' THE ROLE OF INTERMEDIATE ORGANIZATIONS IN A TOTALITARIAN SOCIETY: THE CASE OF COMMUNIST CHINA 1949-1964 By Richard Gerald Mendes The task of this thesis is twofold: first, to utilize the available literature in the field of politica1 authoritarianism for the purpose of synthesizing a model of totalitarian regime behavior; second, to apply a limited portion of this model to an analysis of Communist China during the 1949-1964 period. The first task must be approached with extreme care, for the field of political authoritarianism is one in which conceptual clarity is often lacking. Fascist, monarchical, communist, militaristic, traditional-deSpotic, totalitarian, and still other forms of authoritarian government have tended to be lumped together in a fashion which often lacks any attempt to construct inter-authori- tarian delineations. Thus, the first major goal of this thesis is to present a model totalitarian regime which Possesses both internal consistency and external differ- entiation- The model actually presented is one based upon the axiom that the distinguishing characteristic of a totalitarian regime is the drive of the ruling elite for total centralization of all societal power in its own hands. Richard Gerald Mendes From this basic axiom, via the process of deductive logic, a series of propositions is derived. These propo- sitions represent one functional aSpect of the totalitarian regime, specifically, the relationships between the total— itarian elite and intermediate groups (i.e., any group existing in the organizational Space between the individual and the elite itself) of the society. Thus, the major thrust of the bulk of the thesis is to examine the possible congruence between these postulated propositions and actual behavior in Communist China during the 1949-1964 period. Three types of intermediate groups in China were chosen for examination: (1) minor parties, (2) mass orga— nizations, and (3) mass campaigns. These particular groups were chosen because they were nominally independent or quasi-independent of the leadership elite. Therefore the elite-intermediate group relationships postulated at the outset would logically be more visible in their cases than in those of groups more closely tied to the elite itself (e.g. , the Army or the Party). The data utilized in this examination are reflective of the difficulty in obtaining information concerning "closed" political systems. The Chinese regime has guarded the secrecy of its decision-making procedures and has attempted to structure the flow of information regarding the announcement and implementation of policy in the nation Richard Gerald Mendes at large. Therefore, analysis of the Chinese situation calls for the use of a certain sleuth-like approach strongly reminiscent of pre—l956 studies of the Stalinist regime. However, no nation as large as China can function without leaving tell—tale traces of its activities. Two major sources of information are available, and both are utilized in this thesis. The first source of information is the reportage of scholars and journalists who have been allowed to visit China. The second is the group of Ameri- can governmental agencies in the Far East that constantly monitors internal Chinese communications. These agencies painstakingly collect and translate Chinese newspapers, magazines, and radio broadcasts. By judicious use of both of these sources one can reasonably hope to derive a fairly accurate picture of events in China. The conclusion of this thesis is that the totali— tarian model and the actual behavior of the Chinese regime are similar enough to encourage further use of the totali- tarian model in attempting to understand other functional aSpects of the Chinese system. Furthermore, since a model operates on the basis of analogy, it is a valuable tool for prediction. Therefore, the totalitarian model also holds promise as a framework for anticipating coming events in China. Indeed, the Cultural Revolution can be viewed as a logical extension of the elite-intermediate group rela— tionships postulated at the outset of this thesis. THE ROLE OF INTERMEDIATE ORGANIZATIONS IN A TOTALITARIAN SOCIETY: THE CASE OF COMMUNIST CHINA 1949-1964 By Richard Gerald Mendes A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY JDepartment of Political Science © Copyright by RICHARD GERALD MENDES 1972 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Several persons have made the.preparation of this thesis a possibility. I wish to thank Dr. Thomas Greene for his aid in the early stages of my research. Dr. David Bell and Dr. Alan Spitz, my dissertation committee readers, contributed greatly to the completion of my work. Dr. Bell's analysis and contributions colored the entire theoretical and philOSOphical orientation, while Dr. Spitz provided a wealth of information on the functioning of the Chinese regime as well as insightful methodological com- ments. I wish to especially note my gratitude to Dr. Paul Hiniker, the chairman of my thesis committee. He helped me formulate the basic concepts of this research and sub- sequently provided intellectual and moral support at every stage of my work. Finally, I wish to acknowledge my debt to my parents, who never doubted that I would finish this thesis (which is more than I can say for myself) and were a con- stant source of encouragement. ii CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . ii LIST OF TABLES .- . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . iv Chapter I. INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 II. A TOTALITARIAN MODEL . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 III. MINOR PARTIES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 67 IV. MASS ORGANIZATIONS . . . . . . . . . . . . . 114 V. MASS CAMPAIGNS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 175 VI. CONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 208 BIBLIOGRAPHY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 231 iii Table LIST OF TABLES Theoretical Framework Minor Parties and Mass Organizations Young Pioneers' Membership 1949-1960 Campaign Typology . . . . . iv Page 14 71 146 187 CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION The purpose of this research is to examine possible relationships between the Chinese Communist Government and a model totalitarian state. The first task, therefore, is to explicate the procedures to be used in constructing the model totalitarian state. This task must be considered in terms of both the materials to be used for the process of conceptualization and the structural requisites of model building. Turning first to the unstructured gathering of materials (observations) which are the basics of the proc- ess of conceptualization, one must choose between reliance upon primary experiences and what might be termed "pre— inducted" materials. It is far beyond the scope of this research to construct the model from scratch. That is a project which can fill, and has filled, numerous volumes. Rather, the strategy of this paper is to synthesize avail- able theory in order to provide a model. The intention is to "boil down" the vast quantity of literature on the subject until only the bare bones, the most basic charac- teristics of the totalitarian model remain. The goal is 1 2 to reject totalitarian characteristics unique to a single, or a small, group of authors; but rather to search for characteristics which seem to be consensual across the whole range of investigation into this field. In attempt- ing such a project one must be wary of the subjectivity of many authors, the tendency of various disciplines to use different jargon to describe the same activity, and the sheer bulk of commentary on totalitarianism. A sur- prising fact is that in the great quantity of totalitarian writings, there is a reasonably high degree of agreement upon basics. Presented below are various scholars' char- acterizations of the totalitarian model which, in the opinion of the author, are fairly representative of both the diversity and uniformity of opinion on this topic. Perhaps the most widely known description of a totalitarian model is that presented by Friedrich and Brzezinski in Totalitarian Dictatorship and Autocracy. They conceptualize a totalitarian regime as possessing the following six characteristics: (1) an official ideology which relates to all areas of man's activity; (2) a single mass party which is elitist and usually led by a single individual; (3) a terroristic police system; (4) a "technologically conditioned" almost complete control of mass communications media by the elite; (5) a "technologically conditioned" almost complete 3 elite control of all means of armed combat; (6) a centrally controlled economy.1 Actually, the use of the term "totalitarian" itself seems to have stemmed from an article on Fascist doctrine which Mussolini wrote for the Enciclopedia Italiana in 1932.2 He wrote: The Fascist conception of the State is all—embracing; outside of it no human or spiritual values may exist, much less have any value. Thus understood, Fascism is totalitarianism, and the Fascist State, as a syn- thesis and a unit which includes all values, inter- prets, develops, and lends additional power to the whole life of a people.3 Karl Schmitt was the leading Nazi political theorist. Edmund Walsh in his work Total Power presents Schmitt's interpretation of the essence of totalitarianism: The development of government proceeds "in three dialectic stages: from the absolute state of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, through the neutral state of the liberal nineteenth century to the totalitarian state in which state and society are identical." (Der Huter der Varfassung, 1931, page 79.) The final stage in this evolution was the monopoly of all power, all authority, all will in the Fuhrer, conceived and accepted as a Messiah endowed with unlimited legal prerogatives in a state under perpetual martial law. Here are two descriptions of totalitarianism provided by committed proponents of the system and it is interesting to note they lack the thoroughness of modern, Western descriptions rather than differing in content. The lack of completeness is to be expected on the part of Schmitt, since he was working in a society which frowned upon Western scientific rationalism and urged its citizens to "think with their blood." 