LIBRARY Michigan State “ g‘University This is to certify that the dissertation entitled The Role of the Home Economics Profession in the Reproduction of Social Relations: an Exploration of Selected Theoretical and Historical Questions presented by Mildred Howitson McLachlan has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for PhD degree in Family Ecology 66ka Major professor Date December 14, 1982 MS U is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution 0-12771 -v -—- “Hm—m w-«u—wuae.‘-u.-w-‘—- MSU LIBRARIES m RETURNING MATERIALS: Place in book drop to remove this checkout from your record. FINES will be charged if book is returned after the date stamped below. THE ROLE OF THE HOME ECONOMICS PROFESSION IN THE REPRODUCTION OF SOCIAL RELATIONS: AN EXPLORATION OF SELECTED THEORETICAL AND HISTORICAL QUESTIONS BY Mildred Howitson McLachlan A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Family and Child Ecology 1982 ABSTRACT THE ROLE OF THE HOME ECONOMICS PROFESSION IN THE REPRODUCTION OF SOCIAL RELATIONS: AN EXPLORATION OF SELECTED THEORETICAL AND HISTORICAL QUESTIONS BY Mildred Howitson McLachlan The question underlying this study is the involvement of the home economics profession in power relations. The study brings a critical dimension to the self-examination of the field of home economics. It examines how the political nature of activities of professionals have been understood and explores conceptual issues related to the analysis of power in home economics. The focus is on two sets of rela- tions: the sexual division of labor and the division between intellectual and manual labor. An analysis of historical literature on home economics indicates that studies written by home economists generally do not deal with power in the sexual division of labor or the division between intellectual and nanual labor. The li- mitations of historical studies are eXplored. Functionalist tendencies are pointed out, and the limitations of function- alist approaches for dealing with questions of power are dis- cussed. The influence of positivism is also noted. Using elements from Habermas' social theory, the limitations of a positivist philosophy and its social role are considered. Mildred Howitson McLachlan This analysis lends weight to the proposal that home econo- mists need to understand the political role of their profes- sion, and indicates that frameworks used in existing histori- cal studies are inadequate for that task. Alternative frameworks are required. The study suggests that analytical tools must first be developed to study spe- cific power relations in which home economists are involved. Aspects of Foucault's work are introduced. His conceptuali- zations of knowledge and power seem useful for an analysis of power relations in home economics. The final section explores the fruitfulness of using Foucault's strategy of discursive analysis. Using examples from the home economics literature, an analysis of the dis- course of homemaking is developed and particular power rela- tions are explored. The eXploratory analysis indicates that Foucault's ap- proach illuminates power relations in home economics. Fur- ther research using this framework is suggested. The study indicates that the power relations in which home economists have been involved are complex. These power relations need to be considered when decisions are made about future goals and activities in the profession. Copyright by MILDRED HOWITSON ‘MCLACHLAN 1982 Dedicated to my parents, Toit and Rina McLachlan, and to the memory of my friend and colleague, Marilyn R. Parkhurst iii ACK NOWL EDGMEN TS would like to thank Dr. Beatrice Paolucci, major professor and co-director of the research, for her support, enthusiasm, and keen un- derstanding of the issues facing the home economics pro- fession; Dr. Richard T. Peterson of the Department of Philosophy, co-director of the research, for being the scholar and teacher that he is, and for seeing the merit in this un- dertaking, especially when I had doubts; Dr. Margaret Bubolz and Dr. Barbara Ames, members of the guidance committee, for their interest and sound advice; Dr. Barrie Thorne, for challenging me to explore the links between home economics and feminism; Colleagues at the Non-Formal Education Information Cen- ter, for making my graduate assistantship a job I didn't want to leave; Donald Huntington, for word processing the dissertation with skill, cheerfulness and patience; and Family and friends, for their encouragement and support. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE I 0 INTRODUCTION. 0 O I O O O O O O O O O O O O O O H Context . . . . . . . . . . . . Purpose of the Study. . . . . . . . . Challenges to Professional Practice . Conceptual Issues . . . . . . . . . . The Division of Labor . . . . . . . . . . . 1 Division Between Intellectual and Manual Labor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 14 Sexual Division of Labor . . . . . . . . . 15 Outline of the Study. . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 II. REVIEW OF HISTORICAL LITERATURE IN HOME ECONOMICS O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O 20 Women's Education and Home Economics. . . . . 25 Home Economics, the Public and the Private. . 32 Home Economics and Housework. . . . . . . . . 35 Conclusion. . . . . . . . . . . . . .i. . . . 37 III. CRITIQUE OF HISTORICAL LITERATURE . . . . . . . 39 Theoretical Commitments . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Functionalism. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47 Positivism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48 Habermas' Critique of Positivism. . . . . . . 51 Science and Technology as Ideology . . . . 57 Conclusion. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60 IV. CONCEPTUALIZING POWER AND KNOWLEDGE . . . . . . 61 Power 0 O O O O O O O O I O O O O O O O O O O 64 Further Conceptual Requirements . . . . . . . 68 Foucault: Background . . . . . . . . . . . . 70 Discourse and Discursive Analysis . . . . . . 71 Objects. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 72 Statements . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 73 Concepts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 74 Theoretical Strategies . . . . . . 74 Foucault's Critique of Traditional Notions of Power . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 Micropowers and Normalization . . . . . . . . 78 Foucault's Propositions about Power and How it Should be Studied . . . . . . . . . . . 79 Limitations of Foucault's Conceptualization of Power . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 82 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 83 V vi CHAPTER V. EXPLORATORY ANALYSIS OF THE DISCOURSE HOMEMAKING O O O O O C O O O O C O O The Discourse of Homemaking Objects . . . . . . . . . Statements. . . . . . . . Concepts. . . . . . . . . Theoretical Strategies. . . . Power Relations in the Discourse. New Content for Homemaking. . . Homemaking as Women's Primary Vocation Interrelated Power Dimensions . Summary and Conclusions . . . . . VI. SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS . . . . . . Limitations of the Study. . . . . Suggestions for Future Research . Implications for Home Economics . BIBLIOGRAPHY. . . . . . . . . . . . PAGE OF 87 87 91 95 101 102 114 120 128 O O O O O 133 . . . . . 136 . . . . . 137 . . . . . 138 . . . . . 142 Chapter One INTRODUCTION This study explores some conceptual and theoretical is- sues concerning the development of an adequate framework for the study of home economics in social and historical perspec- tive. It suggests that the social role of the field must be understood in terms of power. First, a critique of conven- tional approaches used in studies of the history of home eco- nomics is developed. On the basis of this analysis a number of requirements for an adequate theoretical framework are outlined. Finally, the study introduces aspects of the work of one theorist, namely Michel Foucault, and examines what discursive analysis, a strategy based on Foucault's work, could contribute to the historical understanding of the so- cial role of home economics. Context The current efforts within the profession of home eco— nomics to reconsider its goals and philosophy provide the context of the study. During the last decade, home econo- mists, like other academic and professional groups, renewed their efforts at self-examination and definition of their field. One of the major elements of this process was the publication, in 1979, of Home Economics: A Definition, a paper commissioned by the American Home Economics Associa- tion, written by Brown and Paolucci. In this work, which home economists have used as a basis for study and continued dialogue about the future of the field, the authors charac- terize home economics as a practical science concerned with the persistent problems of the household and the family. Brown and Paolucci (1979) see as the major dilemma of the era the limitations placed on individuals to participate actively and critically in political thought and action. In light of the present state of affairs, Brown and Paolucci (1979) define the mission of home economics as fol- lows: to enable families, both as individual units and gen- erally as a social institution, to build and maintain systems of action which lead (1) to maturing in indi- vidual self-formation and (2) to enlightened coopera- tive participation in the critique and formulation of axial goals and means for accomplishing them (p. In the final chapters Brown and Paolucci (1979) explore the knowledge required in a field with such a mission, and the kind of social action required from its members. For such a mission to be implemented, however, it would be necessary to add historical and social analyses to the work begun by Brown and Paolucci (1979). In fact, a short- coming of their paper is the absence of reflection on the role home economics professionals may have played in the very process of depoliticization and the rationalization of relations which the authors wish to overcome. In other words, the authors do not consider the political role of the field. Without an understanding of the historical role of the profession in society and the social reality it has be- come, the possibilities open for the field will remain vague. As Peterson (1979) points out in a critique of £2132 Economics: A Definition, It is not enough to state goals for a profession but these must be stated concretely (in the dialectical sense) in their relation to existing conditions. This requires not only consideration of the social context of the profession, but also of the internal state of the profession, the functions it actually performs today, the relations to other institutions it main- tains, the conflicts and dilemmas resulting from these relations . . . (p. 89). Purpose of the Study The present study aims to contribute to the historical analysis of home economics. By examining assumptions and existing theoretical frameworks of historical studies, and exploring an alternative framework, the groundwork is laid for more concrete and specific studies of home economics history. In this way the study seeks to sharpen home econo- mists' views of realistic goals and expectations for their profession. Specific dimensions of the historical evolution of "helping professions" (Lasch, 1979, p. 15) that have come under scrutiny in recent years are the focus of the study. The dimensions addressed are the development of a more specialized and complex division between intellectual and manual labor, and the role of professions in shaping the sexual division of labor. Challenges to Professional Practice Recent historical and sociological studies have raised questions about the outcomes of the various reforms advoca- ted and implemented by intellectuals and professionals. In particular, professionals have been criticized for eroding family autonomy (Lasch, 1979) and for contributing to wo- men's oppression (Ehrenreich and English, 1978). As a field of study and practice that has throughout its history stated its goals in terms of service to families (Vincenti, 1982), home economics needs to take note of the challenge directed to professions with regard to their role in shaping family life. As a field with a predominantly female clientele, and which is generally associated with women's work in the home, home economics must heed the chal- lenge to. professions regarding their role in maintaining women's oppression. Lasch (1979) criticizes professionals for undermining family autonomy. He bemoans the erosion of family life, and claims that social scientists and professionals have usurped the family's rightful role as the primary socializing agent of children. According to Lasch (1979), "The history of modern society, from one point of view, is the assertion of social control over activities once left to individuals and their families” (p. xx). Lasch seeks to show how the ex- perts eroded parents' confidence in their own skills, and increased families' dependence on the expertise of teachers, psychologists, and other helping professionals. He maintains that what social science has called "interdependence" in modern society, is in fact a reflection of "changing modes of domination” (p. 24). In other words, Lasch argues that relations between professionals and family members involve a form of domination. Lasch develops a critique of functional- ist sociology for its view that the changes in family life are the outcome of abstract social forces. In contrast he sets out to argue that, the family did not simply evolve in response to so- cial and economic influences; it was deliberately transformed by the intervention of planners and poli- cymakers (p. 13). Thus Lasch (1979) argues that professionals contribute to shaping social relations through their professional activi- ties. Lasch's argument can be understood in terms of the development of an increasingly complex and specialized divi- sion of labor in which intellectuals have come to play a more direct social role. This intensification of the divi- sion between intellectual and manual labor involves the exer— cise of a form of control through specialized knowledge of one individual or group over another. Thus a set of social relations are developed which involve dependence and domina- tion. The feminist movement also poses a challenge to profes- sionals in general, and to home economists in particular. There are two dimensions to this challenge. Like ILasch (1979), Ehrenreich and English (1978) emphasize the division between intellectual and manual labor.. But they argue that it is women's autonomy in particular that has been eroded by the experts. Ehrenreich and English criticize doctors, home economists, and child psychologists for eroding women's traditional skills and knowledge. They claim. that women have become dependent on "masculinist" experts (p. 18). Furthermore, for Ehrenreich and English (1978), the activities of professionals contributed to shaping relations between men and women and defining women's role in society, by promoting a certain kind of family, of which the wife and mother was the core (Zaretsky, 1982). This latter role of the professionals can be understood in terms of the shaping of the sexual division of labor in society. Other recent historical studies of women's work and fam- ily roles also make mention of the role of home economics. Hartmann (1974) sees home economists as key figures in promo- ting the ideology of motherhood. Hartmann claims that the activities of home economists served to reassert the tradi- tional values of home, family, and motherhood. According to Hartmann the ideology that motherhood was women's primary vocation, and that women's place was in the home, remained essentially the same from the mid-nineteenth century into the twentieth century. However, the way in which women were convinced of the ”truth" of these ideas, had changed. For Hartmann (1974), the new conveyors of the ideology in the twentieth century were the home economists. She states, The particular form that the ideology took in this period was the home economics movement, with its em- phasis on precision, science, and efficiency in house- keeping (p. 183-184). Strasser's (1977) study of women's household work like- wise analyzes home economics in terms of ideology. Her em- phasis, however, is not on the ideology of "women's separate sphere" but rather on the development of a new ideology) ne- cessary for the full incorporation of the home into the capi- talist market. According to Strasser (1977) home economists were involved in, formulating an ideology which applied principles of capitalist social relations -- rationality, wage 1a- bor, class, hierarchy, and privacy -- to household life and promoted new roles for women as workers and consumers in economic life (p. 257). Thus, like Hartmann (1974), Strasser (1977) pictures the role of home economists in society in terms of their contri- bution to shaping ideology related to women's roles in socie- ty. By focusing on their role in intensifying the division between intellectual and manual labor, and in the sexual division of labor, these studies assign a role to profes- sions in the transformation and maintenance of social rela- tions in society. In essence, they assert that professional activity must be understood as actually contributing to the reproduction of specific social institutions and relations in particular ways. Zarestky (1982) argues, for example, that the family was not simply eroded, as Lasch (1979) would argue, but transformed and preserved as an economically pri- vate unit through the activities of various groups, includ- ing professions. These kinds of social activities, which appear to be far removed from explicit political practices, are nevertheless a form of political activity. They involve the exercise of power, and reproduce social relations that, however indirectly, serve to nmintain the existing economic and social order. Taken together, these processes can be understood in terms of a politics of social reproduction. The present study suggests that home economists need to address the challenges directed to them with regard to their role in the intensification of the division between intellec- tual and annual labor, and the sexual division of labor. In other words, home economists need to study the role of their field in social reproduction, particularly with regard to shaping two sets of relations, the division between intellec- tual and manual labor, and the sexual division of labor. Conceptual Issues Such a project poses particular conceptual problems. Some critical remarks on the strategies used by the authors cited earlier indicate the kinds of conceptual and theoreti- cal issues at stake. Lasch (1979) makes a critical point: In order to under- stand the role of social groups such as professions in shap- ing social relations, a functionalist’ analysis is inade- quate. Such an analysis would attribute social change to abstract, social forces, and thus obscure human. agency' in social change. Nevertheless, Lasch (1979) falls into a kind of functionalism himself, by asserting a one-way, and direct influence of social scientists and professionals on families and individuals. He neglects the interests family members may have had in the reforms promoted by the professionals. He also does not consider families' need for the knowledge professionals had to offer. By neglecting these dimensions Lasch (1979) neglects the contribution of individuals and families themselves to the changes brought about in society. Also, Lasch (1979) does not deal with the resistance profes— sionals might have encountered in their attempts to insti- tute reforms. Furthermore, to blame social scientists and professionals for the erosion of traditional knowledge, which in many cases had become dysfunctional because of urbanization and industrialization, is to give them power far beyond what they had. 10 On the one hand, Lasch (1979) seems to assign to profes- sionals a key role in social transformation. Yet, on the oth- er hand, he regards professionals essentially as function- aries of the state or corporate capitalism. Thus, according to Zaretsky (1982), Lasch (1979) maintains that behind the reforms promoted by middle class professionals, lay "the need of twentieth century capitalism to reorganize and soci- alize the sphere of private and familial life” (p. 190). Such a view of the activities of professionals reduces them to "instruments" of a more powerful unit, and so does not allow for the possibility that professionals could also act independently, as human actors who have their own interests as professionals, which may be in conflict with that of the state or corporate concerns. Thus, Lasch's (1979) analysis does not illuminate the particular social role of intellectu- al activity. A similar problem seems to plague recent studies of women's work in the home (Strasser, 1977; Hartmann, 1974; Ehrenreich & English, 1978). Although their emphases differ, these authors all analyze home economics and the role of home economists in society in terms of ideology. The study by Ehrenreich and English (1978) illustrates the conceptual dilemma. On the whole, their study is a careful analysis of the gradual erosion of women's autonomy and the invasion of the home by experts, including home economists, to dictate to women how they should raise their children and do their 11 housework. Nevertheless, their analysis is not discrimina- ting enough. Their analytical framework does not allow them to distinguish carefully between issues of gender and exper— tise at work in the activities of the professionals. Ehren- reich and English (1978) state, for example, The eXperts' answer to the Woman Question was not sci- ence after all, but only the ideology of a masculin- ist society, dressed up as objective truth (p. 5). There may be a more complex set of power relations in- volved in the activities of professionals than is suggested by Ehrenreich and English. The authors seem to oppose know- ledge to ideology, and to reduce the intellectual activities of professionals to expressions of ideology. Such an analy- sis obscures the real knowledge being developed and used by professionals. Furthermore, an emphasis on ideology as a framework of false beliefs or ideas could obscure the real social effects of the cognitive practices of professionals. Thus, an analysis that focuses on ideology seems to exclude the possibility of a richer analysis of the social role of professionals. Similar conceptual problems occur in Zaretsky's (1982) analysis of the relation between the family and the welfare state. Zaretsky wants to maintain Lasch's emphasis on human agency in social change, and the feminist concern for wo— men's ambivalent experience of the modern family. After re- viewing the history of the modern welfare state in America, he concludes that the welfare state has preserved the family 12 as an "economically private unit," and that state policy toward the family was not dictated by any capitalist conspiracy. Rather it was the outcome of a series of single-issue reform movements. . . (p. 218). Thus Zaretsky (1982) acknowledges the contribution of a vari- ety of different actors in efforts to change social rela- tions (as evidenced in state policy). Yet, the actual con- tribution of particular groups, for example, professionals like home economists, are not theorized. It would seem that Zaretsky's analytical categories are inadequate for such a task. This is illustrated by the fact that in the midst of his careful analysis, he can state, I try to show that the class and sexual structure of American society, rather than the intentions of a single group, shaped the meaning of diverse reform efforts in unforeseen (and still untheorized) ways (p. 192). This statement seems contradictory to his eXplicit intent to maintain human agency in social change, because it reduces specific actions to "class and sexual structure." Zaretsky wants to avoid reducing social change to the outcome of in- tentional activity of one group, but then replaces this re- duction with another, namely a set of encompassing terms -- "class and sexual structure." These terms are not very use- ful for eXplaining the role of specific agents in social change. To study the role of home economics in social reproduc- tion a framework is required that would allow one to examine 13 the field in relation to the sexual division of labor and the division between intellectual and manual labor. This should be done in a way that allows one to examine the par- ticular relations in which home economists were involved, and the cooperation and resistance they encountered in their reform efforts. The present study suggests that the intel- lectual activities of home economists could have contributed to power relations in ways that are not open for examination in terms of the categories provided by a class analysis or an analysis of ideology. The study seeks to develop some conceptual tools for such an analysis. The Division of Labor The concept of the division of labor is central to the present study. In particular, two dimensions of the division of labor, the division between intellectual and manual la- bor, and the sexual division of labor, are pertinent. Work- ing definitions of these concepts are developed below. All human societies are characterized by a division of labor. This division of labor concept refers in general to the fact that each individual in a society does not produce everything he or she needs, but specializes in some tasks, while entering into exchange relationships with others to obtain the goods and services needed to live in that society (Braverman, 1974; Lloyd, 1975). 14 Thus specialization and interdependence are key dimen- sions of the division of labor. Although conceptually, at least, such a division does not imply the development of pow- er in relations of interdependence, it seems that historical- ly, specialization and interdependence have been accompanied by relations of power. Division between Intellectual and Manual Labor The division between intellectual and manual labor is based on the rise of distinctively cognitive practices. In a general sense it involves the separation of thought from doing, and thus gives rise to specialization and interdependence. Such a division means, in a general way, that some individuals or groups in society are able to have their material needs met through the manual labor of others. In a more Specific use of the term, it refers to the set of relations that develop through a breakdown of the labor process which separates intellectual activity, organization, planning, and decision making from the actual manual labor process. Based on this kind of development, management practices have evolved which give certain individuals or groups direct or indirect control over other people's labor. Thus the concept can be used to refer to relations in a factory, for example, where planning and management is done by Specialists and managers, and workers carry out the spe- cific tasks assigned to them. Such a division of labor in- volves a lack of control over one's own labor, because the 15 worker does not understand the total work process. Control is exercised more indirectly through the intel- lectual practices of academics and professionals when ab- stract thinking is regarded as necessary to understand and solve social problems. To the extent that intellectuals are recognized as authorities, and their counsel sought in more and more areas of life, and specialized and esoteric know- ledge is developed, the division between intellectual and manual labor is intensified. As indicated earlier, such an intensified division of labor seems to be characteristic of modern society. Sexual Division of Labor It is generally agreed that all known human societies have allocated at least some tasks by gender (Brown, 1970; Kay and Voorhies, 1975; Rubin, 1975). The concept of the sexual division of labor is used to refer to patterns of specialization in particular tasks according to gender. While such a division of labor seems universal, the way in which tasks are allocated is specific to each group or community, and no clear pattern of responsi- bilities can be established (Lloyd, 1975; Illich, 1982). While the allocation of some tasks is influenced by biology, for example, childbearing and lactation, the sexual division of labor in general cannot be regarded as biologically deter- mined. Even the tasks closely associated with childbearing represent cultural variety with regard to the involvement of men and women. The specific form childrearing takes, and the l6 importance assigned to it, also vary from society to socie- ty. Relationships of power between men and women often have an economic dimension, as a woman is economically dependent on a man in a situation where the husband is the sole earner of income in a family (Luxton, 1980). The economic dimen- sion of the sexual division of labor stretches beyond such direct dependence, however. For example, it finds expression in the belief that it is normal that women could be paid less than men, because "they do not have families to sup- port" -- which is concretely expressed in gender-specific jobs in which women earn less than men do in comparable jobs. Central as the economic dimension of the sexual divi- sion of labor is, it is not the only pattern of dependence associated with such a division of labor: Political and cul- tural dependence, for example, are expressions of the fact that women may be dependent on male policy makers, and on male writers or "informers" to form their political opin- ions. Similarly, they may be more or less dependent on the artistic eXpressions of men to develop imagery and patterns of language use. In science and education generally, the exclusion of wo- men from most fields has left them dependent on approaches worked out by and large by men, focusing on topics regarded as important by men, using methods regarded as valuable by men 0 17 The sexual division of labor predates capitalism. Its interaction with class divisions is an important considera- tion -- sets of relations develop in which these divisions intersect in important ways. In industrial society the specialization of the sexual division of labor has been associated with the separation of the domestic domain of home and family from. the [public sphere of decision making and production. Traditionally, in this division and distinction, women work in the home, and are closely associated with it, while men work in, and are associated with, the public domain. Thus the sexual division of labor in industrial society can be associated with pat- terns of specialization with the husband specializing in earning the income, and women being associated with house- hold, family, and children; and interdependence of men and women. Specialization and interdependence serve to emphasize and exacerbate differences between the sexes. The concept of the sexual division of labor also refers to patterns of restriction and exclusion to which women are subjected. For example, they are or have been routinely ex- cluded from political decision making, most professions, ex- ecutive positions in business and industry, and leadership roles in education and religious institutions. They' have been restricted to» certain environments, certain careers, and certain artistic and cultural expressions. Accompanying this has been a measure of isolation and invisibility. 18 Such patterns of distinction, specialization, interde- pendence, exclusion, restriction, and isolation have given rise to relationships of power between men and women. Pat- terns of relative autonomy and dependence emerge, and are institutionalized and internalized, giving to the sexual division of labor a dimension of structural domination. Outline of the Study Chapter II examines how historical literature on home economics portrays the role of the profession in shaping so- cial relations. General comments on the focus of the histor- ical literature are followed by a discussion of the way the literature deals with questions that relate to the sexual division of labor and the role of home economists in shaping this set of relations. Chapter III examines the theoretical assumptions that underlie historical studies of home economics. Using con- cepts from Jurgen Habermas' comprehensive social theory, the political character of professional activity and the failure of functionalist theoretical strategies to account for power in home economics practices are discussed. Given the shortcomings of existing explanations of the social role of home economics, Chapter IV identifies the need to develop a more adequate analysis of power in the practices of home economists. The chapter sets out to devel- op analytical tools appropriate to the task. Finally, the 19 chapter introduces aspects of the work of the French theo- rist, Michel Foucault. Foucault's eXplorations on the inter- relation of knowledge and power appear useful for the pre- sent study. Discursive analysis, a strategy developed by Foucault, may contribute to the kind of analysis of home eco- nomics the present study requires. Chapter V examines the fruitfulness of using discursive analysis to study the role of home economics in social repro- duction. It uses examples from the writings of home econo- mists to develop a discursive analysis. The chapter first sketches the dimensions of a discourse of homemaking, and then develops an analysis of power relations in the dis- course, focusing cxi the intensification of the division be- tween intellectual and annual labor, and the sexual division of labor. Chapter VI includes a summary, and reflections on the limitations of the study, future research, and the implica- tions of the study for the home economics profession. Chapter Two REVIEW OF HISTORICAL LITERATURE IN HOME ECONOMICS The purpose of this chapter is to examine how histori- cal accounts of home economics characterize the role of the field in the reproduction of social relations. In particu- lar, it focuses on how home economists perceive the role of the field in maintaining and shaping a specific set of soci- al relations, namely relations that are a part of the sexual division of labor. Three questions guide the analysis of historical stu- dies of home economics. These questions address particular aSpects of women's roles and the sexual division of labor, namely women's education, the division between the domestic and the public sphere, and the content of women's work. The questions read as follows: 1. How do historical studies characterize develop- ments in women's education, and the relationship between home economics and women's education? 2. How do historical studies portray the relation- ship between the family and other social institu- tions? How do they see the role of the field of home economics in maintaining and transforming relations between the family and society? 20 21 3. How do historical studies describe changes in the content of homemaking, and the role of the field of home economics in those changes? Before turning to a discussion of these questions, a few remarks about the scope of the review and some general comments about historical literature on home economics are in order. The review covers readily available historical accounts of home economics in the United States of America, written or commissioned by home economists. Home economics histori- ans typically associate the beginning of the profession with the Lake Placid Conferences on Home Economics, held from 1898 to 1908, and the subsequent organization of the Ameri- can Home Economics Association. Nevertheless, they recognize earlier educational and other activities as a part of the general history of the field. A similar perspective is adop- ted in the present review. It covers accounts of the history of home economics as a field of study, an educational move- ment, and a profession. Studies of the development of par- ticular content areas and specializations, such as child development, food and nutrition, and textile studies, were not included. While historical accounts reflect, to some extent, the self-perception of home economists about the field and its role in society, it is difficult to gauge the relation be- tween these studies and the actual practices of home 22 economists. The extent to which home economists agreed with published views is a matter of conjecture. As Vincenti (1981) points out in her recent study of the history of the philosophy of home economics, many published accounts of home economics are isolated statements, and seem to reflect the views of only a few home economists. The literature of the professional association, particularly the Journal of Home Economics, shows little dialogue‘on statements among home economists. While Vincenti's (1981) comments pertain specifically to philosophical statements, her observations can be extended to historical studies. The historical literature on home economics is quite ex- tensive. The sources reviewed can be classified into three broad categories. The first group consists of those articles published at regular intervals in the Journal of Home Econo- m_ig§ to commemorate specific events or milestones in the history of the field, such as the fiftieth anniversary of the American Home Economics Association (AHEA) (e.g., Adams, 1959; Andrews, 1948; Bane, 1959; O'Brien, 1948; Zuill, 1959). Typically, these articles serve to promote the pro- fession and its activities and to provide inspiration for the future. It is therefore not surprising that they are generally uncritical, self-congratulatory, and devoid of rigorous theoretical reflection (Fritschner, 1973). Secondly, a large number of studies focus on home eco- nomics in education. There are general studies of home 23 economics education, and specific studies tracing the devel- opment of home economics programs in particular schools and colleges (Bevier, 1928; Bevier & Usher, 1906; Carver, 1979; Eppright & Ferguson, 1971; Ferrar, 1964; McGrath & Johnson, 1968; Paolucci, 1980). Also in this group are accounts of the development of the AHEA (Baldwin, 1949; Pundt, 1980). These accounts share a number of characteristics. They are largely descriptive, giving factual information about when and how and by whom programs were started and conducted. Their intent, in general, is to eXplain the origin and devel- opment of home economics or specific programs in home econom- ics. In most cases, the explanation takes the form of a chronological account of events or developments. For exam- ple, Bevier's (1928) study of the development of home econom- ics as it relates to women's education is in three parts. This widely quoted study starts with a summary of education- a1 developments in early America. This is followed by an ac- count of the development of women's education. In the final section Bevier first describes the various movements and events which led to the founding of the American Home Econom- ics Association, and then recounts “new developments" in the field. Ferrar's (1964) study of the history of home econom— ics in relation to liberal education follows a similar chron- ological pattern. Reviewing developments at the end of the nineteenth century, Ferrar concludes, 24 Home economics was evolving in response to the social and economic conditions created by industrial develop- ment, as well as to the needs, interests and apti- tudes of women in the family (p. 10). Except for occasional references to "social and econo- mic conditions created by the industrial revolution" (Lee & Dressel, 1963) these studies do not systematically relate de- velopments in home economics to social changes. No studies were found that focused on the actual role of home economics in shaping social relations. A third group of studies are those that focus on the philosophy or ideas behind homeeconomics, rather than on its activities and achievements. (Budewig, 1957; Vincenti, 1981). Budewig (1957), for example, criticizes the overem- phasis on events and activities in historical studies of home economics. She proposes that an adequate historical perspective on home economics must focus on the ideas under- lying those events and activities. Budewig traces the "idea" behind home economics to Francis Bacon, who maintained, ac- cording to Budewig, that the concerns of everyday life, such as food, clothing and shelter, were worthy of study and the application of science. Budewig finds this idea also in the work of Count Rumford, Catherine Beecher, and Ellen H. Rich- ards. She concludes that historically, the fundamental idea that gave rise to home economics has been "that the real and the ideal are one in spirit" (p. 305). She continues, "It 25 is the spirit of home economics that must be maintained if home economics is to have meaning for the future" (p. 306). Given this perspective, Budewig criticizes those historical studies that analyze the development of home economics in terms of other social developments, such as the women's move- ment, the cooking school movement, agricultural education or sewing classes (Budewig, 1964). Having rejected an under- standing of the history of home economics in terms of other social events, Budewig (1957) adopts an analysis of the field in terms of the history of thought. Useful as such an analysis may be for establishing the uniqueness and enduring qualities of home economics, it does not contribute to an understanding of its role in social reproduction. As these comments show, the focus in existing studies of the history of home economics does not seem to be on its role in social reproduction. This is borne out by the fol- lowing analysis of the literature at the hand of the ques- tions posed earlier. Women's Education and Home Economics The events and activities generally associated with the origin and development of home economics in the latter half of the nineteenth century took place in the midst of chang- ing views and practices regarding women's education. The ef- fects of education on women, the content of their education, and the merits of coeducation were topics of frequent debate among educators. Although perspectives on this matter 26 differ, most historical writings on home economics relate the development of the field to the issues surrounding women's education. In Home Economics in Education (1928) Bevier studies home economics in relation to women's education. She main- tains, "while the study of the home and its activities has many offerings of interest to men, yet it primarily concerns women, and has developed as a special phase of the education of women" (p. 8). While a tacit acceptance of the sexual division of labor is already evident in this statement, it becomes more explicit in the discussion of educational lead- ers' concerns about coeducation and the content of women's education. Bevier concludes that women had a basic right to higher education and that "the enlargement of the field of woman's activities" necessitated training. Furthermore, co- education had probably become a permanent factor in educa- tion. Referring to the opinions of educational leaders she continues, Neither men nor women overlooked the biological argu- ment for difference in training for men and women be- cause they have different functions in society. Nei- ther men nor women were willing that the best inter- ests of the home should suffer from any cause, and particularly not at the hand of women. Coeducation was clearly one great step in the evolution of women. The question arose what was to be the next step (p. 102). According to Bevier, these educational leaders were con- cerned that women's education was not sufficiently preparing them for their "sacred and imperative task" of being homemak- ers and wives. She states, 27 Women had no desire to evade their high duty as conservers of the race. The home was still the bulwark of the nation, but it was in many ways a new home in which all that was best of the old was to be retained, modified by new conditions and with new problems (p. 107). Bevier quotes a statement made in 1907 by Dr. Elmer E. Brown, United States Commissioner of Education, in which he argued that the integration of women's education had been successfully accomplished, but that its differentiation still had to be worked out, because men and women had differ- ent functions in society. For Bevier, home economics was the embodiment of this differentiation. In a similar manner, Ferrar (1964) regards the differen- tiation of women's education as a progressive step. She characterizes women's education in the new women's colleges of the East as "hampered by tradition." Thus Ferrar argues, There they had continued to struggle for rec0gnition of their intellectual equality and of their right to equal educational opportunity. As a result, the tra- ditional curriculum persisted, long after women in the West had finished this phase and were ready to interest themselves in science applied to the home (p. 6). Ferrar's remark refers to the development of women's programs in the land grant institutions. Historical accounts of these programs reflect an acceptance of the sexual divi- sion of labor, and of the notion of women's moral superiori— ty. Gilcrest (1947) describes the development of home eco- nomics programs at Michigan Agricultural College in such terms. She notes that the legislation passed in 1855 to establish the college did not exclude women from attending. 28 But, the curriculum was to focus on agriculture, English and technical skills related to agriculture. According to Gil- crest, "Such a curriculum, designed for farm boys, naturally did not interest girls . . ." (p. 2). Nevertheless, ten wo- men enrolled in 1870, and in 1879 the first woman graduated in agriculture. Gilcrest (1947) notes, "Women were always welcome at Michigan Agricultural College in the old days be- cause of their needed 'ameliorating effect,‘ so it was said" (p. 4). According to Gilcrest, a Woman's Course of Study was established on the recommendation of a Faculty Committee established in 1895 to examine the reasons for the college's low enrollment. The committee stated that, the organization of a woman's course (was) not only . . . a duty, but . . . the great privilege of the Agri- cultural College to lead in the training for home work, known as domestic economy (p. 4). Similarly, Eppright and Ferguson (1971) describe how the home economics program at Iowa State University grew out of its Ladies course. Initially, when the Iowa State Agricul- tural College opened, women and men were admitted, and they took the same courses. According to Eppright and Ferguson (1971) Mary B. Welch, the wife of the college president, was concerned about the kind of education the women were get- ting, and its lack of relevance to their future tasks as homemakers. The authors state that a program was developed, "that offered three dozen young women of Iowa a kind of edu- cation that would prepare them specifically for homemaking and 'discipline their minds'" (p. 9). 29 In a way similar to Ferrar (1964), Rose (1949) sees the differentiation of women's education in home economics pro- grams as a progressive step. Home economics would give women access to higher education, and a role in the larger socie- ty, without challenging the sexual division of labor, or the notion of the home as women's special sphere. She states, Through the burgeoning of this movement in home econo- mics, women acquired a room of their own in the field of higher education -- a place which they might oc- cupy unchallenged and where they might work freely, a center from which they might extend to the community the results of their thinking about their special in- terests and needs, an oasis of influence centered on the home in the industrial house of Jack's building (p. 511). In summary, these studies of the history of home econo- mics in relation to women's education seems to regard it as a progressive response to the concerns of educational lead- ers regarding women's education. A different perspective on the relationship between home economics and women's education is provided by Budewig (1957). At the beginning of her study, she takes a position similar in some respects to that advanced by Bevier (1928), when she states, Although education for home and family living is not exclusively by and for women but by both men and women for families, we cannot avoid recognition of the still obvious fact that the major portion of re- sponsibility for homemaking and education for homemak- ing falls upon women. Therefore, education for home and family living and the problems of education of women cannot be separated (p. 9). Nevertheless, at the conclusion of her study, she argues that it is a mistake to see home economics as an outgrowth 30 of the women's movement, because it did not further the goals of that movement. She maintains that the feminist goal to prove that women were the intellectual equals of men demanded that women and men study the same courses. And since home economics focused on home and family life, sub- jects considered to be ”strictly feminine pursuits" (Bude- wig, 1964, p. 9) at the time of the development of the field, it could not contribute to that goal. She cites as evidence the fact that few women's colleges offered home eco- nomics courses. Likewise, in Budewig's opinion, the woman's movement did not contribute to the development of home eco- nomics. Budewig (1964) concludes, Therefore, I believe it is erroneous to say that home economics 'grew out of' the woman's movement and un- fruitful to continue to attempt to trace the develop- ment of home economics through the history of women's education. To do so is to ignore the motivating for- ces behind the woman's movement and to be unaware of the profundity of the home economics movement and its significant social implications (p. 10). In spite of these references to the social role of home economics, Budewig's (1957) study does not throw light on that role. This is due to the fact that she focuses on the ”idea" behind home economics, rather than actual social de- velopments in the field. A final perspective on the relationship between home economics and women's education is provided by Marjorie East. In a recent study, Home Economics, Past, Present, and Future (1980) she identifies ”The Education of Women 31 for Womenhood: Homemaking" as one of several ”models" of home economics. She regards this model as "competing" with the "Applied Science" model, and does not attempt to explore how they have historically been interrelated. East also devotes a chapter to the ”Femaleness" of the field but she does not provide any consistently historical or social analy- sis of how its predominantly female clientele and membership have shaped the field. She merely states, "If femaleness has influenced our field it must be because of special char— acteristics of women" (p. 137). In conclusion, historical studies of home economics which relate the development of the field to women's educa- tion recognize the existence of the sexual division of 1a- bor. The development of home economics programs is regarded as a progressive step in contributing to broadening the wo- men's sphere of influence, and bringing science: into 'the household, without challenging or changing the sexual divi- sion of labor. No analysis of the role of home economics in maintaining or shaping the sexual division of labor appeared in the studies available to the researcher. Historians' perceptions of the relation between home economics and its clientele, and the rode of gender in these relations, are further explored in the sections that follow. 32 Home Economics, the Public and the Private Some historians note that the development of the new profession meant access to the public sphere for some women (Rose, 1949). Nevertheless, consistent historical analysis of the relationship between the domestic and the public sphere, the changes in this relationship, and how women, including professional women, experienced these changes, is meagre. The existence of a division between the domestic and the public is generally accepted, and as the previous sec- tion shows, most writers implicitly assume women's associa— tion with home and family. The relation between home and family and the rest of society is usually couched in func- tionalist terms -- society has particular needs that the family must fulfill. It is generally accepted that women are the main actors in the family's efforts to carry out its tasks. Historical writings on home economics reflect a certain ambivalence toward the family and toward women. On the one hand, they emphasize the home as "the bulwark of the nation" and women's role as "preservers of the race" (Bevier, 1928). Yet, they often also deride the home for its backwardness, and women for their ignorance. Thus, Andrews (1948) accepts as a basis for the development of home economics, the follow— ing statement of Edward Youmans: 33 Our kitchens are fortified intrenchments of ignor- ance, prejudice, irrational habits, rule of thumb, and mental vacuity . . . . The spirit of improvement must invade this last stronghold of stupidity, the kitchen (p. 291). Such statements seem to provide a basis for the justifi- cation of home economists' involvement in the home. Without critique or analysis, Bevier quotes extensively from a speech given by Mary E. Sweeney, President of AHEA, at its 15th Annual Meeting in 1922. The statement gives one promi- nent home economist's view on the relation between the pro- fession and its clientele. Sweeney stressed the need for professional input into families, because of housewives' ignorance. She also recognized the difficulty involved in seeking entrance into the home, because of its privacy. Thus she stated, Our professional work has had to do with the home, which as an institution is traditional and conserva- tive. Those within it have had only a half-hearted belief in home-making as a profession and in the func- tioning of science in everyday life. Homes are indi- vidual units; there are few ways of reaching them col- lectively. No outside forces connected with incomes unify their attitude, interest, and point of view, and get certain standards into their mass mind and consciousness (Quoted in Bevier, 1928, pp. 182-183). Sweeney seems to be justifying the existence and expan- sion of home economics on the basis of women's ignorance. What is described here, although not in such terms, is a transformation in the relation between the domestic sphere and the rest of society -- a new set of relationships in which the professional has carved out for herself a key role. 34 Other studies also reflect how social relations between the family, professionals, and other social institutions are viewed by home economists. East (1980), for example, recog- nizes changes in the family's relation to the government, but does not analyze the role of home economics in the loss of family autonomy she perceives as a result of these social changes. In fact, East characterizes the role of the home economist only as one of helping families adapt to increas- ing interdependence in society through educational programs. Similarly, Budewig (1957) sees home economics as being pri- marily concerned with adapting to change in the culture: Home economics itself must adapt, and its task is to help families to adapt also. This, in essence, seems to be the way in which home eco- nomics historians analyze the relation between the family, professionals and other social institutions. Changes are due to abstract social forces over which individuals and families have little control, and home economists can assist them to adapt to these changes. In the next section the perceptions of historians of home economics of the content of household work and the role of home economists in shaping the work is reviewed. While the historical literature does not pay much (attention to this matter, the scattered comments do give some idea of the historical view of the content of women's work in the home, and, particularly, how the role of home economists with re- gard to the work done in the household has been understood. 35 Home Economics and Housework Home economics historians, like other historians of the household, note that home economists recognized the home as a place of work (Hartmann, 1974; Hayden, 1981). Thus, home economists had a more realistic view of the household and family life than many sociologists and others who focused almost exclusively on interpersonal relations. The question is whether and how historians of home economics account for the transformation in household work in the nineteenth and twentieth century, and what role they assign to home econo~ mics in this process. Some historical writings include references to house- work as dignified and important. The authors of such works often stress the role of home economics in making housework dignified, scientific, and professional. Bevier (1928), for example, cites the 1913 syllabus prepared for the American Home Economics Association by its Committee on Nomenclature and Syllabus as evidence for the develOpment of the "scien- tific phase of home economics" and the "scientification" of housework. However, she does not indicate how widely the syllabus was used or what effect it actually had on homemak- ing practices. Other statements link home economics and the develop- ment of scientific homemaking more directly. For example, an editorial in the Journal of Home Economics of 1911, "The Home Economics Movement in the United States," accepts 36 the role of the expert in the redefinition of housework. It states, Just as the chemist in his laboratory has decided for the farmer the proper rotation of crops and the exact kind of fertilizer for each, and has given him the balanced ration for the production of milk or of fat in his cattle, thus revolutionizing farming while raising it to the dignity of a profession, by exactly the same application of the results of science in many fields is housekeeping and homemaking being put on a higher plain (1911, p. 323). In her account of early developments in land grant in- stitutions, Bevier (1928) quotes extensively from statements made by college administrators and early program leaders re- garding housework and home economics. A fragment from a re- port by Mary B. Welch on the program at Iowa State College reflects the view held by many of these leaders, It (the department of domestic economy) has not only given them manual skill, but it has also increased their respect for all branches of such. labor, and added dignity to that part of their life work hither- to considered menial drudgery (Quoted in Bevier, p. 122). In sum, the historical literature: in home economics does not discuss the relationship between housework and home economics in great depth. When a relationship is identified, home economics is credited with putting housework on a busi- nesslike basis and relieving drudgery. 37 Conclusion This chapter examined historical literature in home economics to determine how the role of home economics in social reproduction has been understood by home economists. The review focused on three questions relating to the sexual division of labor. It considered the relationship of home economics to women's education, the role of home economics in shaping relations between the family and. other' social institutions, and its role in transforming the content of housework and homemaking. The analysis indicated that historical studies of home economics generally focus on the field itself rather than on its relations with the larger society. The emphasis is on events and activities in the field. The activities are rare- ly discussed in the context of social and historical change. Where social change is considered, it is regarded as being caused by abstract social forces and the role of home econo— mists is to'respond to those changes, to adapt, and to help individuals and families to adapt also. Studies that attempt to go beyond an emphasis on events and activities are equally abstract. These studies focus on enduring ideas underlying the developments and changes in the field, or on changes in the philosophical underpinnings of activities. Generally, such studies do not relate ideas and philosophies to the actual social role of the profes- sion. 38 With regard to the sexual division of labor, it appears that historical studies accept such a division as a natural and inevitable characteristic of society. While historians do not agree on the association between home economics and women's concerns, they recognize that home economics to a greater or lesser extent is concerned with issues surround- ing women's education, their place in the home and in socie- ty, and the content of their work. While historical studies may credit home economies with specific roles in society, for example, making housework scientific and relieving drud- gery, no study was found that actually analyzed the social role of home economists in shaping and maintaining the sexu- al division of labor. Chapter Three CRITIQUE OF HISTORICAL LITERATURE The previous chapter focused on the portrayal of partic- ular dimensions of the sexual division of labor in home eco- nomics historical literature. The intent was to eXplore and illustrate how home economists have interpreted changes in social relations following in the wake of the development of capitalism. The review showed that the femaleness of the pro~ fession, its links with women's education, and its preoccupa- tion with women's work are accepted by home economics histo- rians. Yet, the complex social relations implied by this interconnection of the sexual division of labor and the di- vision between intellectual and manual labor are not theo- rized. The chapter suggests that the lack of attention to is- sues of gender in relation to professionalization may be linked to particular theoretical commitments and unexamined assumptions made by home economists. The chapter first iden- tifies a number of theoretical commitments evident in the historical literature on home economics. These are then placed in a larger social and historical context. To this end, some theoretical propositions and arguments advanced by 39 40 Jurgen Habermas are sketched, and related to the home econom- ics literature. The chapter concludes that the frameworks and theoretical assumptions adopted in studies of the his- tory of home economics are incapable of dealing with ques- tions of power in social relations, and actually obscure its working. Theoretical Commitments The historical literature in home economics does not have great theoretical sophistication. In this it reflects the home economics literature in general. The emphasis in the field has typically been on practice rather than on theo- rizing. Nevertheless, theoretical commitments and assump- tions about science, the role of intellectuals in society, and the nature of social change can be inferred from the lit- erature. With some notable exceptions, historians accept the faith in science that has dominated home economics since the early years. This faith is probably best; exemplified. by Ellen Richards, who is generally regarded as the founder of the home economics profession. In a biography of the leader, Hunt (1958) records that Richards described herself as that member of the first Lake Placid Conference who had "faith in science as a cure-all" (p. 144). This stance also is reflec- ted in Richards' many books and articles. The applied science model of home economics is often cited by historians as the: definition of the field. In 41 Introduction to Home Economics, Bane and Chapin (1945) open the chapter on the history of the field with this statement: The home economics movement grew out of a realization of the lag between the findings of science and their applications where they would be of untold value to mankind -- in the home (p. 121). Typically, historians see the development of the strong emphasis on science, especially natural science, in home eco- nomics as a neutral event, a consequence of the rapid devel— opment of the sciences. According to Bevier (1928) the rea- son for the early development of the scientific phase of home economics, as indicated in the syllabus of 1913 (Commit- tee on Nomenclature and Syllabus, 1913), was the wideSpread interest in food and the development of nutrition research in the United States Department. of Agriculture. Budewig (1964) sees the reason for the early emphasis on chemistry as largely an historical accident. She argues, If psychology, or sociology, or anthropology had been more developed fields of knowledge at the turn of the century, the face of home economics might look differ- ent today (p. 13). Thus the virtually exclusive emphasis on natural science in the early years of home economics is noted by historians. Where they recognize a need for the study of social phenome- na, the difference between the study of natural and social phenomena is regarded as one only of content, not of methodo- logy. The purpose of both is prediction and control. 42 East's (1980) analysis of the oft-quoted 1902 defini- tion of home economics is indicative of the orientation to- ward a unitary view of social and natural science, and an emphasis on control and prediction as the goals of science. The definition reads as follows: Home economics in its most comprehensive sense is the study of the laws, conditions, principles and ideals which are concerned on the one hand with man's immedi- ate physical environment and on the other hand with his nature as a social being, and specially of the re- lation between those two factors (Lake Placid Confer- ences on Home Economics, 1902, pp. 70-71). In her analysis of the definition, East (1980) understands "laws" as social contracts, "conditions" as empirical data, and "principles" as rules that eXplain or predict. Under "ideals" she includes norms, goals, and hopes. She inter- prets "man's nature as a social being" to refer primarily to the "regularities, predictabilities, and potentials" signi- fied by the concept, human nature. Home economics studies all of these in the same manner, namely through analysis, examination, and recording. Some historians reflect more self-critically on the pre- dominance of science in home economics. Vincenti (1981) identifies it as a major theme in the philosophy of the field. She finds the belief in science dominant from the inception of home economics as a field of study, until the late 1970's. She suggests that until then, “scientific know- ledge and methodology had remained perhaps the most impor- tant means of accomplishing the goals of the field" (p. 43 243). She argues that while some home economists regarded the scientific method as the only valid method to gain know- ledge and therefore also the only method appropriate to home economics, others rejected this view. She states, Home economics seems to have reflected the cultural attitudes toward science. When positivism was strong, home economics accepted science as the bases for its professional activities apparently without qualms. When positivism came under frequent criticism, home economists also began to write about the negative implications of a scientific bias in the philosophy and work of the profession (p. 244). Yet Vincenti is hesitant to conclude that home econo- mists explicitly held to a positivist view of science. She does not regard the omission of other ways of knowing as suf- ficient evidence for such a view. Vincenti seems to oppose science in: ethics and religion, rather than to the question of whether a restricted philosophy of science was accepted by the profession. An earlier critic of the emphasis on science in home economics was Carolyn Budewig (1957, 1964). She recognized the limits of the scientific method, and called for an inte- gration of science and humanities in home economics. Bude- wig (1964) states, For a field that so admirably combines the "two cul- tures," science and the humanities, and depends for its success and effectiveness on the interrelation- ship of the two, it is the more the pity that at least equal attention has not been given its humanis- tic side; or perhaps "core" rather than "side" is the more descriptive word in this case (pp. 13-14). She continues: 44 As we all know, the "idol" today is science, as it has been throughout the lifetimes of all of us. This time span also encompasses the life of home economics as a field of knowledge in the universities. Science being descriptive rather than normative enables many to predict and control. Science is abstract, imper- sonal, objective. It describes what is rather than what ought to be. It is a very important way of know- ing, with this we cannot argue. But science is not the only way. Enduring institutions reflect integra- tion in both the scientific and humanistic "cultures" and home economics can be no exception (p. 14). While Budewig alerts home economists to the one-sidedness of an exclusive emphasis on science and the value of the humani~ ties, it remains unclear how integration could be achieved. Budewig (1957) does not reflect on how the emphasis on sci- ence also permeates perspectives on the profession's role in society. And when she urges home economists to drop their "scientific conceit" and see homemaking for the art it is, she suggests "searching out values that count" but gives no indication of the basis on which these values shall be cho- sen. She still regards it as the professionals' responsibil- ity to decide what kind of education is necessary "for home and family living that will build yet a better home life for all people" (p. 308). Historical studies of home economics which focus on the recounting of facts and figures, with little interpretation of the facts, reflect a kind of empiricism. Though they do not necessarily intend to do so, such studies match a view of the world that gives an independent existence to objec- tive facts, and obscures their relation to the subject 45 observing them, and their relation to other events and cir- cumstances. As pointed out in the previous chapter, such factual or empirical accounts of home economics seldom re- late developments in home economics to other social or his- torical events. Where attempts are made to place those de- velopments in historical context, the relation is usually presented in a unidirectional, causal way. The historically contingent nature of the larger social context is not ex- plored. In the dialectical tradition, such analyses are criti- cized as being abstract, because events are treated as if they exist in isolation from others. In contrast, dialectic- al thinkers stress the need for concrete analysis. Hegel, the father of the modern dialectical tradition, stressed that social events must be understood as part of a totality. The interconnection of objects and subjects leaves neither untouched. Both subjects and objects are also shaped by pre- vious events and experiences. To understand specifics, they must be treated as historical and placed in the larger con— text. This kind of analysis is called concrete analysis. There is a place for abstract thought and analysis, but these must be placed in context. Concrete thought is required if we are to assess the real possibilities of a given historical situation and so if we are to be able to act in it consciously and effectively (Peterson, 1979, p. 67-68). One of the consequences of abstract analysis in home economics is that changes in the field are not related in a 46 systematic way to changes in the larger social system. And, where an effort is made to relate changes to other social events, these changes are generally discussed as the result of the working of abstract social forces. This perspective does not allow for human intention and action in bringing about change. Where changes in the society are recognized, the role of the professional is characterized as one of helping peo- ple adapt to change. Where changes were regarded by the pro- fessionals as negative, it was also their role to stem the tide of change. This reinforces the view that people are not actors, making independent decisions, and thus shaping their own futures. Rather, they respond to changes not of their own making. The abstract analyses of the history of home economics, the general acceptance of the scientific model and a scien- tistic or empiricist world view culminate in home economics historical literature in an absence of critical reflection on professional activity, even an endorsement of social con- trol by experts, and social engineering. While home economics historians do not explicitly sub- scribe to the tenets of functionalism and positivism, it can be argued that the historical literature shows the impact of functionalism as a theoretical model, and positivism as a philosophy of science. This is hardly surprising, for their assumptions have virtually become the common sense of 47 educated people and their influence is pervasive (Peterson, 1979; McCarthy, 1978). To substantiate this claim, the basic assumptions and principles of functionalism and positivism are briefly reviewed below. Functionalism. According to McCarthy (1978), function- alist notions are already discernable in the work of Durk- heim. In the Anglo-American world, Malinowski and Radcliffe- Brown are early proponents of this view. More recently, Tal- cott Parsons (1954) and Robert Merton (1957) have developed complex functionalist theories in sociology. There is wide- spread disagreement among functionalists about specific for- mulations of the approach. In general, however, it is "asso- ciated with unfolding models of change based upon metaphors of biological growth cn: evolution" (Giddens, 1979, p. 236). Thus functionalists hold the view that social systems have organismic characteristics, change is gradual and unfolding, and the result of abstract social forces, rather than human action. In spite of attempts of some functionalists to overcome the limitations of positivism, functionalists generally ac- cept positivistic philosophies of science. Thus Giddens (1979) states, Functionalism has been closely connected with a natur- alistic standpoint in social philosophy, if natural- ism is understood to refer to the thesis that the log- ical frameworks of natural and social science are in essential respects the same (p. 237). 48 As will be shown in the next section, this is a basic tenet of positivism. Ppsitivism. It would be impossible to identify one distinct positivistic philosophy of science about which there is general agreement today. There have been many expo- nents, many revisions, and many critics. Saint-Simon and Comte were early advocates of a positivist philosophy. Spen- cer and Haeckel contributed their evolutionary positivism. More recently, philosophers at the University of Vienna and Cambridge University developed the perspective known as logi— cal positivism (McCarthy, 1978).1 McCarthy states that this perspective has disintegrated as a unified movement. Yet it has been reworked and absorbed into other perspectives, so that the net result is that the "legacy of logical positiv- ism" -u- a legacy of convictions and attitudes, problems and techniques, concepts, and theories -- pervades contemporary thought (pp. 137-138). Although there have been considerable debate and disa- greement among positivists and neo—positivists about the va- lidity of the basic tenets of this philosophical orientation toward science, a number of general assumptions may be put forward to indicate its basic premises. McCarthy (1978) identifies four: 1. "The unity of scientific method." This implies that the methods of the natural sciences also apply to the study of human behavior. 49 "the goals of inquiry -- explanation and prediction -- are identical, as is the form in which they are real- ized: the subsumption of individual cases under hypothe- tically proposed general laws." "The relation of theory to practice is primarily technic- al. If the appropriate general laws are known and the relevant inital (sic) conditions are manipulable, we can produce a desired state of affairs, natural or social. But the question of which states of affairs are to be pro- duced cannot be scientifically resolved. It is ultimately a matter of decision, for no 'ought' can be derived from an 'is,‘ no 'value' from a 'fact.‘ Scientific inquiry is itself 'value-free'; it strives only for objective (inter- subjectively testable) value-neutral results." "The hallmark of scientific knowledge is precisely its testability. . . . Thus the empirical basis of science is composed of observation statements . . . that can be said either to report perceptual experiences or, at least, to be motivated by them" (McCarthy, 1978, pp. 138- 139). Finally, the claim that the methods of the natural and analytical sciences are the only sources of reliable know- ledge, is also generally regarded as part of a positivist philosophy, although it may be more accurately regarded as an objectivistic claim. 50 The influence of positivism is suggested in home econom- ics in the persistent goal of becoming more scientific, and wanting the housewife to be more scientific also; in the emphasis on empirical research to the virtual exclusion of other types of studies, and in the viewPoint that profession- als provide technical knowledge to help families solve their problems. Historical studies and accounts also reflect the influence of positivism. With few exceptions these studies do not raise questions about the veneration of science, and the exclusive concern for doing empirical research. Empiri- cist influences can be seen in the "factual" nature of many historical studies. The question to be considered is whether a positivist self-understanding is an: adequate one for a field like home economics. According to the West-German social theorist and philosopher, Jurgen Habermas, there are epistemological and sociological reasons why positivism must be critiqued and transcended if a more adequate understanding of society is to be developed. By applying elements from Habermas' theoretical frame- work to the self-understanding of home economics as reflec- ted in historical literature, it becomes clear that existing frameworks for studying the social role of home economics are inadequate. The analysis also lends weight to the argu— ment advanced earlier that the role of professionals in soci- ety needs to be understood in terms of power. 51 Habermas' Critique of Positivism Habermas' critique of positivism is premised on the ca- tegorical distinction he makes between work and interaction as the two basic dimensions of human life. According to Habermas (1970a), work, or purposive-rational action, the activities through which human groups control outer nature, involves instrumental action and rational choice. Purposive- rational action is governed by technical rules. It seeks to find the most suitable means to reach given ends under spe- cific conditions. According to Bernstein (1976), "Work, as a primary level of action, refers to the ways in which indi- viduals control and manipulate their environment in order to survive and preserve themselves" (p. 193). With interaction, Habermas understands, communicative action, symbolic interaction. It is governed by binding consensual norms, which define reciprocal expectations about behavior and which must be understood and recognized by at least two acting subjects. Social norms are enforced through sanc- tions. Their meaning is objectified in ordinary lang- uage communication. While the validity of technical rules and strategies depends on that of empirically true or analytically correct propositions, the validi- ty of social norms is grounded only in the intersub- jectivity of the mutual understanding of intentions and secured by the general recognition of obligations (1970a, p. 92). Habermas maintains that human social evolution must be understood in terms that distinguish between work done ac- cording to technical rules, and interaction that proceeds ac- cording to norms that require justification. Habermas works 52 out this distinction between work and interaction at a num— ber of levels (McCarthy, 1978). He develops a theory of cognitive interests in which he maintains that different kinds of interests underlie differ— ent kinds of activity. According to Habermas, cognitive or "knowledge-constitutive interests" are "basic orientations rooted in specific fundamental conditions of possible repro- duction and self-constitution of the human Species, namely work and interaction (1971, p. 196). These cognitive in- terests function to, shape and determine what counts as objects and types of knowledge: they determine the categories relevant to what we take to be knowledge, as well as the proce- dures for discovering and warranting knowledge claims (Bernstein, 1976, p. 192). Habermas maintains that a technical interest in pre- diction and control of objectified processes underlies pur- posive-rational action. A practical interest "in securing and expanding possibilities of mutual and self-understanding in the conduct of life" corresponds to communicative action (McCarthy, 1978, p. 57). On the basis of the theory of cognitive interests, Ha- bermas makes a methodological distinction between the empiri- cal-analytical sciences, which correspond to an interest in technical control, and the historical-hermeneutic sciences which have a practical interest. In summary, Habermas distinguishes between the techni- cal, which refers to means-ends rationality, the empirical- 53 analytical sciences, and purposive-rational action; and the practical, which refers to the rational concern for coming to mutual understanding on the basis of norms and values, and corresponds to the hermeneutic sciences and communica- tive action. Habermas also identifies a third cognitive interest, namely, an emancipatory interest. The status of this inter- est is different from that of the technical and the practi- cal interests. McCarthy (1978) clarifies the distinction as follows: The interest of self-reflection in emancipation is viewed then as an interest in social relations organ- ized on the basis of communication free from domina- tion. From this perspective power, ideology, and cri- tical self-reflection do not have the same anthropolo- gical status as work and interaction (p. 93). Habermas links ideology to power at work in social rela- tions. For Habermas, ideology is more than a set of false notions or ideas making up people's misunderstanding of their social relations and material conditions. Rather, he understands ideology as at work in language and communica- tion. When the working of power in social relations is mis- represented, communication among people becomes distorted, as the interests being served are hidden or distorted (Haber— mas, 1970). The critique of ideology, for Habermas, is aimed at freeing subjects from misconceptions in their understand- ing of themselves and their society, and thus altering the quality of their interaction in the direction of the "ideal speech situation" (McCarthy, 1975, p. xvii). This involves 54 more openness of expression, equality of access to informa- tion, and ease of participation. According to Habermas, an emancipatory interest under- lies critical social science and the critique of ideology. Critical science is concerned with going beyond (the goal of producing nomological knowledge) to determine when theoretical statements grasp invariant regularities of social action as such and when they express ideologically frozen relations of dependence that can in principle be transformed (Habermas, 1971, p. 310). Moving to a more explicitly sociological and historical analysis, Habermas carries the distinction between work and interaction over into the realm of the organization of socie- ty. He differentiates between society's institutional frame- work which "consists of norms that guide symbolic action" and subsystems, such as the economy "in which primarily sets of purposive-rational action are institutionalized" (1970a, p. 93). Habermas develops his critique of positivism on the ba- sis of these distinctions between work and social interac- tion. He claims that positivism obscures the distinction between work and interaction, between the technical and the practical. At the epistemological level, this restricts ra- tionality to the methods of the empirical-analytical sci- ences. The problem with the claim that the methods of the empirical-analytical sciences are the only reliable means to gain knowledge is that it cannot be verified through those methods. 55 The norms governing the activities of scientists are not open to reflection through the methods of the empirical- analytical sciences. It is impossible to explain how a com- munity of scientists could develop solely through technical rationality. A scientific community presupposes a level of action, namely social interaction or communication, that can only be grasped if a more inclusive form of rationality is accepted. The existence of such a community presupposes con- sensus arrived at through interaction about the norms that guide their scientific practice. The objectivism of the so- cial sciences is attributed to the failure to recognize this, and 11) the consequent reduction of all rationality to one kind, namely technical rationality. The reduction of practical rationality to technical ra- tionality leads to a redefinition of the role of the profes- sional as one of applying technical knowledge derived from empirical-analytical sciences to reach given goals. The norms and values underlying these goals are not open to exam- ination through empirical-analytical means. As long as those are considered to be the only rational means, norms and val- ues are beyond rational. discussion. The interests served through the interaction of the professional with the public are not open for discussion. Thus Habermas would argue that a positivistic understanding of intellectual activity is ide- ological because reflection (M: the power exercised in those activities is blocked. 56 Habermas argues further that. a. positivistic self-un- derstanding is not limited to the sciences, but that it oper— ates in advanced capitalist countries on a much larger scale. He identifies two important tendencies in these soci- eties since the 1870's. In the first place, he notes the increased role of science in society. Habermas argues that the interdependence of research and technology has made sci- ence the leading productive force in the society. Secondly, the state is increasingly involved in the eco- nomy. This has become necessary to stabilize the economic system, which is prone to periodic crises, due to over-pro- duction, and under-consumption. Thus the state becomes more actively involved in reproducing class relations. It now has to find a way to justify its involvement in a system which distributes surplus wealth unequally (Habermas, 1975). How- ever, justification