Itu‘ oumwwuflv.” ”IN..." T em.» . . «awaésmmwm . kWh-W“ 'd . 1». i). a :6 I 5.4!. ”at ‘ I . 0"- ’I I ct .1v... .1 , - . (Va... . § U . . 5. u ' > v . t I... .. . . M... a...» .. . yfiurvnx afif. M £5”. . ru. . , n b l a - Iv . .1? 1:9.mn H. J . 3 L: .h . O .I < ‘ Y O‘I‘I ‘ I r h («9%. ‘ WWWWMWHGWWW . , sum Lufumm. .Mfiurnfiu . .. ‘ .1. . 0...... u... 1. 9.5...- zsfimjfifl , “(In “an. . ‘ Julrfaa ‘I . !v.r.....vfi.vHJ: nu écfimmwvwnfi. h . . naive" I 'KMI ‘ V I v v...“ ' L1» . r . . . , Jun-unfiwrdvvvlvr. . . .x -5...t . .. .mwaiuw . L. IJWAAIC . . 9‘ . a 0"... Eu! . fifim a . .r L. “IN v.1. HAP! . uvumdw: Em. {mm ushem ’, v' H ‘5‘... I d...; 3V». “Mitt-wreak“... q... 1. . Enii a...» Hana“. .mmnuf . WWW“. '. ‘. 1“."9' - l I: z n V V» “lug. . . . . ‘ . V4...“ 1. “.4“.an $.Qmwfi : .372... . v 04 I.Ox| . I: to Q .. . 3. Y. ‘ Elfin 96“. IM. 01»... g .v t I.‘ ‘ H LA ligwm antiwflvmu... .yMWuifingduflfihdl ufimurvh .. ting. ...E...uui.uumfivm.s .. . . 2%.;th . .7 . . .12? ..._..v.aw,mz...m.?. .51. , . O.hmun.~\lhbflvnuoo: X .. in“ ARV. . . 3‘ ... . ~ A. ‘ . ‘ . .MWPMWIWHQM? . .. K .,.. LR? I E fill ‘ 3.0 ‘5." . 6. ‘ -i! , . t "vl‘i‘Vv l .0211 ll! .n u 1.t\ y .3 .114I.I.| , ‘ ‘. ‘ ‘ , , 1.n\ ‘I\.l||1\nv0k . . lmflm! at; . ’ \ n , u s at. 3 . . . . l o ‘1'. . . Nbf . . .. . 1U. ‘U‘Nluwflitlltui: .n Mu. .q . ‘ v . \v.!v\ . lo! . tr . . . ' ':1 “‘O"‘ '0 'v‘." ‘ .l 12‘? .izyoulli , .. .. q . ., 9 . .f : .61...an . .mhzsvz‘hl. .7. .. swans. . I.u.v v .0 . . .. ‘ . .. n V .- IV I u‘ ‘ . hilw. 9.. ‘ I. 1‘40. dartl , O F. 4b.,» "1 o Iyn a .‘ ill .. . .||. 1., o Lv‘tvvuuhhns‘tr». [,Fuu‘uu. 1h it :2 . \I L I - Iv Al,‘ I . “33.5.: I.Ll...ml.¢u..- .._ ‘.. .. . l3 IN. 1.. ...uc-!:....»,. . - \Vv unuWWn‘uE .v “O'I ‘ . 4 ‘1'! *3 ‘ t - 'lA : - tv Ht . ‘ .v.‘l'lv..l'“".vlv ti! {aBiF‘vD .. . Film...) mus-Hill. “To... “4 . v I .1 y I. w'vfiltHLl .‘3‘o14 u ‘ l‘.".l‘." . l I 4L 0! «‘81, . «1L. 1.I.n..v...r“d t q l, "b‘ufl', .- .v , . . . , win? C . .r and... .nfinmrfimmmflwku. T-.. |.. i .H.H.‘.1¢§.Ir.l.. . f ‘. . .n F...“ , , .1111 ran}! . . 7.. . v. ‘ . THESIS IliumMimiitiltlitiiiuliumuuil 31293 015 LIBRARY Michigan State University This is to certify that the thesis entitled Dystopian Elements of Richard Rorty's Liberal Utopia presented by Maude Falcone has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for M o A 0 degree in Phi 1.030th Major professor Date ”7204/1 271/7/27 0-7639 MS U is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution 7 PLACE Nhé’URN 86X to @872 int-sew“ horn your record. To AVOID FINESNUHI mar. W dd. dUO. MSU in An Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Instituion mun-unmet DYSTOPIAN ELEMENTS OF RICHARD RORTY'S LIBERAL UTOPIA: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS OF RORTY'S PROPOSAL FOR THE REFORM OF INTELLECTUAL CULTURE AND HIS APPROPRIATION OF GEORGE ORWEll'S NIHEIEEN ElfiflliziQflB IN CONTINGENCX, IBQNX, AND SOLIDABIII BY Maude Falcone A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTERS OF ARTS Department of Philosophy 1997 ABSTRACT DYSTOPIAN ELEMENTS OF RICHARD RORTY'S LIBERAL UTOPIA: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS OF RORTY'S PROPOSAL FOR THE REFORM OF INTELLECTUAL CULTURE AND HIS APPROPRIATION OF GEORGE ORWELL’S NINETEEN ELGEII;EQUB IN QQNIINEENQXL lBQNXL AND SQLIDAELII BY Maude Falcone Richard Rorty's claim that his reconciliation of irony and human solidarity is consistent with the interests of intellectuals is interpreted in terms of the problem of social legitimation. Rorty's neglect of agency and his tendency to totalize discursive activity threatens to subordinate intellectual activity to social institutions and thus relieves those institutions of theoretical accountability. Within this context, Rorty's reading of Nineteen Eighty;£eur is questioned for its failure to account for Orwell's interrogation of the position of the intellectual in the reproduction of social institutions. Reading the novel in this light points to an analogy between Winston Smith and Rorty's ironist. In both cases it is an awareness of the arbitrariness of institutions combined with a thoroughgoing powerless which establishes an identification of the intellectual and institutionalized power. This analogy suggests that Rorty's reconciliation of irony and human solidarity might not be consistent with the interests of intellectuals. Copyright by Maude Falcone 1997 ‘Acknowledgments It goes without saying that no work such as this could be successfully undertaken without the support of others who take an interest in the ideas contained in it. I owe a special debt to Professor Richard T. Peterson who acted as my thesis advisor. His careful readings and thoughtful suggestions have not only substantially improved the final version but-~more importantly—-made a beneficial contribution to the learning process behind it. Professors Stephen L. Esquith and Mark Sullivan, both of whom served on my thesis committee, gave the work generous readings and made the oral examination a pleasant and interesting experience through their insightful questioning. Intellectually stimulating and emotionally supportive personal relationships are indispensable to writing. Rick Yuille has, in addition to reading previous versions of this work, been a dear friend and source of inspiration. Steven Dandaneau accepted responsibility for more than his share of housework and child care throughout the writing of this and, at measurable cost to himself, allowed the completion of my thesis to be our family's top priority. I deeply appreciate his companionship in matters both domestic and intellectual and recognize that I could not have finished without his assistance and encouragement. Finally, there is our son iv Patrick whose patience far exceeds that which is appropriate to his four years of age and whose openness to and being in the world has enabled me to feel what utopia might be like. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION ................................................ 1 PART I: IRONISM, HUMAN SOLIDARITY, AND SOCIAL LEGITIMATION..9 The Problem of Social Legitimation ..................... 9 The Consistency of Liberalism and Ironism .............. 15 PART II: POST-METAPHYSICAL INTELLECTUAL PRACTICE AND HUMAN AGENCY ..................................... . ....... ....23 Language, Selfhood, and Truth ................ . ......... 25 Human Agency and Discursive Totality ................... 36 Social Legitimation without Truth ...................... 43 PART III: RE-DESCRIBING NINETEEN_EIGHIX;EQHB ................ 47 Orwell's Contribution to the Self-Understanding of Contemporary Liberals....................... ...... 50 The Alienation of Winston Smith: The Division of Labor ............................................. 54 The Alienation of Winston Smith: Doublethink ........... 63 CONCLUSION .................................................. 83 ENDNOTES... ................................................. 9O BIBLIOGRAPHY .............................................. 100 vi INTRODUCTION A complex book, Richard Rorty's Centingeneye Irenye and Seliderity is written at the edges of philosophy and the liberal tradition of which it is a part. Rorty negotiates the boundaries between disciplines and fields of study, searching for continuities between such diverse topics as philosophy of science and political theory, metaphysics and psychology. He seeks the point where established understandings wear thin, clear-cutting the last vestiges of a philosophical tradition that has outworn its utility. Having set for himself the task of leading philosophy into its new post-modern, post-metaphysical, but thoroughly bourgeois age, Rorty intends to show the practical implications of his positions for intellectual activity. A central element of Rorty's CentingeneyL Irenye and Seliderity is his call to re-evaluate the status of narratively construed intellectual disciplines such as literature and ethnography relative to the foundationalist disciplines of philosophy and social theory. Specifically, Rorty claims that novels, poems and ethnography, journalism, comic books, and television programs can successfully provide for the development of popular normative commitments at the level of both the individual and the collective [W mm and Selidaritx [CIS], xvi]. Such genres as these can produce the substance of a vibrant intellectual culture capable of meeting the needs for personal meaning and social or communal stability. Philosophy and its close relation, social theory, are thus demoted by Rorty to the status of a special interest: of no general public relevance and the concern of only the few who find it satisfying. That this general position I have attributed to Rorty tends toward the conservative, as has been pointed out, for example, by Cornel West (1993), Nancy Fraser (1989), Richard J. Bernstein, (1987), Jo Burrows (1991), and Roy Bhaskar (1991), should not come as a surprise given that Rorty openly acknowledges that his unapologetic liberal political commitments clearly shape his phiIOSOphical speculations. Indeed, an important strategy in Rorty's attempt to show the desirability of his articulation of post-metaphysical intellectual activity is to establish its consistency with existing liberal political institutions. It is with this in mind that I have organized my position around the theme of social legitimation, as it relates to intellectuals as intellectuals. I focus on Rorty's recommendation that intellectual practices dependant on narratives for their justification should be privileged over intellectual practices dependant on claims to truth, analyzing this claim in terms of how such a recommendation might aid in the task of preserving the taken for granted nature of social institutions. Specifically, I interpret Rorty's intention to convince other intellectuals that his proposed reforms would be consistent with the preservation and expansion of cultural freedom as an appeal to the self interest of intellectuals themselves. I argue, in contrast, that Rorty's promises concerning the freedom of intellectuals are systematically undercut by the various restrictions he places on intellectual activity. Thus, in Part I, I understand Rorty's attempt to reconcile the contrary tendencies of ironism and human solidarity in terms of the legitimation of social institutions. I assume that the task of creating and supporting a sense of human solidarity and the task of social legitimation are the same for at stake in both is the preservation of an institutionalized community in the face of challenges to its pre-given validity. Following Peter L. Berger, in Ihe Sacred gangpy, I define social legitimation as "socially objectivated 'knowledge' that serves to explain and justify the social order. Put differently, legitimations are answers to any questions about the why of institutional arrangements" (1967, 29). The very possibility of asking about the 'whys' of institutions presupposes a break down in the pre-given order of the humanly constructed world such that, the social order appears as a construction. The successful resolution of challenges concerning the whys of institutional arrangements involves actively restoring the 'naturalness' or giveness of the construction. This is, of course, a perfect contradiction, the bearing of which requires the mobilization of intellectual resources necessary to the contradiction's maintenance.1 Placing Rorty's Contingencxi Ironyr and Solidarity in this broad context brings out the full complexity of Rorty's attempted reconciliation of irony and solidarity. Rorty's effective claim is that the legitimation of liberal traditions and institutions is only an issue for an elite population of intellectuals who, by definition, understand the contingency and mutability of social institutions. This understanding would have a reflexive element in that it would include an awareness that the intellectual's own freedom to question the foundations of social institutions is itself dependant on liberal institutions. Because of this, Rorty's implicit claim is that the interests of intellectuals and the interests of liberal institutions are the same. As I read Rorty, his recommendation is that intellectuals should adopt this self-understanding as their own and, as a result, voluntarily privatize their doubts about liberal institutions. In short, Rorty is claiming that intellectuals should see the utility of keeping their ironic awareness of the fragility of institutions out of public discourse, lest their own institutionalized freedom. be threatened. In addition to this primary, self-imposed, political