the Penguin paperback edition of Q: 3gmen_3engege was reprinted seven times. Maugham’s work has enjoyed both popularity and longevity, and surely there are good reasons for that. What Maugham says about the outpatient clinic at the hospital indicates the view of life that is conveyed in his novels, and it seems to me a fairly accurate charac- terization of the novels themselves. The final sentences suggest the neutrality and matter-of-factness (what Dreiser called Maugham’s ”unmoral" stance) that, in part, prompt his critics to hurl at him unanimity-provoking accusations. That neutrality (along with his criticisms of snobbism in literary circles, of course) is, ironi- cally, what makes him controversial: it is also what in my mind makes him enjoyable to read: But on the whole the impression was neither of tragedy nor of comedy. There was no describing it. It was manifold and various: there were tears and laughter, happiness and woe: it was tedious and interesting and indifferent: it was as you saw it. . . . There was neither good nor bad there. There were just facts. It was life. (Qfifi 402) Notes 1 Indeed, in some important respects, critical theory has created a new breed of "philistine." These new phil- istines are those who do not understand en; theory--each particular theory, therefore, can create its own group of philistines. 2 While this may seem an odd form of "justice," it makes sense because accusations of philistinism have ensured that potential readers of Maugham don’t in fact read his work. In addition to this, they dismiss him as being "philistine" without having read him and thereby perpetuate the cycle, discouraging more potential readers. 3 Because the English and American criticism of Maugham’s work ie consistent (numbingly so), I chose some representative pieces to provide a critical orientation rather than trying to scan the body of criticism. The reviews by Wilson and Dreiser are "classics" of Maugham criticism, and much of the more recent work done includes references to one or both of these reviews. The other selections were made on the bases of their representative nature and general availability. While the French and the Japanese work on Maugham has apparently been far more 73 74 favorable than the English and American, I was unable to obtain the French work for this project and the Japanese is inaccessible (to me). 4 This message, which is here delivered implicitly about Maugham’s work, is put forth in general terms in the introduction. In the opening section, their "Address to the Reader," the authors of 311;y_fle;3§ proudly declare that they are attacking philistinism: ”To perpetuate the received opinions about English literature is to force our children into philistinism, even when philistinism is against their natural bent, and at the same time to cheat our great writers of even the posthumous justice which is usually, and by tradition, the best that our society is prepared to offer them" (vii-viii). 5 The relationship of the American Transcendentalists and Romantics to the literary marketplace demonstrates the gradual shift I have in mind here. Thoreau, Emerson, Hawthorne, and Melville all wanted to sell their books to the public, either to influence their fellow citizens through their writings or simply to make a living as a writer. They concerned themselves with the tastes of the marketplace and the nuts and bolts of publishing--even Thoreau wanted his work to appear in cheap editions for mass circulation. None of these writers achieved popular success, however, and their attitudes toward the buying public gradually became hostile and scornful. Melville’s 75 review of Hawthorne’s HQ§§£§_IIQE_QD_91§;HAEEQ advocated the idea that Hawthorne’s work was ”too deserving of popularity to be popular,” and in that statement we see the now-familiar idea that the buying public cannot discern "good" literature and that therefore popular success is an indication of having sold out one’s artistic principles to make a buck. What I would like to stress is the complexity of the Transcendentalist and Romantic attitudes towards popularity: they ganged to achieve popular success, but when that did not happen, they posited the notion that "real" literature never achieves popularity: as Melville wrote, "failure is the true test of greatness." For a much fuller discussion of this issue, see Michael Gilmore’s AmeIieen_3emgngieiem_eng_§3e W- 6 This is how accusations of philistinism function so effectively: a defense of a work or a writer labelled philistine inescapably labels the defender a philistine as well. This is especially problematic in the classroom, for it places an almost insurmountable burden on the student who sees value in work considered "philistine" by the English Department and its faculty: the student who defends the work or writer accused as "philistine" draws that same accusation on him/herself. 