’ g1 .‘.__.‘“‘-. _ q“‘_-u‘——-.—.u. _. . .~-.—-—~v.. . .. . . w l I \ . . u A ' .y . r' . l . . , V ‘ , ' ,. . I, . ‘ - . . ‘ l 4 , . . ~ . . ,. » . . ., t ‘ o v A. . . . . . . ,‘ . . ~. n' , ' -> ‘ ' ' 4‘ 'A 2 Hr!“ - “u u:- uw-u. H ‘ .v. 4 4.. .. .., , . “”4”... . lllllllllllllllllllllllllllllillllllill‘lllllllllllllllllll 3 1293 00877 0228 This is to certify that the dissertation entitled Necessary A Posteriori Truth presented by Cynthia Jayne Bolton has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for W degree in —Ph~i—}esephy é?z/aw/&Oflé€\ Jor professor Date 4404’ all /7y.2‘ (7 6/ MS U is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution l LIBRARY 4 Michigan State 1, Untverstty PLACE IN RETURN BOX to remove this checkout from your record. TO AVOID FINES return on or before due due. DATE DUE DATE DUE DATE DUE W ll JV—l MSU lo An Afflrmetlve ActIoNEquel Opportunlty Institution cmmut ——— NECESSARY A POSTERIORI TRUTH BY Cynthia Jayne Bolton A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Philosophy ABSTRACT NECESSARY A POSTERIORI TRUTH by Cynthia Jayne Bolton Traditionally, philosophers have used the analytic/ synthetic, a priori/a posteriori, and necessary/contingent distinctions to categorize statements. And traditionally, philosophers have used these distinctions to categorize necessary statements as a priori statements. Yet certain statements seem better categorized as necessary and a pos- teriori. Examples of such statements include: (1) Heat is the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules in solids; (2) Gold is the element with atomic number 79; and (3) Water is H20. For while we believe that these statements express empirical discoveries, we also believe that they express the essence of their subjects. I wish to justify the claim that these statements are both necessary and a posteriori. My justification includes a synthesis of the causal theory of reference with the net— work theory of meaning. But once this synthesis is carried out, we have a rather complicated notion of necessity. We no longer have one notion of necessity, but four notions. One notion is the logical positivist's. A statement is necessary if it expresses a linguistic convention. The second notion is the network theorist's. A statement is necessary if it is central to our theoretical network. The third notion is the causal theorist's. A statement is nec- essary if it is a singular statement of identity between two rigid designators. And the fourth notion is the essen- tialist's. A statement is necessary if the predicate ex- presses the essence of the subject. But this essence must be a structural property that plays an explanatory role within our theoretical network. Of these four notions of necessity, only the first must be a priori. The other three are ultimately a posteriori. Statements (1)—(3) fall under the fourth notion. And thus, they are necessary and a posteriori. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to particularly thank my dissertation director, Professor Richard Hall, for his helpful comments and criticisms. Special thanks are also due to Betina Henig, Melanie McLeod, Donna Baker, and Frank Curtis, all of whom have heard much more about this dissertation than they ever wished. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Li st Of Figures 0 O O C O O O C O O O O O O O O O O O . mapter one C C O O O O O O O O C O O O O C O C O O O 0 Setting the Stage: Leibniz and Hume . . . . . . . . . Setting the Stage: Kant . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The Stage is Set: The Logical Positivists . . . . . . Problems: . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Cllapter W0 0 O O O O I O O O O I . O O O O C O O C I O Modifying the Traditional Distinctions . . . . . . . . Proper Names and Necessary A Posteriori Statements . . Underlying Assumptions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . De Re or De Dicto . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Chapter Three . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The Network Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . What Happens to the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction? . . What Happens to the A Priori/A Posteriori Distinction? What Happens to the Necessary/Contingent Distinction? . mapter Four . O O C O O O O O O O O O I O O C O O O O Follesdal: How to Synthesize the Causal Theory and the Network Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Referential Terms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . What Does This Do To The Traditional Distinctions? Types of Necessity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Chapter Five . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Why We Need An Additional Analysis of Necessity . . . . What Is An Essence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Essence and Explanation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . What is an Aristotelian Essence? . . . . . . . . . . . NOtes I O O O O O O I O O O O O O O O O O O I O O O O 0 Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . vi 17 24 30 31 33 42 54 61 61 67 76 84 89 91 95 107 108 123 124 127 135 139 146 153 figure figure figure figure LIST OF vi FIGURES 43 110 120 Chapter One The topic of necessary truth centers about two ques- tions. There is the metaphysical question: Are there such things as necessary truths? And there is the epistemologi— cal question: How do we distinguish those truths that are necessary from those that are not? These two questions are interrelated since much of our interest in the metaphysical question would be lost without an answer to the epistemolo- gical question. Postulating necessary truth would be an idle exercise if we could not determine which truths are necessary. For most of this century, the notion of necessity has been intertwined with the notion of meaning. According to this notion, a statement is necessary if and only if its truth stems solely from the meaning of the words used to express that statement--if its truth depends upon anything else, then it is not necessary. This analysis, at the very least, has the virtue of answering both the metaphysical and epistemological questions. It tells us that there are necessary truths--they are just those statements that are true in virtue of meaning. And it tells us how to distin- guish necessary truths from other truths--we examine the role that meaning plays in determining the truth value of a statement. This examination alone will enable us to separate those statements that are necessary from those that are not. This analysis proved quite popular. While 2 it was originally formulated by the logical positivists, it was soon adopted and advocated by philOSOphers of other per-suasions as well. And only recently have philosophers come to admit that this analysis is possibly wrong. In this chapter, I would like to focus on the logical positivists' notion of necessary truth. We shall examine why the logical positivists tied necessity to meaning; and we shall examine a problem with this analysis. To do this, we must focus on three distinctions: the analytic/synthe- tic distinction, the a priori/a posteriori distinction, and the necessary/contingent distinction. But since the logi— cal positivists' account of these distinctions owes much to Leibniz, Hume, and Kant, we should situate their analysis within some sort of historical perspective because only then can we understand why the logical positivists tied necessity to meaning. Setting the State: Leibniz and Hume Leibniz and Hume are principally concerned with just one distinction-~the distinction between knowledge that is demonstrative and knowledge that is empirical. To make this distinction, Leibniz contrasts truths of reason with truths of fact while Hume contrasts relations of ideas with matters of fact where both truths of reason and relations of ideas refer to demonstrative knowledge while truths of fact and matters of fact refer to empirical knowledge.1 3 Since they are concerned with just one distinction, it may seem rather odd to begin our discussion with Leibniz and Hume. But the distinctions that concern us-—the analytic/ synthetic, the a priori/a posteriori, and the necessary/ contingent distinctions--originate to a great extent with Leibniz's and Hume's distinction between knowledge that is demonstrative and knowledge that is empirical. While Leibniz and Hume disagree on the origin2 and the extent3 of demonstrative knowledge, they agree on its foun- dation. Both believe that demonstrative knowledge is based upon the principle of contradiction. Leibniz, for example, argues that (LD) x is a truth of reason if and only if its truth is established by the prin— ciple of contradiction.[4] while Hume argues that (HD) x is a relation of ideas if and only if its truth is established by the principle of contradiction.[5] According to Leibniz and Hume, demonstrative knowledge, by whatever name we choose to call it, owes its truth to the principle that it is impossible for something to be and not to be at the same time. Since demonstrative knowledge is based upon the prin- ciple of contradiction, it is necessary. By claiming that demonstrative knowledge is necessary, Leibniz and Hume are claiming that such knowledge must be true. It is impossi- ble for such knowledge to be false. To understand the role that the principle of contradiction plays in guaranteeing the truth of demonstrative knowledge, consider the follow- ing statement: 'An equilateral triangle is a triangle'. Although Leibniz would describe this statement as a truth of reason while Hume would describe it as a relation of ideas, they would agree that the statement is necessary. They would argue that it is impossible for it to be false since the statement can only be false if there is an equi- lateral triangle that is not a triangle. Or simply put, the statement is false only when we have something that is both a triangle and not a triangle at the same time. But this would most definitely violate the principle of contra- diction. Since demonstrative knowledge is based upon the prin- ciple of contradiction, it must also be a priori. Accord- ing to Hume, we discover demonstrative knowledge by means of reason. He writes Propositions of this kind [relations of ideas] are discoverable by the mere op- eration of thought, without dependence on what is anywhere existent in the uni- verse. Though there were never a circle or a triangle in nature, the truths dem- onstrated by Euclid would forever re- tain their certainty and truth. [6] As this passage shows, demonstrative knowledge is a priori not only because experience is not needed to determine its truth but also because its truth does not even depend upon what exists empirically. But why would the principle of contradiction lead to 5 a priori knowledge? Traditionally, this principle has been used to separate the possible from the impossible. What- ever is in accordance with this principle is possible while whatever is in violation of this principle is impossible. Think about a triangle. While it is possible for a tri- angle to be a triangle, it is impossible for a triangle not to be a triangle. The former accords with the prin- ciple of contradiction while the latter violates it. Now if something is possible, it is thinkable. Similarly, if something is impossible, it is unthinkable. Whether tri- angles exist or not, we can certainly think of a triangle (although we cannot think of a triangle that is not a triangle). Demonstrative knowledge, which is founded upon the principle of contradiction, is tied to the notion of possibility. As such, it is thus tied to the thinkable. And since it is tied to whatever can be thought, demonstra- tive knowledge can be discovered by thought alone. In this explanation, the principle of contradiction acts as a psychological principle. But simply because something is possible, this does not mean that it is actual. While it is entirely possible for something to be a triangle, this does not mean that triangles actually exist. Possibility and actuality are two different things. While demonstrative knowledge con- cerns the possible, empirical knowledge concerns the ac- tual. Since the principle of contradiction deals with the possible and not the actual, empirical knowledge must be founded on some principle other than that of contradic- tion. Although empirical knowledge cannot violate the the principle of contradiction, it cannot be based solely on it. When it comes to empirical knowledge, Leibniz and Hume break company. While they agree that we gain our knowledge of truths of fact or matters of fact from experience, they disagree on the basis of this knowledge. Leibniz, on one hand, argues that (LE) x is a truth of fact if and only if it is based upon the principle of sufficient reason. [7] Hume, on the other hand, argues that (HE) x is a matter of fact if and only if it based on the relation of cause and effect. [8] It is at this point that the difference between Leibniz, the rationalist, and Hume, the empiricist, becomes most obvious. Although Hume explicitly states that matters of fact are based upon the relation of cause and effect, in real- ity, this comes down to the claim that matters of fact are based upon experience. Consider the following matter of fact: 'Caesar is the person who crossed the Rubicon in the year 49 B.C.'. What is our justification for believing this? Hume argues that our justification for any matter of fact always comes back to another fact; and the relation 7 that allows us to connect these facts is that of cause and effect. But this relation, says Hume, is itself empirical. He writes that the knowledge of this relation is not, in any instance, attained by reason- ings a priori; but arises entirely from experience... [14] Our justification for our belief in the relation of cause and effect ultimately comes back to experience; in particu- lar, our experience that one event regularly follows an- other. Leibniz concedes to the empiricists that when it comes to empirical facts, we, as human beings, need experience to learn these facts. But as a rationalist, he wants to claim that every truth, truths of fact as well as truths of reason, can be deduced by means of reason alone. He just- ifies this claim by arguing that every statement expresses a relationship between two concepts-—the concept expressed by the predicate term and the concept expressed by the sub- ject term. If the statement is true, the concept of the predicate is contained in the concept of the subject. If the statement is false, then the concept of the predicate 10 Since is not contained in the concept of the subject. the concept of the predicate is contained in the concept of the subject, we can, in principle, supply an a priori proof for any true statement, not withstanding its status as a truth of reason or as a truth of fact. When it comes to truths of reason, it is fairly easy 8 to see that one concept is contained in the other. Consid- er the statement 'An equilateral triangle is a triangle'. It is easy to see that the concept of the predicate term 'triangle' is contained in the concept 'equilateral tri— angle'. But when it comes to truths of fact, it is not so easy to see that one concept is contained in the other. Consider the truth of fact 'Caesar is the person who crossed the Rubicon in the year 49 B.C.'. The concept 'the person who crossed the Rubicon in the year 49 B.C.' is not obviously contained in the concept 'Caesar'. But Leibniz believes that this concept is nonetheless contained in the concept 'Caesar'. According to Leibniz, "the indi- vidual notion [concept] of each person includes once for all everything which will ever happen to him."11 And just as we can deduce 'triangle' from the concept 'equilateral triangle' so can we deduce 'the person who crossed the Rubicon in the year 49 B.C.' from the concept 'Caesar'. The difference between truths of reason and truths of fact, according to Leibniz, is not that the former are a priori while the latter are a posteriori. Rather, the difference is that truths of reason depend solely upon the principle of contradiction while truths of fact depend also upon the principle of sufficient reason. It is this prin- ciple that enables us to determine what is actual as op- posed to what is merely possible. Leibniz writes ...we consider that no fact can be real or existing and no proposition can be true unless there is a suf- ficient reason, why it should be thus and not otherwise... [12] For anything and everything that is actual, there must be a reason to explain why this particular possibility, out of all the various possibilities, became actual. For anything and everything that has happened to Caesar, for example, there must be a sufficient reason to explain why these things happened. If we knew these reasons, we could deduce everything that happened to Caesar from the mere concept of 'Caesar'. We could not only deduce that Caesar crossed the Rubicon in the year 49 B.C., but we could also deduce the precise point where he crossed the Rubicon and why he crossed the Rubicon. Since we lack knowledge of these sufficient reasons, we cannot make these deductions. We need to rely on experience to learn the truth of 'Cae- sar is the person who crossed the Rubicon in the year 49 B.C.'. But in principle, we could rely on reason alone. Setting the Stage: Rant The logical positivist's primary debt to Kant is that he is perhaps the first philosopher to recognize that the analytic/synthetic, a priori/a posteriori, and necessary/ contingent distinctions were distinctions worthy of analy- sis in their own right. While Leibniz and Hume made use of the a priori/a posteriori and necessary/contingent distinc- tions and while Leibniz did everything but identify the 10 analytic/synthetic distinction, their interest in these distinctions stemmed solely from the standpoint of their interest in the distinction between demonstrative and empirical knowledge. It was Kant who gave up one all en— compassing distinction in favor of three independent dis- tinctions. Kant's version of the analytic/synthetic distinction owes its genesis to Leibniz. With Leibniz, Kant believes that every statement expresses a relationship between the concept of its predicate term and that of its subject. Furthermore, Kant agrees with Leibniz that this relation— ship takes one of two forms. Either the concept of the predicate belongs to the concept of the subject or it does not. But while Leibniz believes that in the case of true statements, the concept of the predicate always belongs to the concept of the subject, Kant does not. Even in the case of true statements, the relationship between subject and predicate can take one of these two forms. And depend- ing upon which form it takes, the statement is either analytic or synthetic. Kant suggests that (KA) A statement is analytic if and only if the concept of the predicate is is contained in the concept of the subject. (KS) A statement is synthetic if and only if the concept of the predicate is not contained in the concept of the subject. [12] Analytic statements, according to Kant, depend solely upon 11 the principle of contradiction. Since the concept of the predicate is contained in the subject, we cannot deny the truth of an analytic statements without violating this principle. Synthetic statements, in contrast, do not depend solely upon the principle of contradiction. Al- though synthetic statements may not violate this principle, they cannot be founded upon it, for as Kant says ...it is evident... that in synthetic judgments I must have besides the con- cept of the subject something else (X), upon which the understanding may rely, if it is to know that a predicate, not contained in this concept, nevertheless, belongs to it. [14] Up to this point, the discussion may seem vaguely remini- scent of the discussion in the preceding section. Analytic statements, like demonstrative knowledge, depend upon the principle of contradiction while synthetic statements, like empirical knowledge, depend upon something else. The difference is that Kant does not stick with just one distinction but goes on to present two additional distinctions. Although Leibniz and Hume certainly presup- pose the existence of the a priori/a posteriori distinc- tion, Kant is careful to define it. He argues that (KP) x is a priori if and only if it meets one of the following con— ditions: (a) x can be known independently of all experience; or (b) x can be known prior to ex— perience. (KT) x is a posteriori if and only if knowledge of x is dependent 12 on experience. [15] Kant's notion of the a posteriori should sound familiar since it is the same notion that we found with Leibniz and Hume; and since it will be the same notion that we will find with the logical positivists. His notion of the a priori, on the other hand, is not so familiar. Kant's provides us with two conditions for (KP). These conditions correspond to two different senses for the phrase 'a priori'. The first condition corresponds to the epistemological sense. When we use 'a priori' in this sense, we are asserting that experience is irrelevant. All that is needed is reason. The second condition corresponds to the "psychological" sense; where by the term 'psycholo— gical', we mean to refer to certain sorts of mental pro- cesses. Experience is not irrelevant to these processes. But we say that these processes are prior to experience in that our experience, from the very beginning, is structured according to these processes. This "psychological" element becomes even more pro- nounced when we examine Kant's version of the necessary/ contingent distinction. Early in The Critique of Pure Reason, he presents this distinction as thus: (KN) x is necessary if and only if x meets both the following condi- tions: (a) x holds with strict univer- sality; and (b) x must be the case. (KC) x is contingent if and only if 13 x meets the following condi— tions: (a) x does not hold with strict universality; or (b) x may not be the case. [16] By framing the necessary/contingent distinction in terms of strict necessity, Kant contrasts universal statements that must be true with universal statements that merely happen to be true. Consider the following two statements: (1) 5+7=12. (ii) Every president of the United States during the 19th century was a white male. Both (i) and (ii) are universally true; but only (1) holds with strict universality. While we believe that (i) is necessary, we believe that (ii) is contingent; and while we believe that (i) must be true, we believe that (ii) merely happens to be true. If we examine the class of presidents of the United States during the 19th century, we will discover that it is made up entirely of white males; but even so, we do not think that it had to consist solely of white males. But how can we distinguish between those statements that hold with strict universality from those that simply hold universally? We can answer this question by examining the relationship between the necessary/contingent distinc- tion with the a priori/a posteriori distinction. Kant argues that (K1) A statement is necessary if and only if it is a priori. 14 (K2) A statement is contingent if and only if it is a posteriori. Kant equates necessity with the a priori because he agrees with Hume that "experience can teach us that a thing is so and so, but not that it cannot be otherwise."17 Experience may be sufficient to prove that a statement is universally true; but it is not sufficient to show us that that state— ment is strictly universal. If we believe that a statement is strictly universal, we must do so on a priori grounds.18 Reconsider statements (1) and (ii). We accept the truth of (ii) on a posteriori grounds. Thus, it is contingent. But in the case of (i), we argue for its truth on a priori grounds; and that, according to Kant, is the reason why (i) is necessary. Kant also argues for the following: (K3) If a statement is analytic, then it is a priori. Since the concept of the predicate term is included within the concept of the subject term, we need not consider anything beyond the concepts used within that statement. In particular, we need not rely on experience.19 From (K1) and (K3), we can infer (K4) If a statement is analytic, then it is necessary. Given that analytic statements depend upon the principle of contradiction, and given what we learned about this princi- ple in the preceding section, (K4) is exactly what we would expect. 15 Not too surprisingly, Kant also argues for the follow- ing: (K5) If a statement is a posteriori, then it is synthetic. We have already noted that Kant argues that we need some— thing, some (X), to unite the concepts of the predicate and the subject for a synthetic statement. In the case of a posteriori statements, this (X) is experience. Although Kant argues that every analytic statement is both a priori and necessary, he does not argue that every synthetic statement is both a posteriori and contingent. In fact, Kant refuses to equate synthetic statements with a posteriori statement. He argues instead that (K6) If a statement is synthetic, then it it is either a priori or a posteriori. (K7) If a statement is a priori, then it is either analytic or synthetic. Kant believes that certain statements are both synthetic and a priori. And among such statements are the state- ments of mathematics and various metaphysical principles. Let us once more consider statement (1). Since this statement depends upon the principle of contradiction, we may be inclined to argue that it is a priori and analytic. But Kant argues that it is synthetic. While the statement '5+7=12' does not violate the principle of contradiction; nevertheless, the concept of '12' is not contained in the concept of the sum '5+7'; and thus, the statement is syn- thetic. Reasoning in this manner, Kant writes that 16 Arithmetical propositions are therefore always synthetic. This is still more evident if we take larger numbers. For it is then obvious that, however we might turn and twist our concepts, we could never, by the mere analysis of them, and without the aid of intuition, discover what is the sum. [20] Kant also believes that certain "metaphysical" prin— ciples are also synthetic and a priori. For example, the principle 'Every effect has a cause', according to Kant, belongs in this category. (This conclusion has not been widely adopted. Those philosophers who agree with Kant that the principle is a priori argue, however, that it is a priori because it is analytic--the concept of 'cause' is contained in the concept of 'effect'-—while those philoso- phers who agree with Kant that the principle is synthetic argue that it is synthetic because it is a posteriori--it is a principle that is justified by experience.) Kant concedes that statements that are both synthetic and a priori are somewhat problematic. Since they are synthetic, we need something to unite the concepts of the predicate and subject. But since they are a priori, this something cannot be experience. But if it is not experience, what can it be? It is at this point where Kant begins to rely upon his second sense of 'a priori'--the psychological sense. Kant argues that we bring certain a priori intuitions and concepts to particular statements. In the case of mathema- tical statements, we bring our a priori intuitions of space 17 and time. In the case of metaphysical principles, we bring certain a priori concepts--the categories. It is these a priori intuitions and concepts that enable us to unite the subject and predicate within mathematical and metaphysical statements. But Kant does not believe that these intui— tions and concepts are irrelevant to experience. Rather, it is these intuitions and concepts that structure our experience. The Stage is Set: The Logical Positivists The logical positivists owe a great deal to the work of Kant and to the work of Leibniz and Hume. Like Leibniz and Hume, the logical positivists essentially have one overall distinction-—the distinction between knowledge that is demonstrative and knowledge that is empirical. But they analyze this distinction in terms of Kant's three distinc- tions. To distinguish demonstrative knowledge from empiri- cal knowledge, they rely upon the analytic/synthetic dis- tinction, the a priori/a posteriori distinction, and the necessary/contingent distinction. While the logical positivists credit Kant for recog- nizing the importance of the analytic/synthetic distinc- tion, they do not adopt his version of the distinction. Instead, they claim that: (LA) A statement is analytic if and only if its truth value is determined com- pletely by linguistic conventions. 18 (LS) A statement is synthetic if and only if its truth value is not determined completely by linguistic conventions. These linguistic conventions, in turn, are governed by the principle of contradiction. Hence, analytic statements are governed entirely by the principle of contradiction while synthetic statements are not. Examples of analytic statements include the following: (a) A bachelor is an unmarried man. (b) P v -P. (c) 5+7=12. According to the logical positivists, the truth value of each statement is determined by various linguistic conven- tions. The truth of (a) is determined by the conventions that govern the use of English. The truth of (b) is deter- mined by the conventions that govern the use of logical connectives in an appropriate propositional calculus. The truth of (c) is governed by the conventions that govern arithmetic. In each case, we cannot deny the truth of these statements without also violating the principle of contradiction. As we can see, the logical positivists waste little time breaking with Kant. While Kant believed that the mathematical statements were synthetic, the logical posi— tivists believe that they are analytic. Ayer argues that Kant relied on two different criteria when he formulated his analytic/synthetic distinction. One criterion was logical--the principle of contradiction--and it is this 19 criterion that the logical positivists continue to accept. The other criterion was psychological--whether the concept of the predicate was thought in the concept of the subject or not--and it is this criterion that the logical positi- vists reject. We can contrast statements (a)-(c) with the following synthetic statements: (d) Bachelors are neurotic. (e) Jones knows that 'P v —P' is true. (f) This board is seven feet long. To determine the truth value of these statements, we must go beyond linguistic conventions. Bachelors may very well be neurotic; but we cannot discover this fact simply by examining the conventions that govern the use of the term 'bachelor'. And while 'P v -P' is true, we cannot deter- mine whether Jones knows that it is true by linguistic analysis. And the only way we can know that a particular board is seven feet long is by measuring it. Since lin- guistic conventions are not sufficient to tell us the truth values of statements (d)-(f), these statements are synthetic. The logical postivists' version of the a priori/a posteriori distinction also differs from Kant's version. They claim that: (LP) A statement is a priori if and only it can be known independently of ex- perience. (LT) A statement is a posteriori if and only if knowledge of it is dependent 20 on experience. [15] The logical positivists only worry about Kant's epistemolo- gical sense of the phrase 'a priori'. Since they reject Kant's critical project, they have no interest in the psychological sense. They have no interest in the a pri- ori conditions that structure experience. Or to be more accurate, they believe that the conditions that structure experience are empirical and can be studied in psychology. When it comes to the necessary/contingent distinction, the logical positivists again present us with the familiar version. They argue that (LN) A statement is necessary if and only if it must be true--it is impossible for it to be false. (LC) A statement is contingent if and only if it may be false--it is possible for it to be false. This is, of course, the same version of necessity that we first encountered with Leibniz and Hume. Like Kant, the logical positivists equate necessity with the a priori. They argue that: (L1) A statement is necessary if and only if it is a priori. (L2) A statement is contingent if and on- ly if it is a posteriori. The logical positivists, like Kant before them, are re- sponding to Hume's scepticism. Ayer, for example, admits that ...it is impossible on empirical prin- ciples to account for our knowledge of 21 necessary truths. For, as Hume conclu- sively showed, no general proposition whose validity is subject to the test of actual experience can ever be logi- cally certain. No matter how often it is verified in practice, there still re— mains the possibility that it will be confuted on some future occasion. [21] But the logical positivists also believe that necessary knowledge is a priori because we never allow experience to falsify such knowledge. Ayer writes that Whatever instance we care to take, we shall always find that the situations in which a logical or mathematical prin- ciple might appear to be confuted are accounted for in such a way as to leave the principle unassailed. ...The prin- ciples of logic and mathematics are true universally simply because we never al- low them to be anything else. [22] Consider the statement '5+7=12'. Suppose we pushed a pile of 5 pebbles into a pile of 7 pebbles and discovered that the resulting pile was something other than 12 pebbles? Would we then conclude that the principle '5+7=12' has been falsified. Of course not. We would conclude that we had miscounted the number of pebbles in one of our original piles. We do not allow '5+7=12' to be falsified by any sort of experience. But if we do not allow this principle to be falsified by experience, then we must not verify it by experience. So, how do we verify the truth of a statement such as '5+7=12‘? The logical positivists argue that: (L3) A statement is a priori if and only if it is analytic. 22 To justify this claim, the logical positivists point out that apart from what they tell us about linguistic conven- tions, analytic statements have no empirical content what- soever. And since they lack empirical content, we do not use experience to determine their truth or falsify. The statement '5+7=12' owes its truth to the conventions that govern our use of arithmetic. And this explains why ex- perience cannot falsify '5+7=12'. From (L1) and (L3), we can infer that (L4) A statement is necessary if and only if it is analytic. The fact that we can determine the truth or falsity of analytic statements merely by examining linguistic conven— tions also explains why these statements are necessary. Ayer writes They [analytic statements] simply record our determination to use words in a cer- tain fashion. We cannot deny them with- out infringing the conventions which are presupposed by our very denial, and so falling into self-contradiction, and that is the sole ground of their necessity. [23] By tying necessity to analyticity, the logical positivists tie necessity to the principle of contradiction. We vio- late this principle whenever we violate the conventions that we have chosen to adopt. And this explains why analy— tic statements are necessarily true. Running parallel to these claims are the following: (L5) A statement is a posteriori if and only if it is synthetic. 23 (L6) A statement is contingent if and only if it is synthetic. Since we cannot determine the truth value of synthetic statements by linguistic analysis, how can we determine their truth value? The logical positivists argue that the truth value of synthetic statements is determined by experience. Synthetic statements, according to the logical positivists, make claims about the empirical world; and thus, it is only fitting that experience verifies or fal— sifies these statements. But as we have already noted, experience cannot guarantee necessity. Thus, these state- ments will all be contingent. This applies even to "meta- physical" statements, such as 'Every effect has a cause'. We accept this statement only in so far as it continues to be corroborated by experience. Thus, we can see that the logical positivists only permit two classes of statements: we have those statements that are analytic, a priori, and necessary and we have those statements that are synthetic, a posteriori, and contingent. Demonstrative knowledge consists of those statements that belong to the former class while empirical knowledge consists of statements that belong to the latter. Moreover, we can now understand precisely how necessity has been tied to meaning. Necessity is equivalent to analyti- city. 24 Problems An assumption that underlies the distinctions that we have examined is that these distinctions are exclusive and exhaustive. Every statement is either analytic or synthe— tic, a priori or a posteriori, necessary or contingent. The purpose that underlies Kant's and the logical positi- vists' analyses is to explain why a particular statement falls into one category as opposed to another. But consi- der the following three statements: (1) Heat is the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules. (2) Gold is the element with atomic number 79. (3) Water is H O. 2 How should we categorize these statements? Are they analy- tic or synthetic? A priori or a posteriori? Necessary or contingent? As we shall soon see, the analyses provided by Kant and the logical positivists give us great leeway in categorizing these statements. By using the analysis provided by the logical positiv- ists, we can argue that these statements are analytic, a priori, and necessary. If we look in any reasonably decent dictionary, we will discover that these statements are the definitions for 'heat', 'gold', and 'water'. Thus, we could say that statements (1)-(3) are true by definition. But if they are true by definition, then they express the linguistic conventions that govern the way we choose to talk about heat, gold, and water. But this means that 25 statements (1)-(3) are analytic. But if they are analytic, then they are also a priori and necessary. But we can also use the logical positivists' analysis to argue that statements (1)-(3) are synthetic, a poster- iori, and contingent. We did not originally accept the truth of statements (1)-(3) by means of linguistic analy— sis. The fact of the matter is that it was an empirical discovery that heat is a form of energy associated with the motion of atoms and molecules. It was an empirical discovery that gold has an atomic number of 79. It was an empirical discovery that water is H20. The truth of state— ments (1)-(3) was settled empirically, not by an examina- tion of our linguistic conventions. Thus, statements (1)- (3) are a posteriori. And if they are a posteriori, then they are also synthetic and contingent. But while we may be quite willing to concede that statements (1)-(3) are a posteriori, we should not be quite so willing to concede that they are contingent. Heat oc- curs if and only if there is atomic or molecular motion. Something is gold if and only if it has atomic number 79. Something is water if and only if it is H20. We do not believe that statements (1)-(3) express mere correlations. We tend to believe that if our scientific theories are correct, then these statements are necessary. The situation is no better if we use Kant's analysis rather the logical positivist's. We can use Kant's 26 analysis to argue that statements (1)—(3) are analytic, a priori, and necessary. Our concept of heat includes the concept of a form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules. Our concept of gold includes the concept of an element with atomic number 79. Our concept of water includes the concept of H20. Thus, by Kant's criterion, statements (1)-(3) are analytic. And since they are analytic, they are also a priori and necessary. But once again, we can also use Kant's analysis to argue that statements (1)—(3) are synthetic, a posteriori, and contingent. The fact remains that it was an empirical discovery that heat is a form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules, that gold is an element with atomic number 79, that water is H20. Given the state of chemistry in his day, Kant undoubtedly did not include the concept of atomic or molecular motion within his concept of heat, or the concept of the atomic number 79 within his concept of gold, or the concept of H20 in his concept of water. We could argue that Kant has a different conception of heat, gold, and water than we do. We could say that the concepts of heat, gold, and water have changed since Kant's day. But such a suggestion overlooks the fact that these changes were driven by empirical findings. The fact of the matter is that the truth of statements (1)-(3) was settled empirically and not by examining our concepts. Thus, we can argue that statements (1)-(3) are a posteriori; and 27 since they are a posteriori, they are also synthetic and contingent. But once again, we may be unwilling to describe state- statements (1)—(3) as contingent. Our concept of water, for example, includes a great many other concepts. It in- cludes the concept of H20; but it also includes the concept of a liquid that boils at 100°C and freezes at 0°C; it in— cludes the concept of a colorless and odorless liquid. Yet while our concept of water may include concepts other than H O, we feel that the concept of H20 is somehow more impor— 2 tant than these other concepts. If we take Kant's and the logical positivists' analy- ses seriously, then we can categorize statements (1)-(3) as either analytic, a priori, and necessary or as synthetic, a posteriori, and contingent. In either case, we go against certain intuitions that we have about these statements. On the one hand, we believe that statements (1)—(3) provide the definitions for 'heat', 'gold', and 'water'. But on the other hand, we established these definitions empiri- cally. We believe that these statements are necessary; but we also believe that they are a posteriori. But every analysis of necessity that we have examined equates neces- sity with the a priori. Why are statements (1)-(3) so difficult to categorize? The problem is that although we may think that that these statements are definitions, we do not think that they 28 simply express linguistic conventions. Intuitively, we feel that these statements express the essence of their subject; and it is for this reason that we accept these statements as definitions. Aristotle, for example, argues that there are two types of definitions. One type gives the essential nature of its subject while the second type is only a nominal expression. The first type expresses the inherent nature of a thing while the second merely expresses the meaning of a word.24 These two types of definitions are related. We may use the essential nature of a thing as the meaning of the word that designates that thing. For example, the essential nature of water may be H20. We may then end up using 'HZO' as the definition of 'water'. But we have chosen to define 'water' as 'HZO' because H20 is the feature that constitutes the inherent constitution or essence of water. We have reason for defining 'water' in a particular way; but this definition is not the result of linguistic convention. Rather, our linguistic conventions, in the case of 'water', follows our empirical discoveries. Now we could bite the bullet, as many logical positi- vists (and possibly Kant) would recommend, and insist that statements (1)—(3) are synthetic, a posteriori, and contingent. The only reason why we think statements (1)- (3) are necessary is because, intuitively, we feel that they express the essence of their subject. But perhaps 29 this intuition tells us less about statements (1)—(3) than it tells us about ourselves. By feeling that statements (1)-(3) express the essence of their subjects, we have a certain attitude towards these statements. But an atti- tude is hardly sufficient to describe these statements as necessary. Chapter Two If we rely on the criteria provided by the logical positivists, then we have considerable leeway when it comes to categorizing the following statements: (1) Heat is the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules in solids. (2) Gold is the element with atomic number 79. (3) Water is H O. 2 On one hand, we can argue, and we can argue persuasively at that, that these statements are analytic, a priori, and necessary. But on the other hand, we can argue, and we can argue just as persuasively, that these statements are syn- thetic, a posteriori, and contingent. Needless to say, the logical positivists did not intend their criteria to be quite so flexible as this. In this chapter, we shall examine the causal theory of reference, a theory of meaning that has been proposed by Kripke and Putnam. Proponents of this theory argue that statements (1)-(3) are both necessary and a posteriori. This is a rather convenient claim. It not only takes into account our intuitive convictions that these statements express something essential about the nature of their sub- jects but also the fact that the truth of these statements was established empirically. But there is a problem. Al- though the causal theorists may be correct in claiming that statements (1)-(3) are both necessary and a posteriori, their justification for this claim leaves something to be 30 31 desired. Modifying the Traditional Distinctions Surprisingly enough, the causal theory is reminiscent of logical positivism. This is because the causal theor- ists draw the analytic/synthetic, a priori/a posteriori, and necessary/contingent distinctions in much the same way as the logical positivists. They accept these distinc- tions with only a few minor modifications. Yet it is these modifications, minor as they may appear, that enable the the causal theorists to reject the conclusion that neces- sary statements must be a priori. When it comes to the analytic/synthetic distinction, for example, the causal theorists agree with the logical positivists that while analytic statements owe their truth to linguistic conventions, synthetic statements do not. But the causal theorists undermine the importance of this distinction by two moves. First, they deny that this distinction is exhaustive. Putnam, for instance, argues that while some statements are analytic and others are synthetic, many are neither.1 Second, since we decide whether a statement is analytic or synthetic by examining the meaning of the signs used within that statement, the causal theorists argue that this distinction is essentially a semantic distinction. And since it is a semantic dis- tinction, the causal theoriests restrict the analytic/ 32 synthetic distinction to semantics.2 When it comes to the a priori/a posteriori distinc- tion, the causal theorists agree with the logical positi- vists that while a priori statements are independent of experience, a posteriori statements are not. But just as they restrict the analytic/synthetic distinction to a particular area so do they also restrict the a priori/a posteriori distinction. Since this distinction concerns the grounds and nature of knowledge, the causal theorists argue that it is fundamentally an epistemological distinc- tion. And since it is an epistemological distinction, the causal theorists restrict the a priori/a posteriori distinction to epistemology.3 When it comes to the necessary/contingent distinction, the causal theorists agree with the logical positivists that a statement is necessary if it is impossible that it is false and it is contingent otherwise. But once again, they restrict this distinction. The causal theorists argue that this distinction is basically a metaphysical distinction. And since it is a metaphysical distinction, the causal theorists restrict the necessary/contingent distinction to metaphysics.4 By restricting these distinctions to particular areas, the causal theorists have, in effect, divorced the neces- sary/contingent distinction from both the a priori/a pos- teriori distinction and the analytic/synthetic distinction. 33 The causal theorists argue that these three distinctions are independent. And since these distinctions are indepen- dent, we cannot conclude anything about a statement's sem- antical or epistemological status on the basis of its metaphysical status. Simply because a statement is nec- essary, we cannot conclude that it is also analytic and a priori. And thus, we cannot rule out the possibility that certain statements are both necessary and a posteriori. Proper Names and Necessary A Posteriori Statements The causal theorists identify two classes of state- ments that are both necessary and a posteriori. The first class, as we have already noted, consists of statements such as (1) Heat is the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules in solids. (2) Gold is the element with atomic number 79. (3) Water is H20. The second class consists of statements such as (4) Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte. (5) Jolmo Lungma is Mt. Everest. (6) The Malvinas Islands are the Falk- land Islands. The causal theorists believe that these two classes are analogous. Statements (1)-(3) are necessary for much the same reason that statements (4)-(6) are necessary. In fact, to understand just why statements (1)-(3) are neces- sary, we need to first understand why statements (4)-(6) 34 are necessary. Since it is clear that we cannot verify the truth of statements (4)-(6) by the use of reason alone or by lin- guistic analysis, there should be little debate over the claim that these statements are a posteriori. In order to know that Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte, we need some empirical evidence like an admission from Bronte herself or from some member of her publishing company. To know that Jolmo Lungma is Mt. Everest, we need to ask both Tibetans and non-Tibetans the name of a particular moun- tain. To know that the Malvinas Islands are the Falkland Islands, we need to ask both the Argentine government and the British government the name of two small islands in the Atlantic Ocean. In each case, we need some sort of empiri- cal evidence. While it is obvious that statements (4)-(6) are a pos- teriori, it is less obvious that they are necessary. As a matter of fact, we may even be tempted to argue that these statements are contingent. It is certainly contingent that Charlotte Bronte chose to publish her first novel under the pseudonym 'Currer Bell'. It is certainly contingent that the Tibetans chose to name a particular mountain Jolmo Lungma while the British chose to name it Everest. It is certainly contingent that while the Argentines chose to call two islands by one name, the British chose another. All this seems to suggest that statements (4)-(6) are 35 contingent. But the causal theorists argue that such a suggestion is mistaken. Statements (4)-(6), contrary to what we may think, are actually necessary. To understand why the causal theorists believe that these statements are necessary, we need to first understand their analysis of proper names. For much of this century, the issue of proper names came down to a choice between two theories. There was Russell's theory and there was Witt— genstein's. Kripke, in Naming and Necessity, argues that while these theories pose as competitors, they are, for all intents and purposes, the same theory. They are both de— scriptive theories of meaning. While Russell argues that a name is an abbreviation for a definite description, a de- scription that holds only for the referent of that name, Wittgenstein argues that a name is an abbreviation for a cluster of descriptions, some of which may be false but of which a sufficient number hold for the referent of that name. They may disagree on the number of required descrip- tions, but both Russell and Wittgenstein agree that a name is an abbreviation for some number of descriptions. Consider the name 'Aristotle'. There are any number of definite descriptions associated with this name: 'the last great philosopher of antiguity', 'the most famous pupil of Plato', 'the teacher of Alexander', 'the author of the Metaphysics'. According to Russell, the name 'Aris- totle' is simply an abbreviation for some description of 36 this type; and it is the description that gives 'Aristotle' its meaning. According to Wittgenstein, 'Aristotle' is not the abbreviation for some single description but for a cluster of descriptions; and it is this cluster that gives 'Aristotle' its meaning. In either case, the meaning of the name is due to description. In Naminggand Necessity, Kripke argues that the prob- lem with such an account is that it fails in counterfactual situations. Suppose 'Aristotle' is an abbreviation for the definite description 'the last great philosopher of anti- quity'. Now suppose that Aristotle had chosen medicine over philosophy. He certainly could have made such a choice. But ifAristotle had chosen a career in medicine, the description 'the last great philosopher of antiquity' would refer to someone other than Aristotle; so if the name 'Aristotle' is an abbreviation for 'the last great philoso— pher of antiquity', then the name 'Aristotle' no longer refers to Aristotle. But our intuitions are very clear that 'Aristotle' would still refer to Aristotle. When we say that Aristotle might have gone into medicine, we are specifically using 'Aristotle' to refer to Aristotle in a counterfactual situation where Aristotle is not the last great philosopher of antiquity. Nor are things much better if we rely upon a cluster of descriptions rather than a definite description. Not only can we conceive of a counterfactual situation where 37 Aristotle chose medicine over philosophy but we can also conceive of situations where he was not the most famous pupil of Plato, where he was not the tutor of Alexander, where he did not write the Metaphysics. As Kripke points out, we can conceive of a counterfactual situation for almost any description that applies to Aristotle. In such a case, if the cluster of descriptions refer to any- one, it is not Aristotle. And once again, the name 'Aris- totle' no longer refers to Aristotle, contrary to our intuitions. The major presupposition that underlies the descrip- tive theory of meaning is that the sense of a name, which is given by either a definite description or a cluster of descriptions, constitutes its meaning. It is this presup- position, according to the causal theorists, that is false. Kripke argues that names do not obtain their meaning from their sense. (In fact, Kripke does not even believe that names have a sense.) He argues that names, instead, obtain their meaning from their reference. The name, 'Aristotle', for example, obtains its meaning by a certain causal con- nection to Aristotle. 'Aristotle' is nothing more than the tag we use to refer to a particular person. And it is the person that gives the name its meaning. This is not to say that description is pointless. Descriptions may be used to fix a reference. For example, if someone were to ask me who Aristotle was, I might very well reply that Aristotle 38 was the last great philosopher of antiquity. After all, it is easier to supply a definition than it is to supply Aris- totle. But fixing a reference is not the same thing as fixing a meaning. This account of meaning has the advantage over the descriptive theory in that it has no problems with counter- factual situations. Since names are tags that we use to refer to particular entities, we can continue to use them in counterfactual situations. Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. They designate, or pick out, the same entities in every counterfactual situation or in every pos- sible world. The name 'Aristotle' not only allows us to pick out Aristotle in this world but in every possible world (or at the very least, in every possible world where Aristotle exists). Descriptions, on the other hand, are not rigid designators. The description 'the last great philosopher of antiquity' may pick out Aristotle in this world; but it does not pick out Aristotle in every possible world. It is the fact that names are rigid designators that explains why statements (4)-(6) are necessary. Consider (4). The name 'Charlotte Bronte' picks out the same entity in every possible world. 'Currer Bell', although a pseudo- nym, is also a name; and as such, it too picks out the same entity in every possible world. In this world, 'Charlotte Bronte' and 'Currer Bell' designate the same object. But 39 if they designate the same object in this world, and since they are rigid designators, they must designate the same object in every possible world. Thus, the statement 'Cur- rer Bell is Charlotte Bronte', if true in this world, is true in every possible world. This means that it is impos- sible for statement (4) to be false--it must be true; and thus, (4) is necessary. Similar arguments can be made for statements (5) and (6). In general, Kripke argues that if we have an identity statement 'R1=R2', where R1 and R2 rigid designators, then if that statement is true, it is 5 are necessarily true. Kripke argues that statements (1)-(3) are analogous to statements (4)-(6). These statements, too, are both neces- sary and a posteriori. There should be little debate over the claim that (1)—(3) are a posteriori. It was an empiri- cal discovery, after all, that heat is caused by the motion of atoms and molecules. It was an empirical discovery that gold is the element with atomic number 79. It Was an em- pirical discovery that water is H20. The causal theorists argue that the same sort of analysis that proved the necessity of statements (4)-(6) also proves the necessity of statements (1)-(3). The causal theorists argue that natural kind terms, terms such as 'heat', 'gold', and 'water', are analogous to proper names. In fact, we should think of natural kind terms as the names for natural kinds. And just as proper names 40 obtain their meaning from their reference so too do the terms for natural kinds obtain their meaning from their reference. 'Water', for example, obtains its meaning by a certain causal connection to water. 'Water' is nothing more than the tag we use to designate a particular kind of substance. And it is this substance that provides 'water' with its meaning. Since natural kind terms are analogous to proper names, we can now understand why statements (1)-(3) are necessary. Natural kind terms, like proper names, are rigid designators. While a proper name designates the same entity in every possible world, a natural kind term desig— nates the same substance (or phenomena or species) in every possible world. Kripke argues that statements (1)- (3), as theoretical identities, involve two rigid designa— tors. For example, consider (3). As a natural kind term, 'water' designates the same substance in every possible world. While 'HZO' is not exactly a name for a natural kind, it is a name for a chemical kind; and as such, it, too designates the same kind in every possible world. In this world, 'water’ and 'H20' designate the same substance. Since they designate the same substance in this world and since they are rigid designators, they designate the same substance in every possible world. This means that the statement 'Water is HZO', if it is true in this world, (which it is), is true in every possible world. Thus, we 41 may conclude that statement (3) is necessary. And accord- ing to Kripke, similar arguments can be made for (1) and (2).6 But at this point, we may have a few niggling doubts about this account. We may agree with Kripke that natural kind terms obtain their meaning from their reference. We may agree that natural kind terms are rigid designators. We may agree that statements (1)-(3) are both necessary and a posteriori. We may even agree that the statement 'Water is HZO' is necessary for exactly the reason that Kripke gives. But we soon run into one little problem. The phrases 'the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules in solids' and 'the element with atomic number 79' bear a suspicious resemblance to definite de- scriptions. In fact, the more cynical among us may even claim that 'HZO' is actually a definite description rather than a name of a chemical kind. But this makes it rather difficult to argue that statements (1)-(3) owe their neces- sity to the fact that we have two rigid designators that name the same substance. This suggests that statements (1)-(3) are not entirely analogous with statements (4)-(6). This does not imply that statements (1)-(3) are therefore contingent; but it does imply that if these statements are necessary, their necessity hinges on grounds other than those for (4)-(6). This should not surprise us. If we compare statements 42 (4)-(6) with statements (1)—(3), we intuitively feel that the latter are, in some sense, necessary while the former are, in some sense, contingent. This is because we feel that statements (1)-(3) express something essential about the nature of their subjects while (4)-(6) do not. However necessary statements (4)-(6) may be, the fact remains that they are also trivial. They say nothing of any importance about the nature of their subjects. Underlying Assumptions Although the causal theory provides an account of natural kind terms, it does not provide an account of natural kinds. But why is this important? Basically, it is important because while natural kind terms may be alike, natural kinds are not. Hull, for example, writes that From the beginning, a completely satis- factory explication of the notion of a natural kind has eluded philosophers. One explanation for this failure is that the traditional examples of natural kinds in the philosophical literature have been geometric figures, biological species, and physical elements. By now it should be clear that all three are very differ- ent sorts of things. No wonder a gener- al analysis, applicable equally to all of them, has eluded us. [7] But so long as natural kind terms are alike, why should we care if natural kinds are not? There is no reason why we cannot agree with Hull that there are different sorts of natural kinds while we still agree with the causal theor- ists that natural kind terms obtain their meaning from 43 their reference. Only the issue of meaning is relevant for the causal theory. Or is it? Let us assume that Hull is correct. Let us assume that there are different sorts of natural kinds. And let us assume further that these different sorts are the sorts that Hull identified--geometric figures, biological spe— cies, and physical elements. Now consider the following statements: (a) The triangle is a plane figure with an area enclosed by three straight lines. (b) The snow rose is the Hellaborus niger. (c) Gold is the element with atomic number (d) Carrer Bell is Charlotte Bronte. We already noted that the causal theorists believe that (c) and (d) are necessary for substantially the same reason. We also noted that this claim is incorrect. But perhaps the causal theorists merely chose the wrong example. By keep- ing in mind that natural kinds are not alike, we can devel- op a slightly different analysis: essence non-essence a priori (a) (b) The triangle is a plane The snow rose is the figure with an area en- Hellaborus niger. closed by three straight lines. 1 a poster- (c) (d) iori Gold is the element with Currer Bell is Char- .atomic number 79. . lotte Bronte. figure 1 44 The advantage of this chart is that it gives a more accur- ate picture of which statements are analogous and for what reasons. While the vertical axis says something about the epistemic status of our four statements, the horizontal axis says something about the source of their necessity. As we can see, while statements (c) and (d) are analogous in that they are both a posteriori, they are not analgous in the source of their necessity. When it comes to the source of their necessity, state- ments (a) and (c) are analogous. Both (a) and (c) owe their necessity to the fact that they express the essence of their subjects. (Granted, we may believe that (a), as the definition of 'triangle' only expresses a nominal es- sence while (c) expresses an Aristotelian essence; but for the time being, let us treat (a) and (c) as though they are completely analogous in this respect.) Both (a) and (c) express the essence of their subjects in terms of a defin- ite description. Since many causal theorists accept essen- tialism,8 they can certainly accept the necessity of (a) and (c). But should they? Offhand, it may seem as though they should not. After all, they have already rejected description when it comes to the meaning of natural kind terms. 80, how can they suddenly rely upon description when it comes to the essence of a natural kind? The answer to this question is that while the causal theorists reject any role for description when it comes to 45 the meaning of a natural kind term, they allow description a role in fixing the reference of that term. Perhaps it is true that natural kind terms, such as 'gold', obtain their meaning by a causal connection to gold. But still, how do we decide what is gold? Natural kind terms may obtain their meaning from their reference; but what is included within this reference is often open to question. Compared to the referent of a proper name, the reference of a natu- ral kind term is somewhat open-~a fact acknowledged even by the causal theorists. So, how do we determine the refer- ence of a natural kind term? Putnam writes that The use of a word such as 'gold' depends upon our possessing paradigms, standard examples that are agreed to be model mem- bers of the kind. ... What makes some- thing gold is having the same nature as the paradigm. [10] And how do we decide that something has the same nature as our paradigm? We rely upon description. Once we have our paradigm, we choose certain proper- ties to characterize that paradigm. These properties (or descriptions) then permit us to identity additional members of that kind. But this set of properties does not consti- tute any sort of meaning. For one thing, it is subject to change. Kripke goes so far as to argue that it is the task of science to produce better sets of properties. He writes that ...science attempts by investigating basic structural traits to find the nature, and thus the essence (in the 46 philosophical sense) of the kind.[11] As scientists discover the basic structure that members of a kind share, they reflect this knowledge in their choice of properties that characterize that kind. Yet when it comes to certain natural kinds, it seems as though scientists have actually discovered the essence of the kind. Sober writes that A paradigm case [of essentialism] has been the periodic table of elements, which seems to tell us that the essence of each element is its atomic number. ... The atomic number 14 is a character- istic that all and only Nitrogen atoms share, and that an atom must have this atomic number if it is to be Nitrogen. Essentialism of this sort holds that it is no accident that the property of be- ing an atom of Nitrogen and that of hav- ing a given atomic number go together; indeed they must covary since the atomic number is the nature or essence of Nitro- gen. [12] Or let's consider gold. Being the element with atomic num- ber 79 is not some mere property of gold--it is the defin- ing property. This property tells us what gold is. If something is gold, it must have atomic number 79; and if anything has atomic number 79, then it is gold. This is because the statement 'Gold is the element with atomic num- ber 79' expresses the essence of gold. Or, according to Aristotelian terminology, this statement gives the "real" definition of gold. Since the causal theorists divorced a statement's metaphysical status from its epistemic status, it should ya; we all pa am me Ye 47 not bother us that although (a) and (c) are both necessary, one is a priori while the other is a posteriori. We can use the same method to discover the essence of either kind. And this method has been described by Aristotle. According to Aristotle, if we wish to find the essence of a kind, we begin with induction and then follow a method of division. He writes We must start by observing a set of sim- ilar--i.e., specifically identical--in- dividuals, and consider what element they have in common. We must then ap— ply the same process to another set of individuals which belong to one species and are generically but not specifically identical with the former set. When we have established what the common element is in all members of this second species, we should again consider whether the re- sults established possess any identity and persevere until we reach a single formula, since this will be the defini- tion of the thing. [13] This process, however, can be either a priori or a poster- iori. In the case of triangles, we start by examining various triangles and seeing what features these triangles have in common. But since triangles are mental entities, we can carry out this examination by the use of reason alone. In the case of gold, we start by examining our paradigmatic examples and seeing what features these ex— amples have in common. But since gold is a physical ele- ment, we need experience to carry out this examination. Yet in either case, the process is similar. While statements (c) and (d) may not be analogous in 48 the source of their necessity, as the causal theorists thought, statements (b) and (d) are. If the causal theorists had compared (b) to (d), their argument would have been much stronger. Certainly 'snow rose' and 'Hella— borus niger' are comparable to proper names. Hull argues that the names for biological species, whether a taxonomic name or an ordinary name, obtain their meaning from their connection to the species and not from some description. Although Hull points out that he is not a causal theorist, he makes much the same points that they do when he writes As important as the traits listed in [zoological] diagnoses and descriptions may be for a variety of purposes, they are not definitions. Organisms could possess these traits and not be includ- ed in the taxon; conversely, organisms could lack one or more of these traits and be clearcut instances of the tax- on. [14] Hull continues to borrow features from the causal theory when he stresses the similarities between the names of biological species and proper names. While the following passages are taken from Hull, they could have just as easily been written by Kripke. A taxon [species] has the name it has in virtue of the naming ceremony, not in virtue of any trait or traits it might have. If the way in which taxa are named sounds familiar, it should. It is the same way in which people are baptized. [15] If 'homo sapiens' is or is not a cluster concept, it will be for the same reason that 'Moses' is or (more likely) is not. [16] 49 Hull mentions that if philosophers examined how scientists designate biological entities like tigers or mallards or the snow rose, they would have found "rules explicitly for- mulated in the various codes of nomenclature which were in perfect accord with Kripke's analysis--but for the wrong reasons."17 By "wrong reasons", Hull is referring to Kripke's essentialism. Scientists, according to Hull, do not even attempt to find essences. Hull accepts Kripke's account on meaning; but he rejects Kripke's essentialism. As a matter of fact, we need not presuppose any sort of essentialism for either (b) or (d). In the preceding section, we did not need to presuppose essentialism to argue that (d) was necessary. Nor do we need to presuppose essentialism to argue that (b) is necessary. Since species names function like proper names, they are rigid designa- tors. The name 'snow rose' designates the same kind in every possible world; and the name 'Hellaborus niger' also designates the same kind in every possible world. In this world, 'snow rose' and 'Hellaborus niger' designate the same kind. Since they are rigid designators, and since they designate the same kind in this world, they designate the same kind in every possible world. Thus, statement (b) is necessary. The very same sort of argument that justi- fies the claim that 'Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte' is necessary also justifies the claim that 'The snow rose is the Hellaborus niger' is necessary. And neither argument 50 relies in any way on essentialism. While (a) and (c) owe their necessity to essentialism, (b) and (d) owe their necessity to some other assumption. In the arguments we have seen, both in the preceding sec- tion and this section, the causal theorists appeal to our intuitions. And many of the assumptions that underlie these intuitions remain implicit. In "Identity and Neces- sity", Kripke provides a formal version of this intuitive argument. And in this formal version, implicit assumptions become explicit. Kripke's argument goes like this (i) (X)(y)[(X=y)+(FX+Fy)]. This premise states that if x is y, then any property of x is also a property of y. (ii) (X)D(X=X). This premise is the principle of self-identity which states that everything is necessarily identical to itself. (iii) (X)(Y)(X=Y)+[EKX=X)+EKX=Y)l. This premise is a substitution instance of (i). From (iii) and (ii), we can infer the following: (iv) (X)(Y)[(X=Y)*D(X=Y)]- This conclusion states that if x is y, then x is necessar- ily y. Kripke makes it very clear that the substitution instances for x and y must be rigid designators and not descriptions. If we substitute rigid designators for x and y, and these designators refer to the same thing, they do 51 so necessarily. On the other hand, if we substitute de- scriptions for either x or y, and they refer to the same object, they only do so contingently. On the basis of this, we may argue that if the statements 'Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte' and "The snow rose is the Hellaborus niger' are true, they are necessarily true. This argument makes explicit an assumption that up until now has only been implicit. This assumption is the principle of self-identity. Statements such as (b) and (d) owe their necessity to this principle. Without it, we can- not argue that these statements are necessary. This fact is made explicit in the second argument. But the principle of self-identity is also assumed in the first argument, albeit implicitly. When we argue that the statement 'Cur- rer Bell is Charlotte Bronte' is necessary, we are relying implicitly upon the fact that this statement follows from the fact that Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte and the fact that Currer Bell is necessarily Currer Bell. If it were not true that everything is necessarily identical to it- self, then it would not be true that Currer Bell is neces- sarily identical to Charlotte Bronte where Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte. This second argument is also interesting in that it makes it obvious that we justify the necessity of state- ments (b) and (d) via an a priori argument. Whatever their epistemic status may be, their metaphysical status is de— 52 termined by an a priori argument. And this is just as true of (d) as it is for (b). In the case of (b), it may strike us as odd that the metaphysical status of an a posteriori statement can be determined by an a priori argument. But when we argue that (b) and (d) are neces- sary, we are relying upon the following inference pattern (where once again, the substitution instances for x and y are rigid designators). (1) x=y. (ii) (X=Y)+I:1(X=y). (iii) D(x=y). The conclusion, (iii), owes its metaphysical status to Premise (ii). This premise, (ii), is merely a simpli- fied version of the conclusion from Kripke's argument in "Identity and Necessity". The fact that premise (ii) is necessary explains why our conclusion is also necessary. The conclusion owes its epistemic status, however, to Premise (i). In the case of (d), we justify the truth of premise (i) empirically. Thus, the conclusion will b e a- posteriori. In the case of (b), we justify the truth 0f E’themise (1) without the use of experience. Thus, the (3011 Q lusion is a priori. Although statement (b) resembles (d) on metaphysical grguhds’ since (b) is a priori, the causal theorists cannot 113% :1t to justify their claim that certain statements are “egg ssary and a posteriori. Or could they? Certainly it is 1true that philosophers, in the past, believed that (b) 53 was necessary and a priori. Hahn, for example, writes I talk about a well-known plant... and I make the stipulation: Let us call any plant of this kind "snow rose," but let us also call it "hellaborus niger." Thereupon I can pronounce with absolute certainty the universally valid proposi- tion: "every snow rose is a hellaborus niger." It is certainly valid, always and everywhere: it is not refutable by any sort of observation. ...The state- ment merely expresses a convention con- cerning the way we wish to talk about the plant in question. [18] But: is Hahn correct? According to Hahn's account, the statement 'The snow rose is the Hellaborus niger' is analogous to the state- Imerlt: 'A bachelor is an unmarried man' in that each express- es some sort of linguistic convention. We choose to use 'Hellaborus niger' as the taxonomic name for a particular lcir1<3_ of plant just as we choose to use 'bachelor' as a name fcxr- Ei.particular class of humans. The problem, though, is '315‘12- Hahn's account applies just as easily to the statement ”:LIJEVlrer Bell is Charlotte Bronte' as it does to 'The snow ITDSBTEE is the Hellaborus niger'. After all, didn't Bronte StiDUlate that she was to be known as Currer Bell in a eel:N'lr—viain situation? Thus, if the statement 'The snow rose is ‘t:l]ae Hellaborus niger' is a priori, then so is 'Currer BE¥I.;11‘ is Charlotte Bronte'. We can also argue that if 'Currer Bell is Charlotte Brt:> Irivte' is a posteriori, then so is 'The snow rose is the Ik33L_:l‘ aborus niger'. It is not that unusual for botanists, could disc: he 54 particularly botanists who work in the rain forest, to give a particular species a taxonomic name before they discover that the plant has a folk name. In such a case, couldn't we say that the botanists have made an empirical discovery? Isn't such a discovery just as empirical as the discovery that Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte? The a priori/a posteriori distinction is not as clear- xer.. De Re or De Dicto? Towards the beginning of this chapter, we brought up tmvc) (:lasses of statements. One class consisted of state— me hits such as (1) Heat is the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules in solids. (2) Gold is the element with atomic number 79. (3) Water is H20. 131 Q conomics . Or consider statements (4)-(6). These statements Owe their necessity to the principle of self-identity. Mat §kie suggests that ...these de re modalities are, broad sense, de dicto after all. in a very Though 59 these necessities apply to individual things and natural kinds, that they so apply is primarily a feature of the way we think and speak, of how we handle identity in association with counterfac- tual possibility. They reflect implicit rules for the ascription of identity, for the recognition of the same person or thing or stuff or species, in neutrally described merely possible situations. The topic of names (and certain general terms) comes in only because such names (etc.) are intended to belong to things (etc.) whose identity is determined by these rules. [20] Insofar as we follow certain rules in talking and theoriz- ing; about Currer Bell and Charlotte Bronte, for example, thee statement 'Currer Bell is Charlotte Bronte' can be deassczribed as de dicto. Even though the principle of self- irieerjtity applies to Currer Bell and Charlotte Bronte as Obj ects, the fact that this principle applies to these ob- jects is due to the way we talk and think. Thus, we can argue that statements (1)-(6) are actu— ‘a1“1-3?’ necessary de dicto. An object, by itself, may have VaI‘lious properties, but these properties are neither nec- essary or contingent until we consider those properties wi th in a particular context. The fact that we choose to deg Qribe certain properties of an object as necessary with- 1:1 iEL given context reflects our interests and theories ah><:)“‘;lt that object. The fact that we choose to handle iden— t1‘1t:-2i? and self-identity in a particular manner reflects the walEET that we talk and think. But if we decide which proper- 'tjk EE=ES are necessary, and if we base this decision on our {Leon The 0t are Ill 60 theories, then necessity is, in a broad sense, de dicto. The object simply has properties. Whether these properties are necessary or not depends upon us, not the object. I1 V, v . 53%: ‘a it is ZaVe In! In Chapter Three In chapter two, we learned that the causal theorists Categorized the following statements as both necessary and a posteriori: (1) Heat is the form of energy constituted by the motion of atoms and molecules in solids. (2) Gold is the element with atomic number 79. (3) Water is H20. N0“? ‘vhile this suggestion fits nicely with our intuitions, it .143 by no means the only suggestion that philosophers haVe made . A great many philosophers argue that the reason why Statements (1)-(3) prove so difficult to classify is be- cause our distinctions are fundamentally flawed. These p'l'lli--IIL<:>sophers argue that the logical positivists did not EEITJE7 Lin misunderstanding the nature of their distinctions; t: hey erred in accepting these distinctions in the first 3) lace. And according to these philosophers, rather than t - :L.1:l]<;er around with the traditional distinctions, we should $3;j‘ Jrr‘l;>ly reject them altogether. And this conclusion becomes 3" IQE=1F1.more compelling once we adopt a particular theory of rr1 . :Ftnow what is meant by 'King', 'Rook', 'square', and 3t:~ ahki. QB $§-t:: But if our entire knowledge of castling consisted 12-his definition, then we can hardly be said to under- I‘JVICi the meaning of the term 'castling'. To understand 63 'castling', we also need to know a few rules of chess, particularly those rules that govern castling. To under- stand 'castling', we should recognize the move when we see it. To understand 'castling', we should be able to make time move ourselves. Thus, to understand 'castling', we neexi to know a fair amount about chess. And as a matter of facfl:, when we first learn chess, we do not learn a few terms and rules in isolation. Rather, we are given a great deéil. of information about the game as a whole from the very Start. The network theorists claim that all terms resemble 'castling' in respect to the fact that all terms obtain t11€3£i¢r meaning within some sort of theoretical context. {P51]<:rists. They agree with Putnam when he writes The concept 'energy' is an excellent ex— ample of a law~cluster concept. It enters into a great many laws. It plays a great many roles, and these laws and inference roles constitute its meaning collectively, not individually. [2] Despite our equation for energy, Putnam argues that the meaning of 'energy' is not given by a single defining law (3 1:. «E1 single defining characteristic. Rather, it takes its IT! ea11ing from its overall role and position within physics. TE'E) ‘51 term 'energy' is best understood within the overall <==<:: ‘Tth:ext of physics. Although we may be willing to concede that game terms EEJI=> Q o o o rm their theoretical context, we may not believe that all terms from mathematics and science obtain their meaning ‘Es: 53::7rns obtain their meaning from their context. For exam— 1;).Ili . 53: 0' consider observation terms--terms such as 'hot', =53: ‘:::’Ifit', 'white', or 'sweet'. Intuitively, we tend to think IA 65 that these terms obtain their meaning from their connection to a particular sensation. 'Hot' means the sensation hot, for example. But the network theorists argue that even these terms obtain their meaning from their role and posi— ticni within a theoretical network. But how can they jus— tify this claim? They could justify this claim by appealing to Wittgen- SteaiJu's point that even observation terms have public cri— teriafor their use. If I describe newly fallen snow as 113C1.- for example, few people, apart from my optometrist aILéi ‘physician, will care what my visual sensation happened tc> lash Perhaps it was red or perhaps it was white. But "nC’SSWt; people will simply say that my description is incor- Ifea¢::t:. This is because we have public criteria for our use ()1? (:olor terms. Taking this point, network theorists can aJrglsle that public criteria are provided by some sort of t:lj“53<:retical network. Churchland supports this claim by means of the follow- jLaljlel thought experiment. He proposes that we imagine a EE:]E: ‘Ei<:ies of beings who perceive temperature visually. Ac- <:=..::> JCT~ ‘Eéiry respect but two: First, their language lacks a color Q. . ":=€ibulary. And second, the temperature vocabulary is ‘ HIE vat: He 66 learned visually rather than tactilely. So, Churchland asks, how should we interpret their terms 'hot', 'warm', and 'cold'? If we believe that sensation terms obtain their meaning from their relationship to a sensation, theni‘we should interpret their terms 'hot', 'warm', and 'ccild' as 'white', 'gray', and 'black'. After all, the serusation that these beings call 'hot' is the sensation that we call 'white'. But such a translation seems incorrect. Our intuition -iS tihat these beings mean the same thing by 'hot' that we "Kiéiri by 'hot'. Moreover, Churchland points out that such a trEtrislation also makes many of their beliefs about tempera- t“JdI?€e incorrect. Churchland concludes from this that obser- V511tlion terms do not obtain their meaning from sensation. He Writes that The meaning of a term (or the identity of a concept) is not determined by the intrinsic quality of whatever sensation happens to prompt its observational use, but by the network of assumptions/be- liefs/principles in which it figures. Sensations are just the causal middle— men in the process of perception, and one kind will serve as well as another so long as it enjoys the right causal connections. [3] ‘N711s to learn their temperature vocabulary. But so long §§ fih ‘:::'K1t.temperature as these beings, their temperature terms “ve share the same beliefs, assumptions, and principles have thE as we st 55.16 me t' . Wt? COTLV inc drawn 1 cal p0: to the failur tional netwo: tions What dI' at; tit Co: be 67 have the same meaning as our temperature terms. So long as we share the same theoretical network, terms have the same meaning. We may or may not find the network theory of meaning (xnrvincing. But one reason why philosophers have felt drawn to this theory is because it is a response to logi- cal. positivism. Or to be more accurate, it is a response to tile failure of logical positivism. But the reason for faiLIJJre of logical positivism is the failure of the tradi- ti<311ial distinctions. Many philosophers have adopted the network theory as they gave up the traditional distinc— tions. “at Happens to the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction? As we know from Chapter One, the logical positivists Ci ltrial‘flr the analytic/synthetic distinction as follows: (LA) A statement is analytic if and only if its truth value is determined completely by linquistic convention. (LS) A statement is synthetic if and only if its truth value is not de— termined by linquistic convention. 3§L<:: ‘<::‘:>rding to the network theorists, if we base the analy- t:-:i. ‘<:= J’synthetic distinction on the notion of linquistic (:2‘::.thl It) ‘\7ention, then we cannot justify a sharp demarcation 53’ 1t:; 3L 'Vveen those statements that we wish to describe as ana— ‘:¥’ ‘it:; - :LIZ and those that we wish to describe as synthetic. The logical positivists believe that there are two 68 notions of analyticity. One type can be described as the logical notion of analyticity. The statements that fall under this type include statements such as 'Bachelors are bachelors' and 'Fv-F'. The linquistic conventions that determine the truth value of these statements are the conventions that govern our use of logical words and logical participles. Quine says that The logical truths, then, are those true sentences which involve only lo- gical words essentially. What this means is that any other words, though they may also occur in a logical truth (as witness 'Brutus', 'kill', and 'Cae- sar' in 'Brutus killed or did not kill Caesar'), can be varied at will without engendering falsity. [4] The 1:11.53 second type of analyticity is what Putnam describes as linquistic notion of analyticity. The statements that Iféa-JL I. under this type include 'Bachelors are unmarried men' and 'Brothers are male siblings'. The conventions that govern these statements are synonymy relations. The state- It! Gatlrlft: 'Bachelors are unmarried men', for example, owes its 1:;3:. 151*t2h to the fact that in English, 'bachelor' is synonymous w '- 1 t1“: 'unmarried man'. In 'Two Dogmas of Empiricism", Quine attacks the JL-Ii‘ Irjl ‘c‘ “9‘7 do we know that 'bachelor' is synonymous with 'unmar- .:i‘ . EE=<3 man'? We could argue that they are synonymous because 5 Q“LThelor' is defined as 'unmarried man' in the dictionary. 69 But as Quine points out, the dictionary does not make 'bachelor' synonymous with 'unmarried man'-—it only reports that 'bachelor' and 'unmarried man' are synonymous. We could argue that 'bachelor' and 'unmarried man' are synony- mous because they are interchangeable. But what do we mean by "interchangeable"? Do we mean that they are inter— changeable because they are extensionally equivalent or be— cause they are intensionally equivalent? When we claim that 'bachelor' and 'unmarried man' are synonymous, Quine argues that we are making a stronger claim than that they are extensionally equivalent. 'Morning star' and 'evening star' are extensionally equivalent; but they are hardly 'un- synonymous. So, we want to claim that 'bachelor' and married man' are interchangeable because they are inten- sionally equivalent. But how do we know when two terms are intensionally equivalent? According to Quine, when we say that two terms are intensionally equivalent, we mean that a statement that unites the terms, such as 'Bachelors are un- married men', is analytic. Thus, to justify the analyti-