limitation on the freedom of intellectuals, I argue in Part II that Rorty's articulation of a post-metaphysical intellectual activity also involves various restrictions on that activity. Specifically, in order to avoid epistemological quandaries, Rorty tends to treat discursive and non-discursive practice as if they were two separate spheres of activity. This results in a severing of intellectual activity from material, non-discursive practice. With the goal of showing how this works, I devote Part II of this essay to examining various aspects of the construction of Rorty's text. I explore such issues as Rorty's dismissal of the problem of epistemology, his metaphoric re-descriptions of various elements of linguistic activity, his neglect of human agency, and his unification of the concepts of contingency and freedom. My aim is to show that, while Rorty's stated intention is to avoid taking a position on epistemological issues, his consistent privileging of the discursive side of the epistemological problematic results in a text that asserts the primacy of language over the facticity of the body and the embeddedness of social action in always already existing social institutions and cultural patterns. While this position appears to privilege the language user, I argue that it is a privilege limited by Rorty's tendency to hypostatise the world as 'out there', immune to human influence. The result of this, so I claim, is that, because Rorty openly discounts the possibility that social and political institutions could be justified independent of their factual existence, this hypostatization of the world works to relieve social institutions, and thus institutionalized social power, of any burden of theoretical accountability. I discuss this through a reconsideration of Rorty's treatment of social legitimation that is focused on how Rorty's dismissal of 'truth' serves the interests of existing liberal institutions. After presenting this interpretation of Qootiogoooyi ltonyi and Solidarity, I consider Rorty's reading of George Orwell's Nineteen Eighty;£ont. I assume it to be given that, in the process of furthering various points made by Rorty in previous chapters, Rorty's reading of Nineteen Eighty;£ont provides a concrete model of a post-metaphysical intellectual practice that exemplifies Rorty's intellectual and political ideals. More precisely, Rorty redescribes Orwell's last novel in such a way as to both support his own claim concerning the centrality of social hope to the liberal tradition and obscure Orwell's own interrogation of the position of the intellectual in the reproduction of institutionalized social power and a manifestly irrational form of social organization. In contrast, I argue that a reconstruction of Orwell's insights into social reproduction--including Orwell's emphasis on the institutional roots and latent functions of the alienation of intellectuals which he articulated through the character Winston Smith--suggests an analogy between the situation of Winston in Nineteen Eighty;£ont and that of the liberal ironist populating the pages of Qontingenoyi ltonyi and Soiioetity. The interpretive act of placing Winston's resistance in the context of the material operation and intellectual logic of power in Oceanic Society indicates that Winston's alienation and Rorty's irony have the same function of establishing the commitment on the part of intellectuals to the maintenance of existing institutions. The ironic consequence of this analogy is that it suggests that in both texts it is a combination of an awareness of the arbitrariness of social institutions combined with a thoroughgoing powerlessness that establishes the primacy of institutionalized social power. While this situation might undermine the plausibility of Rorty's appeal to the legacy of George Orwell in the furthering of his own positions, it also and most importantly illustrates the potential efficacy of Rorty's practice of re—description in the pursuit of his political ends. The analysis of this dynamic helps to illuminate the technical strengths of Rorty's positions concerning the reformation of intellectual culture for the legitimation of social institutions. Even so, recognizing the technical strengths of Rorty's practice of re-description does not alleviate the burden of examining that practice for its desirability, but instead, underscores the urgency of such an examination. Given that Rorty's proposals for intellectual reform depend for their implementation on the voluntary compliance of intellectuals, Rorty's appeals to the self-interest of intellectuals would seem an appropriate perspective from which to interrogate their desirability. I. SOCIAL LEGITIMATION, HUMAN SOLIDARITY, AND IRONISM Having rejected theories of human nature, Rorty does not posit a universal characteristic common to all members of a post-metaphysical culture. Instead, the population would be divided according to the extent to which members question not only who they are but the social processes that create who they are. On this basis Rorty suggests that the population of a non-metaphysical culture would be divided into commonsensical non-metaphysicians and ironists.2 It is with this distinction in mind that Rorty frames the issue of creating and supporting a sense of human solidarity as the posited foundation for a general commitment to liberal institutions.3 The Problem of Social Legitimation Rorty introduces the distinction between the ironist intellectual and the commonsensical non-metaphysician through a discussion of his idea of a "final vocabulary"4 as the limit of language and thus the linguistically construed self. A final vocabulary is composed of words which, if questioned, cannot be defended argumentatively. Their defense can only be circular. In Rorty's words, a final vocabulary is, a set of words which...[people]...employ to justify their actions, their beliefs, and their lives. These are the words in which we formulate praise of our friends and contempt for our enemies, our long term projects, our deepest self- doubts and our highest hopes. They are the words in which we tell...the story of our lives (CIS, 73). In essense, then, one's final vocabulary effectively draws a circle around the core region of the self. It is the last resort of a differentiated identity and within that circle is undifferentiated otherness. The commonsensical non-metaphysician takes for granted the taken for granted nature of this vocabulary. As Rorty describes it, a person operating under the sign of commonsense would "unselfconsciously describe everything important in terms of the final vocabulary to which they and those around them are habituated" (CIS, 73). Thus, while they might acknowledge a relation between social processes and their final vocabulary, they do not question the facticity of either this relation or the social processes themselves. Most people would not be concerned with such matters, for Rorty "cannot imagine a culture which socialized its youth in such a way as to make them continually dubious of their own processes of socialization" (CIS, 94). 10 Some people, ironist intellectuals in particular, will harbor such doubts. According to Rorty, this is because, having been impressed with other final vocabularies, the ironist understands that even this last resort of language is contingent on something other than itself. The ironist knows that while final vocabularies may be the last words on the matter, they are never the end of the matter, for there is always an element of arbitrariness to the terms in which individuals settle on their selves. It is within the context of this distinction between ironists and commonsensical non-metaphysicians that Rorty's position concerning the legitimation of the social bond can be understood. At stake in Rorty's articulation is the possibility of grounding and justifying a sense of human solidarity in a liberal society without recourse to metaphysical concepts. Rorty claims in the first place that, "The idea that liberal societies are bound together by philosophical beliefs...is...ludicrous" (CIS, 87). Instead, for Rorty, it is common vocabularies and common hopes which bind liberal societies together. The vocabularies are dependant on the hopes in so far as "...the principle function of the vocabularies is to tell stories about future outcomes which compensate for present sacrifices" (CIS,86). Such stories of 'social hope' underwrite the commitment of 11 most people to the liberal tradition; and, in "modern, literate, secular societies (CIS, 86)," these stories are political in emphasis. Describing these stories, Rorty writes, To retain social hope, members of such a society need to be able to tell themselves a story about how things might get better, and to see no insuperable obstacle to this story's coming true (CIS, 85). In general, then, Rorty's answer to the question of what underwrites a sense of social solidarity in a post- metaphysical culture is a shared belief in progress articulated through a common vocabulary and narrative tradition.5 Rorty approaches the problem of justifying and legitimating such a belief in progress in terms of different rhetorical strategies appropriate to different segments of the population. As a rule, this issue of social legitimation is hardly a dilemma for the majority pOpulation of commonsensical non-metaphysicians. Because Rorty defines commonsensical non-metaphysicians, contra ironist intellectuals, in terms of their lack of reflexivity towards their final vocabularies, it is unlikely that the issue of justifying one's sense of solidarity will ever be an issue for this group. In Rorty's formulation, a commonsensical non-metaphysician would not need such justification, "...for 12 she was not raised to play the language game in which one asks for and gets justifications for that sort of belief" (CIS, 87). Moreover, the political commitments and allegiances of commonsensical non-metaphysicians would not be grounded philosophically through the exploration of principles and definitions, but, instead, would be grounded through the exploration of concrete practical alternatives and programs (CIS, 87). In a different context, Rorty maintains that liberal political institutions would be better off if relieved of the burden of philosophical justification. Appealing to the authority of such figures as John Dewey, Michael Oakeshott and John Rawls, Rorty writes "...that a circular justification of our practices which makes one feature of our culture look good by citing still another, or comparing our culture invidiously with others with reference to our own standards, is the only sort of justification we are going to get" (CIS, 57). Rorty's claim is that, as a rule, legitimation issues can be resolved through the narrative re-description of the concrete alternatives to liberal institutions that make the alternatives look bad and the liberal institutions look good. For the ironist, however, social legitimation is a problem, for it is the habit of ironists to doubt their 13 final vocabularies and reflect on the processes which create those vocabularies. In other words, the ironist questions the shared narrative tradition that would otherwise establish, as given, a sense of human solidarity within a post-metaphysical liberal society. It is with this group in mind that Rorty frames the the problem of reconciling the need for human solidarity or community with the ironic awareness of the contingency of the same. This problem is not, for Rorty, irresolvable: although 'irony' and 'community' may involve contrary impulses, they need not be thought of as contradictory or mutually exclusive. Thus, while Rorty is fully aware that the combination of a skill with re-description and a heightened awareness of the contingency of the terms of re-description can interfere with the taken for granted nature of community and is thus potentially dangerous to social stability, he also contends that intellectuals can choose not to make this a problem by privatizing such ironic tendencies.6 This privatization of irony would constitute a basic feature of intellectual life in Rorty's post-metaphysical intellectual culture. Rorty contends that the privatization of irony contradicts neither the needs of liberal institutions nor the interests of a well-intentioned ironist. Intellectuals who understand the inter- l4 relationship between liberal institutions and private freedom will voluntarily censor their ironic reflection. Moreover, this voluntary compliance with the requirements of liberalism is itself