an “mm cu z. . ( Esau—WW pm“... ‘ . .3 . ‘ . ‘ v, u 'u . ‘ y?!) ‘ uh , 3:43. : u .. fr.» 5 . a “J? V. 1531.»; , 4.2%., .63 E . a: K; #3.? 9 a «nix: “a x “$3 . ‘ 13.2» x . dz. 4.. { , a» .1. umwvrng‘vflwhym :rh. 'Il . : ‘ V 4...: . w 1 1;? L... z. ,3... L ..f 7.11.. I. . c¢1.‘3I \, ML: . fiwfifi mafia; THs-‘mg This is to certify that the dissertation entitled Sincerity and Reading: Dilemmas in Constructivism presented by Michael J. Pardales has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for Ph.D. Educational Psychology degree in David Nanak Major professor U rho/0t MS U i: an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution 0- 12771 I LIBRARY ' Michigan State ; University ! __j PLACE IN RETURN BOX to remove this checkout from your record. To AVOID FINES return on or before date due. MAY BE RECALLED with earlier due date if requested. DATE DUE DATE DUE DATE DUE “irritant 6/01 cJCIRC/DateDuepfis-sz SINCERITY AND READING: DILEMMAS IN CONSTRUCTIVISM By Michael J. Pardales A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Counseling, Educational Psychology, and Special Education 200 l Abstract SINCERITY AND READING: DILEMMAS IN CONSTRUCTIVISM BY Michael J. Pardales In an attempt to understand the way social and individual forms of constructivism might manifest themselves in classroom practice, this dissertation studies the theoretical discourse over constructivism in education, and, empirically studies the shift in one teacher’s praxis as he moves from an individual constructivist pedagogy to a social constructivist pedagogy, in middle school philosophical inquiry classes. Since this is a study of my teaching, this work is, in part, a self-study of teaching practice. While there has been theorizing about the ways individual constructivism translates into pedagogy, social constructivists do not say much about the specifics of teaching and learning as they are mostly engaged in postmodern critiques of modern epistemology. This leads me to ask the following questions: 1) How does a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy differ (for the teacher) from a modern form of constructivism? 2) How does a teacher trying to enact a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy remain faithful to both subject matter content and their students’ ideas, experiences, and developing understandings? 3) What role does “community of inquiry” play in modern and postmodern forms of social constructivism? Two significant dilemmas appeared through my study of the discourse and practice of social and individual forms of constructivism. First, taking a constructivist stance towards teaching can create an illusion for a teacher committed to a discipline based pedagogy. This illusion can make a teacher think he is being more humane to his students when he may be seducing them into learning what he was going to teach them anyway. This introduces the issues of sincerity into the discourse over constructivist teaching by examining what of a teacher’s pedagogical motivations he is obliged to reveal to his students. Second, the empirical study raised questions about the enterprise of reading in constructivist classrooms. These questions lead to a revealing discussion about the purposes of reading beyond exegesis in constructivist classrooms. Copyright by Michael James Pardales 2001 To Stacey and Isabella, whose patience, love, and support make everything possible ACKNOWLEDGMENT S I would like to thank David Wong, the director of this dissertation and my advisor; his steady confidence and interest in this project made it possible. Steve Weiland hired me to be his graduate assistant six years ago, and helped me transition to the college of education from philosophy. I would like to thank David Pearson: all of my interactions with you have been to my benefit. I would like to thank Helen Featherstone whose interest, kindness, and support always came at the right time. Mark Girod and I had many conversations about our dissertations over pizza at Georgio’s; these conversations, and our relationship, were vital. Gina Cervetti and I have been collaborating since we met, and it is this collaboration which inspired the topic of this dissertation. My parents have never given me anything but support, even when I told them 10 years ago that I was going to study philosophy. They made most of the good things in my life possible. And thanks to Paul, Andrea, Amy, Erin, and Kevin who always asked how things were going and assumed vi only the best. And “thank you” to Mom and Dad Lamparter, for the people you are; I've learned much from you. Also, my grandmother — sharp, caring, and always encouraging. I am indebted to all of the students who participated in philosophy over the last three summers, and to the administrator's of the Dimensions program. The following people have all been important to me, and I cannot begin to detail in how many different ways (in alphabetical order): Greg Alexander, Martin Benjamin, James Damico, Matt Ebert, Carol Sue Englert, Steve Esquith, Tanna Girod, Bill Hoaglin, Carolyn Jaynes, Rachel Lander, Matt Lipman, Dick Prawat, Cheryl Rau, Shari Levine Rose, Ann Schulte, Jack Smith, Brandon Stallard, and Valerie Worthington. vfi TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER ONE INTRODUCTION Constructivism. . . . . Individual/Psychological Constructivism. .1 6 Criticisms of Individual/Psychological Constructivism. Social Constructivism. Criticisms of Social Constructivism. . Critique of Social Constructivist Teaching Modernism and Postmodernism Postmodern Social Constructivist Pedagogy. Broad Purpose of this Dissertation. CHAPTER TWO INTRODUCTION C. S. Peirce and Community of Inquiry. Community of Inquiry in Philosophy for Children. Mechanisms of Community Formation in P4C. Other Understandings of Community of Inquiry. Community of Inquiry and This Dissertation CHAPTER THREE. Methodology. . . . Data Collection and analysis. Description of Teacher's Stance. CHAPTER FOUR INTRODUCTION. Analysis 1: Treatment of Text. Analysis 2: Opening Day. Analysis 3: Topics of Discussion. CHAPTER FIVE vfii 10 .12 .14 .17 23 .32 34 37 .38 .45 51 56 .60 63 .63 69 .71 .77 .78 .98 .109 DISCUSSION. A Look to This Summer’s Philosophy Class Concluding Remarks. REFERENCES . ix 118 133 134 138 LI ST OF TABLES Table l - Analysis of Discussion Topics (p. 111) Chapter 1 Introduction In this chapter I will examine issues relating to individual and social forms of constructivism, modernism and postmodernism. My purpose is to review the various forms of constructivism and their connections to modernism and postmodernism, corresponding views of teaching, and then consider the relationships between pedagogy and purpose. Constructivism There are terms used in specific discourses that take on almost transcendental status as they get defined, redefined, and used in many different ways in the service of influencing, arguing, questioning and the like. In educational parlance, “constructivism” is one of these terms. Constructivism is used in many different ways. There are constructivist learning theories, world views, teaching methods, theories of cognition and more. In his introduction to the NSSE yearbook, Constructivism in Education, D.C. Phillips (1999) offers an initial distinction in an attempt to begin mapping out the broad landscape of constructivism. He distinguishes between constructivism as “a thesis about the disciplines or bodies of knowledge that have been built up during the course of human history (p. 6)”, and constructivism as “a set of views about how individuals learn (and about how those who help them to learn ought to teach) (p. 7).” While this is a sweeping cut in the landscape, it is an important distinction that I will make use of. It is interesting to note that Phillips has divided the constructivist landscape, roughly, in terms of individual and social sorts, corresponding to an individual/social distinction. Next, I will briefly consider some of the ideas which helped contemporary constructivist discourse take shape, and then attend to some broader characterizations of constructivism which fall on either side of Phillips’ distinction. Within the broad domain of constructivism, there are many places one could begin an analysis of important philosophical influences. I will deal specifically with Kant and Wittgenstein. Kant can be given credit for synthesizing the dominant world views of empiricism (starting with Locke), and rationalism (starting with Descartes), and can also be considered one of the seminal theorizers of constructivist epistemology (Bredo, 2000, p. 128). Kant argued that neither the empiricist nor rationalist traditions adequately dealt with the subject of how individuals make sense of the world. While classical empiricists struggled with how the mind receives (constructs) experiential knowledge from the outside world, rationalists struggled with how the mind reasons about (constructs) an apparently given world. In the empiricist View, we find an emphasis on experience, and in the rationalist View we find an emphasis on reason. Kant sought to synthesize the two Views by claiming that the mind is predisposed to organize experience in a particular way because of its fundamental organizing categories of space, time, causation, and substance. Howe and Berv (2000) sum this up nicely, Kant’s View exemplifies a true constructivist View because it is more thoroughgoing. . .It denies that there can be any Egg sensory experience that the mind takes as given and then performs its formal operations on (empiricism). Alternatively, conceptual schemes are not pgrg (rationalism), but have meaning only as they construct experience. (p. 21) It is important to note the influence Kant had on Piaget here. Piaget adopted the Kantian categories, and experimented and theorized on the developmental unfolding of these categories in children. While I will say more about this later, for now suffice it to say that Kant was one of the key figures in the development of individual/psychological constructivism and dictated some of the very terms key psychological constructivists (like Piaget) used in developing their theories of learning and development. The linguistic turn in philosophy (Rorty, 1992; 1991) placed language, as opposed to experience, as the new unit of analysis in theorizing about mind and knowledge. One of the key figures in this turn was Ludwig Wittgenstein. The later work of Wittgenstein was radical both in its form (Wittgenstein wrote in an aphoristic style), and in its claims about the traditional projects of epistemology. Wittgenstein believed that to understand anything about mind or knowledge we must understand something about how language works. He posited the notion that how we talk about things dramatically effects how we learn and understand because how we talk about things is governed by rgles, or, forms of life (Wittgenstein, 1953). That is, we learn about happiness, pain, knowledge, etc. by participating in language games where key terms are used in particular ways. An example of a language game would be the practice of a discipline like chemistry. Chemists use the particular nomenclature of the discipline and the corresponding actions (laboratory practices and scholarship) to constitute the practice of the language game of chemistry. One becomes a chemist by using the language and performing the actions (participating in the form of life) of the chemistry discipline. The thinking of both Kant and Wittgenstein influenced the way constructivist epistemology took shape. Kant, through his synthesis of rationalism and empiricism, forced us to think about the human experience in the world as a experience shaped by particularly human categories of understanding. Wittgenstein helped introduce language as the new unit of analysis and shifted the emphasis of construction away from experience to discourse. Other scholars have given more thorough accounts of the philosophical underpinnings of constructivist thinking (Steffe & Gale, 1995; Elgin, 1997). Given Phillips general distinction between constructivism as either a thesis about the bodies of knowledge of human creation, or a set of views about how individuals learn (and teach), some general comments about constructivism can be offered along those lines. Individual/Psychological Constructivism Ken Strike (1987) has said, “the claim that people are active in learning or knowledge construction is rather uninteresting because no one, beyond a few aberrant behaviorists, denies it” (p. 483). This statement contains one of the most basic tenets of individual constructivism, that people are active in learning/knowledge construction. In trying to consider strains of constructivism that start from individual/psychological concerns, we must consider the work of Jean Piaget. As mentioned earlier, Piaget was heavily influenced by Kant, and took Kant’s categories as an important starting place for his theorizing about learning and development. Piaget’s genetic epistemology can be understood as a theory about how innate structures of knowledge develop as the individual matures and interacts in the world (Piaget and Inhelder 1969, Piaget, 1954). Fundamental to this is the process of equilibration, which entails the processes of accommodation and assimilation. Piaget believed that cognitive structures develop as individuals assimilate new information, situate new information (accommodation), and reach subsequent stages of equilibrium. This process is brought about when, through one’s interactions in the world, one’s cognitive understandings meet with conflicting information (cognitive dissonance). In general, Piaget’s theory of genetic epistemology and his account of learning and development have been criticized as overly individualistic, relying too much on a rationalistic world view (Bruner, 1985). However, his ideas have had great influence on constructivist thinking and have infused such notions as prior knowledge into the discourse of education (Leinhardt, 1992). Piaget’s work has greatly influenced another theory of individual/psychological constructivism, Ernst Von Glasersfeld’s (1995) theory of radical constructivism. McCarty and Schwandt state that, “Von Glasersfeld’s views on the fine details of constructing derive from a careful reading of Piagetian developmental theory on which a child builds up concepts and cognitive schemes by isolating different experiences and treating them as equal or near equal (p. 45).” For von Glasersfeld, individuals engage in an unending series of constructions that the individual either accepts and makes use of, or rejects based on the viability of these constructions for their life purposes. That is, the individual only has knowledge of whether their constructions work in the world and never directly knows or experiences anything outside of his own constructions (Von Glasersfeld, 1991). As McCarty and Schwandt (2000) state, Von Glasersfeld does not deny extra—mental existence outright (and, on this point, joins forces with Kant against Berkeley and Hume), but prefers to insist that external reality cannot be known. What remains of knowledge for the constructivist extends no further than the edges of the individual mind.(p. 44) From these constructivist views of individual learning, corresponding views of pedagogy can be extrapolated as well. Howe and Berv (2000) identified two premises of constructivist learning theory as, (1) learning takes as its starting point the knowledge, attitudes, and interests students bring to the learning, and (2) learning results from the interaction between these characteristics and experiences in such a way that learners construct their own understanding, from the inside, as it were.(p. 31) Both of these premises have a direct lineage to Piaget's work. Beyond these premises of constructivist learning theory Howe and Berv identify two parallel premises of constructivist teaching. The first premise states that instruction must begin by considering the knowledge, attitudes, and beliefs that learners bring to a learning situation (p. 31). The second premise is, that “instruction must be designed so as to provide experiences that effectively interact with these characteristics of students so they may construct their own understandings (p. 31).” Interestingly enough, nothing in these premises reveals anything about a learner’s relationship to a discipline, or about a learners relationship to other learners. These are truly premises of individual learning. These points give a fair characterization of some basic constructivist beliefs about individual learning and teaching. Criticisms of Individual/Psychological Constructivism Matthews (2000) summarizes what he believes to be the main contributions of constructivism at the same time qualifying these contributions as not of purely constructivist inspiration, Constructivism has done a service to science and mathematics education by alerting teachers to the function of prior learning and extant concepts in the process of learning new material, by stressing the importance of understanding as a goal of science instruction, by fostering pupil engagement in lessons, and other such progressive matters. But liberal educationists can rightly say that these are pedagogical commonplaces, the recognition of which goes back to Socrates. . .Constructivism has also done a service by making educators aware of the human dimension of science, its fallibility, its connections to culture and interests, the place of convention in scientific theory, the historicity of concepts, the complex procedures of theory appraisal, and much else. But again realist philosophers can rightly maintain that constructivism does not have a monopoly on these insights. (p.187) 10 Matthews also suggests that the influence of constructivism has resulted, in part, in a substitution of terms. For example, he contrasts what he calls “Orthodox Old Speak” with “Constructivist New Speak”, in the following translations: learning = construction of knowledge, theory = scheme, graphs = mediational tools, writing = discourse, education 2 cognitive apprenticeship, paying attention = student engagement, etc., (p. 182). Howe and Berv (2000) point out the basic premises that constructivist thinking has introduced regarding learning and teaching (those of individual constructivism), but there are those who believe that reform oriented teachers, whether they profess a commitment to constructivism or not, enact such premises of teaching and learning all the time (Ball and Bass, 2000; Solomon, 2000). While on one hand the contributions of constructivism seem to be noteworthy, they may not be the contributions of constructivism alone. Also, as Matthews (2000) points out, one can enact constructivist premises of teaching without being a constructivist: he gives Plato’s Meno, specifically Socrates work with the slave-boy, as an example of constructivist teaching ll informed by an epistemology that is not really constructivist (p. 187). This suggests that constructivists who enact premises of individual learning and teaching have reintroduced some ideas that have been around for a long time (many which can be associated with progressivism), and have mildly supported teaching practices that are often enacted by reform—oriented teachers anyway. Social Constructivism There are also some basic statements that characterize social constructivist views about the bodies of disciplinary knowledge that humans have come to work within. Phillips (2000) summarizes the view of “Strong Program” sociologists who believe that disciplinary knowledge “can be fully explained, and accounted for, in sociological terms (p.8).” That is, knowledge, in any field, is constructed by sociological forces of ideology, religion, human interests, political influence, and the like (Phillips, 2000, p. 9; Bloor, 1976; Woolgar 1988). Kenneth Gergen’s (1994) Social Constructionism is one of 12 the more coherent views about the social construction of knowledge and reality. Gergen believes that, 1” The terms by which we account for the world and ourselves are not dictated by the stipulated objects of such accounts. 2.’Fhe terms and forms by which we achieve understanding of the world and ourselves are social artifacts, products of historically and culturally situated interchanges among people. Z3.The degree to which a given account of the world or self is sustained across time is not dependent on the objective validity of the account but the vicissitudes of social processes. 4.Ianguage derives its significance in human affairs from the way in which it functions within patterns of relationship.(p. 48—52) This View is different than other social constructivist views as it mostly ignores metaphysical talk of reality in favor or a focus on microsocial processes (p. 69). Though, I agree with McCarty and Schwandt (2000) who point out that Gergen (and Von Glasersefeld) can be criticized for smuggling in talk about knowledge and reality even though he denies these charges. Vygotsky’s (1978) Cultural—Historical theory spans both sides of Phillips’ broad distinction. Vygotsky proposes mechanisms by which individuals internalize 13 thought and the broader norms of culture by participation in linguistic communities. He also proposes a theory of human development along onto and phylo genetic lines that accounts for the broader development of the species. Bredo (2000) summarizes Vygotsky’s place in this landscape and elaborates in a way that illuminates this side of Phillips distinction, Vygotsky can be viewed as a constructivist because he considered basic forms (and contents) of minds to be socially constructed (and constructing). He Viewed symbolically mediated thought as a social process, like a dialogue, that is “internalized” through participation in social interaction. . .As Russia modernized, for example, people’s ways of thinking changed to become more formal-logical as a result of schooling and other experiences. Seen in this way, society is not just an environmental variable or a content that one learns about. Rather, modern social life creates the very form of modern minds. (p. 133) Criticisms of Social Constructivism The side of Phillips' distinction that does not talk about views of individual learning is concerned with the bodies of knowledge that have been constructed by humans throughout history (disciplinary knowledge that is). The wars over epistemology in educational theory over the last 14 twenty years have been largely due to social constructivist criticisms of disciplinary knowledge as not reflective of some external reality, but as constructions dependent upon such things as power, particular discursive communities, and ideology. In part, these critiques have been inspired by neopragmatists and poststructuralists philosophical critiques of modern epistemology. This has led to debates within education, like the “science wars” (Slezak, 2000) between those who uphold the legitimacy of the modern world View and preeminence of science, and those who believe science to be claiming foundations it cannot support. However, these debates mirror, and draw upon, the debates in philosophy between realists like Popper and Fodor, and neopragmatists and poststructuralists like Rorty, Derrida, and Foucault. This kind of constructivism does not have as its primary focus, teaching and learning. There are general statements made that resist authoritarian forms of teaching, and a call for communal learning and dialogue, but no detailed accounts of what teaching as a postmodern social constructivist might look like (McCarty and Schwandt, 2000). So, it would seem that social IS constructivist theorizing, with its powerful critiques of foundationalism and the modern world View, offers no significant prescription for teaching and learning, and mostly mirrors the long standing debate in philosophy. Thousands of pounds of paper and gallons of ink have been used by educational theorists in recreating the philosophical debate between realists and those espousing non—realist (often postmodern) theories. Burbules (2000) brings a note of clarity to these debates, In short, realists on this issue are more likely to think that knowledge can be objective, complete, and unchanging, and that knowledge disputes can be settled by allusions to “the way the world is.” Constructivists and others who reject that premise are more likely to think that knowledge will be partial, provisional, and imperfect, and that knowledge disputes will be more intractable because strongly held beliefs are intertwined with other social and cultural elements that groups may be reluctant to give up or change. Who is right on this issue? I hope to have made it clear that the question cannot be answered at that level; bgth positions tend to prejudge what sorts of social agreement will or will not be possible, and they use claims about “reality” (one way or another) to undergird what are really premises about the likelihood of being able to settle certain types of disagreement. (p. 317-318) What Burbules is suggesting is that the debates on this side of the constructivist landscape are of little use to 16 educators and have more to do with matters of temperament than anything productive for thinking about teaching and learning. He echoes this claim when he gives his view, which I agree with, on the metaphysical war between social constructivists and their critics, On the issue of metaphysics, we come to the timeless philosophical question about the independent existence of an external world. I have given long and careful thought to this problem, and I would like to propose a seriously considered response: Who cares? The question of the existence of an external world is, I believe, one of those philosophical pseudo—questions that are not answerable in the terms given. . .It expresses an article of faith rather than a demonstrable philosophical postulate, and as with other faith it is not interesting to ask whether or not, but only why people believe it and effects their belief has. (p. 317—318) I accept Burbules’ criticisms and think it wise the topic of conversation to ones of importance practical effect. Critique of Social Constructivist Teaching articles of it is true what to change and Some of the criticisms made of both kinds of constructivism point to a real problem for educators. If one is charged with the responsibility of teaching a well defined set of facts/concepts, say in Biology, 17 Algebra, or American history, how does one balance that responsibility with staying committed to helping students construct their own knowledge and understandings? This question has been wrestled with by several scholars working with constructivist ideas within the context of disciplinary teaching (Ball, 1993; Ball and Chazan 1999; Rose, 1999; Yackel, Cobb, and Wood 1991). These studies have shown that there is a place for constructivist premises of teaching within the teaching of a discipline, but, that the disciplines have their own requirements for what counts as legitimate, contested, appropriate, etc. As Ball and Bass (2000) point out, As children engage with interesting mathematical problems, they produce different solution strategies and solutions. Quite often, however, classes end with no comparative inspection of these. Instead, multiple representations, methods, and solutions are left to uneasy coexistence, implying either a mathematically unverified equivalence, or the message that multiple solutions simply exist, much like multiple interpretations of text. But the disciplines of mathematics and literary interpretation differ, and the imperative to inspect and compare multiple ideas is central to mathematics. (p. 199) While I think that there is an imperative to inspect and compare in any subject, I take from Ball and Bass that some 18 of the premises of individual constructivist teaching can open up spaces for dialogue and inquiry within what are sometimes thought of as air-tight spaces (mathematics teaching); also, that the opening of space for dialogue and inquiry must be accompanied by a certain rigor dictated by the specifics of the discipline. But this points to a potential disconnect when a teacher has content that they “have” to “get” to the students, yet, they want students to construct their own knowledge. Smith, et al. (1993) skillfully point this out in their criticism of misconceptions research. It seems that in many cases the attempt to apply constructivist premises of teaching within disciplines has taken the form of trying to relieve and replace students misconceptions, which, as Smith et a1. point out, is not very constructivist. Sexias (1993) points out this discrepancy in relation to the teaching of history, Even where alternative interpretations of the past are presented, they are conveyed with the authority of a community of which the students are not a part. .rather the voice of the historical text systematically excludes them. If the constructivist theories are right, there is not much room for real learning here. If the philosophers of hiStory are 19 right, there is not much real history, either (p. 314). In the examples of disciplinary teaching cited above we see students working in communities, with the teacher playing an important role as leader and moderator. The students are given the space necessary to explore their reasoning with one another with the result that students often engaged in similar activities to their professional counterparts in the disciplines (Ball, 2000; Rose, 1999). That is, students reasoned in mathematically (in Ball, and Cobb et al.) and historically (in Rose’s case) sophisticated ways that sometimes resembled the kinds of moves mathematicians and historians make. These teachers consider and make use of their students’ attitudes, beliefs and understandings, and use these to foster a lively discourse around the subject matter they are teaching. They also use a more communal organization as opposed to a more didactic style. Ball and Chazan (1999) and Rose (1999) skillfully illustrate the tensions constructivist teachers face as they try to balance student understanding and lively discourse with the demands of subject matter knowledge their students need to know. While the level of student engagement is remarkable, 20 and they have fascinating conversations that defy what many believe students capable of, perhaps this is a more humane way of seducing students into learnigggwhat states, districts, and teachers want them to know? Wouldn’t a serious attempt at trying to teach in a social constructivist way demand that teachers not just use premises of individual constructivism as a different way to “get” the content of a course through to students? Doesn’t taking both sides of the constructivist distinction Phillips makes require a different, more critical stance towards disciplinary thinking? Doesn’t more need to be made of the understandings students construct, knowledge in general, and issues of authority and power, etc.? The disciplinary attempts at teaching in a social constructivist way, while they have many positive things to teach us about the kinds of thinking and inquiry students are capable of within disciplines, while they are skillfully enacting the premises of individual constructivist teaching and should and can be held up as exemplary cases in skillful constructivist teaching in inquiry oriented environments, wrongly identify what they 21 are doing “social constructivism”. I am not saying that this teaching is not constructivist, it is. I am suggesting that it is more akin to individual constructivism or sociocultural theory than social constructivism. If we take Phillips distinction, and look at the some of the premises of social constructivism, we see that these teacher/researchers are not enacting the beliefs of social constructivism. In fact, the social constructivist discourse discussed above has very little to say about pedagogy. It is possible constructivist teaching has not gone far enough in attempting to employ more of its philosophical tenets in the realm of pedagogy? It would seem that outside of the research on disciplinary teaching cited above, which is really more sociocultural than social constructivist, we have few examples of what taking a postmodern constructivism seriously, would look like. Wouldn’t we be doing something different than trying to find a more humane way to get students to know what we want them too? This analysis suggests that the contribution of constructivism, especially the side of Phillips’ distinction having to do 22 with views of how individuals learn and how people should teach, has mostly been a cognitivization of the idea that we should listen to what students think and encourage them to work together so we can better teach them what we were going to teach them anyway. Also, it suggests that we have not seen a more thoroughgoing social constructivism that incorporates its postmodern, philosophical points into pedagogy. Modernism.and Postmodernism In the 1996 special issue of The Educational Psychologist, Richard Prawat identifies six constructivisms and undertakes the task of organizing these six views into two camps, one modern the other postmodern. The distinction between modernism and postmodernism, for Prawat, lies in the epistemology of each of the two groups. The difference between the modern and postmodern epistemologies is, the postmodern views, “refute the assumptions that knowledge is primarily the property of individuals and that, if it is to have any claim on our allegiance, it must be the product of a foolproof inferential system (p. 215).” The modern 23 constructivisms Prawat identifies are Radical Constructivism and Information Processing. The postmodern constructivisms he identifies are Sociocultural theory, Symbolic Interactionism, Social Constructionism, and his own, “idea-based social constructivism” which is supported by the thinking of Peirce and Dewey. In the constructivist literature reviewed thus far, knowledge (and to some extent, reality) is a key issue. But the lines cannot be drawn quite as cleanly as Prawat suggests. For example, McCarty and Schwandt (2000) put Von Glasersfeld’s radical constructivism squarely in the postmodern camp because of its refusal to speak of reality and knowledge as anything but personal constructions. And while Sociocultural theory, specifically Vygotsky’s Cultural-Historical theory, and Symbolic Interactionism, the view of Mead, have distinctive postmodern elements (the way they ignore mind/world, inside/outside binaries, and focus on language), they also have commitments that would classify them as modern in orientation (their developmental theory and taking of reality as essentially given). The lines between different forms of constructivism quickly get 24 blurry, and trying to differentiate the pedagogical, let alone the epistemological, elements of modern and postmodern constructivisms is difficult. So, I will attempt an analysis of modern and postmodern discourse that will help bring into relief different aspects of what a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy might look like. This analysis will help us answer the questions posed above as to what a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy would need to entail. So, let us move to consider the discourse over modernism and postmodernism. This will help us better understand what difference these differences make, and will suggest what the important differences means to educational enactments of social constructivism. Discussion about modernism and postmodernism is contentious. Neither term designates a particular theory or a comprehensive philosophy. While we can identify certain beliefs and values as modern or postmodern, no description or attribution is final or definitive. Even the words modern, postmodern, modernity, postmodernity, have contested meanings and uses (Usher and Edwards, 1994). On this point, Usher and Edwards (1994) state, 25 To talk about postmodernity, postmodernism, or the postmodern is not therefore to designate some fixed and systematic ‘thing’. Rather, it is to use a loose umbrella term under whose broad cover can be encompassed at one and a the same time a condition, a set of practices, a cultural discourse, an attitude and a mode of analysis. (p. X) My tack will be to lay out some thoughtful descriptions of these terms in an effort to paint, in broad brush strokes, postmodernism in contrast to modernism in a way that will render a fuller account of social constructivist teaching and learning.1 Modernism can be used to describe a historical period and corresponding world views beginning with the Renaissance and Enlightenment, and leading into the 19th and 20th centuries. John McGowan (1991) describes events connected to the Enlightenment that helped create the conditions of the modern world, The challenge to Catholicism by various protestant sects, the challenge to Eurocentrism in the discovery of radically different societies in other parts of the globe, the challenge to religion manifested in both new scientific discoveries and new economic practices, the challenge to monarchy/oligarchy in the rise of popular, democratic agitation, and the challenge of traditional patterns of social lFor expanded treatments of the discussion over Modernism and Postmodernism see, Usher and Edwards 1994; Best and Kellner, 1991; Jameson 1991; Featherstone 1991; Hassan 1987; Smart 1992. 26 integration in changing modes of production and distribution and the growth of towns and cities all combine over a three—hundred-year period (1500—1800) to transform Europe. By the end of this period, the West has recognized, in the face of diversity and change, that it is thrown back upon itself to ground, legitimate, and make significant its own practices. (p. 4) Challenges to traditional forms of authority and knowing created the conditions from which a new View of the world would emerge. Vaclav Havel (1992, Quoted in Cherryholmes 1999) communicated some of the spirit of the modern world View in a speech he delivered to the United Nations: The modern era has been dominated by the culminating belief that the world. . .is a wholly knowable system governed by a finite number of universal laws that man can grasp and rationally direct for his own benefit. This era, beginning in the Renaissance and developing from the Enlightenment to socialism, from positivism to scientism, from the Industrial Revolution to the information revolution, was characterized by rapid advances in rational, cognitive thinking. This, in turn gave rise to the proud belief that man, as the pinnacle of everything that exists, was capable of objectively describing, explaining and controlling everything that exists, and of possessing the one and only truth about the world. It was an era in which there was a cult of depersonalized objectivity, and era in which objective knowledge was amassed and technologically exploited, an era of belief in automatic progress brokered by the scientific method. It was an era of systems, ideologies, doctrines, interpretations, of reality, an era in which the goal was to find a universal theory of the world, and thus a universal key to unlock its prosperity. (p. 15) 27 The modern world is very much the world we still live in. The preeminence of scientific method is palpable. This preeminence, as Havel noted, is fueled by the desire to explain, predict, and control as mankind continues to progress via the technological advancement and control of nature and self. In the modern world View, the individual (especially the individual mind) is the preferable unit of analysis, and is conceived of as a unified, autonomous, subject with a stable identity. These dispositions, and View of the self, it is assumed, helps us get along in our world. It is precisely these drives that postmodernists criticize as being the product of a scientistic View of the world. Feminist scholars have pointed out that these drives have a basis in gender differences (Harding, 1987). It is this world that many theorists believe to be in transition: transition to a world “after” modernity, that is, “post” modernity. Cherryholmes outlines this transition with regard to education, For much of the twentieth century, efforts to describe, explain and prescribe theories and practices of education have been couched in a modernist rhetoric that has highlighted rationality, hierarchy, 28 expertise, accountability, and differentiation in order to promote progress and productivity. .Modernism and rationality assume distinctions between logic and rhetoric, planning and spontaneity, text and context. Empiricism granted a central role to logic validating theories, practices and discourses. . .We are required to abandon a logic/rhetoric distinction, however, because of developments in modern logic. .The effect for educators and others is that we are forced to think about the world in a way that relies less on logic to validate our conceptions and more on rhetoric to persuade ourselves and others about the world and how it operates. (p. 91) The “post” in “postmodern” attaches to other areas that go along with this purported shift. Analytic philosophy transitions to postanalytic philosophy; Structuralism in linguistics transitions to poststructuralism, and colonialism transitions into postcolonialism. That is, each of these movements develops in reaction to an established tradition, as opposed to an apriori justification based on a new epistemology or metaphysic (Cherryholmes, 1999, p. 89). For example, certain poststructural criticism made by Derrida, of the structural linguistics of Levi—Strauss, involve Derrida’s using the very logic of structuralism to show its inconsistency and ambiguity. He does this by showing how Levi—Strauss’ use of the binary nature/culture deconstructs: within Levi-Strauss’ own studies one can find 29 phenomena that fall into both the natural and the cultural (Derrida, 1974/1997, p. 101—2). This means that what is considered postmodern, or entailed in any of the “posts”, was, in some measure, already present in what came before it. As Natoli and Hutcheon (1993) state, “Postmodern paradox, ambiguity, irony, indeterminacy, and contingency are seen to replace modern closure, unity, order, the absolute, and the rational (p. ix).” In many ways, postmodernism arose out of modernism. Thus, postmodernism can be seen as a reaction to modern projects and views of the world. While it cannot be labeled as only a particular time, logic, argument, architecture, or theory, it can be thought of as all of these things, and more. As Usher and Edwards state, The postmodern moment . . .can therefore be seen as a celebration and tolerance of pluralism, and difference leading to a much more ambivalent and less fixed positioning of subjectivity. The self and subjectivity can no longer be thought of as unified and coherent but ‘decentered’. . .the ‘centered’ subject does not exist naturally and preformed but is rather a cultural construct, inscribed by the meaning system that is language and by discourses, particular and systematic uses of language. . .As the postmodern problematises the logic of naming, representation and language, so the constitutive power of language is foregrounded. .Being located in the postmodern also points to the importance of textuality, of writing, and of 30 reflexivity in the sense of having an elaborated awareness of what is done and what is constructed through text and discourse. (p. 16) Of course, postmodern thinkers (those who propose such ideas), have their critics. Frederic Jameson (1991) proposes the idea that a close examination of postmodernism shows that all of its elements can be found in Modernism. This leads him to suggest that what is called postmodern is actually not a new period so much as a late stage of Modern Capitalism. Terry Eagleton (1996) takes a hard line against postmodernism and has made critiques against it similar to the ones postmodernists use against modernism. He states, for all its talk of difference, plurality, heterogeneity, postmodern theory often operates with quite rigid binary oppositions, with ‘difference’, ‘plurality’ and allied terms lined up bravely on one side of the theoretical fence as unequivocally positive, and whatever their antitheses might be (unity, identity, totality, universality) ranged balefully on the other. (p. 25—6) The debates around postmodernism are intense, and thoughtful scholars in many different disciplines have lined up on every possible side of it. I am not so much interested in a correct characterization or description of 31 any particular side of these debates. I assume the social constructivist critique of modern epistemology, at least as it animates educational discourse, is as much at play and to be learned from as modern, psychological constructivism. With this, albeit brief, assemblage of characterizations of the tension/transition between modernism and postmodernism, let us move to consider what these characterizations might mean in relation to a social constructivist pedagogy. Postmodern Social Constructivist Pedagogy First of all, postmodernism necessarily shifts our attention away from a preoccupation with the individual toward issues of sociality. Therefore, we are more likely to consider constructivist premises of individual learning within the broader context of thinking about learning and teaching as social enterprises. Also, students constructions will be taken up as key texts in the class and not considered only for the purpose of more effective disciplinary teaching. 32 Postmodernism gets us talking about the role of language and discourse, specifically textuality. Textuality can be thought of as a way of being in the world that takes seriously the idea that the world is socio-politically layered/constructed and must be read purposefully. Following certain post-structural lines of thinking, specifically Derrida, we consider an exploded notion of text as any attempt to mean/interpret, whether spoken, written, or gestured. As Derrida (1982) states, It is precisely for strategic reasons that I find it necessary to recast the concept of the text by generalizing it almost without limit, without any limit that is. That’s why there is nothing ‘beyond the text’. That’s why South Africa and apartheid are, like you and me, part of this general text, which is not to say that it can be read as one reads a book. That’s why the text is always a field of forces: heterogeneous, differential, open. That’s why deconstructive readings are concerned not only with library books. . .they are not simply analyses of discourse. They are also effective or active interventions that transform contexts without limiting themselves to theoretical utterances even though they must also produce such utterances. (p. 167—8) This means that textuality will be an important issue in any enactment of a postmodern social constructivism. Trying to describe a notion of postmodern social constructivism also requires that we pay attention to 33 authority and relations of power that shape subjects in the classroom. A postmodern social constructivism will consider issues of authority and power central and explicit resulting in teaching that will make these issues central to the teaching. Given that social constructivism, as noted earlier in the chapter, consists mainly of critiques of modern epistemology, a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy will directly confront issues of disciplinary faithfulness in the context of teaching. That is, while teaching may occur within the outward confines of a discipline, the borders of disciplinary practice will be crossed in the process. Broad Purpose of this Dissertation This dissertation will present an examination of my own teaching, which changes from a modern constructivist to that of a postmodern social constructivist within the context of a sequence of philosophical inquiry classes. In order to clarify what the differences might mean in terms of an actual teacher and actual students, I will look at my 34 pedagogy in philosophical inquiry across the three years and compare the teaching on a set of issues that will bring into relief modern constructivist teaching that was discussed earlier with a postmodern social constructivist style of teaching. I am, in one sense, the same teacher across the three years. But, my own thinking changes across a three year period of time. In the first year I enacted a traditional, disciplinary based philosophical inquiry. As I begins to interact with more postmodern/critical ideas, my teaching in the second year began to look different, and so the community of inquiry looked different as well. In the third year I attempted to enact a fuller postmodern community of inquiry in the classroom, one that tried to take seriously the elements of a postmodern social constructivism described above. Analyses that span the three communities will help differentiate a postmodern social constructivism from a more modern constructivism that adheres to disciplinary boundaries. By reading the three different communities as text, my analyses demonstrate the differences between modern and postmodern forms of social constructivism, and demonstrate a more 35 thoroughgoing social constructivism invigorated by postmodern thinking. There are few examples of teachers trying to teach on the postmodern side of constructivism. While there are teachers who employ social/communal beliefs and strategies in their classrooms, there are few cases where postmodern issues like textuality, authority, disciplinary boundaries, difference etc., are integrated into the teaching, and students are encouraged to interrogate the subjects of their schooling (especially pre high—school). 36 Chapter 2 Introduction In this chapter I will represent community of inquiry in a way that takes into consideration its development as it pertains to the teaching of philosophical inquiry while distinguishing it from other notions of communal learning that are part of the discourse of theories that are social and constructive. “Community” is becoming a greater and greater part of educational discourse. Community of practice (Wenger 1998), learning community (Peterson, 1992), community of learners (Rogoff, Matusov, and White, 1996), classroom community (Bridges, 1995), and other phrases involving community can readily be found in a search of educational topics involving the word “community”. This suggests the term community is at play in educational discourse, and its prolific use means that it plays in many ways in that discourse. My intent is to discuss “community” in relation to its use in “community of inquiry”. How and why a classroom 37 might become a community of inquiry is different depending on what one’s views of constructivist teaching is. The teaching studied in this dissertation invokes different understandings of community of inquiry and I will try to explain the differences between them. The notion of community of inquiry that is at work in the philosophical communities of inquiry I will study in the empirical portion of the dissertation has its roots in the work of C. S. Peirce. Therefore, I will begin with a particular consideration of the phrase “community of inquiry” in Peirce. C. S. Peirce and Community of Inquiry Charles Sanders Peirce (1839—1914) was both a scientist and a philosopher. These dispositions had a major impact on his work as he sought to bring the method of science to philosophy. Peirce’s drive to bring scientific inquiry to philosophy was in large part a reaction to the dominance of Cartesianism in modern philosophy (Murphy, 1990, p. 8—9). Peirce believed that philosophy had gone awry with its adoption of a Cartesian View of knowledge. 38 Descartes reconstituted the Western View of knowledge by positing the mind as an inner space which directly apprehends ideas, and it is these ideas which, when clearly and distinctly perceived, constitute knowledge. It is worth quoting Peirce’s understanding and criticisms of Cartesianism at length as it is his reaction to this system that inspires his notion of community of inquiry: Descartes is the father of modern philosophy and the spirit of Cartesianism—that which principally distinguishes it from the scholasticism which it displaced—may be compendiously stated as follows: 1. It teaches that philosophy must begin with universal doubt; whereas scholasticism had never questioned fundamentals. 2. It teaches that the ultimate test of certainty is to be found in the individual consciousness; whereas scholasticism had rested on the testimony of sages and of the Catholic Church. 3. The multiform argumentation of the middle ages is replaced by a single thread of inference depending often upon inconspicuous premises. 4. Scholasticism had its mysteries of faith, but undertook to explain all created things. But there are many facts which Cartesianism not only does not explain, but renders absolutely inexplicable, unless to say that “God makes them so” is to be regarded as an explanation. In some, or all of these respects, most modern philosophers have been in effect, Cartesians. Now without wishing to return to scholasticism, it seems to me that modern science and modern logic require us to stand upon a very different platform from this. (Buchler, 1990, p. 228) 39 Peirce offers specific and fatal criticisms to what he calls the “spirit of Cartesianism”. His objections are important because it is within his objections that we begin to understand the development of his notion of community of inquiry. First of all, Perice rejects the notion that philosophy must begin with universal doubt. He says, “We cannot begin with complete doubt. We must begin with all the prejudices which we actually have when we enter upon the study of philosophy (1990, p. 228).” Peirce did not believe a person could doubt everything as we must act in the world, and action requires belief in a great many things. Any attempt at universal doubt would end in self- deception. To the second tenet, Peirce argues that if truth and certainty are to be found in the individual consciousness then, “If I were really convinced, I should have done with reasoning, and should require no test of certainty. But thus, to make single individuals absolute judges of truth is most pernicious (1990, p. 229).” It is in his rejection of this tenet of Cartesianism that we find Peirce mention the importance of community, In sciences in which men come to agreement, when a theory has been broached, it is considered to be on 40 probation until this agreement is reached. After it is reached, the question of certainty becomes an idle one, because there is no one left who doubts it. We individually cannot reasonably hope to attain the ultimate philosophy which we pursue; we can only seek it, therefore, for the community of philosophers. Hence, if disciplined and candid minds carefully examine a theory and refuse to accept it, this ought to create doubts in the mind of the author of the theory himself. (1990, p. 229) This notion of people coming together to serve as jury to ideas and hypotheses is the basis for Peirce’s notion of community of inquiry. Where people come together in agreement, “one can speak of knowledge, truth, and reality, but these concepts will be grounded in the community of inquirers, not in the individual consciousness (Murphy, 1990, p. 12).” Community of inquiry is central for Peirce who used the terms community and inquiry to refer to a group of individuals (most often scientists) employing an interpersonal method for arriving at results. In Peirce’s work, the issue of community develops further around his treatment of theories of reality (metaphysics). In his philosophical writings, Peirce argued for the idea that there is a world independent of our minds, which we can develop beliefs about. He says, “The 41 real is that which is not what we happen to think it, but is unaffected by what we may think of it. (Peirce, 8.12)” For Peirce, we come to know the world via a communal and pluralistic community of inquirers engaged in a scientific method of inquiry. If persistent, Peirce believed, the community would eventually arrive at the same conclusions, thus coming to know the real. In Peirce’s own words, “[T]he opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed upon to by all who investigate, is what we mean by the truth, and the object represented in this opinion is the real (p.40).” Inquiry, for Peirce, is embodied in the scientific method of arriving at conclusions through synthetic reasoning. This kind of reasoning is inductive in its character as it moves from old beliefs, through experience, to new beliefs. Peirce believed that the human mind moves between poles of doubt and belief. Doubts is a state of agitation which leads to uncertainty. Belief is a state which allows for action, and confidence, eventually turning into habit. Between doubt and belief lies inquiry (Smith, 1983, p. 47).Smith explains this further, Serious inquiry aimed at acquiring knowledge of the real world. . .starts with the assumption that there 42 is an answer, thg answer to the question that directs the process. Moreover, there is the further assumption that this answer would be found if the inquiry persisted. (Smith, 1983, p. 48) So the method of inquiry for Peirce is what is crucial to producing knowledge that can be believed. That is, “[r]eality, insofar as it is identified through ultimate belief resulting from inquiry, is defined by a form of rationality rather than by the fact of a belief’s being held (1983, p. 49).” Peirce believes inquiry to be a rational, scientific process that by virtue of its logic (form) will yield the same conclusion regardless of the interests of those inquiring. Peirce vehemently rejected the idea that we can achieve any significant insights, or reliable knowledge, from introspection. This belief is a reaction to the Cartesian View that we can be clear and distinct about our own thinking. For Peirce, it is necessary for us to subject our thinking to standards that lie outside of our own interests, concerns, and reflections. In this way, thinking must continually be subject to a community whose standards allow us to correct and revise our ideas in the course of living our lives. 43 From this position, we get a feel for the importance of community to Peirce’s View of inquiry. The community of inquirers, accepting of the method of scientific investigation, serves as the arbiter of standards and the justification for the production of reliable knowledge. The individual scientist conducting experiments is never really alone, for she uses methods that are accepted by a community and she must continually revise her thought processes and observations in relation to the standards set by that community. Smith adds insight to this position, The community of investigators purporting to be scientific is defined by the willingness of each individual member to sacrifice what is personal and private. . .in order to follow the dictates of an interpersonal method that involves free exchange of views and results. (1983, p. 50) In this way, the individual inquirer is always subject to the standards of the community which they have accepted by the adoption of methods of science. Community, in this case, is the actual community of scientific inquirers who are engaged in the rational deployment of synthetic reasoning. I’ll end with a quote by Smith which sums up Peirce’s notion of the community of inquiry, The idea of science as an activity engaged in by a community of inquirers, and the conception of reality as an ultimate opinion reached by the process of inquiry, are reciprocal notions. On the one side we have the idea of the real as an ultimate opinion which is, though not external to thought in general, still independent of what this, that, or the other individual thinker may happen to think. On the other side we have the idea of the method reaching such an opinion that requires individual inquirers to constitute themselves as members of the community of science through their willingness to sacrifice their privacy and bind themselves by the rules of an interpersonal method. (Smith, 1983, p. 51) A community of inquiry, Peirce believes, is the model for the production of knowledge which will lead us from doubt to belief, and eventually to the real. Peirce’s use of these terms is important because aspects of his usage remain in tact in recent uses of community of inquiry. Community of Inquiry in Philosophy for Children Peirce’s use of community of inquiry was a reaction to the dominant philosophy of his time. Peirce’s extrapolation of community of inquiry from his reading of the scientific method, and application of community of inquiry to philosophy, was a way of establishing a new pragmatic system in philosophy designed to challenge and replace the preeminence of Cartesian dualism. 45 By the time community of inquiry was adopted by Matthew Lipman, and Ann Sharp, founders of Philosophy for Children, Dewey had adopted community of inquiry and made it integral to his theorizing about classrooms and curriculum (see Dewey, 1938; 1902). It is also discussed, though not using the specific phrase “community of inquiry” by Jerome Bruner (1960) in his influential book, The Process of Education. Community of inquiry receives an extended treatment in Philosophy for Children. Philosophy for Children is both a curriculum (in all senses of the term) from which to View educational practice and purpose. This perspective takes seriously the notion that philosophical inquiry should be one of the core elements of elementary school life (Lipman, Sharp, & Oscanyan, 1980). The reason for this? Education should empower children to be thoughtful about the lives they lead, and doing philosophy is important to that goal. Philosophical inquiry involves the taking of different perspectives and serious reflection, and it teaches ways of reasoning about the world that enhances student’s abilities to think critically, deliberately, and imaginatively. The 46 vehicle by which philosophical inquiry is implemented in elementary schools is a curriculum based on philosophical novels that students and teachers read together in teacher— led communities of inquiry. A typical Philosophy for Children class session might begin with the teacher and students choral reading part of a chapter from one of the curriculum novels. The inquiry would begin with the teacher soliciting remarks from the students. This is an important feature of this practice because, in this forum, it is the students who choose what is interesting and raise issues for discussion. To the extent that most classrooms focus on the teacher as the director of inquiry, this shift of power is an important step in the empowerment of students. By shifting the balance of power in the classroom away from the teacher, one shifts the frameworks for participation in the classrooms (O’Connor, M. C. & Michaels, S. 1996). When this happens, students have the potential to become more engaged in classroom discourse, take more speaking turns, and speak for longer periods of time (Cazden 1988, Anderson et al. 1998). These changes are important because they position 47 students in fundamentally different ways; students become an important part of the inquiry and their thoughts on the issue are an integral part of any discussion. In this environment students are actively responsible for creating and sustaining discussions, and are confronted with their own thinking and the thoughts of their fellow students in an environment of mutual respect with an accomplished inquirer (the teacher). The novels traditionally used in Philosophy for Children are sprinkled heavily with philosophical subject matter. Discussions about reality (metaphysics), what is right (ethics), and language are common topics for inquiry. In the end though, it is the process of inquiry that is most important, and the discussions often begin in areas that are not philosophical. But this does not mean that the teacher does not have any say how topics are discussed. Let me say more about this process of inquiry. A discourse community centered around philosophical inquiry is the primary vehicle by which philosophical ways of talking and thinking are fostered. Early in the formation of a community of inquiry, the teacher 48 facilitates discussion and scaffolds appropriate forms of participation in the community (put in “community values” and “principles of philosophical inquiry” here). Ideally, as the community becomes more skilled and begins to gain confidence, the teacher takes a less active role in the inquiry. “Inquiry”, in Philosophy for Children, means, “perseverance in self—corrective exploration of issues that are felt to be both important and problematic (Lipman, 1988, p.20).” In other words, an inquiry is a sustained exploration of a topic or issue that is of interest to students; community members participate in inquiries in the hope of understanding the many ways of thinking about an issue and the production of knowledge about the self and the world. Simply put, a community of inquiry in the discourse of Philosophy for Children (hereafter P4C), is the conversion of a classroom into a place for the self—corrective, disciplined exploration of issues with philosophical relevance. As Lipman says, “Such a community is committed to the procedures of inquiry, to responsible search techniques that presuppose an openness to evidence and to 49 reason (Lipman, et al, 1980, p. 45).” The community of inquiry must arise from an environment that has certain preconditions. Preconditions of Community of Inquiry in P4C: 1. Readiness to reason 2. Mutual respect (of children towards one another, and of children and teachers towards one another) 3. An absence of indoctrination (1980, p. 45) To a certain extent, the readiness to reason is assumed by virtue of the fact the children are language users. The use of language necessitates certain basics of reasoning even though they are mostly informal and implicit. Since reasoning is one of the things the P4C curriculum purports to cultivate, the readiness to reason will eventually be transformed into formal abilities to reason through the teaching of formal and informal logic. While the second presupposition might seem overly egalitarian, it is not the case that the teacher and students are seen as equals. The teacher is viewed as the authority when it comes to the procedures and techniques of inquiry, and philosophical background knowledge. But this authority is not supposed to extend to the favoring of 50 particular points of view. The teacher must assist students in following the paths of their own thinking. But the teacher must always stop at the point of legitimizing or delegitimizing particular points of View. As Lipman et al explain, “Under the banner of “pluralism,” it may be contended, the convergence of views is precluded, agreement and assent are ruled out, and intellectual diversity becomes the order of the day (1980, p, 45—6).” Building on the previous point, indoctrination is thought to be subverted through the adoption of a pluralistic stance. On one level this is naive, as teaching, of any sort, involves an ideological stance which precludes neutrality. Pluralism is a doctrine of sorts, a doctrine against monism. However, this presupposition is meant to convey the idea that the teacher must not hold the belief that ideas and opinions must always converge. They present this precondition as necessary to the creation of a community of inquiry. My point here is that community of inquiry is not neutral, or without ideological commitments. 51 Mechanisms of Community Formation in P4C According to P4C, the community is brought together by the following means: 1.Group solidarity through dialogical inquiry 2.The primacy of activity and reflection 3.The articulation of disagreements and the quest for understanding 4.Fostering cognitive skills (e.g., assumption finding, generalization, exemplification) through dialogical practice. 5.Learning to employ cognitive tools (e.g., reasons, criteria, concepts, algorithms, rules, principles) 6.Joining together in cooperative reasoning (e.g., building on each other's ideas, offering counterexamples or alternative hypotheses, etc.) 7.Internalization of the overt cognitive behavior of the community (e.g., introjecting the ways in which classmates correct one another until each becomes systematically self—corrective) - “intrapsychical reproduction of the interpsychical” (Vygotsky) 8.Becoming increasingly sensitive to meaningful nuance of contextual differences 9.Group collectively groping its way along, following the argument where it leads (1991, p. 242) These nine mechanisms of community formation are the constitutive elements of Community of Inquiry for Lipman. They are the “ways” a group of students and a teacher becomes a community. Described a little differently, the community forms by: being dialogically inquisitive, active and reflective, articulate, cognitively adept, cooperative, sensitive to context, and explorative. 52 For Lipman (1991), Community of Inquiry is not just a classroom phenomena, it is curriculum. Community of Inquiry involves a valuing of certain stances towards written texts. Lipman states that Community of Inquiry begins with narrative texts that model Community of Inquiry. This is reflected in the P4C curriculum which is organized around novels where the characters are a community of inquiry. This, virtual community, or, textual community, adds a another dimension of community to the community forming in any particular classroom. The text reflects: accepted values and beliefs, mental reflections of an author, and, examples of thinking that can be internalized (Lipman, 1991, p. 241). The text mediates between the culture and the individual, and portrays “human relationships as possibly analyzable into logical relations. (1991, P. 241).” Reading printed text aloud in the community has ethical dimensions which involve turn taking; this turn taking is also a division of labor. Reading aloud also involves the reproduction of the written text into oral form. This stance toward text allows students to discover 53 that text is meaningful and worthy. That is, texts are full of meaning and relevance (1991, p. 242). Deciding what ideas or issues will be taken up by a community is another key feature of Community of Inquiry in Philosophy for Children. Agenda setting is public from the standpoint that it begins with questions from the students. Questions are organized collaboratively reflecting the interests and priorities of the group (1991, p. 242). A given starting point for an inquiry comes from the collaboratively constructed agenda and is negotiated by the entire community (including the teacher - who is a member of the community — albeit a more capable one). Specific curricular materials in P4C have been designed to augment community of inquiry. These materials, in the form of exercises, discussion plans, etc., allow the methodology of P4C to more easily be appropriated by community members, and can help instantiate particular features of philosophical inquiry. For example, each novel in the Philosophy for Children curriculum comes with a teacher’s manual that gives exercises and elucidations of key philosophical topics that appear in the novels. In the 54 manual accompanying the novel Lisa, a novel which emphasizes ethical inquiry, one can find philosophically relevant explanations and exercises on human rights, friendship, death, and fairness (amongst others). Finally, efforts must be made to incorporate the critical and the creative by exploring other forms of cognitive expression (writing, painting, music, etc.) and judgment (1991, p. 243). Philosophy for Children has been practiced for 30 years. Community of Inquiry remains at the heart of the movement and has received extensive development by those using principles of Philosophy for Children in the classroom. We can see the influence of Pierce and Dewey in the articulation of community of inquiry offered by those in Philosophy for Children. The description of inquiry as a self corrective process, and the emphasis on the form (logic) of inquiry come directly from Peirce. Communities of inquiry are modeled after scientific communities of inquiry where the explorations of ideas and reasoning are publicly displayed and scrutinized. This display and 55 scrutiny eventually lead to the creation/construction of knowledge about the self, and the world. While many different avenues of thought can be explored in a philosophical community of inquiry some topics and forms of reasoning with be more legitimate than others. Every participant in a community is like an individual scientific inquirer, making the community of inquiry itself a microcosm of the scientific community of inquirers at large. It is this notion of community of inquiry that provided the parameters by which the philosophical communities of inquiry in this study are enacted. In order to round out this picture a little, let’s look at some other understandings of community of inquiry. Other understandings of Community of Inquiry In studying community of inquiry in the teaching of history, Peter Sexias (1993) distinguishes between two different communities of inquiry: the intellectual community of inquiring historians and the community of inquiry in the classroom. The community of inquiring 56 historians, Sexias notes, are engaged in the production of historical knowledge. This community's task has been greatly problematized by the challenges to modern epistemology discussed in chapter 1 (some of these challenges come from Social Constructivists, others, from people, like Kuhn (1970), Lakatos & Musgrave (1970). As Sexias notes, “[t]he constructivist recasting of curriculum thought in the past 15 years has been based not in a Kuhnian revision in epistemology of the subject disciplines but in developments in learning theory and psychology (Sexais, 1993, p. 306).” This re—introduces the dilemma spoken about in chapter one, that of the relationship between premises of individual constructivist learning and teaching, and social constructivist critiques of disciplinary knowledge. Sexias characterizes this tension nicely as it relates to communities of inquiry, First, what are the limits to the analogy between scholarly and school—based communities of inquiry, whose participants have not been inducted through graduate programs and doctoral degrees? Second, if knowledge is based on the conversation within a community of the competent, what is the status of the products of that conversation? Third, what is required of teachers who, in this conceptualization, must bridge two significantly different communities? (p. 306) 57 On the one hand we have the communities of discipline based inquirers, be they from history, philosophy, or mathematics, and, on the other hand, we have communities of inquiring students in classrooms. The relationship between these two has traditionally been one way, where knowledge constructed in the disciplines gets transformed into curricula for students in schools. Historians have their own sets of problems they deal with, lately ones of epistemology and historical sense making (Sexias, 1993), and teachers and students have their own struggles with the teaching and learning of history. Sexias believes that any attempt to conflate the two groups is dangerous. I guess he has reservations about students abilities to “do” what historians do. At the same time, he believes that many historians would not support the one way flow of knowledge from professional historians becoming the basis for school curriculum (p. 313). In some ways Sexias is caught in the constructivist dilemma that frames this dissertation. He has pointed to, within theorizing about the teaching of history, the 58 disjunction between what historians do and what students in school do. Gordon Wells (1999) addresses the practice of communities of inquiry in terms of cultural-historical activity theory (Cole 1996). As Wells states, Central to this approach is the building of a ‘community of inquiry’, in which students frequently work together in groups on the same or related inquiries, and in which a critically important activity is whole class meetings for review and reflection on what is planned, in progress or has been achieved. It is in these meetings, in particular, that the dialogue of knowledge building occurs most deliberately and systematically as the relationship among the individual or group inquiries are explored in relation to the common theme, alternative suggestions and perspectives are considered and evaluated. . .These meetings also provide an occasion for taking a ‘meta’ stance with respect to the processes in which students are engaging, for describing strategies that seem to be effective, and for recognizing and valuing the diversity of ideas that are contributed to the forging of a common understanding. (p. 7—8) We can see many similarities between, the statements Wells puts forth and those of Philosophy for Children. The basic idea being students and teachers engaged in communities that actively engage in dialogue over topics of interest, in the service of constructing knowledge and common 59 understanding, and internalizing the discourse of the inquiring community. Community of Inquiry and This Dissertation The description of community of inquiry I gave above, especially the conception of community of inquiry from Philosophy for Children, is a good statement of how I understood community of inquiry going into the first summer of teaching philosophical inquiry. I believed myself to be introducing a formal discourse of philosophy (through Philosophy for Children) to my students in a way that would bring out what I believed at the time to be their natural inclinations to inquire in philosophical ways. I was the more capable other, and I would engage my students in a discursive apprenticeship that would help cultivate creative and critical ways of thinking (in order to improve their own reasoning abilities) that they could partake in. For me, at that time/place, there was no constructivist dilemma, nogproblem of sincerity and reading. The teaching was straightforward. But this thinking changed over the course of the next two years. I have documented my teaching 60 over these three years, and have a data set that allows me to examine how the changes in my thinking, from a modern constructivist discourse social constructivist discourse. This forced me to alter my practice. The communities of inquiry I participated in as a teacher began to look very different. This change forced me to consider a different understanding of community of inquiry. Thinking about communities of inquiry as microcosms of scientific methodology became problematic for me as I began to reconsider my potentially disingenuous stance as “bringer of formal philosophical” discourse to my students. This is a very modern notion of community with its modeling of scientific method as its paradigm case. It is also modern because of its focus on epistemology and the transmission of a discourse as its goal. If inquiry is of a sort where the rules, and sometimes the topics, of inquiry are determined ahead of time by the teacher, where is there room for students ideas, experiences, and developing understandings? Is community of inquiry ever critiqued by a community of inquiry? If, as the teacher, my stance toward 61 community of inquiry is modern in its orientation, what does a more postmodern stance toward community of inquiry look like and how does it change things? In the next chapter I discuss the methodology of this of this study, and detail the procedures I used in collecting and analyzing my data set. 62 Chapter 3 Methodology In support of theoretical frameworks for action research, Sanders and McCutcheon (1986) make the case that professional knowledge is essentially theoretical knowledge because “teaching requires intentional and skillful action within real—world situations. The success of these actions depends on the ability to perceive relevant features of complex, problematic, and changeable situations and to make appropriate choices.” Argyris calls these “theories of action”(in Cochran-Smith & Lytle, 1993, p. 16). The forms of documentation and analysis for action research are similar to traditional forms of qualitative research such as field notes, interviews, and classroom documents. Teacher researchers, such as myself, may also use audiotapes, videotapes, and research journals. In addition to using these methods for documentation, many experienced teachers are able to provide an emic view that outsiders could not accomplish. Some believe this makes them more suitable for the appropriate collection of data (e.g. Cochran-Smith and Lytle, 1993). 63 Some of the literature on self—study is drawn from the larger field of action research, defined by Cochran—Smith and Lytle (1993) as “systematic and intentional inquiry carried out by teachers (p. 7).” Cochran-Smith and Lytle (1999) provide an overview of the conceptual frameworks for teacher research. The perspective of teacher research as social inquiry maintains that knowledge is constructed collaboratively with the emphasis on transforming educational theory and practice toward a more equitable society. Theorizing teacher research as ways of knowing in communities blurs the boundaries of research and practice and attempts to recognize practice as theory- building in order to change schools. Teacher research as practical inquiry emphasizes the use of teacher research to create and/or enhance practical knowledge. Although this dissertation seeks to accomplish all of those tasks, it best subscribes to the framework of social inquiry. A major element of the self—study process is critical reflection. Brookfield (1995) suggests six reasons why learning critical reflection is important: to take informed actions, to develop a rationale for practice, to avoid 64 self—laceration (self-blame for student failing), to ground us emotionally, to enliven our classrooms, and increase democratic trust. But reflection is not enough. “Reflection must be placed in action and look backward and forward to make choices about educational dilemmas” (Samaras, 1998, p. 62). Hamilton and Pinnegar (1998) contend that self-study is a formalization of reframing — a way to rethink and expose yourself “to new interpretations and to create different strategies for educating students that bring their practice into concert with the moral values they espouse” (p. 2). This is in line with what Dewey emphasized as the importance of teachers being both consumers and producers of knowledge about teaching. He encouraged teachers to be reflective and to act on their reflections. Cole and Knowles (1998b) define self—study research as “qualitative research focused inward” which primarily uses qualitative research tools such as observation, interview, and artifact collection (p.229). More than just qualitative research, self-study is “post-modern in its perspective...self—study scholars attempt to embrace that 65 uncertainty and reject calls for validity and reliability as they are traditionally known” (Hamilton & Pinnegar, 1998, p. 235). Although such rebellion is exhilarating to think about, the real world demands that self-study scholars define it in a way that legitimizes its title of “Research”. Some contend that participant research does not fit neatly into any other research genre, and it deserves recognition and acknowledgment in its own right (e.g. Wong, 1995; Baumann, 1996; Elliot, 1991). Cole and Knowles (1995) define six major issues in self-study and life history work: technical, interpersonal, procedural, ethical, political, and educational. Technical issues surround the facilitation and progression of the self-study process. Interpersonal issues are integral to the process when self—study is done in collaboration with others. Procedural issues are those which involve how the research is carried out including the methods, time line, and routines. Because self—study is highly personal and uncommonly revealing, ethical issues regarding confidentiality may be unusually salient. Cole and Knowles regard the personal revelations necessary for self-study 66 work as potential political issues when, what can be, very private analysis is read by those in the academy. Similarly, educational issues such as the validation of self-study research by academe constantly lingers for those attempting to be professionally recognized for such research. Cole and Knowles (1998a) view self-study as a tool for broadening the concept of research. They specify two main purposes: personal-professional development and “broader purposes of enhanced understanding of teacher education practices, processes, programs, and contexts” (p. 42). The former purpose provides a more practical goal for teachers to engage in reflective inquiry in order to improve their practice. The second purpose is aimed at challenging what counts as research and knowledge. Self—study is commonly believed to be “soft” research. Cochran—Smith and Lytle (1993) provide four standards for methodological rigor when discussing teacher research: the research question, generalizability, theoretical framework, and documentation and analysis. With regard to the research question, they say that although teacher research questions 67 are not framed in educational theory, they are “implicit questions about the relationships of concrete, particular cases, to more general and abstract of learning and teaching” (p. 15). In other words, each situation “is a case of some larger practice/theory dilemma”, and therefore, more relevant that initially estimated (p. 15). A common critique of teacher research is its lack of generalizability. This critique, in a sense, speaks to the recipe formula for teaching and denies the legitimacy of serious research questions emanating from individual classrooms. Cochran-Smith and Lytle argue that not only are some teacher research questions similar to those other teachers have, but in fact, it is often the generic educational research that misses the point when insight is needed about particular contexts. In this way, the import of a piece of research is left to the readers of research who may make use of it in many different ways. Also, the work is generalizable from the standpoint that it is situated in a practice (teaching) that many others are actively engaged in. 68 Educational philosophers and researchers (e.g. Fenstermacher, 1994; Huberman, 1996) critique action research, and by association self—study. Some critics conceive of knowledge as formal, theoretical, scientific and generalizable, and distinguish it from, and in the process usually devalue, practical knowledge (Cochran—Smith and Lytle, 1999). This type of comparison “offers a binary description of a world that is, instead, far more dynamic and complex” (Hamilton & Pinnegar, 1998, p. 241). Whitehead calls self-study “living educational theory. It is living because, as people engage in understanding it, they learn more and their theory changes as they understand more. Further, because they are living what they learn, new knowledge emerges” (in Hamilton & Pinnegar, 1998, p. 242). In support of that idea, Russell (1998) writes “There is only one way to understand self—study, and that is to experience it personally” (p. 6). 69 Data Collection and Analysis The site for this study was a one-month long summer program for high-ability middle—school students held on the campus of a major mid-western university.2 Each of the students selected philosophy as one of two academic classes they took during the program. Students also took one course in the Arts. The program was organized by local (public) schools districts, and was designed to provide students with opportunities they might not otherwise have during the school year. The philosophical inquiry course met one hour each morning, four days a week. I studied three separate classes taught over three consecutive summers (1998, 1999, 2000). Data sources (98, 99, 00) 1. Tape/video recordings of most of the class sessions for each summer. 2I had human subjects approval to begin data collection in the Summer of 1998. I received renewals of this approval for each of the following two summers as well. 70 2. A whole class interview conducted at the end of each course as well as individual student reactions to the class which I have written copies of. 3. Interviews with individual students conducted during the final week of each class. 4. Samples of student writing from each week of the class for all students. 5. A set of notes from a colleague who observed the classes at least once each week. 6. The teacher journal for each year. 7. Results of a short survey given to students and parents by program administrators (not the teacher). Description of the Teacher's Stance I am the teacher in each year of the course. In the next few paragraphs I characterize the stance from which I approached the teaching of philosophy during each summer of the philosophical inquiry class. 71 My teaching during the Summer 1998 When I taught the philosophy class 2 years ago, my pedagogy was situated in the modern world view discussed in chapter 1. I believed in reason and rationality as the best end for education because it would free our minds and allow people to communicate with one another toward a common goal of enlightenment (Cervetti, Pardales, and Damico, 2001). These beliefs led me to dedicate myself to teaching philosophy for children in the traditional way (discussed in chapter 2), where my job was to cultivate and formalize the natural “human” dispositions of philosophy that lye nascent in young students. My teaching during the Summer 99 During this summer I felt very much like I did in the summer of 1998, but over time, as I continued my education in graduate school, and confronted critical and postmodern ideas, my thinking began to change. I became less comfortable with teaching children how to “do” philosophy for the purposes of increasing rational thinking and 72 enlightenment. I began to wonder, why philosophy? Why the emphasis on reasoning? Especially a style of philosophical inquiry whose roots sit squarely in the liberal—humanist tradition, which I was beginning to subject to serious criticism. I also became aware that many students were questioning and criticizing the traditional texts, and I no longer felt the need to defend the curriculum like I used to. Eventually, I felt that is was more important to help the students shape their own criticism of printed texts and society. I altered my teaching, spending less time modeling what I thought philosophical discourse should look like, and more time helping the students shape their own criticism of issues related to the traditional texts and nontraditional texts (aspects of their own lives, non— traditional literature). My teaching during the Summer 2000 In this summer I taught two sections of philosophy. In one section I used the exact readings used in the first summer of teaching; using the same readings as the first summer and some of the same readings as the second, should have 73 the effect of highlighting the difference between my approach because some of the same issues arose due to the similarities in printed material. Having some of the same issues arise will highlight the differences in my practice because I will be able to look closely at the different I handled discussions around similar topics and issues. In the second class, I used different printed texts that I thought would correspond to a more thoroughgoing social constructivism within the philosophy class. I tried to make more room for non—traditional texts (student experience, beliefs, values) to become primary texts for the class, and to be more open to elements of a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy discussed near the end of chapter 1. Since I began teaching in the first summer I have kept a journal for each summer’s activities. My journal is part autobiography, part field—note, part self—analysis. I used my journal to record events that were otherwise not documented. I also used it to have an inner dialogue about issues that were arising in my work as a teacher of 74 philosophical inquiry. This lead me to ask the following research questions: 1) How does a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy differ (for the teacher) from a modern form of constructivism? 2) How does a teacher trying to enact a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy remain faithful to both subject matter content and their students’ ideas, experiences, and developing understandings? 3) What role does “community of inquiry” play in modern and postmodern forms of social constructivism? My main strategy for analysis was to study all of the data sources I have collected and read the data in ways that will help me to bring the issues I have raised around the constructivist dilemma to the fore. I created a catalog of every recorded session by taking reflective, critical, and descriptive notes as I listened to class sessions, viewed videotapes, and read transcriptions. This catalog is like a running record of the three years of philosophical inquiry. After this catalog was complete, I studied the catalog and coded it with topical markers related to the issues raised in my discussion of the constructivist dilemma. Some of the topical markers I used were: 75 1. issues of authority 2. treatment of text 3. issues of community 15 specific topics of discussion (reality, history, community, views of philosophy, popular culture, etc., etc.) 5. rhetorical stance of teacher 6. students’ commentary 7. discursive moves of teachers and students This coding allowed me to then explore the ways these issues played in different ways across the three summers and also allowed me to read significant thematic differences across the three years of my teaching. My analyses were guided by this coding and reading, and it is within the analyses that I created responses to my research question about the constructivist dilemma and the possibilities afforded and constrained by my adherence to the modern and postmodern forms of constructivist teaching that I tried to enact. 76 Chapter 4 Introduction In this chapter I perform several analyses that will help to explain how my teaching across the three years of philosophy changes. These analyses bring into relief the question of constructivist teaching in its modern and postmodern forms. The first analysis is pivotal. It shows the transition between a modern, discipline oriented, and somewhat insincere form of constructivism, and, the transition toward a more thoroughgoing postmodern social constructivism by examining how each class treats printed texts and issues of textuality. The second analysis looks at the topics that were discussed in each year of the philosophy class. This analysis suggests that as the years of the philosophy class progressed, I included more topics of student interest and was also more open to topics that seemed appropriate to a postmodern social constructivism. The third analysis shows how the beginning of each class was different in ways that reveal the difference between a modern form of constructivism and a form of social constructivist teaching informed by postmodern elements. 77 Analysis 1: Treatment of Text As I looked across the three years of philosophical inquiry I noticed that in each year the treatment of text changed dramatically. In traditional philosophical inquiry, one reads a text in an effort to make meaning of an authors words. That is, the traditional project is exegesis. This stance assumes that there are meanings in the text and the meanings need to be extracted in order to be discussed. So, in the community of inquiry, this would yield an activity where the community would seek to first understand the text and the meanings in the text, and after these meanings have been extracted discussion about the meanings of the texts and criticisms of ideas could be pursued. This reflects a belief that the text is the springboard for dialogue. This means that the text itself is given status as a vehicle of meaning, and while the meanings in the text are appropriate for discussion, the text as an artifact is not. This seems like a fine distinction, but in traditional philosophy teaching the focus is on talking about philosophical ideas. As the teacher, I enforce this understanding and in year one, I consider our project of reading, exegesis. Let us 78 look at some concrete examples of the stance toward text in each year of the philosophy classes. We begin with an examination of the year one philosophy classes stance toward text by looking at some of the notes I made while reviewing pieces of transcript from day 5 and day 12 of year one philosophy class. On the second full day of class I began by asking the students to go back to the text and consider the questions that the philosopher asks Sophie in the first two chapters of Sophie’s World. I ask the students, point blank, “what are the questions that the philosopher asks of Sophie?”. Several students state the first question, “Who are you?” and I write it down on the board. When several students begin stating what the second question is, I make them, and specify one student in particular, go back to the book and find the exact wording of the second question, “Where does the world come from?” (Transcript 6/16/98 —Day 3). This, going back to the book to get the exact wording, seems important. In fact, we stay very close to the text and I make sure they are able to retell, in part, what they have read. 79 In looking at a piece of transcript from day 12, when our subject was Martin Luther King’s, Letter from a Birmingham Jail, our conversation starts out with me questioning the students about the basic situation described in the text. I want to know if they understand who’s in jail, why they are in Jail, and who is writing the letter. After that correct portrayal of the text is complete it seems, then, the discussion begins, and it does. I do stop and direct the cross—talk very early in the conversation on this day, asking the students to speak one at a time. More references to the text are made with an eventual visit to the text where I have a student read the section we are dealing with. Why do I ask the students to read the section and go back to the text so much? Apparently I really want them to “get it” even if they have to reread it because I let two minutes of quiet searching time go by. Anna points to the passage and I ask her to read it. It comes out that MLK was arrested for parading without a permit. I ask the students for the argument that is embedded in MLK’s writing. I ask them for no easy thing. I then lay out the law that was used to imprison MLK on the 80 board in the form of an If—Then statement. Apparently, I think this is very important because I am really making sure we walk through every step of the argument making process. Connor builds on what Lara says and helps clarify an If—Then statement. I ask them what they think about the situation of the law being applied to this peacefully marching group. I point out that there seems to be a contradiction. Ahh, “contradiction”, the language of philosophy. Example, Counterexample, fact, opinion, If—Then statements, arguments, my language is littered with philosophical references (referring to Day 12 transcript — 6/16/98). This transcript commentary illustrate the exegetical stance toward text I enforced as the leader of the community and also reflects my strong alignment with issues traditional to the teaching of philosophy. There is a constant going back to the text to get the right meaning and the exact quote to base the discussion on. While these may not be the only reasons to go back to the text, they were certainly the ones I privileged. I recall in other discussions from this class that students would 81 occasionally make comments about their dissatisfaction with one of the novels we were reading (specifically the Philosophy for Children novel, Lisa, 1983). One of the responses I gave to one statement of dissatisfaction, “I know this text may be a little different, but it is the ideas in the text that I want you to pay attention to (Class 098, Day 5)”, signals a desire to avoid spending time critiquing the text itself, when the text, as I believed, is merely a vehicle for meanings and ideas. In the second year of philosophy, a different community of inquiry and a different teacher, my stance towards the printed text changes. In the second year, I am more open to critique of our texts as artifacts and do not explain away student criticism. This next data segment offers an example of dialogue that ensues when a student expresses discontent with the Philosophy for Children text we are reading (Lisa). Her critique begins as an indictment of the format of the novel. The novel is written as a series of episodes that do not flow in a logical manner. One episode could refer to one characters dilemma with a piece clothing and then the next episode might be about 82 another character’s argument with a friend over an ethical issue. -——Begins Data Segment——- (Day 7 — 99) Jana: Well, this book [the P4C novel, Lisa] bothers me because it goes from —— you know that part about the dress, you know, how she gets that dress and then it skips right on to Maria or whoever. I wish they would have a section of the book on Lisa and a section of the book on Maria, because you're like well, what happens to the dress? Is she grounded or something? It leaves you hanging. Then you get sick of reading about all those other people. Tamara: Especially it's kind of like it doesn't seem like a novel. It seems like something that isn't real. Like you don't normally go and like run into your friends in the street and start asking them the difference between right and wrong and stuff. I mean, it just doesn't seem like very realistic. Michael: Mmmm. Why do you think this novel is written this way? Nicholas: I think it's like a discussion book. Like if I -- I wouldn't read it if it was just a book. But I think maybe it's like that because you're supposed to discuss what you think about the book or what's happening. Michael: So, it's more of a book that people can discuss things about. Amanda: I think it tries to make you think deeper than you thought before. Michael: Hmm. Why so? 83 Amanda: Because like the kids ask really different questions than probably people ask. So, it kind of gets deep a little bit. Callie: Yeah. Michael: Nick, you expressed some displeasure with Harry. How's it different -- I've been calling this book a novel. How is this different from other things you've read that you've been told were novels? Nick: Aren't novels usually thicker? Michael: maybe, longer or thicker. Michelle: They have plots. Rhea: Yeah. Michael: They have plots? Michelle: Characters. Murphy: This lacks a plot. William: Like —— I don't know, you don't know a lot about the characters, really. They're just who they are. It's not like, you know, they don't go into description a whole bunch about them. Michael: Mm hmm. This is true. Sarah: Kind of seems like episodes like on T.V. Jana: Yeah. It seems more like —- it seems more like it's written like a script than it is like an actual novel. --—End Data Segment——- 84 This kind of critique, allows the community to take a step back from the activity of mining for meaning and see the text as a product designed for a particular purpose. When Nicholas commented, “I think it's like a discussion book. Like if I -— I wouldn't read it if it was just a book. But I think maybe it's like that because you're supposed to discuss what you think about the book or what's happening (Class 99, Day 7, Transcript).” he is making a critical judgment of the text which gives him some say in how he will think about and approach this and possibly other texts he encounters. By doing this he has taken an important step toward understanding that texts are not neutral, that they are constructed, even designed, and that they have a particular agenda. He, as well as some of the other students, knew that this “novel”, as I called it, was different than other novels they read, and this opportunity to critique the texts we were reading offers them an important sense making experience about traditional texts as particular kinds of representations. Terry thought this book looked more like a script for a TV show. Her comment has to do with the fact that Lisa is 85 divided into many free standing episodes within each chapter. In this way, each episode can be likened to a situational drama or comedy that there are so many examples of on television. I am not arguing for the point that there is nothing to exegesis. There are certainly times when our purposes dictate that we read a text in order to try and understand what an author is saying. But, opportunities for thinking and learning are opened up when criticism of a text becomes a legitimate activity. This could also be a first step toward considering that there are other potential meanings in a text apart from the authors, even though this did not come up in our class. It is important to ask at this point, why is there space for this kind of critique now, when in the previous year’s class this kind of critique was not supported? One answer I can give to this question is, my own values and beliefs about texts changed. The time between year one and two was filled with a great deal of reading in the critical and postmodern traditions. In the intervening year between 98 and 99 I participated in a small study 86 group that attempted to assemble an understanding of critical literacy. We engaged with a broad range of ideas from critical social theory to critical pedagogy (Freire, 1970) and critical literacy (Mclaren, 1992). Critical literacy, specifically, condones an approach to reading that seeks to illuminate the ideological and political forces that underpin a texts construction. That is, students need to be encouraged to research, speculate about and second—guess the institutional agendas, ideologies and human agents behind and at work in the text (conditions of production). . .This requires more than a technical analysis of language, but as well a ‘reading of the cultures’ around, behind, underneath, alongside, after and within the text (Luke, Comber & O’Brien, 1996). I took this way of thinking seriously. And it was not that I actively encouraged students to engage in the kind of critique they did, in fact, only a year prior to this I actively tried to sidestep this kind of critique because I believed it to be superfluous to the kinds of discussion I thought we needed to be having. What changed, in part, was that I did not discourage the critique of text. I recognized that the students had different readings of the works we were engaged with, and I became curious about what 87 a discussion of their critical readings would produce. Since I came to understand texts as artifacts designed for particular purposes, as representative of politics and views of the world, it made sense to create a space for the kind of critique we engaged in; this activity began to feel like a natural part of philosophical inquiry. In the year three community of inquiry, the stance towards text takes a very different twist. In this community, there was exegesis, critique of texts, but unprecedented in the philosophy teaching examined in this study, textuality as an issue in and of itself, became a topic for inquiry. We talked about textuality, its relationship to perspective, and what it means to read. The following segment, which I offer at length, is the bulk of a discussion the year three community of inquiry had around the topic of “text”. This topic arose out of a dialogue the community had about two different books we had read. One of the books was a work of historical fiction, MorninggGirl (1999). This novel was written from the perspective of Arawak Indians immediately prior to the arrival of Columbus. We then discussed a section of a 88 middle school social studies textbook (American Nation, 1989) that discussed the arrival of Columbus to North America. At the time we were beginning to inquire about the different representations of this period in history offered by each of these pieces. After discussing the section on Columbus in the middle school textbook, I asked the question, “Why are they called textbooks?”, and the following dialogue ensued. —--Begin Data Segment--— (Day 7, Class 00B — Transcript) Michael: Why are they called textbooks? Emily: are those the things that we’re supposed to read in class? Michael: why are they called textbooks? Sophie: Cause they have text Several: all books have text John: what about picture books? Caitie: well, usually when a teacher says read this text its going to be something really boring. . text means that it's a book of boring words. Liza: maybe it means that its only text, there’s not, its just text 89 Emma: there’s no meaning behind it, its just a bunch of facts that we’re supposed to memorize. Tayler: Your thinking to specifically, a textbook is just a word that makes us think about a big book of information, your thinking way to specifically, trying to determine what “text” means and what “book” means. You’ve got to think about the whole word and what it makes you think about. Michael: What about. . um, what about a song (student: lyrics), could we think of a song as a text. (Some comments about listening to the words and listening to the music. Some talk about specific bands.) Michael: But could we think of a song, that had lyrics, as a text? (Some “yea’s” and “I guess” — there is reluctance to entertain this notion) Linda: songs are like poetry that have a melody James: Well, when you’re using text very loosely, yeah, I mean that depends on the specific series of text. Michael: What if we’re using, like according to the definition we’re discussing. James: Well is the musician an author, is he classified as an author? Sophie: Well songs aren’t always written down, when you hear them there not exactly text because their not written down when you hear them. You can’t hear things that are written down. James: Are we trying to distinguish between sight and sound? Michael: No, I’m actually pushing the question of what are texts? 9O Sophie: Now if the lyrics are written down it could be text cause their written down. Michael: Well when you read, when you read words on a page don’t you hear them? Janice: yes Sophie: In your head, yes, but its not really sound. Mika: unless you’re trying to speed read. Tayler: But what about when you’re speaking, just speaking, not reading off anything. James: Text is written Michael: Couldn’t it be a spoken text? Sophie: yeah you have to read it off the page and its spoken text Liza: yeah but I don’t think if your not reading a long it counts as text, like, there’s books on tape, I know some people that prefer that, and because you don’t have the book right in front of you, I don’t think its seen as text anymore. Sara: But isn’t the person on the tape reading text? Liza: they’re reading text but to you its not really text anymore. Cause you don’t have words (Caitlin: text is something you can see it isn’t what you hear) on a page to look at. Michael: But can’t hearing a book being read to you in the same way reading a text, create sort of all of the images and thoughts that reading the book would? Several: yeah..uh—huh [Much skepticism] 91 Liza: but also you’d see different things cause you would have, more time, time to actually think about em. Cause your not concentrating on going back to the next word, and you know seeing, and if your being read to you can think of other things and not pay attention and see things differently. Janice: But its kind of the same kind of thing, just different Michael: How’s it different? Janice: Well, like she said, if your being read a book or something you have more time to concentrate on the image instead of the words Mika: you can go at your own pace and you can look back, like you have to actually focus on reading, its not like some people can listen to something and do something else. When your reading most of the time you have to actually focus on reading, (T: okay) so you absorb most of the material. Michael: When I, let’s see, if I see two people, I’m just sitting in front of the building, and I see two people meet, and one person, ya know, shakes the other person’s hand, and they’re talking, and one person looks like they get really angry and they, they sort of stomp off and I look at that situation, I have some understanding, I mean, I can sort of make up a story about what just happened there, ya know somebody just got really mad about something and they disagreed and they stomped off. . Did I read that situation. Mika: In a sense James: It depends how your translating it. Liza: you didn’t read it. 92 Sophie: by the definition text is something written down on a page. Mika: you read into what information you gathered Chen: you read signals to Liza: you don’t read through your mind and form the words Sophie: its not text cause text is written on a page Michael: did we say that it had to be words on a page or an author’s intent? Linda: I know like, at the library books on tape are considered audio-text because your listening to the author’s words James: Isn’t that word contradictive though, audio-text, think about it, audio—sound, text—written. Michael: Why is it contradictory? Matt: a text doesn’t have to be written down Anna: well we’re defining text right now it doesn’t necessarily have to bem(inaudible) Matt: according to the first half of our definition it doesn’t need to be written down Nyali: yeah it doesn’t have to be written down it just mean’s somebody’s reading it Tayler: Let me ask something, let me ask something for all of you. Are we all agreed to the idea that text is always in written form? Several students (in different tones of voice): no; no; ugh-ugh; mmngh-mmngh; that’s what we’re talking about! Tayler: okay, alright (apologetically) 93 Michael: Well, if, if reading a book and listening to a book being read, or listening to a song, all make you think of things, and you know, feel things, do what they do, why couldn’t we consider them all, and perhaps other things, texts? Janice: Because I think that everyone has always like, kinda been taught that you have to read it for it to be text. Caitie: It’s not that you read it, because like, if I hear a song on the radio, the words to the song would be text, but if I know the song from memory, then I can just sing it without reading anything or hearing the radio. Nyal: Well that would be the author’s words. Caitlin: yeah but it wouldn’t have to be reading. Michael: So when I see two people arguing across the street, and I make up an explanation for what happened between them, (Nyal: you’re the author) aren’t I the author? Several: yeah, yes Liza: but if you write it down and someone else reads it, it is text but its not (inaudible) Michael: what if I tell somebody, like I just told you Sophie: if you actually say it in words then I think it is text. .but it has to be the actual words Caitie: But then everything that you think in your head would be text because you’re the author of your thoughtsm ———-End Data Segment-—-— 94 Intrigued by the critique of texts we engaged in during year two, I designed this section of the course, where we would look at three different representations of the same historical time period (the arrival of Columbus to the Americas), to see if I could cultivate a more intensive critique of texts and get into issues of “representation”. Why these issues? Between the second and third year of philosophy I undertook a more serious study of both critical and poststructural ideas. Between year one and two, I became sensitive to the constructed, ideological position of texts; between year two and three, I read Derrida, and seriously considered his phrase, “there is no outside text” (Derrida, 1976). I became sensitive to issues of textuality. As Derrida (1982) states, It is precisely for strategic reasons that I find it necessary to recast the concept of the text by generalizing it almost without limit, without any limit that is. That’s why there is nothing ‘beyond the text’. That’s why South Africa and apartheid are, like you and me, part of this general text, which is not to say that it can be read as one reads a book. That’s why the text is always a field of forces: heterogeneous, differential, open. That’s why deconstructive readings are concerned not only with library books. . .they are not simply analyses of discourse. They are also effective or active 95 interventions that transform contexts without limiting themselves to theoretical utterances even though they must also produce such utterances. (p. 167—8) The idea of textuality, that features of the world are subject to interpretation and readings that consider the discursive formations, and must be read in multiple ways to unearth differential relations of power and ideological positions, is a powerful one that changed the way I think of reading. This explodes the notion of reading as potential readers become interpreters who interpret for different purposes depending on their time, place, status in society and gender (amongst other things) (Cherryholmes, 1999). These politicized notions of text and reading come from poststructural thinking, which can be characterized by, Attention to questions of language, power and desire that emphasizes the contexts in which meaning is produced and makes problematic all universal truth and meaning claims; a suspicion of binary, opposition thinking. . .; a suspicion of the figure of the humanistic human subject, challenging the assumptions of autonomy and transparent self—consciousness while situating the subject as a complex intersections of discursive, libidinal, and social forces and practices; [and] a resistance to claims of unversality and unity, preferring instead to acknowledge difference and fragmentation (Schrift, 1996, p. 452). 96 At many points in this discussion it occurred to me that our discussion had strong poststructural undertones. We were talking about what texts were, what authors were, and what it meant to read. The shifts in my own thinking from year one to year two helped me make space in the community’s discourse for previously illegitimate activities (critique of texts). Shifts in my thinking from year two to year three opened up more space not only for textual critique but also for topics not previously explored in philosophy for children, at least not in any of the discussions I had led or observed. In fact, my orientation in the third year (in one of the sections of philosophy) even caused me to break from using any of the canonical texts normally used in this teaching. I chose only a few works of literature to try out this representation and historical place experiment, the rest of the text came from the students: Topics they wanted to talk about, things they wanted to read, shared experiences from their own lives in and out of school. I will say more about the overall implications of this first attempt at teaching in a postmodern social 97 constructivist way in the chapter on implications, but this analysis gives one demonstration of the shift in my teaching from year one through to year three. The shifts in my views on the treatment of texts created new spaces in the community of inquiry for critique and discussions of textuality and readings where there was once only room for exegesis. Analysis 2: Opening Day At the beginning of year two, I remember thinking, “I don’t want to start class this way”. In the first and second year of the philosophy class I began the first day of class with an exercise central to the teaching of philosophy for children. The exercise begins when I ask my students, “what is a question?" When I initiated this exercise in year one, I did not doubt the merit of this inquiry. After all, questions and question asking are central to philosophical inquiry. When I began class in year two, I was less comfortable with beginning the class in this way, but I did not understand enough about my mixed feelings to change what I was doing. In year three I understood my ambivalence 98 a little more, and decided to do things differently. The following analysis compares the opening day of the first and third year classes. In year one, the first day of philosophy class opens (after customary introductions) with me putting forth a question for the class to consider. The question I posed is, “What is a question?” The students’ offered several different responses to this question that had to do with “why” we ask questions. For example, Greg said: “A person asks questions when they want to know something or find something out.” Basically, they responded to my question by giving several different reasons that a person might ask a question. Reasons like, to find out information, to indirectly command (“Could someone close the door?”), to begin an inquiry (“Why are frogs green?”), or, for the questioner to open a place to speak for themselves, like when a teacher asks a rhetorical question (“How did World War I begin?”). They were very familiar with questions like this. The students’, with some gentle prodding from me, generated quite an impressive list of reasons why a person 99 might ask a question. We made a list on the board of some purposes we have for asking questions. 1. When we don’t know 2. When we want more information 3. When we don’t understand 4. When we want to know the truth 5. When we tell a joke 6. As a polite command 7. When we are suspicious or want to accuse someone 8. When we already know the answer but want to see if others know (teachers do this) 9. When we want to allow ourselves to speak (rhetorical) I asked the students this question to “get them” thinking about something important to philosophy (asking questions), which they may not have thought much about before. The list they generated is noteworthy for its variety. I paraphrased the students’ contributions when I listed them on the board (I put the students’ contributions in my words). The activity looked very much like a traditional Initiate—Respond-Evaluate (Cazden 1988) 100 exercise where the teacher asks a question, waits for a response, and then evaluates the student’s response. I spent a lot of time handling each contribution, asking follow—up questions, and asking the students to think of examples from their own experience. Short discussions came out of several of the responses but not all of them. We then spent several minutes talking about rhetorical questions and I gave a short lecture near the end of this class period where I explained that, “the asking of questions is very important in philosophy, will be important to what we do in this class, and will be something I want you to do whenever a question occurs to you.” This topic was important to me. In traditional Philosophy for Children teaching, encouraging students to ask questions, especially questions of the form, “What is X?” is a form that lies at the heart of Philosophy. Philosophers have been asking “what is” questions for at least two thousands years. The very form of this question Suggests that there is “something” at the heart of the Inatter, in this case, at the heart of a question. 101 Customarily philosophers have asked this question in search of a fundamental nature or essence. Plato is perhaps most famous for this as most of his dialogues feature Socrates conversing with some interlocutor over the nature of justice, beauty, love, piety, etc. Interestingly enough, I do not announce to my class that there is such a nature to questions, nor do I insist that their inquiry yield a definition that would serve as essence. In fact, I allow the class to shift the discussion to the purposes of question asking, a decidedly different project than essence finding. I do this in much the same way Socrates will allow his interlocutor to offer examples of justice just so he can later pounce on their indiscretion of offering many where there should only be one. But I do not pounce. While I phrase my question in the traditional manner, “What is X?”, I do not insist, as Socrates does, that an identity be made, “A question is X." However, I do have the students’ create a list of possible X’s, and I do consider this topic central to the discipline. 102 I was very directive in trying to explore this issue of questions. I focussed on picking this issue apart. I really wanted to explore the different kinds of questions that can be asked, and I really wanted to get at the students’ understandings of what kinds of questions are in their world. I jumped all over the response from one student who brought up the subject of rhetorical questions. I remarked, “I think you're right”. . .“sidebar” and point out to students that if you take the “a” and the “1” off of rhetorical, you get the word rhetoric. Then I ask the students if they know what rhetoric is. When a student offers an example of what they think rhetoric is. I side— step it and begin to lecture about what rhetoric is. I was thinking about rhetoric as a branch of philosophy attributed to the Sophists (particularly Protagoras) that has to do with making the weaker argument .the stronger, or, the art of argument: I was thinking about it in classical terms for the most part. At this point, I was centered on the idea that my students’ need to understand the importance of question asking to the enterprise of philosophical discourse. I 103 began the year one philosophy class with a typical topic and taught them things about question asking that I believed they were unaware of. Also, I believed that they needed to know something about “questions”. I remember feeling very ambivalent about this class session when it ended. This ambivalence lingered with me for months, and with even greater ambivalence and more doubt, I did the same opening exercise in year two. However, communing with the critical and postmodern ideas mentioned in the “treatment of text” analysis forced me to reconsider the introduction to the course, and in year three of the philosophy class I started things out differently. In year three I began the first discussion of the course in a similar, yet importantly different way. I did ask the students a question, but it was not a question about something so central to philosophical inquiry as asking them to consider the nature of question asking. I asked them, “Why are you here?" “Why are you here. . .in school, now, this summer,”. The following discussion ensued: Michael: Dean did you have something? 104 Dean: Um, cause we’re smart. Michael: Cause your smart?. .okay Carrie: I’m here cause I like to learn. I like school. Michael: You like school, you like to learn Dean: Cause summer’s boring. .without anything to do Michael: Okay, so this is better than -— Dan: Watching TV or something Michael: (revoices) Watching TV (at the same time) Oliver: I would be sleeping right now. Donna: (hesitantly) Umm, my parents made me Michael: your parents made you, alright, that’s an honest answer Oliver: I liked the listing of the topics that they had Michael: So you read the course descriptions and this sounded interesting, more interesting than your alternatives? Did you have any alternatives? What were the alternatives? Oliver: Um, I go down to a parking lot that has a big (couldn’t hear) in it and play. Michael: Alright, so this was better than that, at least seemed better than that. . . Others. .why are you here? Jack: At first like I wanted to take the two computer classes, and neuroscience, but they changed neuroscience and both the computer classes were filled up. So then I thought that philosophy 1 would be okay. ~——End Data Segment—-— 105 What is important about this shift in opening topics is that starting the courses in such different ways arose out of a certain discontent with stance in the first years of philosophy. I began to question why it was I would start the class in the way I did when I did not even know how the students had come to be in this class in the first place. These concerns were spurred on by my postmodern and critical studies which speak of the importance of time, place, location, in short, context. I thought to myself, if I begin the class with a lesson on question asking, and the importance of rhetorical questions, yet I do not even know how these students have come to be in my class, then I am guilty of beginning my relationship with these students without an appreciation for the context of our situation. This did not sit well with me as it did not reflect the appreciation I began to have for the contextual factors that determine much of our existence. It was important for me to know that Donna was in my class, in fact the program itself, because her parents made her. It was important for me to know that philosophy was Jack’s last choice, and that he really wanted to be in the computer classes. It was 106 important for me to understand that several of my student’s did not know why they were in the program let alone this class. This was, I think, the beginning of my trying to translate into pedagogy the postmodern concerns of historical location and one’s place in their social world. On one level, this is not just an attempt by me to appreciate something of my students’ situation, it is me trying to make my students’ motives a more explicit consideration of the class curriculum. As I look back to year one, I can construct a plausible motive for my question exercise: I was trying to find out what my students’ understood about questions so I could make use of those understandings in our discussion of the importance of question asking in philosophical inquiry. But I was not trying to understand my students in any meaningful way that would help me understand their motives. In some ways this distinction is subtle, because in both cases I am asking the students for information about themselves: in the first case a question about their understandings of questions and in the second case a question about their purpose for being 107 in the philosophy class. This difference has two important implications. First, I am still asking a question, and initiating the first inquiry of the class. One of the seductive, even illusory elements of constructivism is that it can lead us to believe that there is more freedom for students than is really the case. While in certain respects there is more freedom, the notion that there is considerably more freedom is a seductive illusion. So, while my asking students to share their personal experiences about question asking was inspired by a commitment to a modern constructivist teaching, I chose and asked the question and I shaped the discussion to illustrate something I wanted students to understand. Secondly, year three was different from the standpoint that I felt the need to appreciate my students’ situation in relation to the course. I did not have a specific motive for asking them that was tied to getting them to understand something about philosophical inquiry. It was meant to allow me to appreciate the circumstances by which they have come to be in the class. This reflects an attempt to 108 appreciate our place in time and society, and the situated condition of our circumstance. Analysis 3: Topics of Discussion In a further attempt to understand the differences in the three years of philosophy teaching and the dilemma of constructivism I have confronted, I decided to look across the topics of discussion for each of the years of the philosophical inquiry class. I believe this to be another way of looking at my stance as a teacher shifting from a modern form of constructivism to a more postmodern social constructivism. In Figure 1, I have listed the topics of discussion for each year of the philosophy. This Figure will allow for a