m . .w . 3.3.“...0...‘ or—Mm aw... £2 ‘. . . . .~\ . a» . .. r. 5% n...» ‘ 61...: :23 1 iii. 1 in? has .. 4 ;. finnnum‘itf :Rhaiarv‘. l¥¥. 5; 1.3%., , . .3..an 2-: an. . 4 n rzfiunmwuryfi ("Warm .. 2, .2... .rsvunfihi. .2. .3”: ‘ 30.")an 3.91:...) («on I .33.: . P31. 3%.“ h s gmfifluu . ‘ Qifldavnw .?t . h. L141 iwvuidzi. 5‘ ha. v.43.» a. :: hivumm . .513“ .15. Ml: 788 Illllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllll:llllllllllllllllllllll 31293 01688 0480 This is to certify that the thesis entitled Open Relationships/Honest Answers: A Dying Child's Understanding of Terminal Illness and the Value in Making the Truth Available presented by Sara A. Raza has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for MA degree in IPHH Sid/fl fi/Im/ZLL/ “/7 Major professor 5 11 98 Date I / 0-7639 MS U is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution LIBRARY Michigan State ~ Unlverslty PLACE IN RETURN BOX to remove this checkout from your record. TO AVOID FINE return on or before date due. MTE DUE DATE DUE use mm“ OPEN RELATIONSHIPS/ HONEST ANSWERS: A DYING CHILD'S UNDERSTANDING OF TERMINAL ILLNESS AND THE VALUE IN MAKING THE TRUTH AVAILABLE By Sara A. Raza A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Interdisciplinary Program in Health and Humanities 1998 ABSTRACT OPEN RELATIONSHIPS/HONEST ANSWERS: A DYING CHILD'S UNDERSTANDING OF TERMINAL ILLNESS AND THE VALUE IN MAKING THE TRUTH AVAILABLE By Sara A. Raza This thesis argues that dying children have a moral claim to an open relationship with their practitioner. First, I explain that an open relationship allows honest communication between the patient and the practitioner. Such a relationship cannot exist without sharing, autonomy, benevolence, compassion, courage, prudence, phronesis, and justice; Next, I argue that such a relationship is morally ideal; then, that contemporary theories of cognitive development do not rule out the possibility that children are capable of such a relationship; finally, that some children's literature may be a beneficial tool for helping children communicate about and understand difficult issues. To all my friends and family who constantly remind me of the power of faith, hope and love. To my two furry angels, who always know when I need them most. To those who are forever gone from this earth, you are always with me and give me the strength to get up when 1 fall. And, mostly to all the children who have touched my life and help me open my eyes to the. miracles all around- .you are the true miracles. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This thesis would not be possible without the constant guidance and encouragement I received from members of my thesis committee, Dr. Judith Andre, Dr. Lillian Phenice, and Dr. Linda Spence. Thank you so much for you suggestions and support. A special thanks to Dr. Judith Andre, my thesis advisor, who helped to encourage me to continue working on this thesis with the simple words that the topic is really important. Judy, I really couldn't have done this without your direction, guidance, grammar help and most importantly your willingness to listen and care. I owe many of my thoughts and my ability to think in an interdisciplinary way to the lPl-iH department and all the professors that conduct their courses in a way that opens the minds of students and helps us to draw parallels among ideas that at first glance seem to have no connections. A special thanks to Dr. Tom Tomlinson for expanding my mind and to all my colleagues that kept me thinking of good arguments to all I believe. Finally, I would like to thank my mom for reading more prospective and thesis drafts than one person should have to. You always told me pursue those things that caught my heart and made me happy. That has to be the best advice that a parent could ever give. Hopefully one day I will be able to give to others as much as you have always given to me. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION CHAPTER] REVIEW OF SCHOLARLY LITERATURE 5 Research about Children' 5 Ability to Understand Death 5 Work on Honesty in Health care 9 Work on the Use of Literature in Communicating with Children .................. 12 CHAPTER 2 WHAT'S SO GREAT ABOUT THE TRUTH? 13 To Tell the Truth 13 On the Other Side 14 Another Important Question - 16 Do These Reasons Fit for Children? 17 CHAPTER 3 AN ATMOSPHERE OF OPENNFSS 21 Open Relationships 21 Establishment of the Relationship 22 Harm 25 Personal Interaction Z6 . Practitioner/ Child Patient Relationship 27 Potential Problems 29 CHAPTER 4 COGNITIVE DEVELOPMENT: HOW A CHILD DYING FROM A TERMINAL ILLNESS UNDERSTANDS DEATH 31 What Is It? 31 Views that Cast Doubt on Piagetian Theory 34 Other Issues in Child Development 36 CHAPTER 5 CHILDREN'S LITERATURE: A TOOL FOR APPROPRIATE DISCLOSURE 39 Literature's Value 39 'What Makes a Book Good? 40 Growing Through the Use of Literature - 40 Trouble: Bad literature 41 The Tools 41 Examples of Good literature 42 CONCLUSION 46 BIBLIOGRAPHY 49 INTRODUCTION No one knows with regard to death whether it is not really the greatest blessing that can happen to a man: but people dread it as though they were certain that it is the greatest evil. This is ignorance, which thinks that it knows what it does not, must surely be ignorance most culpable. ~Plato, The Apology Death is one of the most difficult subjects to talk about because it reminds us that we have little control over the world; this is never clearer than when we look at children and realize that they too, die. I began this thesis trying to understand what it is like to be a child with a terminal illness, yet there was no real way for me to understand that without projecting my own feelings on the children that I so desperately wanted to help. I I figured that children needed hope, but only hope that was valid and true. I believed that children needed and wanted to know the truth in all its nuances. Then, it struck me that l was no better than the people before me. And I had to rethink my plan of attack. If I really wanted to help children and make dying an easier process, then I had to look at what the dying child really wants to know. So, I have changed my focus, knowing full well that children are capable of much more than we adults sometimes suspect. I began to think not about what children should be told, but rather what they want to know. I cannot say that l fully‘understand what is going on in the dying child's mind, but my aim in this thesis is to explore how a dying child might see death and the dying process, what type of relationship might make the dying process easier and finally whether there are tools available to aid in the dying child's understanding of death. I feel much passion about this subject. Much of me thinks that it is unfair that a child has to die and most of me wishes that we never had to wade 2 through such painful subjects. And yet I feel fortunate that I can bring a new look to this age old problem. In this thesis I am looking at children living with terminal illness, age seven to ten, who have reached the terminal phase of their illness. I have chosen this age group because it comes between the times when a child still does not fully understand the notion of personhood and when the child desperately wants to be an adult. I have also chosen to look at children who are in settings where death is all around and presumed to affect their minds, as well as their bodies. In addition, these children will have been primarily raised in health care settings. Therefore, they have spent a considerable amount of time in the hospital. 1 This may also mean that some of the children were first diagnosed with chronic illnesses and have since become terminal. I have learned, through conversation with Dr. Linda Spence,2 that children are given different information about their diagnosis and prognosis in different care settings. In today's health care system, children are usually cared for at the clinic or the hospital, although sometimes children are cared for at home or in hospice type settings. Because children may receive different information depending on the setting in which they receive their care, it is important, throughout this thesis, to keep in mind that the children I will be focusing on have been cared for in the hospital and may not be able to benefit from insight that the caring team in the clinic may have. Finally, my focus in this study will only be on the white, middle class culture with which I am familiar. Given more time, this study would be complemented by a 1"Considerable," meaning that they have been hospitalized at least once a month since diagnosis. 2 Dr. Linda Spence, RN teaches in the Nursing department at Michigan State University and has done considerable clinic and hospital work with dying children throughout her career. 3 look at other cultures and how they might view children and terminal illness differently. In this thesis, I will be exploring how children living with terminal illness might come to understand and question death and dying. i will look at the value an honest open relationship might have for children and at their ability to ask questions about their health and receive honest answers. In addition, I will discuss studies relevant to children's ability to understand death. Finally, I will review some of the tools that might aid in the child's understanding of such an abstract concept. 3 Throughout this thesis, I will focus on what we need to do for dying children. I will pay particular attention to the ways relationships between the caring team and the child affect that child's understanding of death and dying and their ability to receive honest answers to their questions. I will also look at the value of personal engagement between the child and the caring team. Finally, I will look at literature as a promising tool in the dying child's understanding of death and loss. However, I will not be looking at the social world that is created for the dying child or the emotional help children might need to get through this process.4 On a final note, I will look at the child as separate from the unit of family. I am doing this for the reason that dying children are facing a trauma that has already caused them to disengage from their family. They are In the hospital and by this very fact have experienced separation from the family unit and isolation from other children. 5 In this thesis, I will focus my attention on the child's development and 3i will primarily be looking at literature as an aid in this understanding process. 480th of these are interesting questions, but there is not enough time to explore them in this thesis. For more information on these topics refer to work done by Myra Bluebond-Langer in her dissertation and several of her books. sBauer, David. "What of the Dying Child?" In Death in the Life of Children, ed. Kaoru Yamamoto (Arizona: Kappa Delta Pi, 1978) 83. 4 their understanding. This understanding certainly does not occur in a vacuum. The child is exposed to what other people think and understand, but I have chosen not to look at the family context for several reasons. The most important reason is that much work has been done on the family and how they, as a unit, deal with the crisis of death and dying. Clare Mulholland once said that there is nothing worse than not knowing what you already knew. 6 Let us not sentence our children to this fate that may be worse than death. 6 Clare Mulholland, 1973. Chapter 1 REVIEW OF SCHOLARLY LITERATURE My review of the scholarly literature is based on four disciplines. These are: child development, philosophy, nursing and children's literature about death and dying. I have taken this interdisciplinary approach to this thesis because I think that it is important to keep in mind that children, even those that are facing death, are trying to make sense of a world that is complex and mutt-faceted. While there have been few studies and little written about communication between a child and their provider, it is fairly plausible that some of the issues I am looking at may have been explored in other disciplines. A more complete study of dying children and the benefits of open relationships would certainly include a review of scholarly literature in anthropology and sociology. However, those disciplines, along with others, are beyond the scope of this thesis. Research about children's ability to understand death We have for centuries been thinking and writing about death and dying, but these discussions have mostly concerned adults. Studies that have adult subjects may seem irrelevant to this discussion of children dying from terminal illness, but it has been noticed by Kenneth Doka that studies done on adults may show us something about children. Ideally we would focus our attention on studies done on dying children, but very few of these studies exist and it is likely that they never will. 7 Despite these impediments, we can make sense of some of these data as they apply to 71 suggest this because it is almost impossible to be allowed to study children, especially those dying from terminal illness. Organizations that are designed to protect research subjects are not likely to allow studies on children, especially if those studies are dealing with issues of death and dying. children when we realize that "as a general rule, a child's struggle with life- threatening illness is both similar to and different from that of an adult." 3 It is hard to see how it is possible for the child to have experiences Similar to an adult; after all children are not just small adults. However, Doka noticed that a child's death experience is similar to that of adults in the ways of coping with the physical and social aspects. Doka noted that children were well aware of and able to experience loss of the physical, in similar ways to adults. This means that dying children and adults coped with body function loss in similar enough ways that it is possible to use studies conducted on adults to explore children. Although there were those similarities, Doka noted that adults and children were different in the ways of available communication and development issues. Children, especially those who are young, have fewer words to draw from for active communication. On the other hand, adults are able to communicate more clearly because they have more words available. Also, children are still developing in a number of ways. Children are physically growing, gaining motor skills and strength and are experiencing much mental growth. Adults, while they may be experiencing some minor mental growth, are fully matured beings. Because of these differences, it was an important time for children and those people interested in their development, when studies involving children began. However, it was not until the 1930s that this really happened. Even then there were few studies, but beginning in the 1970s intense interest began in the study of 8Doka, Kenneth. ”The Cruel Paradox: Children Who Are Living with Life- Threatening Illnesses." In Handbook of Childhood Death and Bereavement, ed. Charles Corr and Donna Corr, ( New York: Springer Publishing Co., 1996) 94. 7 children and how they might come to understand death. 9 Yet, despite the number of studies in the 70s and 80s, there has been little progress in this area of child development. There are several reasons for this lack of progress, though most have something to do with the fact that results of these studies are confusing and the models of the studies usually begin with assumptions that may not be accurate. For example, in the majority of these studies, "it has been generally assumed that children's concepts of death develop in accordance with Piaget's general theory of cognitive development." 10 This may be an accurate assumption for well children and some sick children, but many people call the development stages, which Piaget's claims occur in all persons, into question. Several experts in the field of child development, who have done studies of this sort, including Flanel and Gelman and Balllargeon, believe that the "process of concept development in general is more complex, extends over a longer period of the life span and results In more varied and individualized outcomes." 11 So, at this point we are left with little understanding on how the child actually understands death and dying. This becomes more clear when we look at how the ill child, especially the terminally ill child, understands these concepts. There have been few studies done on the understanding a child who is sick or terminally ill may have about death. Yet, in these studies and others (those on children that are well) we can notice one relationship that helps us to understand how the child dying from a terminal illness may develop an understanding of death that is far more 9Speece, Mark and Sandor Brent. "The Development of Children's Understanding of Death." In Handbook of Childhood Death and Bereavement , ed. Charles Corr and Donna Corr (New York: Springer Publishing Co.,1996) 29. 10Speece, ”The Development of Children's Understanding of Death” 43. “Flanel 1985 and Gelman and Baillargeon 1983. 8 mature than the understanding the average child may have. This relationship shows that more experienced children, those that see and think about death more, were more likely to have mature concepts of death. The first clinician to really suggest this about ill children was Myra Bluebond—Langer who stated that children who had experience and exposure to life threatening illness may have a more mature concept of death than held by healthy children of relatively the same age.12 Since the time of her study, in 197 8, six major studies have been done, but the results are equivocal. Studies done in 1984 by Fetch and in 1990 by Groolman found a significant relationship between a mature concept of death and life experience, but the other four studies showed mixed results or no relationship. 13 Further studies have done little to show how the child with terminal illness understands death, but have indicated that children with life threatening illnesses are aware of what is going on in their bodies, even when parents and caregivers try to conceal or withhold that information. 14 At this point, even with the studies that have been conducted on well children, dying children from other cultures, and dying adults we are left without a definite answer to how the child with illness or terminal illness may develop an understanding of death. However, on the studies that have been conducted, it is plausible that children who are terminally ill do have a more advanced notion and understanding of death. I suggest this, because it seems plausible that children who are constantly exposed to death and dying would be better able to grasp these concepts because they are no longer abstract concepts to them. These children have spent much of their time in an 12BIuebond-Langer, Myra. "Awareness and Communication In Terminally Ill Children: Pattern, Process, and Pretense," (Diss. University of Illinois, 1975). 13Fetch 1984 and Groolman 1990. as described by Speece, "The Development of Children's Understanding of Death” 49. 14Doka97. 9 institution. They make their friends on the hospital ward and their friends die there. These children hear about and witness death and are certainly affected by that. My intention is to shed light on the child living with terminal illness in an institution so that it is clear that their experiences do affect their understanding. With the help of the studies conducted in the past and careful consideration of how those studies may relate to the dying child, I plan to examine the following questions: should we, health care professionals, acknowledge that death is approaching for the child? Do children sense that they are dying, even without our explicit words? Do we rob children of their right to come to a finis (end) after having possessed an end (telos), if we do not tell them what they ask to know? Are children not able to make end of life decisions without accurate information? These questions seem to be of utmost importance, if we really want to help dying children. We must look at these questions, despite the confusion we have seen in the outcomes of various studies. And, we must decide what children need from us, so that they can reach their end. In the body of this thesis, I will suggest that honest relationships, that involve personal engagement, will provide the child an appropriate platform from which they can ask questions and receive honest answers. Work on Honesty in Health Care In order to talk about honest relationships we must take a look at Sissela Bok's book, Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life. 15 From this look at truthfulness, trust and the consequences of lying, we can come to some conclusions about the value of honest relationships. The next step will be to see if this relationship is possible in the medical setting. To establish this, we must turn our focus to philosophy and truth- telling in the medical setting. 15Bok, Sissela. Lying: Moral Choice in Public and Private Life, (New York: Pantheon Books, 1978). 10 In the world where doctors control the information and patients are only able to possess that information if the doctor chooses to disclose it to them, it is important to see if doctors do in fact disclose crucial information 16 and if they do not what are their reasons for not doing so. Until the 19608 the pattern was that doctors did not disclose information (88% of physicians followed this policy of nondisclosure) because they feared that patients rich with the knowledge about their terminal condition would "commit suicide, not cooperate with treatment or become depressed."l7 Interestingly enough at the same time a study, by Samp and Currei, that surveyed cancer patients and their families, showed that 87% believed that patients should be told their diagnosis and prognosis.18 It was not until the end of the 19703 that physicians started to change their beliefs about disclosure practices. At this point in time, 9896 of physicians reported that their usual policy was to tell patients their diagnosis.19 This is obviously quite a dramatic change from the 12% that had, the usual policy of disclosure in the 1960s. Unfortunately this dramatic change in disclosure practices only occurred if the patient was an adult. It turned out that physicians clearly had a different policy when it came to disclosure with a child patient. Novack, et al. found that 1896 of a sample of 16] suggest that crucial information is that about diagnosis and prognosis, but also any other Information that the patient might request. 17Beauchamp, Tom and Robert Veatch. Ethical Issues in Death and Dying. 2nd ed, (New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1996) 64. 18Samp, Robert and Anthony R. Currei. "A Questionnaire Survey on Public Cancer Education Obtained from Cancer Patients and their Families.” Cancer 10 ( 1957): 382. 19Novack, Dennis, Robin Plumer, Raymond Smith, Herbert Ochitill, Gary Marrow and John Bennett. " Changes in Physicians' Attitudes Toward Telling the Cancer Patient.” Journal of the AMA 241 (March 1979): 898. 11 219 physicians were less likely to tell children their diagnosis. 20 It seems that the reasons for this discrepancy in disclosure practices between adults and children had much to do with age, intelligence, and emOtional stability of the patient.21 These results are not surprising and are easy to understand, though it is not clear how physicians, in these studies, were able to gauge the intelligence or the emotional stability of patients. However much we look at the changes in the practice of disclosure it is clear that the children are left out of this movement. This may be due to the very protective nature we all seem to have toward children or may be just plain unfair to the young patient. Philosophers and lay persons stand on both sides of this issue about telling the available truth (for the standard reasons: see chapter 2). However, we notice again that we must look at this issue first from outside the realm of the child dying from a terminal illness. It is unfortunate that we must do that, but the reality is that, "although references to children sometimes occur in the context of discussions of particular topics, those who have proposed ethical theory have, by and large, ignored children."22 After a look at honest relationships and truth-telling in the medical setting, we will turn our attention to children and how they develop the skills to understand abstract concepts and how an honest and supportive relationship might benefit them. There is unfortunately a lack of literature available to begin this type of discussion. Therefore, I will spend much of this chapter laying out the important parts of cognitive development for all children and using some of the more salient ideas given to us by the nursing field. 20Novaclt, et al. 899. 21Novack, et al. 900. 22"Children and Ethical Theory." Encyclopedia of Ethics. 1992 ed., 137. 12 Work on the use of Literature in Communicating with Children Currently there is a lack of available information and studies that attempt to show the positive effect that literature may have on the dying child's understanding of death and dying. Therefore, this section of the thesis will draw from information on the use of literature in aiding the moral imagination of adults and the new biobliotherapy movement. Bloliotherapy is a tool to help people solve problems and show them that they are not the first to encounter such a problem, together with Martha Nussbaum's proposal that the literary imagination has some value in aiding our thinking about concepts that are abstract to us, points us to the notion that literature may have some value for the dying child. However, there is little literature designed to teach a child about their own death. It is clear that, despite the fact that some people have looked at the merits of literature, we are left with questions about the value literature has for the dying child. Along with looking at honest relationships, the possibility of such a relationship in the medical setting, cognitive development in children, and the value of children's literature, I will constantly be making it clear that the most important aspect of relationships with dying children may be the personal engagement that allows for honest answers to sometimes difficult questions. Chapter 2 WHAT'S 80 GREAT ABOUT THE TRUTH? What tormented Ivan llych most was the deception, the lie, which for some reason they all accepted, that he was not dying but was simply ill, and that he need keep quiet and undergo a treatment and then something very good would result. He however knew that nothing would come of it, only still more agonizing suffering and death. This deception tortured hime their not wishing to admit what they all knew and what he knew, but wanting to lie to him concerning his terrible condition, and wishing and forcing him to participate in that lie. Those lies- lies enacted over him on the eve of his death and destined to degrade this awful solemn act to the level of their visitings, their curtains, their sturgeon for dinner- were a terrible agony for Ivan llych. -Leo Tolstoy, The Death of [van llych. In this chapter we are going to take a look at the basic philosophical arguments for and against truth telling. This chapter will lay out the ground work for the next three chapters. Chapter 3 will deal with the nature and value of open relationships. Chapter 4 will look at the cognitive development of the dying child and make the claim that dying children may need the personal engagement set up in honest relationships. Finally, in chapter 5, the focus will turn to an appropriate tool that might aid in a dying child's understanding of death and dying. Now, we turn to truth. Recall that we must first look at truth without any discussion of children. later, we will have to ask if any of the reasons for telling or not telling the truth can be used to deal with dying children. To Tell the Truth On one side of the issue about the importance of truth-telling and its value, are those people who believe that it is simply wrong to lie. They claim that honesty is an inherent duty of morality and is not dependent on whether telling the lie or the truth l3 14 does any harm. 23 This is an absolutist position which says that telling the truth is always more important than the consequences of that truth. These people make the claim that to tell the truth is a duty. This means that in any relationship or practice the truth must be told or the practice fails. This way of looking at truth and its value may work in the world that has little to do with children and even less to do with Illness and dying. It goes too far for my purposes, but cannot be easily dismissed. We cannot dismiss this because in many situations a veracious person would be an ideal participant. Just imagine a situation where it was impossible to count on another person's word or action, and you can easily see how a person who is able to be honest, truthful and accurate would be ideal, at least in that respect. On the Other Side On the other extreme is the thought that people are entirely unable to handle any of the truth, but this view does not seem to be held by anyone who has a reasonable idea about the value of truth or the nature of human beings. Instead, people who disagree with the idea that the truth should be told no matter what the costs, tend to be very concerned about the possible negative consequences that disclosure might have. Most people who hold varying philosophical beliefs fit on the spectrum between telling the whole truth and complete nondisclosure. Here I will be discussing consequentialist ideas about truth telling, though there are also non-consequentialist ideas for this same type of limited disclosure. Sidgwick claims that the truth may cause harm and we must take that into consideration, but we must also ”weigh the gain of any deception against the 23’This is like the views expressed by Immanuel Kant. 15 lmperilment of mutual confidence involved in all violation of truth.” 24 He justifies such a statement on consequentialist grounds, and states that in order to act in the right way, we must compare the consequences of lying to those of not lying in each particular case. Others agree with Sidgwick when they claim that generally ”harms done by lying and failing to speak truthfully are greater than the expected gains."25 W.D. Ross agrees with Sidgwick's proposal that both duty and consequences matter.26 These philosophers and many more seem to all be saying something similar. They are stating a need for truth, but hold that truth need not be complete and is open to interpretation. Sissela Bok states that "the whole truth is out of reach. But this fact has very little to do with our choices about whether to lie or to speak honestly, about what we say and what we hold back.” 27 I agree completely: Complete information about illness and the processes the body would go through during that illness would be impossible information to give. 'However, giving known information in a completely truthful way is not absurd unless the patient cannot handle that information or does not want it. Additionally, if patients want and can handle the truth, then there must be some practical or operational reasons for telling the truth. These reasons have something to do with gaining patient cooperation and giving patients some kind of control of their lives. There is also the possibility that when patients are misinformed or lied to they lose complete trust in their practitioners and become suspicious of all the care that is given to them. 24Sidgwick, Henry. "The Classification of Duties of Veracity.” Methods of Ethics (1907),312. 25Cabot, Richard. ”The Use of Truth and Falsehood in Medicine: An Experimental Study." American Medicine 5 (1903) 344. 26 Ross, W.D. The Right and the Good, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930) 28. 2730k 4. 