motivated by an awareness of contingency”, or irony. Rorty argues this position concerning the consistency of liberalism and ironism through a combined appeal to the sympathy and self—interest of ironist intellectuals. The Consistency of Ironism With Liberalism In his appeal to the sympathy of ironist intellectuals, Rorty contends that the liberal ironist's understanding of the power of re-description is the foundation for a sense of solidarity with the commonsensical non-metaphysician. In other words, the ironist understands the world-destroying power of words and hence the potentially cruel consequences of re-descriptive activity. Rorty writes of the liberal ironist: She thinks that what unites her with the rest of the species is not a common language but inst susceptibility to pain, and in particular to that special sort of pain which the brutes do not share with the humans--humiliation (CIS, 92, emphasis in original); and, 15 What matters for the liberal ironist is not finding such a reason [to care about suffering] but making sure that she notioes suffering when it occurs. Her hope is that she will not be limited by her own final vocabulary when faced with the possibility of humiliating someone with a quite different final vocabulary (CIS, 93). Implicit in this argument that liberal ironists can be motivated to limit their re-descriptive skills is Rorty's assumption that liberalism is best understood in terms of its primary publicly relevant end, "the elimination of cruelty" (CIS, 65, 68), and that the liberal is one for whom cruelty is the worst thing humans can do (CIS, xv, 74). In addition to the relatively unimportant phenomena of its physical manifestation, in Rorty's lexicon, cruelty refers to humiliation, a form of cruelty produced through re- description. Following Elaine Scarry (1985), Rorty writes, The best way to cause people long lasting pain is to humiliate them by making the things that seemed most important to them to look facile, obsolete, and powerless (CIS, 89). This is precisely what the intellectual does to the non- intellectual, for the intellectual's moons ooetsnoi is re- description and "re-description often humiliates" (CIS, 90). While this tendency to humiliate is characteristic of both metaphysical and ironist intellectual activity, ironist intellectual activity is particularly humiliating, given that it is informed by an "awareness of the power of re- 16 description" itself (CIS, 89). Because metaphysical re— description assumes a relationship between a particular re- description and some sort of truth, its humiliating tendencies are compensated for by promises of an increase in power, freedom, enlightenment or some other such value. It is a humiliation attenuated by hope. Ironists make no such promises, for their heightened awareness of the arbitrary moment in all re-descriptive activity prevents this. Ironists thus humiliate without the ancillary claim that something good will come of it. According to Rorty, ironists who desire not to be cruel will, in public life, not like a metaphysician or hold their tongues, reserving their irony for the privacy of their own homes.8 Of course, this can only be counted on in the liberal, one who, above all else, is dedicated to the elimination of cruelty. Rorty is aware that not all ironists are liberal. It is, perhaps, with the non-liberal ironist in mind-- the intellectual who does not care about caring--that Rorty includes within his attempt to establish the compatibility of liberalism and ironism suggestions that it would be in the self-interest of ironists themselves to recognize the validity, or at least the utility, of his position.9 .Again, Rorty's definition of liberalism provides the basis for this argument. According to Rorty, the liberal desire to 17 eliminate cruelty is related to the desire to expand private freedom in the interest of increasing opportunities for self-creation. Because cruelty deprives humans of their ability to use language (CIS, 94) and thus of their ability to create their selves, cruelty is contrary to this end. Because ironism is potentially humiliating and thus potentially cruel, it is inappropriate for political discourse and should be limited to the private sphere. Such a limitation might on the surface appear to contradict the end of expanding freedom, but, in Rorty's accounting, it does no such thing. This is because Rorty works with two understandings of 'freedom', one appropriate to public life and one appropriate to private life. With regard to the former, Rorty resists defining political freedom in terms other than existing liberal political institutions, which, in his View, should be thought of as having been "designed to diminish cruelty, make possible government by consent of the governed, and permit as much domination-free communication as possible to take place" (CIS, 68) in order to optimize the "balance between leaving people's private life alone and preventing suffering" (CIS, 63). Public, or political freedoms, such as those which exist "when the press, the judiciary, the elections and the universities are free" (CIS, 84), are 18 necessary to the liberal goal of maximizing opportunities for self-creation. Rorty writes, ...without the protection of something like the institutions of bourgeois liberal society, people will be less able to work out their private salvations, create their private self-images, reweave their webs of belief and desire in light of whatever new people and books they happen to encounter (CIS, 84-5). Understood in this way, freedom in the public sphere is limited by the goal of maximizing freedom in the private sphere. It is here that Rorty's counsel that ironists should privatize "their attempts at authenticity and purity" lest they come "to think that there is some social goal more important than avoiding cruelty" (CIS, 65) can be seen as an appeal to the self—interests of ironists themselves. As Rorty understands it, irony, an attitude oriented towards questioning that which is held in common by members of a community, especially the pre-given sense of human solidarity, is necessarily parasitic on, and disruptive of, common traditions and vocabularies. Additionally, and for this reason, irony involves a reflexive understanding of the contingent nature of communal institutions and is thus intimately aware of the fragility of those institutions. Even the liberal value of private freedom oriented towards self-creation is contingent on the lucky coincidence of various historical tendencies. Because of this, Rorty 19 suggests that not only are liberal institutions contingent on such things as peace, wealth, universal literacy, and higher education, but that the ironist's freedom to question those institutions, and recreate their selves according to an alternative image of their own choosing, is equally contingent. In short, the freedom to pursue the project of private perfection is a liberal freedom dependant on the institutions characteristic of a liberal society. The implication of Rorty's claim is that the interest of the ironist and the interest of liberal institutions are the same: the ironist seeks private perfection and liberal institutions create and preserve the conditions wherein that search might be possible for the greatest number of people. The ironist should thus recognize the utility of keeping whatever doubts they may have about those institutions to themselves, lest they shake the ground of their own freedom. Summarizing these considerations, Rorty confronts the problem of creating a sense of human solidarity in the interest of preserving a general commitment to social institutions from two perspectives, that appropriate to the general population of commonsensical non—metaphysicians and that appropriate to an elite population of ironist intellectuals. It is the latter issue which is the more complex one, for, as a rule, social legitimation is only a 20 problem for intellectuals who question the foundation-— philosophical or otherwise--of social institutions. Rorty provides a dual response to this issue which involves an appeal to sympathy directed at those who might find such an appeal compelling and an appeal to self-interest for those who do not. Thus, even if one is not instinctively repulsed by cruelty or if one is not quite taken by Rorty's equation of 'cruelty', 'humiliation', 're-description', and 'intellectual activity,’ one might be persuaded of the validity of the liberal cause by considerations of one's own interest in that cause, namely, that Rorty's liberalism promises to protect even the most difficult and recalcitrant ironist. It has been argued by Nancy Fraser (1989, 100-2), Roy Bhaskar (1991, 89-91), Charles Anderson (1991, 367), and others, that, if taken at face value, this reconciliation of the contrary tendencies of ironism and liberalism would seem to depend on the salience of Rorty's distinction between 'public' and 'private' spheres-—a distinction which is notoriously unstable in liberal political thought. Criticizing Rorty on this count, however, assumes that there ought to be a relation between the ideas expressed in W ILQDX... and Solidaritx and non-discursive material practice. In essence, such criticisms assume that 21 this work is best interpreted as a program for institutional change and that questions of practicability are relevant issues. That Rorty does often adopt the voice and persona of a strident critic and reformer tirelessly dedicated to social causes--a post-modern Jane Addams--lends credence to this assumption. However, if one brackets these rhetorical devices and focuses on Rorty's stated commitment to a consistently maintained rejection of attempts to posit or assume a positive relation between linguistically construed artifacts and those which are not linguistically construed, the relevance of such questions is immediately brought into question. Having set aside the epistemological problematic as irretrievably metaphysical, Rorty also sets aside all issues revolving around the relation between language and that which is external to language. This includes concrete programs for institutional reform as well as problems arising from actual attempts to practice his posited reconciliation of the pursuit of private perfection and the pursuit of human solidarity. That Rorty's stated intention is conservative with respect to existing social institutions implies that part of his aim is precisely to prevent the translation of ironic reflection on the contingency of institutions into a viable program for institutional change. When set in the context of the historical fact that the 22 public-private split has proven, in practice, to be very stable given the absence of revolution in liberal societies, Rorty's own sophisticated, participatory self-understanding renders questionable the relevancy of criticizing Contingsncyi Ironyi and Solidarity on these grounds. II. POST-METAPHYSICAL INTELLECTUAL PRACTICE AND HUMAN.AGENCY It is now possible to consider in closer detail Rorty's attempt to develop an understanding of intellectual activity which neither posits nor assumes an epistemological position. Rorty's stated intention is to avoid entanglement in what he considers to be the irresolvable problems inherent in a concept of truth which involves understanding truth as a representation of "the world". These problems have been articulated in his earlier work, Eniiosoohy and tbs Mitten of Nature (1979). In gentinaanayi thnxi and soiiostity, Rorty assumes, as given, many of the positions worked out in BhlLQSQDhX and Lbs MiILQI Qfi Nainzfit applying them to new problems and contexts.10 Because of this, those positions lose contact with their origins in a specific argument against the Cartesian tradition of philosophy. It is this aspect of Contingsngyi Ironyi and Solidarity that I 23 am considering here. For example, Rorty's interrogation of the problems inherent in conceptualizing "truth" as a representation or correspondence to reality outlined in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature... has, by the time of Contingency; Ironyz and Solidarity. been extended by Rorty to include any posited or assumed relation between 'language' and something external to it. "Truth" is thus dispensed with as a regulative ideal. My concern is to explore some of the consequences of this, focusing on Rorty's tendency in contingenoyi itonyi end solidstity to treat 'language' and the 'world' as separate spheres. I argue that this separation, when combined with his textual practice of privileging the sphere of 'language', has a double result: it restricts the significance of language to its pragmatic utility in furthering the immediate concerns of the language user at the same time as it works to hypostatize the world, as it exists. In order to develop this analysis, I will first provide a brief summary of Rorty's positions on language and self- hood. After this, I will turn my attention to an examination of Rorty's practice of text construction.11 This, in order to explore how Rorty's explicit positions are refined, taking on added meanings and shapes, in the articulation of his positions. In other words, I endeavor 24 to show how Rorty's practice of text construction exerts a constitutive influence on his positions. To this end, I analyze Rorty's emphasis on the power of the language user and how this emphasis is consistently undermined by an invocation of objective contexts of powerlessness (illustrated in the metaphors he uses to describe language use within given vocabularies, vocabularies as a whole, and a posited post-metaphysical culture) and Rorty's tendency to totalize discursive activity (illustrated in his treatment of the prudence/morality distinction). I conclude from these considerations that Rorty does not give sufficient attention to non-discursive human agency--the human capacity to affect the objective structural conditions of their existence through material practice--in his articulation of his conception of intellectual activity. At this point, I consider how this relates to Rorty's position that "freedom" is founded on and limited by "contingency". I conclude this section with a reconsideration of Rorty's proposed solution to the problem of creating and preserving a general commitment to liberal social institutions. Language, Self-Hood, and Truth Rorty lobbies for a disenchanted View of language that 25 neither depends on a conception of truth as anything other than habit nor requires the positing of an inner truth prior to or beyond language (CIS, 19). According to Rorty, versions of language which treat language as a medium (CIS, 10-11) or third thing (CIS, 14) coming between humans and the world, imply access to something external to language, either to be represented or expressed. Rorty argues that because this view involves a subject-object picture of language, they remain entangled in irresolvable problems (CIS, 10-11). While Rorty does not deny the existence of worlds outside of language, he resists philosophical integration of these worlds. Instead, Rorty approaches language pragmatically. Thus, for Rorty, languages are composed of vocabularies which neither represent the world nor express an inner truth or message (CIS, 19). Instead, vocabularies are the means for describing and redescribing the world and one's relations in it. Significantly, different vocabularies might be used to describe the same object, there being no necessary connection between a given vocabulary and the object in question. The choice between two incompatible vocabularies is not a question of their relation to the object. Rather, such a choice is a question of their relative efficacy in the pursuit of given ends (CIS, 19, 21). In Rorty's articulation, these ends are 26 external to the vocabulary, referring to the language user's social or communal context (CIS, 11-15, 20-22). Rorty's treatment of self-hood follows from and is consistent with his treatment of language. Having already rejected as metaphysical notions of something prior to language, Rorty presents the sense of having a self, or self-hood, as a function of its linguistically construed identity. The self, as Rorty articulates it, is nothing more than that which employs language, particularly metaphor, to construct a personal history which would distinguish it from its fellow humans. Rorty describes three basic approaches to this problem of identity, describing each in terms of their attitude to the problem of contingency which is primarily understood in terms of one's dependency on other humans (CIS, 27, 37—38). There is, first, the metaphysical approach, which never comes to terms with the fact of contingency, instead seeking refuge in its identification with that which is not contingent (CIS, 26-7). There is, second, the strongly poetic approach which, in its appreciation of contingency, attempts to appropriate it for its own purposes, thereby hoping to individuate itself by making others contingent upon it (CIS, 27—30). Finally, there is the approach of the weak poet”, who has come to terms with contingency in the 27 knowledge that its individuation can only be a partial unfinished project, always parasitic on a wider community (CIS, 35-8, 42-3). It is this weakly poetic model of self- creation that Rorty takes to be the most appropriate for describing what most people in his liberal utopia would be like. In his discussion of this model, Rorty attempts to establish the plausibility of a self which receives its identity, its sense of itself, and its individuation, from the social network of which it is a part (CIS, 42-3).13 Rorty's intention to avoid metaphysics“ encourages him to reject a concept of 'truth' that is anything more than a convenient term for describing settled habits or conventions (CIS, 5—7). Because of this, Rorty rejects any attempt to establish a concrete relation between language and the world or between language and a pre-linguistic self, such as is implied in a correspondence or expressive theory of truth. His thinking is that, since truth is a property of statements (CIS, 5, 7), and since statements always take a language dependant form and are thus socially and culturally determined by the conventions of the language community, then truth can mean nothing other than the conventions and habits regulating discourse (CIS, 18—19). At best, then, and mostly by implication,15 'truth' is, for Rorty, a shorthand expression for the totality of institutions 28 assumed in the use of language. Truth is not, therefore, a property of the world to be discovered or even a characteristic of the relation between discursive systems and something external to those systems (CIS, 5). Because of considerations such as these, Rorty dismisses a theory of truth which posits a connection between language and something that exists independently of language. This unwillingness to assume such a connection between language and that which is external to it is evident in both his pragmatic understanding of language and his understanding of self-hood as a coping mechanism. In both cases, Rorty avoids defining his objects of analysis in terms of what they one, choosing instead to define them functionally, in terms of how they work in the human effort to deal with contingency on other humans. From this perspective, language is a means to directly manipulate other people. A sense of self is, in its turn, the product of processes of indirect manipulation, or imaginative re- descriptions of one's personal relationships in terms of ones own choosing. Rorty's focus, in both cases, is centered on the active agent or subject and his emphasis is on empowerment. This empowerment, however, occurs in an objective context of powerlessness. He writes of the power of the objective 29 world that it is not "the sort we can appropriate by adopting and then transforming its language, thereby becoming identical with the threatening power and subsuming it under our own more powerful selves. This latter strategy is appropriate only for coping with other persons..." (CIS, 40). As an instrument uniquely suited for overcoming the power of other humans, language is, as Rorty presents it, of no use for influencing the extra-linguistic environment. Thus, while "the world can blindly and inarticulately crush us; mute despair, intense mental pain can cause us to blot ourselves out" (CIS, 40), re-description is a poor defense against that sort of thing. 'The world' which exists independent of its description is not vulnerable to the transformative power of language, nor is the body of the self so vulnerable, since it, too, exists independent of one's linguistically construed identity.16 Rorty writes that "...our relationship to the world, to brute power and to naked pain, is not the sort of relation we have to persons," concluding that, "when faced with the non-human and the non—linguistic, we no longer have an ability to overcome contingency and pain" (CIS, 40). This tension between Rorty's subject-centered focus and his invocation of an objective context of powerlessness is illustrated in Rorty's choice of metaphors that he employs 30 to describe elements of linguistic activity. Such metaphors, as Rorty acknowledges, exert a constitutive influence on the conception of language Rorty is presenting and the implicit conception of the kinds of humans who might use it. Understanding the implications of these metaphors is thus essential to a full understanding of the complexities of Rorty's positions. For example, the descriptive differences between Rorty's treatment of language use within discursive systems and discursive systems as a whole point directly to the conception of human agency Rorty is working with. When describing language use within a given vocabulary, Rorty relies on metaphors which privilege the acting subject such as those implied in his use of the terms "language game" or "tool." Through these metaphors, Rorty creates a picture of linguistic interaction which is both inherently empowering and manipulative. For example, in comparing language to a "tool," Rorty suggests it is an instrument ideally suited to coping with the human environment. In this way, Rorty presents language as a means through which the subject increases its power in the world. Along the same lines, Rorty's use of the metaphor "language game" creates a picture of language use that resembles a strategic competition in which words and sentences are the means of 31 play and metaphor the characteristic maneuver. While Rorty does not concretely specify how one "wins," he does indicate that the goal is always to produce effects on one's linguistic partner. For Rorty, this means to change how others speak, and in this way change how they act and who they are (CIS, 18, 20). Both of these metaphors privilege the acting, speaking subject at the expense of their communicative partner, treating the latter as a contingency to be dealt with or overcome. Referring to vocabularies as a whole, Rorty relies on metaphors which are very different from those just described in that they work to displace the privilege of the speaking subject. In presenting his View of the history of ideas, Rorty often uses naturalistic metaphors such as "contingency" and "evolution" (CIS, 16-17). For example, referring to his analogy between natural evolution and the history of ideas, Rorty writes, This analogy lets us think of "our language"--that is, of the science and culture of twentieth- century Europe--as something that took shape as a result of a great number of sheer contingencies. Our language and our culture are as much a contingency, as much a result of thousands of small mutations finding niches (and millions of others finding no niches) as are the orchids and anthropoids (CIS, 16). As this statement indicates, in Rorty's usage, these metaphors suggest that, while language as a whole may be 32 subject to change, it, like all natural systems, is not subject to conscious manipulation. Given Rorty's usage of such phrases as "random factors" (CIS, l7) and "blind contingent mechanical forces" (CIS, l7), Rorty's treatment of these metaphors precludes a discussion of the specifically historical. At issue is the role of conscious human activity: the concept of history preserves a place for it while concepts like contingency and evolution do not. The result of relying on these metaphors is that Rorty treats the history of discursive systems or vocabularies with the same reverent indifference typically reserved for natural phenomena beyond the scope of human agency: "It hardly matters how the trick was done. The results were marvelous" (CIS, 17). A troubling dynamic emerges when, in the act of interpretation, these two sets of metaphors are brought together. On the one hand, Rorty's use of instrumentalist and gaming metaphors appears to empower the language user. On the other hand, this empowerment is undermined by his further reliance on the metaphors of contingency and evolution which demand passivity in the face of the language system. In this way, empowerment occurs only within the context of a greater dis-empowerment. This dynamic is intensified in Rorty's use of the 33 metaphor "playfulness" to describe the culture anticipated in his re-description of intellectual activity. This metaphor points to a culture wherein an empowered subject operates and is limited by an objective context of powerlessness. A culture characterized by playfulness would be made possible by the de-devinization of both "the world" and "the self." As Rorty presents it, such de—devinization would involve no longer seeing the world and the self in anthropomorphic terms, or as "quasi-persons" (CIS, 40). Because the world and the self are insensitive to language, caring neither to be represented or expressed, re- description is useless. The use of metaphor to represent and transform only applies to other people and is of little value when dealing with the non-human and the non- linguistic. According to Rorty, then, this resignation in the face of the world and the non-linguistic self would allow for the development of a culture wherein projects of self-creation would be characterized by a "spirit of playfulness" (CIS, 39-40). Importantly, it is the recognition of contingency that underwrites this cultural freedom. Presumably, once reconciled to their own contingency, people would no longer feel responsible to the conditions of their existence and would no longer feel responsible for things they cannot 34 change. Unconstrained by the objective demands of their situation and reconciled to their own powerlessness, they could afford to dispense with seriousness and pretension; they would be free to pursue diverse projects of self- creation.l7 In general, then, Rorty's use of subject-centered metaphors to describe language use and his re-description of intellectual culture in terms of play both imply an effective objective state of powerlessness. Rorty's instrumentalist and gaming metaphors suggest that individuals can use language to further their own immediate ends or desires. However, Rorty's language users are powerless in the face of the objective context in which they use language. They may successfully maneuver within a particular language game, but the nature of the game itself, its rules and conditions, is beyond their control. Furthermore, Rorty's contention that an intellectual culture premised on the full appreciation of contingency and characterized by an experimental, non-binding approach to its artifacts suggests that members of such a culture would be free to choose their own narrative identities. They would, however, remain passive with respect to the conditions of their existence. In other words, their freedom would be of a compensatory, coping nature, and not 35 expandable to material practice. Human Agency and Discursive Totality As both Rorty's dismissal of the problem of the relation between language and phenomena that exist independent of it and the above consideration of the various metaphors Rorty uses to describe elements of intellectual practice is intended to show, Rorty's evasion of the epistemological problematic limits his recognition of human agency to its manifestation in discursive activity. In other words, Rorty does not include within his accounting the human capacity for concretely influencing the conditions of their existence through material practice, or practice which takes a non-discursive form. Simply stated, Rorty devalues the activity of bodies. At the same time, he does not deny this activity. His claim that language is useless against the real power of the world and self implies that there is something beyond language even if it cannot be articulated or known. The result is that Rorty works with two spheres of activity which do not come into contact with each other. Moreover, Rorty's performative privileging of that which can be articulated, or that which takes a discursive form, renders the two spheres not only separate 36 but unequal as well. This can be seen, for example, in Rorty's inclination to totalize discursive activity treating it as a self- contained sphere, evident in Rorty's adoption of a coherence theory of truth. Rorty's strictures against referentiality necessitates the replacement of an intellectual standard that might recognize the binding force of an objective order such as was implied in the conceptions of language he opposes, with that of internal consistency. The criteria for evaluating any given discursive system is rendered by Rorty to be internal to that system. A consequence of this inclination to totalize the universe of discourse by making the criteria for evaluation internal to the discursive unit is that, in neither assuming nor positing a possible connection between intellectual and material phenomena, Rorty extends the ban on metaphysics to include anthropology, sociology, history and other theory dependant empirical research projects.18 Illustrating this, Rorty provides various narrative accounts of the history of philosophy in the last two or three centuries.19 In none of these accounts does Rorty intend to provide an empirical description of what actually happened in the historical period he addresses. Instead, through re—description, Rorty provides various definitions of the history of philosophy, 37 and thus prefigures the sorts of responses adequate to that history. Moreover, without ever appealing to what, in fact, 'actually happened,’ Rorty invokes what happened some two or three hundred years ago to give rise to philosophy as we know it, thereby reducing history to its telling.20 Explaining his method in general, he writes of his project: The method is to redescribe lots and lots of things in new ways, until you have created a pattern of linguistic behavior which will temp the rising generation to adopt it, thereby causing them to look for appropriate new forms of non- linguistic behavior (CIS, 9). This suggests both the extent of his intent to redescribe and its acknowledged manipulative tendencies. A further illustration of Rorty's tendency to totalize the universe of discourse occurs in his discussion of the distinction between prudence and morality.21 Appealing to the insights of Freud, who "lets us see the moral consciousness as historically conditioned, a product as much of time and chance as of political or aesthetic consciousness" (CIS, 30), Rorty redescribes morality in terms of prudence (CIS, 32-3). His suggestion is this: what is usually understood as a function of 'moral consciousness' is better understood as a possible or attempted adaptation to a particular situation. Accordingly, the distinction between morality and prudence is that between alternative modes of adaptation or the expression of a particular self 38 in the attempt to cope with certain contingent facts of its existence. In other words, Rorty understands morality in terms of prudence. Following from this, Rorty redescribes Kantian morality in terms of Kant's psychology, that is, Kant's idiosyncratic, though perhaps laudable, desire to make room for "the unselfish, un-self conscious, unimaginative, decent, honest, dutiful person" (CIS, 34) with whom, Rorty suggests, Kant identified due to (unspecified) events of his personal history (CIS, 33). This tendency to interpret intellectual positions in terms of psychological dispositions, establishes, in Rorty's text, the totality of psychological processes. Given Rorty's understanding of the 'self' as a linguistically construed identity, this totality remains a discursive totality, one which is limited by the narratives individuals settle on to tell their life's story. Intellectual commitments become indicative of nothing more than one's own experiences, narratively construed. This, in turn, threatens a closed system where the significance of intellectual claims is reduced by the fact that, unlike intellectual differences which beg resolution, psychological differences, making no claims to objectivity, are easily tolerated and need not be settled one way or the other. It is here that Rorty's overriding emphasis on 39 psychological processes, and his re—description of intellectual matters in terms of those processes, can be seen to subordinate thought to social institutions, and thereby contains thought's powers of negation to individual concerns.22 The details of Rorty's attempt to come to terms with the conditionedness of intellectual and cultural productions in Qontinoenoyi ltonyi end Soiioetity renders invisible and thus unaccountable the highly mediated social processes that have also been said to exert their influence. In the working out of his position, Rorty places the burden of explanation on those variables immediately present within the individual life-world, privileging that which is close at hand. At issue in all this is that, in the working out of his account of an intellectual activity which can avoid what he takes to be the intractable dilemmas of the epistemological problematic, Rorty fails to incorporate into his position any recognition of the long acknowledged human capacity for influencing objective conditions through material practice. This results in the assumption of two self-contained spheres of activity, one relating to intellectual phenomena and one relating to material phenomena. This suggests a duality applicable at the level of lived experience. However, as is suggested by Rorty's tendency to totalize the 40 universe of discourse, this dualism is not sufficiently sustained in the working out of the details of his position in contingenoyi itonyi end Soiidstity. The tension between the two poles quickly collapses. The consequences of this collapse can be seen most clearly in Rorty's contention that freedom is best understood in terms of the "recognition of contingency" (CIS, 46), which means that freedom is both founded on and limited by the experienced awareness of contingency (CIS, 40). Rorty's privileging of the speaking subject does preserve a form of freedom”; however, Rorty's neglect of human agency--the power to impact the material conditions of one's existence and the existence of others through concrete practice--limits his articulation of the concept freedom to its most abstract, subjective form. Moreover, combined with his abstract, negative rendering of contingency, this downgrading of agency obscures the self- directed, self-formative structuring of human behavior. Rorty's equation of contingency with randomness24 closes off from analysis that which human behavior is contingent upon, suggesting, at times, that such analysis is the product of an only psychologically relevant, metaphysical approach to the world (CIS, 26-7). There would be no point to inquiring into the concrete determinants of 41 human behavior if those determinants are already assumed to be randomly distributed. Agency is in this way rendered inexplicable and unanalyzable and thus not subject to evaluation. This last move effectively unifies the concepts of contingency and freedom. Rorty concludes from his recognition that there is nothing universal governing human behavior that human behavior is contingent upon unpredictable random events not subject to conscious control. When combined with Rorty's implied understanding of freedom in negative terms, as not being subject to conscious control, this leads Rorty to assume that contingency is the foundation for human freedom. An embracing of contingency is the best protection freedom can hope for. In summary, then, I have considered Rorty's attempt to develop what he considers to be a post-metaphysical account of intellectual activity. His stated intention to avoid epistemological issues, combined with his neglect of agency, creates an unstable dualism in the face of the relation between intellectual and material phenomena. In the articulation of his positions, this dualism collapses into a monistic totality of discourse. Intellectual activity is in this way rendered by Rorty to be a self-contained, self- 42 referential sphere, its objective significance limited to the immediate concerns of the language user. Finally, this results in the hypostatization of existing social institutions and institutional social power. This dynamic is consistent with Rorty's intention to develop a model of intellectual practice capable of meeting intellectual challenges to social institutions, for it occurs in a context where Rorty discounts the possibility that social and political institutions can be justified independent of the fact that they exist.25 In short, Rorty's tendency to hypostatize the world independent of language helps to relieve social institutions of any burden of accountability, both theoretical and practical. Social Legi timation Without Truth A central aspect of Rorty's attempt to persuade intellectuals to relieve themselves of metaphysics involves his contention that the embracing of the contingency of community would be a step further in the progressive disenchantment of the world, a step which most liberal intellectuals have been unwilling to take. Rorty's claim is that liberal social institutions would not be endangered by a general appreciation of the fact and its implications that 43 communities are not permanent self—subsisting entities, but, rather, are dependent always on situations and conditions (CIS, 44, 57). Such an appreciation would aid in the development of a world view consistent with the liberal values of individual freedom and tolerance, particularly in the domain of culture (CIS, 52). This is because institutions would not (if they ever did [CIS, 86]) depend on philosophical justifications for their legitimacy. Intellectuals would thus be liberated to pursue the popular forms of literature and political rhetoric (CIS, 53-5). Furthermore, this shift away from epistemology and metaphysics would neutralize long established ideological threats to existing institutions (CIS, 53, 69). Rorty hints at the potential efficacy of his position in his recognition that, if it were widely accepted, it would be necessary to give up the idea that liberalism could be justified, and Nazi and Marxist enemies refuted, by driving the latter up against an argumentative brick wall...