7 Of course, Dreiser is someone who has his own style critics, and his praise might not be considered sufficient 76 refutation of the complaints about Maugham’s style. However, I think there is a way to explain how it is that one faction can see qualities like banality, inelegance, and superficiality, while the other sees writing that is clear, honest, and colloquial. The intentional difficulty of the Modern is lacking in Maugham, and this strikes critics in such radically different ways because while one group expects to encounter it and sees its absence as a fault, the other group does not require it and thus is not bothered by its absence. 8 After all, if the term "literature" is to have any real meaning, if it is to stand for something special, it must somehow set itself off from gene; kinds of writing. What better category to use as an example of what "litera- ture" is not than "philistine" writings? 9 The strong connection between Americans and philis- tines almost goes without saying: after the connection between the Victorian middle classes and philistinism, there is no more obvious pairing. Philistinism is usually implied in literary treatments of Americans, particularly by British writers, and the words are often linked explic- itly: as Michael Cohen remarks in his article on American bashing, "American plain style has [in Wodehouse] a short range of feelings from a certain diffidence about learning and the arts to a definite Philistinism" (320). This 77 connection could be examined at some length, but it is not all that relevant for a study of Somerset Maugham. What I would like to point out, though, is the self-satisfaction that comes from philistine bashing and American bashing, because it is that very self-satisfaction that usually prevents portrayals (like some of Maugham’s) which are sympathetic to the accused rather than the accuser. As Cohen remarks in the context of Kingsley Amis, “when anything horrible or foolish is to be depicted, letting it be depicted by an American will give just the requisite dash of chauvinist self-satisfaction to the writer and reader, if the reader happens to be English" (321). Bashing philistines makes the basher feel smug: that is why balanced presentations like Maugham’s are so rare and so valuable. 10 Because Maugham’s work does not provoke unanimity on its own, there might be those who would eheeee not to teach it. Such a choice is certainly defensible: the automatic, unthinking omission of his work is not. Works Cited Arnold, Matthew. gnl;n;e_gn§_3ng;ehy. Selections in The W. Ed. Gordon 8. Height- New York: Viking, 1972. 190-210. Brophy, Brigid, Michael Levey, and Charles Osborne. 313:2 MW. London: Rapp and Carroll, 1967. Burgess . Anthony. W 1232. New York: Summit, 1984. Cohen, Michael. "The Sport of American-Bashing in Modern English Authors." figegiee_in_;3e_neye1 20.3 (1988): 316-22. Drabble, Margaret. Rev. of Megghem, by Ted Morgan. Meg 22;3_Iimee_3egfi_3e21eg 9 March 1980: 1+. Dreiser, Theodore. "As a Realist Sees It." Rev. of 3: W. by W- Somerset Maugham Wis 25 December 1915: 202-04. Gilmore. Michael T. W pleee. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1985. Girard. Rene. MW. Trans. Yvonne Freccero. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1965. 78 79 ---- Eeneenge_remantisne_et_xerite_remanesgne- Paris: Bernard Grasset, 1961. ---. Te_39331e_3geineee_3egng. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins UP, 1978. Greene, Graham. ”Notes on Somerset Maugham." Qelleeeeg Eeeeye. London: Bodley Head, 1969. 197-205. Higdon, David Leon. Rev. of Maugham, by Ted Morgan. Mgfie:n_£1§§193_§§3§iefi 26.4 (1980): 708-10. Maugham, William Somerset. Qekee_en§_31e. 1930. Middlesex, Eng.: Penguin, 1948. ---. 13e_ne;;eg_gezne1. 1932. Middlesex: Penguin, 1963. ---. Qf_figmen_3engege. 1915. Middlesex: Penguin, 1963. Morgan, Ted. Meggnem. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1980. ,Qzfierg_33g11e3_nie;iene;y (Compact Ed.). Oxford: Oxford UP, 1971. 2 vols. Wilson, Edmund. "The Apotheosis of Somerset Maugham." June 8. 1946- ReV- and rpto in classiss_and_§2mmer: eiele. New York: Farrar Straus, 1950. 319-26. MICHIGAN STATE UNIV. LIBRARIES IllII“WI”UNIIIIWIIIIIIHIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIHHIIIIIWIIHI 31293007875226