)V1€SI_J RETURNING MATERIALS: P1ace in book drop to LIBRARJES remove this checkout from -_ your record. FINES will - be charged if book is returned after the date stamped below. i i EDUCATIONAL SAGA: DOING PHILOSOPHY WITH CHILDREN IN ICELAND 3! Hreinn Palsson A DISSERTATION submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Teacher Education 1987 ABSTRACT EDUCATIONAL SAGA: DOING PHILOSOPHY VITH CHILDREN IN ICELAND By Hreinn Palsson What are the basic conditions for operation of communities of inquiry? This question was fundamental to the research. The research purpose was to document the presence. absence. or the genesis of communities of inquiry among twelve year old students in two classrooms in Iceland taught by two teachers with ten years of experience in teaching. The research was conducted as participant observation for a period of sixteen weeks in the fall of 1986. Each group had 26 lessons on a philosophical novel by Lipman.. Documentation of observations was made in fieldnotes. recordings and in transcripts. Researcher's participation included being a teaching consultant. a coach. a model teacher. and a substitute teacher. Lessons were evaluated in terms of content. application of philosophical discussions as a method of instruction. and the teachers' perceptions. i.e. whether they were pleased or disappointed with their lessons. The students' reasoning improved considerably as assessed through pre- and post-tests with the New Jersey Test of Reasoning Skills. Communities of inquiry were not found to be present in the classrooms studied. In one of the classrooms such a community was established and major interactional changes took place in that classroom. Students accepted responsibilities for setting an agenda to their lessons and they monitored their own procedures; they questioned and reprimanded one another. they reminded the teacher of who should really be holding the floor. Although on its way. a community of inquiry was not established with the other group. but that group showed more rapid growth in performance on the reasoning test. The study indicates that students' reasoning can be improved. for example by drill and practice. without the community of inquiry being at work. The teacher that succeeded in creating a community of inquiry claimed having matured and that her everyday thinking was sharper because of her participation in the project. To this the other teacher agreed and both claimed having learned a lot through the project. Q Lipman. N. (1982). garry Stottlemeier's Discovery. New Jersey: First Mountain Foundation. Copyright by HREINN PALSSON 1987 In honor and memory of my parents Pall Johannes Porsteinsson (1900-1981) and Juliana Johannsdottir (1915-1987) ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to express my most sincere thanks to the members of my dissertation committee: Drs. Martin Benjamin. Doug Campbell. Perry E. Lanier. Matthew Lipman and Michael Sedlak. Dr. Lanier deserves special thanks for leading the committee and for his thoughtful guidance as my academic advisor. Special thanks go to Dr. Ann M. Sharp of the Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children. New Jersey. If not for her and Mat's encouragement I would never have ventured into doctoral studies in teacher education. My friends. housemates and fellow students Eugenio Echeverria. Helga Loebell. and John Zeuli have a big place in my heart. I doubt that I would have made my first year through at Michigan State without them. I often recall our suppers and discussions that sometimes led into the night at our home in Haslett. In particular. I thank John Zeuli and Linda Versteeg for their support during the summer of 1987. Last. but by no means least. I thank my wife. Arna. and two daughters. Asta Brynja and Sigurlaug Maria. for putting up with me while in front of my computer all the time. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS C H A P T E R I: I N T R O D U C T I O N BACKGROUND......................................................1 THE PHILOSOPHY FOR CHILDREN PROGRAM.............................5 Novels and Literature...........................................5 Instructional Peatures..........................................6 The Teacher's Role..............................................7 Children........................................................8 Review of Research.................................. ....... .....9 Needed Research.................................................12 COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY............................................14 Inquiry........................................... ..... .........14 Reflective Thinking.............................................19 The Social Development of Self..................................22 Why Communities of Inquiry in Classrooms?.......................27 RESEARCH PLAN............................j......................29 The General Questions............................... ...... ......52 The Middle-level Ouestions......................................32 Thematic Questions..............................................52 Analysis................................... ..... .. ..... .........33 C H A P T E R I I: S E T T I N G A N D A C T O R S THE EDUCATIONAL SCENE IN ICELAND... ............. ... ..... ........34 THE TRAINING SCHOOL.............................................58 Negotiating Entry...............................................39 THE ACTORS......................................................44 Linda's Background..............................................44 Linda's Pupils..................................................48 Summary.........................................................54 Helga’s Background..............................................56 Helga's Pupils..................................................58 Summary.........................................................65 CHAPTER III: INTERPRETATION OF CLASSROOM INTERACTIONS AND DIALOGUE Introduction....................................................67 SEPTEMBER 1-22: GETTING READY...................................68 Basic patterns..................................................71 Central Reflections.............................................82 SEPTEMBER 25 - OCTOBER 14: UPS AND DONNS........................85 Introduction....................................................85 week one: Mixed reactions.......................................88 Reflections on week one.........................................96 Neck two: Difficulties..........................................97 Reflections on week two.........................................103 week three: Retreat.............................................104 Reflections on week three.......................................116 Neek four:A turning point.......................................117 vii OCTOBER 14-22: MODELING.................. ..... . ...... ... ..... ...121 Week four continued.............................................121 Reflections on practice.........................................136 Modeling continued..............................................138 Reflections on week four........................................158 Week five: Modeling and experience..............................159 OCTOBER 22 - NOVEMBER 27: MORE UPS THAN DOWNS...................169 Week five continued.............................................169 Reflections on week five........................................180 Week six: Moving forward........................... ...... .......182 Reflections on week six...................... ............ .......198 Week seven: Helga's class takes off.............................199 Reflections on week seven.......................................213 Week eight: Spontaneity versus convention.......................214 Reflection on week eight........................................253 Week nine: Community of inquiry at work................£........234 Reflection on week nine.........................................246 Week ten: Commitment to the procedures of inquiry...............247 Reflections on week ten.........................................265 LOOKING BACK: AGENDA FOR PARENTAL MEETING.......................268 RECREATION AND POSTSCRIPT.......................................271 Reflections on postscript........................... ............ 276 Looking back with Helga and Linda.............. ......... ........277 C H A P T E R I V : C O N C L U S I O N Improved reasoning..............................................279 Reasoning and conduct...........................................285 Review of research questions....................................288 The general questions...........................................288 The middle-level questions......................................297 Questions to begin with.........................................299 Weaknesses of the study................... ..... .................301 APPENDIX A: A distant perspective on Iceland...................302 APPENDIX B: Individual students' performance...................305 WCEOOOIO......OOOOOOO......OOOOOOOOOOOOOO......00.0.00000309 viii LIST OF TABLES TABLE I: A SCHEDULE OF TEACHING HOURS FOR PRIMARY SCHOOLS......57 TABLE II: SOCIAL TAXONOMY OF LINDA’S PUPILS...................54 TABLE III: SOCIAL TAXONOMY OF HELGA’S PUPILS..................65 TABLE IV: SUMMARY OF TEACHING FACTORS IN HELGA’S CLASSROOM.....86 TABLE V: SUMMARY OF TEACHING FACTORS IN LINDA’S CLASSROOM......87 TABLE VI: DISTRIBUTION OF SCORES IN PRE— AND POST-TESTS.......280 TABLE VII: DISTRIBUTION OF ERRORS..............................281 A. DISTRIBUTION OF ITEMS ON N.J. REASONING TEST BY SKILL AREAS.281 B. DISTRIBUTION OF ERRORS BY SKILL AREAS AND CLASSES...........281 TABLE VIII: LINDA’S STUDENTS’ REASONING SCORES.................505 TABLE II: HELGA’S STUDENTS’ REASONING SCORES...................306 TABLE I: LINDA’S STUDENTS’ PERFORMANCE WITHIN SKILL AREAS ON THE NEW JERSEY TEST OF REASONING SKILLS...............307 TABLE II: HELGA’S STUDENTS’ PERFORMANCE WITHIN SKILL AREAS ON THE NEW JERSEY TEST OF REASONING SKILLS...............508 ix C H A P T E R I: I N T R O D U C T I O N BACKGROUND Thinking is in. riding as it has come to on the latest educational bandwagon. Even those who claim that thinking has always been in now recognise that we have begun to overcome the fragmented understanding of the thinking process that limited its teaching. Among others. Glaser is optimistic about the increasing likelihood ”that we can move to a new level of application” (1984. p. 102) in teaching of thinking. The trend has escalated to such an extent that people who work at the pro-college level who want to intellectually empower their students are faced with the dilemma of choosing between several programs that have been specially designed for this purpose. e.g. Cort (Cognitive Research Trust) developed by deBono. SOI (Structure of the Intellect) developed by Meeker. Instrumental Enrichment developed by Feuerstein. Philosophy for Children developed by Lipman: Chicago Mastery Learning Reading Program developed by Jones. Strategic Reasoning developed by Glade. In a thorough review of three programs. Sternberg endorsed one of them in particular: ”No program I am aware of is more likely to teach durable and transferable thinking skills than Philosophy for Children 01984. p. 44). As I have studied and taught the Philosophy for Children program I chose to focus on it in this dissertation. Even if the present emphasis on thinking is just the latest fad for professional educators. philosophers have taken an interest in the issue for over 2500 years. The question of how thinking and talking relate is a classical question among philosophers. Of course they have not been able to reach a final conclusion. but few. if any. would claim that 1 2 thinking and talking are unrelated. Thinking is not only related to talking but also to knowledge. Philosophers value good thinking. but they don't agree on what exactly it is that makes or characterises a good thinker. In general they see good thinking as something that can be taught or fostered. the basic disagreement is on whether it must be done within the disciplines (Ryle 1968: McPeck. 1981). whether we can teach good thinking across the disciplines (Smock. 1974) or whether we need both (Pass-ore. 1972). In other words. philosophers disagree on how. when. and where good thinking should be taught as well as on the nature of good thinking. So despite their interest in thinking. philosophers are not of much help when it comes to classroom practice or actual interactions with children. Their professional interests are primarily in conceptual analysis without relating the results or their implications concretely to classrooms. Benjamin and Echeverria (in press) point out that conventional teaching rests on a traditional conception of knowledge. dating back to Descartes. where the spectator's mind is supposed to mirror nature as it “Really“ is (of. Rorty. 1979). The person that acquires knowledge. the learner. is on this view a.passive receiver of the knowledge he or she is to acquire. Benjamin and Boheverria remind us. furthermore. that the arrangement of having students learn in groups does not mean that they learn 5; a group. Teaching students as individuals in groups rest on the same traditional conception where thinking and knowledge acquisition are ultimately considered to be a personal affair. Supporting their argument with references to lbhn (1962). Rorty (1979. 1982). and Bernstein (1983) Benjamin and Echeverria (in press) maintain. that a different conception of knowledge needs to be taken into account in teaching. A conception that sees knowledge and thinking,as being 3 essentially social and inescapably linguistic in nature as we cannot get outside of language to get to know the world. Dialogue resting on mutual trust and respect in a classroom community of inquiry would be at the center of such teaching. they claim. Benjamin and Echeverria are inspired by Lipman's Philosophy for Children program. who first tried his approach to the teaching of thinking via a community of inquiry with children when he was a philosopher at Columbia University. His trials led to the foundation of the Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children at Montclair State College. New Jersey. The differences between Lipman and mainstream philosophers are important and some of them will now be highlighted. Pirst. Lipman agrees that formal and informal logic. skills and dispositions are important components of good thinking (1984. Mars. personal conversation: of. also 1985b). He is not willing. however. to rank them in hierarchical order and he denies that they are 5;; important. His difference lies in giving those components in his curricula equal status. Second. for Lipman practice comes before theory. For example. he did not publish gnything on the possibilities or the justification of teaching philosophy. thinking. or reasoning to children until after he had himself tried it out using his own materials. Philosophers usually have a more distant perspective on the classroom. Third. both philosophers in general and philosophers of education in particular usually do not design curricula. Snook. for example. stated simply that: ”the task of devising a curriculum is one which is beyond the scope of a philosopher of education" (1974. p. 146. see also p. 161). During the past 18 years Lipman has devoted much of his energy to designing and writing curricula. 4 Fourth. Lipman assumes that it is as much of a responsibility for professional philosophers to work with young children (K-12th grade) as it is to work with college students. He points out that philoscphy has been conceived of as putting the final touch on the educational process. To change this. and ”to enter the elementary school. philosophy has not had to change itself so much as its image of itself” (1985b. p. 20). However. it is Lipman. not philosophy. that has created this different image of the responsibility of his discipline. Thus. according to Lipman. philosophy does not have to lose its integrity as a discipline when done with children: the ideas. the logic. the method or the dialogue remain the same (1985b. p. 20). This should be of some comfort to those that claim that thinking can only be taught within the disciplines (McPeck. 1981: Ryle 1968). But Lipman also claims that students’ work in philosophy carries over in a positive manner to other disciplines. i.e.. thinking in philosophy is a preparation for thinking in other disciplines (of. 1985b. p. 21. see also Appendix B in Lipman. Sharp a Oscanyan. 1980. and Lipman 1985c. p. 101). In short. if the aim of education is to promote children's thinking. then knowledge acquisition and subject-specific problem solving readily assume a subsidiary status: they remain valuable functions but are no longer the focus of learning. Philosophy must be taught as a subject in its own right. rather than ignored or taught only as a subcomponent of other academic knowledge acquisition and problem-solving activities (Lipman. 1985c. pp. 100-1). Lipman's argument is twofold: on the one hand it is claimed that philosophy prepares the ground for thinking in other disciplines. 0n the other hand. philosophy deserves no subsidiary status and deserves to be taught to children as a subject in its own right. Finally. Lipman has mapped out the skills that his program.fosters (1985c. PP. 88-96). He claims that this is more of a postscript to the 5 program so far than a prescription for classroom practice. He also admits that there is a certain arbitrariness to his list as there is with any list of cognitive skills that are said to be promoted (p. 87). THE PHILOSOPHY FOR CHILDREN PROGRAM Novels and Literature Since the novel Harry Stottlemeier's Discovery was first published in 1974. Lipman has written five other novels constituting the Philosophy for Children program: gig; (1976/1985). §E§l (1978). May! (1980). {$513 (1981). and Rio and Gus (1982). intended for use in K-12th grade. Each novel is accompanied by an extensive manual. The manuals’ names are descriptive of the program. but they are. in the same sequence as above: Philosophical Inquiry (1975/197911984. with Sharp and Oscanyan). Ethical Inquiry (1977. with Oscanyan and Sharp: 1985. with Sharp). Writing: How and 3;; (1980b. with Sharp). Social Inquiry (1980a. with Sharp). Looking for Meaning (1982. with Sharp). and Wondering at the World (1986. with Sharp). Each novel avoids traditional philosophical terminology. Perplexities within students' own experiences are emphasized instead. Readers of the novels are provided with alternative examples of how different participants reflect on their experiences and how they make sense out of it. The characters have many different styles of thinking with no one style portrayed as the correct one. Lipman and Sharp (1978. p. 568) argue that ”only literature has shown the delicacy and flexibility needed to penetrate and communicate the many-layered.multiplicity of human relationships.” Consequently they argue that the novel is of central importance in bringing philosophy to children as well as in motivating them and in giving context to the ideas under scrutiny. Instructional Features A Philosophy for Children lesson often begins when the classmembers form a circle and read aloud. by taking turns or by role-reading. a chapter or a piece from one of the novels. After the reading. the teacher usually opens the discussion by asking the class whether any idea interested them. or whether there is something else in the chapter that they would like to talk about. Thus. a philosophy lesson starts with the children's own experience in a twofold sense: first. the novels are written for children about children at a similar age. Second. the teacher elicits the discussion agenda from the children: there are no detailed lesson plans to be followed step-by-step. Lipman g§_gl. (1980). while admitting that the effects of the program are not precisely known. claim that ”learning to think philosophically takes place primarily in the process of interpersonal discussion. and the reflection that follows such a discussion" (p. 65). But the discussion also brings other advantages: in particular. it promotes children's awareness of one another's personalities. interests. values. beliefs. and biases. This increased sensitivity is one of the most valuable by-products of classroom communication. Unless children have some insight into the nature of the individuals with whom they share their lives. they are not likely to make sound judgments regarding them (p. 65). What is at stake here is cooperation which requires listening as well as self-corrective communication. After the discussion opens. the class becomes engaged in a student-to-student dialogue with the teacher guiding students' inquiries and participating as one of the class. The Teacher’s Role “Teachers who can model an endless quest for meaning...are the most important ingredient in the philosophy for children program“ (Lipman gt 5;. 1980. p. 84). Such teachers have partly to improvise their activities as they direct discussions along philosophical lines by the questioning technique employed. and by bringing up exercises and discussion plans from the manuals where they are appropriate. The discussion plans and exercises are of such nature that they operationalise concepts presented in the novels and help students understand what the ideas mean and how they work. The teacher does not bring up exercises if they do not relate to what the students want to discuss. In other words. the reading in the beginning of the lesson and the ideas presented serve as a springboard for discussions of things that matter to students. However. if the students do not catch on. the teacher has to elicit themes through questioning or. at last resort. simply point them out as a member of the classroom community. But by no means is the teacher’s role to import answers into the classroom. Addressing the teacher directly. Lipman gt_gl. (1980. p. 90) explicitly state: ”It is not your role to dictate to children what their philosophies of life should be.” In the same place they advise the teacher to take cues from the novels where children struggle to understand as well as to learn from experience. Although a variety of topics are discussed in a Philosophy for Children classroom. it is not the case that these topics can be discussed in simply any form. It requires both knowledge and skill on the part of the teacher to keep the discussion integrated with the students’ ideas and the ideas in the novel. Although the following questions are simple. it takes great skill on the teacher’s behalf to use them on appropriate occasions in the dialogue. What reasons do you have for saying that? Why do you agree (or disagree) on that point? How are you using the term you just used? What do you mean by that expression? Could you clarify that remark? (Lipman. et al. 1980. p. 112). Apart from this "philosophical" list. the program also calls for questions that are directed at communicative interactions. such as: Did all of you hear what was just being said? Can somebody repeat what was just said? Questions of this kind are asked to increase the student-to- student interactions as well as to foster listening skills. Children In the Philosophy for Children program children are seen as being intellectually lively and as having a natural curiosity for philosophical ideas such as friendship. truth. beauty. and fairness. It is often said that philosophy and childhood both begin in wonder. This does not mean that the philosophical questions of children are ”childish." On the contrary. philosophers and children can be of great help to one another if their relationship is cultivated on mutual grounds (of. Matthews. 1980: Pritchard. 1985). Children offer deep philosophical insights but they do need help with making sense out of their everyday puzzles and wondering. Philosophy is useless for this task if it is reduced to a mere memorization of “who. what. when.“ "It takes on significance only when children begin to manifest the capacity to think for themselves and to figure out their own answers about life’s important issues” (Lipman gt 5;. 1980. p. 85). Sense is certainly not made by simply telling or describing to children how things are: the problem is 323 that children do not believe what they are told but that often what they are told has no meaning to them. Children do not question the truth of much of what they are told. but they do contend that it is often meaningless to them. It is unlikely that an educational process can work if it fails to take this craving for meaning into account (Lipman. 1985. p. 100: see also Lipman. Sharp. & Oscanyan. 1980. ch. 2). Review of Research Several studies have been done to assess the educational significance of Philosophy for Children. They have centered on the impact of Baggy Stottlemeier’s Discovery since that novel was the first one to be written in the program and is still a central part of it. These studies vary greatly in scope and effort. The first study was done by Lipman and Bierman in 1970. (reported by Lipman in Metaphilosophy. 1976). The study involved 40 5th graders who were assigned randomly to two groups. Lipman taught Hgggy to the experimental group and the control group was assigned to a social science project. In his teaching ”there was no homework. no grades. no written classwork - it was all discussion" (Lipman 1976. p. 55). After nine weeks the experimental group had.gained 27 months in mental age compared to the control group and as measured by the California Test of Mental Maturity (p<.01). This study was replicated by Cummings (1980) and again with significant (p<.05) gain on the California Test of Mental Maturity. However. the studies were done on different grounds. For example. although not having any experience in teaching children Lipman was a professional philosopher with fifteen years of teaching experience at the college level. Also. after analysis e.graduate assistant lost all the - data collected for the Lipman/Bierman study. Cummings's teaching was. on the other hand. 50% paper-pencil exercises some of which she designed herself. 40% discussion and 10% lecture (1980. p. 90). The retreat into 10 sheetwork was partly because of serious discipline problems that she ran into ”from the very first day” (1980. p. 91). Simmon (1979) found §355y_to be effective in working with emotionally handicapped students (n25). Higa (1980) did a study in Hawaii involving twelve elementary school classes. Positive impact on reasoning skills were reported but there was no control group involved in the study. Iarras (1980) did a study involving six hundred 5th and 6th graders and found significant improvements in reasoning. Teasill (1981) found significant gains (p<.01) in 6th graders’ reading comprehension in using ggggy as contrasted with students that did not use §§g_y. Burnes (1981) also reported significant improvement in reading comprehension as well as in reasoning. Reed and Henderson (1981) used two 4th grade classrooms as experimental groups. and two as control. They reported significant gains (p<.001) in reasoning for the Baggy group. Weinstein and Martin (1982) also reported improvement in reasoning skills for students that used §a£_y5 Cinquino (1981) used ggggy with academically talented 5th graders with positive results. Three more extensive studies stand out among the research that has been done on Philosophy for Children. The first major study was done in 1975 in the Newark. New Jersey public schools and directed and designed by Hope Haas of the Institute for Cognitive Studies at Rutgers University (see Appendix B in Lipman. Sharp 2 Oscanyan. 1980). Four hundred 5th and 6th graders in sixteen different classrooms. in two control schools and two experimental ones. were involved in the study. Over ten months the experimental students gained eight months on the Metropolitan Achievement Test (MAT) in contrast to a five month gain of the control students. A second study was designed and carried out by Virgina Shipman (1978) at the Educational Testing Service. Princeton. New Jersey. This study 11 was more extensive and took two years (1976-78) at Pompton Lakes and Newark. New Jersey. In brief. in Newark the conclusions gave indication of a carry over effect from philosophy to other disciplines: in mathematics the experimental gain was 56% larger than control and in reading the experimental gain was 66% larger than control (significance at .0001 and measured by MAT). The Pompton Lakes groups did not show such drastic improvements: this was explained by the Educational Testing Service as being due ”to the overflow of program effects into the control group. causing the latter’s performance to improve along with that of the experimental group” (Lipman. Sharp. 2 Oscanyan. 1980. p. 225). It was during the first year of this study that Shipman developed a criterion- referenced formal reasoning test known as 0-5 and designed to assess improvements in students’ thinking. Later 0-5 became 0-4 and finally it was copyrighted in 1985 as the New Jersey Test of Reasoning Skills (for more details. see Morante and Ulesky. 1984). Following the Newark/Pompton Lakes’ study the Philosophy for Children program received Title IV-C ‘validation in New Jersey. After a 2-day review of the data by a team of out-of-state educators. the program was given 124 of a possible 126 points for effectiveness and 45 of a possible 45 points for exportability (1985b. p. 105). Lipman and Gassard (1986. p. 82) report that ”in 1986. the 0.8. Department of Education’s Joint Dissemination Review Panel identified Philosophy for Children as a meritorious educational program and granted it ’national validation’." The third and most extensive evaluation was done in New Jersey and Pennsylvania in 1980-81 and involved over three thousand students. Again. Shipman designed and evaluated the experiments using the 0-4 test. In New Jersey Shipman found the experimental group’s gain of 5.25 to be 80% greater than the 2.91 gain of the control group. 0f 52 classrooms 12 that received philosophy in Pennsylvania 29 showed significant (p<.05) improvement. 19 of which where significant at the .005 level. For the remaining three classrooms the improvements ranged between .06 and .10 (Shipman. 1982). Needed Research Despite favorable evaluations. such as Sternberg's (p. 1). detailed descriptive and scholarly case studies of how the Philosophy for Children program works in ordinary classrooms are not available. The more substantive studies on the program in general. have been arranged in such a way that working with Harry Stottlemeier's Discovery (Lipman. 1974) has constituted an independent variable. while academic achievement. however measured. has been used as the dependent variable. This has led to interesting conclusions. but the investigators have not reported in details what (except using Baggy as a 'treatment.') happened in these classrooms. In other words. research has been focused on reasoning as measured by tests: such assessment rest ultimately on each individual’s isolated performance. rather than on thinking in a classroom community. ~~-....—...,.fl......-w- I V ‘ , , 4 Consequently. it is questionable whether communities of inquiry were at work in the studies that have been conducted on the program thus far. Originators of the Philosophy for Children program claim that not only does the program improve students’ reasoning skills. but also that classmates will increase their respect for one another as well as for themselves in a philosophical community of inquiry (Sharp. 1986). This is supposed to take place within a specific classroom context or within a classroom frame of reference. in which teaching and/or learning activities can be understood. just as books provide the context for sentences to be understood. 15 One of the characteristics of a Philosophy for Children classroom is to deal openly with the question: "Who are we and what are we doing now?” g The first part is dealt with by asking questions that have to do with personal identity. such as: "What makes you you? Is it your name? Is it your clothes? Is it your thoughts?” The second part is dealt with by asking questions such as: ”What makes you say that? How do you know? What do you mean by that?” (see Lipman et al. 1979/1984 p. ii. 10. 55 and 1980 ch. 7). Thus the Philosophy for Children program attempts to create a context for open inquiry where the context itself does not Wire-M "- Ir.._.‘~ escape scrutiny. Thinking is seen to be interwoven and inspired by the ) context at hand. This happens to be in line with Rogoff (1982. p. 149). M ..W '__.. ? who defines