quick comparison between the topics. One thing that is apparent as I look across the topics we discussed across the three years is the focus, during year one, on topics that are central to philosophical inquiry in the philosophy for children tradition. One aspect of this that is important is the fact the these are topics that, one way or another, I knew would become part of the class before the class even started. Syllogisms, the 109 values of the community of inquiry, making arguments, questions, etc. are all topics I would make it a point to bring up in my classes. Several of the other topics came directly out of the printed texts we were dealing with. The questions “Who are you?”, and “Where does the world come from?”, as well as the discussion about Plato and Aristotle, came directly out of Sophie’s World (1994). The topic of animal/human rights came directly out of the Philosophy for Children novel, Lisa (1983). While a few of the topics on that list were introduced by the students, they were sanctioned topics from the standpoint that they came out of the printed texts we were reading. The fact that almost all of the topics we discussed were either pre-selected by me or came directly from the printed texts we read suggest to me that the constructivist teaching going on here had more to do with how the Students’ experiences, developing understandings, and background knowledge were related to topics that were not so much of their choosing as they were mine. And while I allowed a fair amount of space with regard to how the 110 Table 1: Analysis of Discussion Topics Across Three years of Philosophy a -What is a Question? -Who are you? — Where does the world come from? —Syllogisms/If—then statements/All statements (Logic) —What are we doing in philosophy? —Creation and Evolution and Religious Belief —Animal Rights/Human Rights —Values of Community of Inquiry —Plato and Aristotle on Society -Making arguments -Cultural Relativism/Ethical relativism 23 —What is a Question? —Purpose of Life —Freedom of Speech/Rights —Friendship —What happens in our discussions -Religion and Mythology —Belief and action —Political correctness— Popular Culture -Disney’s distortion of historical events -Identity and role playing —What it means to be a living being (medical ethics) —Pro—life vs. Pro— choice —Morality- Consistency of belief and action —Time/Calendars— Measuring time 111 93 -Why are you here? —Ways of Reading/ Perspective —Student response to literature —We give ourselves Native American Names—Meaning of a name —Historical Fiction and Textbook representation of history —Text and Textuality —Historical Location—Context -Who writes History? —Perspective —Forms of Government -Power/Media Influence —Peer pressure as an indirect form of media influence -Sharing Music & Poetry —Eastern Philosophy students related to these topics in our discussions, the students’ interests did not really become primary texts for the class. My teaching stuck very close to my mission of cultivating formal philosophical discourse (Pardales and Cervetti, 1999). In the second year topics are related to the printed texts, but, we take a decided step away from a pre- determined set of topics. Four of the first five topics we discuss are either brought up by me or come from the printed texts we are engaged with. The topics related to political correctness, Disney’s distortion of history, and Identity and Role playing were brought up by the students, but the life I helped give them in our discussion was influenced by my readings in critical pedagogy. These topics stemmed from issues the students’ raised and seemed interested in. But, the direction I took these conversations in was influenced by my interests as well. One key moment in our discussion over Disney movies occurred when I made a move that was uncharacteristic of my teaching in prior years. I asked the students if they would 112 consider taking action against the distorted portrayal of Pocahontas in the Disney movie of the same name. ———-Begin Data Segment ————— Jana: I mean like in Disney shows, like MULAN, you wouldn't have seen that back in 1970, 1960. But like it still has like the same plot and the same basic meaning. But it has different womanly heroic characters. It's still the same thing, though. It's really not much different. Michael: Is there anything that we could do to make things actually change? Shauna: Write Disney and send them a whole bunch of angry letters? Chris: Yeah! Bryan: In my class, we kind of almost did that once, but nobody really wanted to go through with it. Michael: What —- what kind of letter might we write if we were going to write one. Lucia: Well, like say don't always make the girls get rescued by the guys. Try to make it equal and like try to stay true to the story. Seely: Stop corrupting our society. Lucia: And they shouldn't take like historical events and sort of totally rewrite them just to make a movie. If they're trying to inform kids about like history, then it's not the way to do it by changing it. When everyone dies, they shouldn't be like they all live happily ever after. bdichael: Would you --. 113 Matt: They should just end it before they die. Michael: Is there any interest amongst you in doing that? Bryan: I would. Seely: I would. James: I wrote a letter to the Kool cigarette company, but I never sent it. ———End Data Segment--— I had never before proposed that we move from our discussion towards taking some action related to what we talked about. The students’ showed a lot of interest in discussing how many of the movies they watch are distorted or re—written for greater appeal. I definitely encouraged this kind of critique. In particular, it was passages from Giroux’s (1996) book Fugitive Culture’s that spurred me in this direction, Given the influence that the Disney ideology has on children, it is imperative for parents, teachers, and other adults to understand how such films attract the attention and shape the values of the children who view and buy them. As a producer of children’s culture, Disney should not be given an easy pardon because it is defined as a universal citadel of fun and good cheer. On the contrary, as one of the primary institutions constructing childhood culture in the United States, it warrants healthy suspicion and critical debate. Such a debate should be limited to the home, but should be a central feature of the 114 school and any other critical public sites of learning. (pp. 95—96) So, while I did involve the students’ interests as a more significant subject of the class, I also encouraged a different kind of inquiry in the second year. In this way my teaching was more social constructivist than it was in the first year, but in some ways, aspects of my philosophical agenda were replaced by my burgeoning critical agenda. In Class B (00), I made a sincere attempt at letting the students’ background experiences and interests become genuine texts in our class. I still needed to chose some printed texts for the class and have some activities planned, but more than I ever have before, I tried to harbor less of a pre-determined agenda. And while having less of a pre—determined agenda is still an agenda, I was determined to dictate fewer of the topics of discussion. We began with a different kind of question, and over the next several days, we talked about the student’s responses to the novels we were reading. I let our conversations in 115 these days revolve around what the students found interesting in the novels. One of the activities I did design was the reading of three different texts that provided different representations of Columbus’s arrival to North America. This activity resulted in our discussions about historical fiction/representation, text/textuality, who writes history, and historical location. The rest of the topics were ones that came directly from the students; in other words, they told me explicitly that they wanted to discuss these other topics. 116 Chapter 5 Discussion The analyses made in the previous chapter were conducted in order to help me answer the research questions stated in chapter three. I will now respond to each of these questions and offer some response to them based on my analyses. 1) How does a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy differ (for the teacher) from a modern form of constructivism? When I taught philosophy in 98, my goal was clear: teach my students philosophical inquiry. Do this by apprenticing the students to philosophical ways of talking, thereby helping them internalize the discourse of philosophy and think more critically and reasonably. I actively scaffolded students’ 3 induction into this discourse. I would publicly identify when good reasons were given, arguments were constructed, 3In year one, some of the students were very willing to be inducted, others less so, and some, resistant. I concerned myself with the first two groups mostly. There was even one student, who, while very interested in traditional philosophical topics, was consistently ignored by me because her attempts to bring up these topics did not mesh with the agenda I had. I have not stopped thinking about my treatment of this student and fear she left my class quite frustrated and justifiably soured to my brand of philosophical inquiry, probably to anything called philosophy. 117 effective counterexamples were offered, and when sound reasoning was portrayed. And when students' attempts at participation fell outside of these acceptable forms of participation, sometimes I would re—voice a contribution so that it took the form I deemed appropriate, other times I would ask students’ to reconsider what or how they said what they said. It is clear though, I clear in my purpose and way of teaching philosophy to them. I wanted my students to understand something of philosophical discourse. My agenda was clear (at least to me). Both the form and content of our discussions was important to me, and I largely controlled both. By any normal standards, I was engaged in modern, social constructivist philosophy teaching. Also in year one, I tried to include my students’ experiences, background knowledge, and developing understandings into discussions even though I largely influenced most of the topics and the rules of engagement. I felt compelled to form a community of philosophical inquiry. I was enacting a social constructivist pedagogy, just not a postmodern social constructivism. 118 In year two, I was ambivalent towards the project of teaching philosophical inquiry displayed in year one of this study. My studies of critical pedagogy led me to be suspicious of attempts to apprentice others and made me very sensitive to the act of imposing the discourse of reason (philosophy) onto my students. I began to think of myself as colonizing an exploiting an unsuspecting people. I also began to question what at one time seemed to me a tacit good, the teaching of rational argumentation and critical thinking. The privileging of reason was largely a product of Enlightenment rationality which my readings in post—structuralism and critical pedagogy had forced me to begin to criticize. This gave me reason to want to include more of my students’ experiences and to take a softer line toward my influencing of both the form and content of our discussions. I encouraged social critique, and in one instance, a pivotal moment in this summer’s teaching, I even encouraged social action. I was more genuinely open to the students making their specific interests part of the text of the class. And this is evidenced in how a larger 119 proportion of the topics we discussed were not the traditional projects detailed in year one. Yet, by year three, I had even begun to question my encouragement of a critical pedagogy style of social critique and action. As Elizabeth Ellsworth (1989) argues, critical pedagogy, is still tied to the mastery and masterfulness of reason with the consequence that the role of the critical pedagogue becomes one of ensuring that students are given the chance to arrive at the “universally valid proposition” underlying the discourse of critical pedagogy - namely, that all people have a right to freedom from oppression guaranteed by the democratic social contract — in other words, there is the danger of an agenda being established where learners are led to pre—defined goals; (p. 304) Ellsworth goes on to argue that critical pedagogy, masks a reconfiguration of the imbalance of power between teacher and student in its discourse of empowerment and dialogue: student empowerment has been defined in the broadest possible humanist terms, and becomes a “capacity to act effectively" in a way that fails to challenge any identifiable social or political position, institution, or group. (p. 307) Adhering to modern social constructivist premises of teaching, which critical pedagogy can be included as, can put a teacher into a position of creating illusions for 120 themselves. These illusions are potentially dangerous as they can compel a teacher to think they are doing something much more innocent that they are. By taking students’ ideas, background knowledge, and life experience seriously, a teacher can seduce himself into believing that he is imposing less on students. A teacher can deceive himself—- believing he is starting from where the students are. Thus, the teacher can be lulled into the idea that he is really allowing the students’ concerns and interests to become primary texts of the class when he is actually seducing students into learning what he wanted them to learn in the first place. A teacher may also be seducing himself into believing he is being more humane to his students than if he were inconsiderate of students’ background knowledge, experiences, and beliefs. The seduction is strong. Even in year three I was bringing some modern ideas/structures into the text of the class, sometimes overtly sometimes covertly. To the extent that I made these topics central to the teaching, and did not render my motivations transparent 121 to my students, I was engaged in as insincere a form of constructivist teaching as I was in year one. Alas, was my teaching in year three really any different than what I did in year one/two? Is it anymore sincere or insincere than my teaching in year one/two? When, in year three, some of the postmodern social constructivist elements were present (textuality, authority, power, etc.) I made it clear what I thought the issue was and why I believed it to be worth discussion. I tried very hard to only discuss these topics as they seemed pertinent to the students’ experiences. I was less covert in my actions and I think I presented a style of teaching that was more transparent. I began to see that one has to have an agenda, or at least be part of a system that demands that one have an agenda, in order to teach. Trying to rid myself of an agenda led me to a brief state of paralysis. I did not know what or how to teach. So, with a much more modest and open agenda than ever before, I still entered my teaching of class B—-year three--with the agenda of being sensitive and open to the elements of a postmodern social constructivism 122 as well as my students’ interests and experiences. The only position I have been able to live with is to resolve to be forthright with my students about what I consider important and why. To justify to my students what I think I am doing, how I view their role in the process, why I think this activity is important to them, and to be sincere in my attempts at actually making student texts a part of the curriculum of the class. Even this stance, though, must be accompanied by a willingness to open up aspects of one’s teaching to scrutiny by oneself and one’s students. I do not think I did as good a job of this in my third year of teaching as I might have. I did this far more than I did in either of the first two years, but, there is still plenty of room for reducing illusion and increasing sincerity. I am using the term “sincerity” to indicate a forthrightness and honesty regarding what it is I thought I was teaching. In year one/two I was not honest with my students about the discourse I was attempting to initiate my students’ into. In some ways I wanted to induct them without their awareness of what they were being inducted in to. This reflected the belief I had that we learn best by 123 assimilation (Gee, 1989). My project in year one/two was to get students to internalize the discourse of philosophy by following the norms of philosophical inquiry (in year one), and social critique associated with critical pedagogy (in year two). To the extent that I was not honest or forthright about my intentions and use of the students’ ideas, experiences and understandings, I was engaged in an insincere form of social constructivist teaching. My motivations remained opaque instead of more transparent. Regarding the aspect of my theorizing about a postmodern social constructivism, there was one thing I was not able to achieve. I never managed to open a critique of the discipline of philosophy in my classroom. One reason for this was that I was unsure I was still teaching philosophy. One would have to have some understanding of a discipline in order to critique it, and while in year one I taught a method of philosophy that the students had learned enough about to critique (Pardales & Cervetti, 1998), I was far less clear of what it was we would critique in year three. Postmodern social constructivists do critique the very enterprise of disciplinary inquiry, but we were not in 124 a position to critique philosophy in year three because we were doing as much literary criticism, social and political critique, and historiography as we were doing something that resembled philosophy. I personally engaged in many critiques of the discipline, and the enterprise of philosophy over the course of this study, but never was able to make disciplinary critique of philosophy a substantive part of the class.4 2) How does a teacher trying to enact a postmodern social constructivist pedagogy remain faithful to both subject matter and their students’ ideas, experiences, and developing understandings? In year one of philosophy class I faithfully enacted the teaching of philosophical inquiry as outlined in Philosophy for Children. To this extent, I enacted a modern from of social constructivism and as outlined above, introduced formal philosophical inquiry to my students, and initiated 4We came close one day in year two when we talked about the distinctions between mythology, religion, and fables. This discussion bordered on disciplinary critique from the standpoint that we were discussing genres of writing. Also, in year three, Class B, we engaged in a similar exercise when we talked about “who writes history”, which broached the topic of the differences between fictional and non- fictional representations of history. Considering aspects of 125 them into the discourse of philosophy. This was my primary objective and I did not have, as a central concern, this tension between the curriculum on one hand, and disciplinary faithfulness on the other. I took students’ ideas, experiences, and developing understandings into consideration in service to the apprenticing of my students into philosophical discourse. In year two I sought to make students’ ideas experiences, and developing understandings (i.e. student texts) a more genuine part of the class, and this was evidenced in the way I took students’ critique of texts and topical interests more seriously. But as the analysis of topics suggested, this lead us into areas not traditionally part of philosophy for children discussions. And my encouragement of social critique and aspects of a critical pedagogy brought discussions and printed texts not traditionally part of philosophical discourse. We began to transgress and cross the tradition borders of philosophy. By year three we were engaged in an activity genuinely different. Student texts became primary texts for the class disciplinary faithfulness is the subject of my second research 126 and I no longer worried about an ultimate balance between student texts and traditional philosophical texts. We read and responded to literature according to student interests and we embarked on discussions over topics that were of concern to the students. Of course, I did initiate some discussions and topics that were aligned to issues related to my burgeoning postmodern concerns. But my agenda here was less dogmatic than it was in year one, and I tried to make my motivations for raising such topics more transparent to the students. In short, I tried to justify why I thought such issues were important. It is pertinent to raise the question of whether we were still doing philosophy in year three. As I argued earlier, we seemed to be engaged in reader response to literature and a more open—ended style of dialogical inquiry about the printed texts we were reading and the students’ emergent texts. It could even be described as a rhetorical inquiry of a particular sort; we spent a lot of time considering how we use language and words. This leads me to suggest that when one makes student texts a question. 127 significant part of the inquiry, it becomes difficult to remain squarely within the borders of a discipline. 3) What role does “community of inquiry" play in modern and postmodern forms constructivism? As I argued in chapter two, community of inquiry can be applied to groups of students in classrooms, or, to the practitioners of a discipline like history or chemistry. Peirce theorized that philosophy should adopt the kind of community of inquiry that characterized communities of inquiring scientists where each scientist was faithful to the scientific method as they made their own individual inquiries and then subjected his/her findings to public scrutiny. Dewey naturalized this conception of community of inquiry and applied it to schooling. Lipman gave a distinctive characterization of philosophical communities of inquiry while arguing for the place of philosophy in K- 12 education. Other thinkers have called for the creation of communities of inquiry as the new form groups of teachers and students should adopt. This would yield classrooms where teachers and students would inquire into topics of mutual interest with one another. Classrooms 128 would become places where interest—inspired inquiry would become the new curriculum, replacing the model where teachers and other authorities alone dictated what and how things are learned. This is especially the case where an inquiry approach to education is being practiced because an inquiry approach, with its emphasis on student interests, i is used to structure discussion. In each year of the philosophy classes, 1“.“ III. u-— characteristics of a community of inquiry specified in chapter two were enacted. But in year one, the community of inquiry was less genuine. I say it was less genuine because I largely dictated both the content and rules of participation in the community; in the year one class the community was one mostly by my designation and not one of the communities creation. One person does not a community make. One aspect of a group of people being a community is that they, to some extent, dictate the terms of their relationship to one another. Now, there are many instances where individuals join communities and accept that the rules they are agreeing to are not one’s of their making. In fact, joining a political, social, or academic 129 organization often requires that one accept certain terms of membership without having a say in those terms. But communities of inquiry in classrooms, where the community’s mandate requires that student interest, and mutual respect and concern, are key elements of the community, requires that the members of the community be active in determining some of the constitution of the community. Apart from the unspoken agreements that are part of any classroom environment, this did not happen in any significant way in year one or year two. As the teacher, I imposed the rules of engagement and the mandate that we do philosophical inquiry. In year one and two I even presented an exercise from a philosophy for children teaching manual that gave characterizations of behaviors that were and were not part of communities of inquiry. My job was to engage students in a discussion of the behaviors on this approved list and get them to agree to the behaviors that were sanctioned as legitimate aspects of a community of inquiry. If I had allowed the space for a more genuine critique of the values and behaviors of community of inquiry, this 130 would not have been a problem. But I did not allow for this space. A community of inquirers must have some freedom to dictate how it will operate and what it will operate on. In the first two years of philosophy I never opened up a space for the class to talk about how we should be with one another. In year two I allowed more space for student inspired topics of discussion to be legitimate parts of the class, but I did not allow for or create a space for the community to negotiate its own terms. And while most of the communities we belong to are not constituted by our preferences, philosophical communities of inquiry are supposed to be more genuine in their determination of community constitution. In year three, we did have some discussions of how we would be with one another. On two occasions, in each of the classes, the students put forth the idea that on some occasions it would be good for students who wanted to discuss particular topics to break off into small groups and have separate discussions. They also decided that we 131 could do things that would make it more conducive to a larger number of people participating in our discussion. Though I attempted to create spaces where students might dictate the terms by which we would become a community in year three, I still have a long way to go in re—thinking what community of inquiry will mean in my teaching. As I ask myself the question, “Was community present during any of the years of philosophy class?” many thoughts arise. My purpose in asking the question is not to answer “yes” or “no” so much as to consider of what importance community is in my teaching of philosophy. In Peirce’s conception of community of inquiry, the community was important because it held the public criteria by which scientific work would be inspired, critiqued, scrutinized, and legitimated. In Philosophy for children the community served these purposes though focussed on one’s reasoning over philosophical matters; it was also a place where mutual respect and concern for all participants is a primary value. But the term “community” denotes a fellowship or togetherness that may not be a necessary condition for the kind of inquiry we had in the philosophy 132 classes. Community might be something to strive for, but takes a long time to develop, and may not be essential. In the meantime, teachers can still try to have inquiry be a sincere part of the day by limiting the topics of possible inquiries to those topics mandated by districts and tests. The work of Ball and Levine—Rose are exemplary on this point. While I consider this somewhat of a compromise, to act otherwise could handicap students in an environment where their futures are heavily determined by high—stakes tests. A Look to This Summer's Philosophy Class In the coming Summer (2001) I will again teach philosophical inquiry. If I had the power to change the title of the course, which I will next year if I am still teaching in the same program, I would rename it “Philosophical Encounters with Literature”. I say this because, while we still engage in many of the activities related to philosophical inquiry mentioned in chapter 2, issues of reading have begun to be more important and central to the class. Because of this, I have chosen more 133 genuine literary texts that take on postmodern issues, and, I am resolved to make student text a legitimate part of the course curriculum. Language, representation, power, textuality, etc. will become important themes in the class that I will attempt to occasionally culture and justify to my students. In this way we will be engaging in some of the same things members of a literary criticism class might. We will make central to our projects reading, discussions of perspective, interpretation, and other topics that the students deem important. I will do my best to be sincere with the students when I take a discussion in a particular direction or am pushing an aspect of my agenda. Concluding Remarks The analyses I made of the data suggest that social constructivist teaching can have potential dilemmas of reading and sincerity. I would like to offer some final remarks on these dilemmas. The problem of reading came out most clearly in the first analysis made in chapter 4. In that analysis I showed how my stance toward the purposes of reading contributed to 134 different treatments of text, and hence, very different kinds of activities and discussions in my classroom. As I began to think about texts differently the issue of what to read, how to read, and what reading is, led into issues of textuality. We moved from reading traditional philosophy for children texts and issues to reading less traditional texts, and, more of the students' experiences and understandings. My own notion of reading exploded and this effected the kinds of discussions we had in class. We moved from doing mostly exegesis to treating texts as socially constructed artifacts, and eventually, we discussed texts as representations of ideology and power. We began to read the world. The other issue central to this dissertation is that of sincerity. I used the term sincerity in at least three different ways earlier in this chapter. The three ways are, 1) being clear and up-front with my students and myself about what my agenda for the class is; 2) taking students’ ideas and understandings seriously enough to allow them to become curriculum, and, 3) having a modest vision of the goals of the class, and creating a genuine space for students to develop their own understandings. 135 In chapter 1 I suggested that constructivist views of teaching which claim to take students’ ideas, interests, and understandings into consideration, but, which only do so in order to teach a well defined, pre—determined, curriculum, can be charged with being a seductive form of humanism that is at best illusory and at worst insincere. To the extent that I taught philosophy with a clear vision of the end product our class discussions were to conform to, I was engaged in what I think was a less than sincere form of social constructivism. It is rarely, if ever, possible to be completely honest or transparent. After all, there are times when we are not clear about our own motivations. For this reason, it would be futile for me to advocate the strong position that, “we must always be completely honest about our agendas with our students”. I submit the idea that it is insincere for teachers to use constructivist thinking in support of deceiving their students in ways that allow them to more comfortably transmit specific content. This is an insincere use of constructivist thinking and I submit that there is more to be gained by being sincere in one’s 136 teaching in the ways I discussed. Given my discussion of the issues of sincerity in one’s teaching, for constructivists especially, it can no longer be ignored. 137 REFERENCES 138 REFERENCES Anderson, R., Chin, C. Waggoner, M. Nguyen, K. (1998). Intellectually Stimulating Story Discussions. In J. Osborn & F. Lehr (Eds.) literacy for all: Issues In Teaching And Learning. (pp. 170—186). New York, NY: Guilford Press. Ball, D. L. & Bass, H. (2000). Making Believe: The Collective Construction of Public Mathematical Knowledge in the Elementary Classroom. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety— ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ball, D. L. (1993). With an Eye on the Mathematical Horizon: Dilemmas of Teaching Elementary School Mathematics. Elementary School Journal 93: 373—397. Ball, D. L. & Chazan, D. (1999). Beyond Being Told What to Tell. The Learning of Mathematics (9) July. Baumann, J. F. (1996). Conflict or compatibility in classroom inquiry? One teacher's struggle to balance teaching and research. Educational Researcher, 25, 29- 36. Best, S. & Kellner, D. (1991). Postmodern Theory. New York: Guilford Press. Bloor, D. (1976). Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Bredo, E. (2000). Reconsidering Social Constructivism: The Relevance of George Herbert Mead’s Interactionism. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety—ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the 139 Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Bridges, L. (1995). Creating Your Classroom Community. York: Stenhouse Publishers Brookfield, S. D. (1995). Becoming a critically reflective teacher. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass. Brown, J. S., Collins, A. and Guguid, P. (1989). Situated Cognition and the Culture of Learning. Educational Researcher, 18, 32-42. Bruner, J. (1985). vygotsky: A Historical and Conceptual Perspective. In James V. Wertsch (Ed.) Culture, Communication, and Cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bruner, J. (1960). The Process of Education. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Burbules, N. (2000). Moving Beyond the Impasse. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety- ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Cazden, C. (1988). Classroom Discourse: The Language of Teachingand Learning. Portsmouth, NH: Heinemann Cervetti, G., Pardales, M.J., & Damico, J.S. (2001, April). A tale of differences: Comparing the traditions, perspectives, and educational goals of critical reading and critical literacy. Reading Online, 4(9). Available: http://www.readingonline.org/articles/ art_index.asp?HREF=/articles/cervetti/index.html Cherryholmes, C. (1999). Reading Pragmatism. New York: Teachers College Press. Cochran—Smith, M. & S. L. Lytle (1993). Inside/Oustide. NY: 140 Teachers College Press. Cochran-Smith, M. & S. L. Lytle (1999). The teacher research movement: A decade later. Educational Researcher, 28(7), 15-25. Cole, A. L. & J. G. Knowles (1998a). Reforming teacher education through self-study. In A. L. Cole, R. Elijah, J. G. Knowles (Eds.), The heart of the matter. San Francisco, CA: Caddo Gap Press. Cole, A. L. & J. G. Knowles (1998b). The self-study of teacher education practices and the reform of teacher education. In M. L. Hamilton (Ed.), Reconceptualizing teachingpractice: Self-study in teacher education. London: Falmer Press. Cole, M. (1996). Cultural Psychology: once and future discipline. Cambridge: The Bellknap Press of Harvard University Press. Davidson, W. J. & Batchelor, J. E. (1989). The American Nation. Englewood Cliffs: New Jersey. Derrida, J. (1982). Margins of Philosophy. Brighton: Harvester Press. Derrida, J. (1976). Of Grammatology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Dewey, J. (1938). Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt and Co. Dewey, J. (1902). The Child and the Curriculum. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dorris, M. (1999). Morninngirl. New York: Hyperion Eagleton, T. (1996). The Illusions of Postmodernism. Malden: Blackwell Publishers Ltd. 141 Elgin, C. Z. (1997). Between the Absolute and the Arbitrary. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Elliott, J. (1991). Action research for educational change. Philadelphia, PA: Open University Press. Ellsworth, E. (1989). Why doesn't this feel empowering? Working through the repressive myths of critical pedagogy. Harvard Educational Review, 59(3), 297—324. Freire, P. (1970/1993). Pedagogy of the oppressed. New York: Continuum. Featherstone, M. (1991). Consumer Culture and Postmodernism. London: Sage Publications. Gaardner, J. (1994). Sophies World: A novel about the history of philosophy. Gee, J. P. Literacy, Discourse, and Linguistics: Introduction. Journal of Education, Volume 171 Number 1, 1989. Gee, J. P. (1992). The Social Mind: Language, Ideology, and Social Practice. New York, NY: Bergen & Garvey. Gergen, K. (1994). Realities and Relationships: Soundingg in Social Construction. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Glasersfeld, E. V. (1995). Radical Constructivism: A Way of Knowingand Learning. London: Falmer Press. Glasersfeld, E. V. (1991). Knowing Without Metaphysics: Aspects of the Radical Constructivist Position. In F. Steier (Ed.) Research and Reflexivity. London: Sage Books. Hamilton, M. L. & Pinnegar, S. (1998). The value and promise of self-study. In M. L. Hamilton (Ed.), Reconceptualizingteaching practice: Self—study in teacher education. London: Falmer Press. 142 Harding, S. (1987). Feminism and methodology; Social Science issues. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. The discursive mind. & Gillett, G. (1994). Harré, R., CA: Sage Publications. Thousand Oaks, Hassan I. (1987). The Postmodern Turn: Essays in Postmodern Theory and Culture. Columbus: Ohio State University Press. K. R. & Berv, J. (2000). Constructing Constructivism, Epistemological and Pedagogical. In D. C. Phillips Constructivism in Education: Opinions and (Ed.), Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety-ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Howe, Jameson, F. (1991). Postmodernism Or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions Kuhn, T. (1970). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lakatos, I. & Musgrave, A. (Eds.). (1970). the growth of knowledgg. Cambridge: Cambridge Criticism and University Press. Leinhardt, G. (1992). What Research on Learning Tells Us ( ) 1992. About Teaching. Educational Leadership Lipman, M. (1991). Thinking in education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Philosophy Goes To School. Philadelphia: Lipman, M. (1988). Temple University Press. F. S. (1980). Lipman, M., Sharp, A. M., & Oscanyan, Philosophy in the classroom. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. 143 Lipman, M. (1983). Lisa. Upper Montclair, NJ: Upper Mountain Press. Luke, A., Comber, B., & O’Brien, J. (1996). Critical Literacies and Cultural Studies. In G. Bull & M. Anstey (Eds.) The Literacy Lexicon. Melbourne: Prentice—Hall. Matthews, M. R. (2000). Appraising Constructivism in Science and Mathematics. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety—ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. McCarty, L. P., & Schwandt, T. A. (2000). Seductive Illusions: Von Glasersfeld and Gergen on Epistemology and Education. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety—ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. McGowan, J. (1991). Postmodernism and Its Critics. Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press. McLaren, P.L. (1992). Literacy research and the postmodern turn: Cautions from the margins. In R. Beach, J. L. Green, M. L. Kamil, and T. Shanahan (Eds.), Multidisciplinary perspectives on literacy research. Urbana, IL: National Conference on Research in English. Michaels, S. & O’Connor, M.C. (1990). Literacy as reasoning within multiple discourses: Implications for policy and educational reform. Paper presented at the Council of Chief State School Officers 1990 Summer Institute: “Restructuring Learning.” Murphy, J. P. (1990). Pragmatism: From Peirce to Davidson. 144 Boulder: Westview Press. Natoli, J. & Hutcheon, L. (1993). Introduction: Reading a Postmodern Reader. In J. Natoli & L. Hutcheon (Eds.) A Postmodern Reader. Albany: SUNY Press. O’Connor, M.C. & Michaels, S. (1996). Shifting participant frameworks: Orchestrating thinking practices in group discussion. In D. Hicks (Ed.), Discourse, learning; and schooling. New York: Cambridge University Press. Pardales, M. J. and Cervetti, G. N. (April 1999 — Montreal) American Educational Research Association. Learning to Talk Philosophy: Growth in a Discourse Community of Inquiry. Poster Presentation for Division C, section 1, of AERA. Peirce, C. S. (1955). In, J. Buchler (Ed.) The Philosophical Writings of Peirce. New York: Dover. Peterson, D. (1992). Life in a Crowded Place: Making a Learning Community. Portsmouth: Heinmann. Phillips, D. C. (2000). An Opinionated Account of the Constructivist Landscape. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety—ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Piaget, J. & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child. New York: Basic Books. Piaget, J. (1954). The Construction of Reality in the Child, (trans.) Margaret Cook. New York: Basic Books. Prawat, R. S. (1996). Constructivisms: modern and postmodern. Educational Psychologist. 31(3/4), 215— 225. Rogoff, B., Matusov, E. & White, C. (1996). Models of 145 Teaching and Learning: Participation in a Community of Learners. In D. R. Olson & N. Torrance (Eds.), The handbook of education and human development. Oxford: Blackwell. Rorty, R. (1992). Twenty—Five Years After. In R. Rorty (Ed.) The Linguistic Turn in Philosophy: Essays in Philosophical Method. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rose, S. L. (1999). UnderstandingChildren’s Historical Sense-making: A View From the Classroom (Ph.D. dissertation: Michigan State University.) Russell, T. (1998). Introduction. In M. L. Hamilton (Ed.), Reconceptualizing teaching practice: Self-study in teacher education. London: Falmer Press. Samaras, A. P. (1998). Finding my way: Teaching methods courses from a sociocultural perspective. In A. L. Cole, R. Sanders and McCutcheon (1986). Sexias, P. (1993). The Community of Inquiry as a Basis for Knowledge and Learning: The Case of History. American Educational Research Journal. 30(2) 305-324. Slezak, P. (2000). A Critique of Radical Social Constructivism. In D. C. Phillips (Ed.), Constructivism in Education: Opinions and Second Opinions on Controversial Issues. Ninety-ninth Yearbook of the National Society for the Study of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Smart, B. (1992). Modern Conditions, Postmodern Controversies. London: Routledge. Smith, J. E. Community and Reality. In Freeman (Ed.) The 146 Relevance of Charles S. Pierce. XX Institute. Smith, J. P., diSessa, A. A., Roschelle, J. (1993). Misconceptions reconceived: A constructivist analysis of knowledge in transition. Journal of the Learning Sciences. Steffe, L. & Gale, J. (1995). Constructivism in Education. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Strike, K. A. (1987). Toward a coherent constructivism, In J. D. Novak (Ed.), Proceedings of the second International seminar: Misconceptions and educational strategies in science and mathematics (Vol. 1, pp. 481-489) Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Usher, R. & Edwards, R. (1994). Postmodernism and Education. London & New York: Routledge. Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in Society: The Development of Higher Psychological Processes. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Wells, G. (1999). Creating and Sustaining Communities of Inquiry. Paper presented at the National Reading Conference. Orlando, FL. December. Wenger, E. (1998). Communities of Practice: Learning; Meaning, Memory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Whitehead, J. (1995). Educative relationships with the writings of others. Teachers who teach teachers: Reflections on teacher education. London: Falmer Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan. Wong, E. D. (1995). Challenges confronting the 147 researcher/teacher. Educational Researcher, 24(3), 22— 28. Woolgar, S. (1988). Science: The Very Idea London: Tavistock Publications Yackel, E. Cobb, P. & Wood, T. (1991). Small group interactions as a source of learning opportunities in second-grade mathematics education. Journal for Research in Mathematics Education. Vol. 22, No. 5, 390-408. 148 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII illill1111(1))llllllllzlllljllzllfllll