16 Another Important Question Here we are faced with a completely new question. Do patients really want to know the truth? Experts stand on both sides of this issue as well. Some say that patients do in fact want the truth and the harm that might result from such disclosure is much less than physicians think.28 Others say that falsehoods may be wrong, but full disclosure is not needed and that the physician has a right to withhold information from the patient for the good of that patient.29 Along these lines, some experts note that even when the patient seeks the truth, this may be the last thing that they really want. 30 So far we are left with a dilemma. We still are not aware of what value truth telling might have for children and we still are unaware of what patients want. The statements and arguments on both sides of the issue are pretty convincing and none of them can be easily dismissed. Up until nowwe have been looking at adult patients, for which the increasing ethical consensus is that the truth should be made available. However, there. remains disagreement about the degree of truth that should be given and the detail with which information should be supplies. Now we will turn our focus to the child dying from a terminal illness and decide which arguments and statements fit that situation best. 288olt 13. 29Worthington, Hooker. Physician and Patient: Or, a Practical View of the Mutual Duties, Relations and Interests of the Medical Profession and Community, (New York: Baker and Schribbner, 1849). 359. Recall that this was written well before the doctrine of Informed consent. 30 Meyer, Bernard. "Truth and the Physician." In Ethical Issues in Medicine: The Role of the Physician in Today's Society, ed. 13. Fuller Torrey, (New York: Little Brown and Company, 1968) 167. 17 Do These Reasons Fit For Children? Lantos makes it clear that we are now moving into practically uncharted territory with his statement, "as with most modern bioethics paradigms, all bets are off when it comes to pediatrics." 31 He is right about this, but then makes the claim that, "if it is a good thing to tell children the truth, it is not for the same practical or operational reasons we tell adults."32 I disagree, however his thinking is in line with the idea that children are going through similar, but not the same, things as adults when they face death. However, if we come to the conclusion that it is our moral duty to tell adults at least some of the truth, then we must want to gain their cooperation or empower them and give them some control of their lives. I believe that these are at least three good reasons to tell the truth to adults and may be the same reasons for telling children the truth. It seems as if it is important that children, as well as adults, cooperate with their practitioners, continue to have some control over their lives, and have some sense of responsibility about their health care. Sissela Bok points out that "some level of truthfulneSs has always been seen as essential to human society." 33 I take this to mean that this truthfulness is essential to all members of human society. Our human society does include dying children who may have the same need to hear the truth that adults possess. I am not advocating full disclosure. I am sure that in some cases the complete complex truth could have devastating effects. Imagine a scenario in which the child begins to ask questions about their illness, but not about death. In this situation, if they were told that they are about to die, then that might devastate the child and make them 31Lantos, John. "Should we Always Tell Children the Truth?" In Perspectives in Biology and Medicine (Autumn 1996), ed. Richard Iandu, et al. (Illinois: University of Chicago Press, 1996) 84. 32Lantos 84. 33Bok 18. 18 less willing to cooperate with future medical procedures. I am also convinced that if we truly want a child to participate in their medical care then we must give them information. Doka writes, "if the child is going to have a sense of participation and control in the illness, he or she will need to know what ls wrong and what is likely to occur." 34 We are practically convinced that adults need this control and have a right to make choices about their lives and their deaths. Why is that not the case for children? Aside from the fact that some people have come to believe that "generally minors below the ages of 1 1-13 do not possess many of the cognitive capacities one would associate with the psychological elements of intelligent consent." 35 My fear is that the only true reason we fail to disclose to children dying from a terminal illness is that it is really hard to be emotionally superficial when everyone is aware of the truth. It hardly seems clear that children have no need or want of the truth. What does seem clear is that, "adults own difficulties in dealing with the deaths of children probably underlies their inclination to withhold information from children."36 I believe that the only conclusions that we can draw from the studies done and the arguments laid out by experts in their field is that there are truly, ”no established criteria as to how much to tell children."37 Though I think, in light of the idea that children dying from a terminal illness may have knowledge about disease that surpasses the knowledge a well child may have (an idea expressed fully in chapter four) and keeping in mind that I am not advocating full disclosure, it is fairly possible to see a need for health care professionals to give "straight answers to straight 34Dol