[for]...any attempt to drive one's opponent up against a wall in this way fails when the wall against which he is driven comes to be seen as one more vocabulary, one more way of describing things (CIS, 53). This, however, is only a minor problem, for while it does undermine the possibility of meeting social criticism with arguments, it also neutralizes the impact of those criticisms. An intellectual culture that viewed all 44 positions as artifacts, that seeks a multiplicity of vocabularies and perspectives, could tolerate even highly critical perspectives so long as they were considered just examples of many possible perspectives.26 It seems that Rorty's suggestion is that liberal institutions would be strengthened if their justifications were always dependent on the institutions being legitimated. Such circularity, when accepted as valid, would render the intellect an ineffective weapon against social institutions and established powers. This would, in turn, create the conditions for the generalization of intellectual freedom: no longer able to do much damage, intellectuals could also provide a positive legitimating function both in the practice of that freedom and its product. Rorty's claims further that the product of a liberated intellect would not be restricted to negative, de- legitimating practices, but would still prove useful to attempts to generate positive legitimacy. This claim refers to the significance of "stories of social hope" described above. According to Rorty, such stories underwrite the commitment of the general population to liberal social institutions. Providing these stories is a literary project, and therefore, according to Rorty, is not a job for philosophers or even social theorists. Rather, this 45 important task is ceded to novelists, ethnographers, and others who produce thick descriptions of everyday life. As Rorty presents it, the focus of such thick descriptions would be on private, inarticulate suffering, thereby giving this suffering a linguistic, and thus, potentially, public form.27 In this process, writers contribute to creating the conditions for solidarity with the victims.28 Summarizing this position, Rorty writes: Within an ironist culture,...it is the disciplines which specialize in thick descriptions of the private and idiosyncratic which are assigned this job of [of creating human solidarity]. In particular, novels and ethnographies which sensitize one to the pain of those who do not speak our language must do the job which demonstrations of a common human nature were supposed to do. Solidarity has to be created out of little pieces...(CIS, 94). In the above discussion, I have explored some of the implications of Rorty's proposed compromise with intellectuals in which he urges the limitation of philosophy and social theory to the private sphere which, in his rendering, effectively subordinates public discourse to the task of maintaining social institutions. His acknowledged goals are political: he describes his intentions concerning ironist theory in terms of how, through privatization, ironism can be prevented from "becoming a threat to political liberalism" (CIS, 190, see also 197). Assuming a liberal world as the best possible world, Rorty devotes 46 himself to the project of developing an understanding of intellectual practice which would not and could not come into conflict with liberal social institutions. The extremes to which he is willing to go--illustrated in his ban on concrete referentiality, whereby he cuts language, and thus thought, off from the world, transforming it into a self-contained sphere, capable of referring only to the idiosyncratic needs of individuals--is suggestive of the tenacity of his commitment to the status quo.29 Even so, that Rorty is willing to go to such extremes in the disabling of the intellect further implies that an unfettered intellect must be very powerful indeed. Alternatively, but equally to the point, Rorty's restriction of all intellectual practice to a very narrow sphere, indicates, as much as anything else, that the customs and institutions he intends to defend rest on very shaky ground. III. RE-DESCRIBING HIEEIEEB 21931122928 I will now consider Richard Rorty's treatment of George Orwell's Nineteen Eighty;£ont as a concrete model of a post— metaphysical intellectual practice which, in addition to furthering the specific claims made in Qontinoenoyi Ironyi 47 and fioiidatity, exemplifies Rorty's intellectual ideals. In general, Rorty appeals to Orwell's legacy30 in his effort to support his claim that literature and related genres can do the job of developing a normative framework consistent with the liberal goal of preventing cruelty and furthering human solidarity that has been traditionally reserved for foundationalist disciplines such as philosophy (CIS, 95, 185-6, 190). This appeal is combined with an interpretation of Nineteen Eighty;£ont which treats this novel as a concrete alternative to Rorty's own posited utopia. Through the character O'Brien, Nineteen Eighty;£ont provides a model of intellectual activity not informed by liberal hope, and in this way the novelist George Orwell has proved useful to Richard Rorty's liberalism. Indeed, for Rorty, Orwell has provided contemporary intellectuals with a compelling narrative that renders attractive even the most minimalist vision of his liberalism.31 After briefly considering Rorty's reading of Nineteen Eighty;£ont as it relates to the self-understanding of intellectuals, I will argue that Rorty's interpretation obscures Orwell's interrogation of the position of the intellectual relative to the reproduction of institutionalized social power. Specifically, I propose that, in Nineteen Eighty—Four, Orwell articulates through 48 the character Winston Smith one danger facing intellectuals who, by virtue of their profession, contribute to the reproduction of their own domination, which, also by virtue of their profession, they only partially understand. This is significant because an interpretation of Nineteen Eighty; Eon; which adopts this as its organizing theme is not only truer to the text in question, but also suggests an analogy between the resistance of Winston Smith to the Party's power and Rorty's use of the idea of irony as underwriting social legitimation in liberal societies. Just as Rorty claims that irony, as the experienced awareness of contingency, both undermines and re-establishes the primacy of liberal institutions, Winston's half—articulated recognition of the arbitrariness of the Party's power was the foundation for establishing a thorough going identification with that power. More to the point, Rorty's irony and Winston's alienation have the same latent function of establishing the primacy of institutionalized social power. Because of this, I will argue, contra Rorty, that the primary danger presented in Nineteen Eighty;£ont is not cruelty or humiliation, but the failure of intellectuals to place their own selves in their objective context and incorporate into their self-understanding their own powerlessness. I will also draw out the analogy between Winston's alienation and 49 Rorty's ironism, effectively redescribing Winston Smith as an ironic intellectual. Orwell's Contribution to the Self-understanding of Contemporary Liberals Rorty's interpretation of Nineteen Eighty;£ont revolves around Orwell's contribution to the self-understanding of intellectuals in a climate threatened by a loss of liberal hope, where it seems that liberal ideals have little chance of realization. According to Rorty, the character O'Brien is Orwell's answer to the question of how intellectuals "might conceive of themselves, once it had become clear that liberal ideals had no relation to a possible human future" (CIS, 171). The lesson of O'Brien is particularly urgent given that Rorty does "not think that we liberals son now imagine a future of 'human dignity, freedom and peace'" (CIS, 181-2). The current situation is one that is likely to favor the emergence of intellectuals like O'Brien, whose only pleasure in life is the spectacle of other people's pain. In general, then, Rorty interprets Orwell's positive achievement in the writing of Nineteen Eighty-Eonr as a sort of object lesson, invoking it as a thinly veiled threat: in the absence of liberal hope, intellectuals are in danger of 50 becoming sadistic torturers. The plausibility of this interpretation depends on Rorty's decision to treat the last part of Nineteen Eighty;£ont as being about O'Brien and not Winston Smith. Involved in this decision is Rorty's contention that the third part of the novel is fundamentally different from the first two parts implying that Part III can be read as an independent whole, without reference to the entirety of the novel. He writes: ...In the last third of i984 we get something different--something not topical, prospective rather than descriptive. After Winston and Julia go to O'Brien's apartment, 1983 becomes a book about O'Brien...(CIS, 171; see also, 175). Additionally, Rorty's focus on O'Brien, to the neglect of Winston Smith, overlooks Orwell's consistent and uninterrupted employment of the third person singular perspective through which the story of Nineteen Eighty;£ont is limited by Winston's own perceptions.” These interpretive decisions are significant in as much as they result in a reading of Orwell's last novel that is difficult to reconcile with the text.33 Treating Nineteen Eighty;£ont as a unified whole with the character Winston Smith at its center, a reading which is more consistent with the book Orwell presumably wrote, discloses that Winston's resistance related directly to his position as a Party intellectual. Placing Winston's rebellion, arrest, torture, 51 and subsequent love of Big Brother in the context of the material operation and logic of power illuminates the origins of Winston's rebellion in his employment by the Party at the Ministry of Truth. Of equal importance, Winston's failure to understand his experience of alienation in the context of objective social processes was constitutive of the organizing logic of Oceanic society. In other words, both Winston's alienation-~his sense of himself as a self distinct from other selves--and his failure to understand the causes of that alienation were both consistent with the demands of social reproduction within Oceania. On the surface, the interpretation I am proposing would seem irreconcilable with the third part of Nineteen Eighty; F , the part about Winston's imprisonment in the Ministry of Love, at least if that imprisonment is understood as a "reprogramming" or a "brainwashing." If, as I am suggesting, Winston was already a functional member of his society, and an integral part of the reproduction of power, why torture him? Richard Rorty's answer that the Party engaged in torture for its own sake, without regard to purpose or function, is minimally consistent with the reading of Nineteen Eighty;£ont I am proposing. Its consistency lies 52 in the fact that Rorty directs attention away from what Winston does or does not do, thinks or does not think, as the explanation for Winston's torture. Rorty writes: The Inner Party does not torture Winston because it is afraid of a revolution or it is offended that someone might not love Big Brother. It is torturing Winston for the sake of causing Winston pain and thereby increasing the pleasure of its members, particularly O'Brien (CIS, 179). Despite its surface plausibility, this position is out of sync with the text in two important ways. First, there is no textual evidence that O'Brien enjoyed torturing Winston, at least not in the sense alluded to in Rorty's description of a "rich, complicated, delicate absorbing spectacle of mental pain" (CIS, 179). While it is clear that O'Brien was challenged by the problem posed by Winston, there is no indication of sadistic pleasure. Instead, there is in O'Brien an enthusiastic dedication to the task at hand, a tiredness combined with lunatic intensity (NEF, 202, 209, 216, 217). That Orwell's descriptions of O'Brien at work echo his descriptions of Winston at work suggests that the crucial operating emotional dynamic is not a transgressive sadism but the far more mundane dynamic of worker satisfaction.34 Second, Rorty's understanding of torture as a means of increasing the pleasure of Party members, and as "the only art form and the only intellectual discipline available to 53 sensitive intellectuals in a post-totalitarian culture" (CIS, 180), is contrary to the telos of the Party towards an undifferentiated totality. Sensual pleasure, even that produced through torture, would necessitate a differentiation between the Party as a hegemonic collective and the individual Party member. Pleasure, like pain, is an embodied individuating experience. Torturing for the sake of enjoyment would be as foreign to the logic of this power, which is a total power, as making love for the sake of enjoyment. Both pleasure and pain presuppose an existence external to the Party. The.Alienation of'Winston Smith: The Division of Labor For these reasons, Rorty's understanding of the function of torture is simply insufficient to the text of Nineteen Eighty;£ont, failing to attend to Orwell's complex conceptualization of power and the position of Winston Smith, as an intellectual, in the reproduction of that power. The crucial question is whether or not Winston could have avoided imprisonment and Room 101. The first clue to the answering of this question involves various hints in the text that Winston's resistance was not his own; that it was 54 created by O'Brien in his work as a functionary of the Party. For example, O'Brien explained to Winston: This drama I have played out with you during seven years will be played out over and over again, generation after generation, always in subtler forms (NEF, 221, see also, 201). Here, O'Brien claimed agency for himself, if not in actually creating Winston's rebellion, then in shaping it, encouraging it, and cultivating it. Furthermore and significantly, Winston's specifically unorthodox feelings and actions appear always to be initiated by external events and occurrences that were, in principle, outside his control.35 For example, the geography of his room, in conjunction with the young ladies keepsake album he had bought, suggested to him that he start a diary. That a photograph of three former Party elites who had by then become "unpersons" mysteriously appeared among other work-a-day documents suggested to Winston the possibility of truth, and of documenting that the Party histories were lies. A piece of paper, passed to him in full View of the telescreen with the words 'I love you' on it, suggested to Winston that he not only engage in adultery, but that he also fall in love with a woman for whom he had previously felt only hatred and rage. On the basis of these clues it is conceivable that Winston's resistance should be considered an entrapment or the product 55 of a conspiracy and Winston but a hapless puppet on a string.36 Though such a scenario seems consistent with the text and tenor of Nineteen Eighty;£ont, the extent to which Winston's resistance was the product of a conspiracy is never conclusively determined, nor is there any real need for such a settlement. It could have gone either way. All that really mattered was that if Winston's resistance did not exist, it could have been and probably would have been created. Power is as power does, and what power does is overcome opposition. Opposition, real or concocted, is essential to power's movement (NEF, 221).37 Why, then, was Winston arrested? And, could he have done anything to avoid imprisonment? Recall that on the sixth day of Hate Week, when the general delirium inspired by the ceremonies reached its peak, it became known to the citizens of Oceania that the country "...was not, after all, at war with Eurasia. Oceania was at war with Eastasia. Eurasia was an ally" (NEF, 148). Although the Hate Week continued "exactly as before, except that the target had been changed" (NEF, 150), this change meant a great deal of work for Winston and his colleagues at the Ministry of Truth. As a matter of course, and without any external 56 motivation, Winston reported to his post as soon as the demonstrations were over. And for just short of a week, Winston toiled, working eighteen hour days, sleeping in the corridors, and eating sandwiches at his work station (NEF, 150). The history of the previous five years required re-writing and Winston and his colleagues at the Ministry of Truth were responsible for the task. Less than a day after their work was complete, Winston was arrested. This coincidence of events seems hardly accidental, for it is in keeping with the principles of doublethink, as the organizing logic of Oceania, that the process through which reality is continuously remade according to the demands of the moment be relegated to the same oblivion as the inconvenient details as that reality (NEF, 176-7).38 Because of this, Winston was as culpable in his conformity as he was in his deviance. His very existence as a worker in the Ministry of Truth was evidence of the fallibility of the Party, for it suggested that the Party should need, at arbitrarily decided times, to re-write its own political history, and remake its past. Only through a remaking of Winston himself, and, presumably, his colleagues, could the Party remake itself as total. On these grounds, the tension between conformity and deviance, submission and resistance, 57 obedience and rebellion, simply implodes. As an employee of the Ministry of Truth, Winston was doomed, regardless of anything he did or did not do.39 I have placed Winston's arrest in the context of his work for the Party, arguing that this work explains Winston's arrest. In other words, it was his very conformity to Party expectations which made him suspect. Attention to the inherent contradictions of maintaining a class hierarchy in a highly differentiated, complex society helps to clarify this point. A highly differentiated society such as Oceania cannot help but allow to exist a certain degree of individuation, if only that which results from the jagged combination of the division of labor40 necessary to the maintenance of a complex society with the human species' diverse biological inheritance. A form of social organization requiring poets and proletarians, housewives and prostitutes, historians and soldiers, intellectuals and machinists, will inevitably give rise to people who act and feel like poets and proletarians, housewives and prostitutes, historians and soldiers, intellectuals and machinists. In addition to this social division of labor characteristic of Oceanic society was a detailed division of labor organized according to assembly line processes of industrialized production where no single 58 individual makes more than a minute contribution to any given whole. In and through these divisions are those differentiating characteristics which are in some sense related to human biology: the differences between males and females, associated with the necessaries of reproduction; the differences between those newly born into the species and those who have been around for sometime; the differences which result from the fragility of the biological body, creating the potential for illness and disability and leading inevitably towards death. And then there is that irreducible, indivisible fact that each of the species is its own body, enduring its own pain and enjoying its own pleasure. Since no two bodies can occupy the same space, each body lives out its life-span in a unique fashion and from its own perspective. Winston's individuation, his alienation, his sense of his self distinct from the collective, were all functional, a consequence of his social position and the intelligence required of him in his duties to the Party. He could not have rewritten history with sufficient precision had he not developed a sophisticated historical sense, or pondered the metaphysics of history. Moreover, because his task required more than an arbitrary rewriting—-because it required that his creations were consistent with Party aims and doctrines 59 intellectually upholding the Party in its power--his political consciousness also needed to be highly developed. This job requirement called for the expansion and simultaneous contraction of Winston's historical consciousness. Understanding the nature of power and the relation of power to history was essential to his work. Winston Smith was, therefore, a walking talking version of a highly differentiated member of a complex society, ruled by an apparently all powerful elite, fiercely dedicated to the goal of maintaining its position. The individual was both necessary and dangerous to the maintenance of the hierarchical structure of Oceanic society. The Party's intent to put an end to class struggle, to stop history in its tracks, was first and foremost a practical problem, namely, the problem of what to do with surplus individuation (NEF, 170-1).41 Summarizing these considerations, attention to this social level of analysis reveals that Winston's rebellion and alienation were more an occupational hazard and a function of his position in the social structure of Oceania than a autonomous product of Winston's independent consciousness. A complex society like Oceania requires a degree of individuation, if only that it might continue as a going concern. That Winston's alienation can be explained 60 this way does not invalidate his experiences, but it does provide a context for understanding them. That Winston himself did not understand his own self as a product of his place in the social and detailed division of labor, and that he was unaware of the consistency between his own consciousness and the institutionalized power of the Party, is one of the more interesting features of Nineteen Eighty Eon; in so far as it establishes the primacy of the intellectual dynamic Orwell famously named "doublethink" as the organizing logic of both Winston's consciousness and Party power. At this point, it is possible to draw an analogy between Rorty's liberal ironist, characteristic of a post- metaphysical culture, and Winston Smith. Like Rorty's ironist, Winston was an intellectual subject to doubts concerning the nature of his work devoted to the production of propaganda for mass consumption. Just as Rorty's ironist is not troubled by epistemological doubts, Winston understood well the epistemological status of his intellectual activity: he knew knowledge to be a sham, knowing well his own participation in the systematic production of lies within the Ministry of Truth. And, just as Rorty's ironists stoically accept their political commitments as given by existing institutions, privatizing 61 their doubts about the foundations of those institutions, Winston also knew politics to be a sham, even in the face of its penetration into every aspect of existence given the Party's monopoly on power. Of course, Winston knew better than to publically articulate his political doubts. The question that continued to riddle Winston and the question which Rorty dismisses as both inappropriate to a post- metaphysical ironist culture and irrelevant to the understanding of Nineteen Eignty;£ont, referring to it as a "red herring" (CIS, 182), concerned the metaphysical implications of the Party's power to alter history. In other words, it was the systematic dislocation of reality itself--"the power of re-description," to use Rorty's phrase--which Winston felt to be the final and most disturbing consequence of the Party's practice of propaganda in the interests of preserving its hegemonic position. Thus, Winston writes in his diary, "I understand HOW: I do not understand WHY" (NEF, 68). It is this question, both a question of ultimate motive and purpose, and a question of social legitimation which Rorty dismisses as unanswerable in a post—metaphysical culture. Unfortunately, it was also Winston's inability or unwillingness to answer this question which establishes his ultimate complicity with Party power. 62 The.Alienation of'Winston Smith: Doublethink It is truly one of literature's little ironies that Winston Smith's attempt to maintain a tension between his utopian wishes for a life worth living and the dreary futility of his everyday existence required of him a habit of thinking indistinguishable from 'doublethink.‘ All the key features of that habit of thinking were involved in Winston's intellectual consciousness: To know and not know, to be conscious of complete truthfulness while telling carefully constructed lies, to hold consciously two opinions which cancelled out, knowing them to be contradictory and believing in both of them, to use logic against logic, to repudiate morality while laying claim to it (NEF, 32). At the extreme, Winston's faith in the concept of resistance in the name of abstract ideas, to which he never gave concrete determination, led him to assent to the commission of all manner of atrocities in the employ of the "Brotherhood." Winston promised "to do anything which is likely to cause demoralization and weaken the power of the Party" (NEF, 142, emphasis added). This suggests that, for Winston, resistance had become an end in itself, as continuous and all-embracing as the perpetual war engaged in by Nineteen Eighty;£onr's three superpowers. Mirroring the unity of war and peace, freedom 63 and slavery, and ignorance and strength, Winston's resistance, once totalized, became its opposite. It therefore involved a submission indistinguishable from that demanded by the Party. This aspect of Nineteen Eighty-Eon; is consistently overlooked in the commentary on the novel, Rorty's included. For example, in the context of considering whether or not O'Brien was an ironist, Rorty writes, "O'Brien has mastered doublethink, and is not troubled by doubts about himself or the Party" (CIS, 185). Rorty concludes from this that O'Brien was not an ironist. The question which Rorty does not consider, a neglect which is consistent with his general tendency to de-emphasize the character Winston, is whether or not Winston had mastered the practice of doublethink. I propose that Winston had mastered doublethink. More than a literary curiosity, recognizing that Winston Smith was no amateur practitioner of doublethink provides the key to understanding the full complexity of George Orwell's Nineteen Eighty;Eont. Doublethink was the intellectual means through which the Party maintained itself as the ruling elite of Oceania, because it was through this logic that the Party was able to preserve the myth of itself as an omnipotent totality. Doublethink was the governing logic of the Party's power, but doublethink was more than a habit of 64 thinking imposed on a passive literati by an all powerful elite. In Nineteen Eighty;£ont, Orwell portrayed doublethink to be a fully ambiguous, emergent phenomena, rooted in the division of labor and the irrational social structure of Oceania.42 While there are many examples of Winston's daily practice of doublethink, Winston's devotion to his work for the Party in conjunction with his continuing indignation at the Party's systematic distortion of 'truth' and 'history' is particularly useful in illustrating the normal workings of Winston's doublethinkful existence. This is because of the structural role of this value complex in establishing the unity of Winston's subjective consciousness with objective social processes. When it came to his employment at the Ministry of Truth, Winston was no slacker, having internalized a work ethic worthy of any dedicated professional: Winston's greatest pleasure in life was in his work. Most of it was a tedious routine, but included in it were also jobs so difficult and intricate that you could loose yourself in them...delicate pieces of forgery in which you had nothing to guide you except your estimate of what the Party wanted you to say. Winston was good at that kind of thing (NEF, 39). This commitment to his work devoted to the rectification of printed matter in accordance with the ever-changing needs of the Party coexisted with Winston's outrage and fright 65 concerning the metaphysical significance of the Party's practice of propaganda. Importantly, this commitment to his job-—a job wholly devoted to the re-writing of history--did not waiver even after he pledged himself, in the name of history (NEF, 146), to the resistance. Thus, shortly after his meeting with O'Brien concerning his entry into the Brotherhood, Winston and his colleagues at the Ministry of Truth were charged with the task of rectifying most of the political literature of five years past, which, due to a change in Oceania's wartime alliance, had become obsolete. While the work was demanding and necessitated the utmost exertion and dedication, Winston was not philosophically or morally bothered by it: It was like struggling with some crushing physical task which one had the right to refuse and which one was never the less neurotically anxious to accomplish. In so far as he had time to remember it, he was not troubled by the fact that every word he murmured into the speakwrite, every stroke of his inkpencil was a deliberate lie. He was as anxious as anyone else in the department that the forgery be perfect (NEF, 151). In the heat of the moment, then, Winston was not concerned with the rectification's metaphysical implications. Rather, Winston attended dutifully to the job at hand. Clearly, this ability to forget his internal rebellion against the Party as he dedicated his entire being to its arbitrary 66 purposes illuminates both the degree and nature of Winston's submission to that habit of mind called doublethink. Winston's resistance is illustrative of the contradictory nature of Winston's thought process at the extremes. His attitude toward his work illustrates the extent to which Winston lived up to the demands of Party conformity in his everyday activity. His relations with other humans were no less affected. For example, Winston took minor comfort in his conviction that, ”If there was hope, it must lie in the Proles;" a conviction which haunted him like "a mystical truth and a palatable absurdity" (CIS, 60). The great expectations he placed on the proles were inversely related to the low esteem with which he regarded them. Thus Winston's estimation that the proles were without intelligence or general ideas did not deter him from imposing on them the burden of utopia or the responsibility of realizing his revolution (NEF, 60—61). This contradiction is captured in Winston's thought that "...the proles, if only they could somehow become conscious of their own strength, would have no need to conspire. They need only rise up and shake themselves like a horse shaking off flies" (NEF, 60). Winston's view here is that if the proles had insight into their own strategic position within Oceanic society, they would comprehend their 67 own raw power and could generate the force necessary to the revolution. The analogy with the horse suggests that such an event would require nothing more than a reflexive aversion response; thus, even in their triumph, the proles would remain mindless. Winston's willingness to entertain the possibility that the proles might attain consciousness was limited by his unwillingness to think beyond his own immediate interest in the proles as revolutionary fodder. His insight boiled down to the dubious conclusion that 'if the proles could become conscious, they would have no need for consciousness'. As Winston saw it, then, the proles would provide the raw power necessary to the overthrow of the Party while intellectuals such as himself would provide the ideas. In addition to merely replicating a value system rooted in Party doctrine and the exploitative social structure of Oceania, Winston's evaluation of the relation between intellectuals and the masses is exaggerated to the point where its core lunacy emerges. Thus, just before his and Julia's arrest, Winston contemplates a prole woman while she hangs the laundry, pondering the world historical significance of her female form. He thinks, ...everywhere stood the same solid unconquerable figure, made monstrous by work and childbearing, toiling from birth to death and still singing. Out of those mighty loins a race of conscious 68 beings must one day come. You were the dead, theirs was the future. But you could share in that future if you kept alive the mind as they kept alive the body, and passed on the secret doctrine that two plus two make four (CIS, 182). This scenario imagined by Winston is as preposterous as any provided by the Party: A child's arithmetic problem is transformed into "a secret doctrine" containing an insight of utmost importance destined to save the great masses of humankind. A woman tending to her household chores is exaggerated in the same way, first reduced to her physical body, the strength of her arms, and the productivity of her womb, that body then grows enormous, a monster enveloping all of history. These examples are intended to illustrate Winston's adoption of a ludicrous doctrine vis—a-vis the proles. His attitudes towards his colleagues at the records department, his obsessive categorizing of individuals according to his conclusions about their Party loyalty and intelligence, suggests further that Winston had internalized the demands of the thought police vis-a-vis his peers. His every interaction was colored by his speculations about any given persons's chance of disappearing or turning him in as a thought criminal. Winston assumed that, in principle, there is always external evidence of one's inner life. This, despite the fact that he took great pains to conceal his own 69 feelings from casual observation, arranging his face into an appropriate expression, managing his presentation of self so as not to disclose his heretical leanings.43 Of course, Winston's powers of perception were consistently undermined by events, in the end with disastrous consequences. Julia was not a member of the thought police, nor was she saddled with any thorough going orthodoxy. Parsons was as vulnerable to thought crime as anybody else. Charrington, the shopkeeper in the prole quarter, was in the employ of the thought police, and, of course, O'Brien was not a revolutionary. Still, Winston never questioned the principle that you could tell, or even that it mattered. The above discussion is intended to show the skill with which Winston practiced doublethink. There was no necessary connection between his thoughts and his actions nor was there even a basic consistency within his internal, reflexive thought process. Obsessed with visions of resistance, Winston was ignorant of his own complicity. Convinced of the profundity of trivia, insight slipped through Winston's fingers. Unable to implicate himself in his own thought process, Winston's essential identity with the Party remained in tact, as obvious as the blue overalls of his Party uniform were to the proles (NEF, 71). 7O Moreover, it becomes clear that, for Orwell, doublethink is more than just a form of consciousness, abstracted from social processes. Doublethink refers directly to the concrete means through which the ruling elite maintained the myth of its absolute power. That the Party was required to actively maintain this myth through material practice necessitated a performative concession that its power was, in fact, limited. This relates directly to the problem of social legitimation which I defined in terms of the requirement that the institutions being legitimated can maintain their giveness in the face of the recognition that they are humanly constructed. Both the challenge to giveness and the mobilization of resources necessary to the resolution of the challenge point to the contradiction inherent in the requirement that the 'giveness' of institutions must be justified at all. Applying this to the situation of Oceania, it can be said that the Party's desire to constitute its own past required a tremendous expenditure of resources, as did the Party's insistence on controlling its own members. The Party's ‘willingness to thus exert itself involved entangling itself in a core contradiction, namely, the recognition of its own limited power. The Party insisted on the myth of its