4 In any case, modern analyses of the totalitarian model are strongly reminiscent of these earlier state- ments. Sydney Hook wrote in 1959: A totalitarian society is one in which there is an absolute and interlocking monopoly of power--economic, juridical, military, educational, and political--in the hands of a minority party which countenances no legal opposition and is not removable by the processes of freely given consent.5 This type of description more closely parallels that of Mussolini and Schmitt than does that of Friedrich and Brzezinski. In point of fact, most contemporary analysts of totalitarianism prefer to follow the example of Friedrich and Brzezinski, and describe totalitarianism in terms of a determining set of characteristics. A. James Gregor very closely parallels Friedrich and Brzezinski in his list of totalitarian features: (1) an official ideology that extends to all areas of human activity; (2) a unitary party which is elitist; (3) a governmental monopoly of police, weapons, and com- munications; (4) a centralized economy.6 Similarly, Boris Meissner, writing in Brzezinski's col— lection Dilemmas of Change in Soviet Politics, character- izes a totalitarian regime as one possessing the following: (1) unrestricted autocracy of the party (the lack of any restrictions constitutes the difference between total- itarian and autocratic regimes); 5 (2) total control from above (terror serves as a reminder of this control) which extends to all areas of life and all groups and organizations; (3) total planning in the economic, social, political, and cultural Spheres.7 N. S. Timasheff also presents a set of characteristics: (1) concentration of power in the hands of a few; (2) lack of individual rights vis a vis the collectivity; (3) expansion of the state until it becomes almost synon- ymous with the society.8 Karl Deutsch characterizes the totalitarian regime in much the same fashion as above; however, his language varies somewhat. He perceives three crucial characteristics of a totalitarian regime: (l) mobilization of effort (i.e., an active support by the citizenry); (2) unity of command (once again, centralization of power); (3) effective power of enforcement (which implies govern- mental control of weapons, police, and communications).9 Barrington Moore provides a more condensed version of many of the above characterizations when he describes a central— ized totalitarian system as: . . . a society all of whose activities, from the rearing of children to the production and distri- bution of economic goods, are controlled and directed from a single center. Presumably coercion plays a large part in this centralized control. Finally, Hannah Arendt distinguishes two central factors of a totalitarian system. First, the atomization 6 of the individual. That is, the citizen of the ideal totalitarian state has no allegiance, no frame of refer- ence, and no empathy for any form of group whatsoever aside from the monolithic state itself. Second, the 11 Bronislaw totalitarian state is an imperialistic state. Malinowski concurs, and indeed emphasizes this second feature when he states, "Totalitarianism can be defined as the supreme mobilization of natural resources for war efficiency."12 The above descriptions of totalitarianism are but a sample of the voluminous descriptions of totalitarianism. Actually, most of the remaining descriptions differ from those above not generally in meaning, but rather in com— pleteness. How the preceding authors, among others, per- ceive totalitarianism will be presented in greater depth below, as a model of totalitarianism is synthesized point by point. The second task mentioned at the outset was to comment upon the process of model building as it relates to this research. Until now the term "model" has been used in the lexical sense, primarily because many writers quoted above made use of this term and it is inadvisable for the author of this paper to account for EEEEE usage(s). For the purposes of the research to follow, however, it is necessary to present a stipulative definition of "model" in the interests of clarity and rigor. 7 The term "model" seems to have a multiplicity of usages in the social sciences. Items labeled as models may be more or less rigorous, physical, formal, or pre- scriptive. Scott Greer comments: The term model is used, however, in various senses. In the policy sciences it is sometimes used to refer to ideal conditions--model behavior by model peOple. It is sometimes just a way of referring to fairly abstract theory. And it sometimes refers to the process of quantifying laws.13 Van Dyke also notes this problem in stating " . . . that imitation, explanation, and prescription are all associa- ted with the notion of a model and that some confusion results."14 The ambiguity inherent in the term "model" seems to be partitionable into three distinct areas: (1) the idea of "formal" and "informal" models; (2) the rela— tionship between "model" and "theory"; and (3) the distinction between "model" and "ideal type." The idea of a formal model seems to hinge upon the degree to which the model is symbolic and divorced from empirical referents.15 Meehan contends: What is a formal model? In the simplest terms possible, it consists of a set of carefully defined elements and the rules for manipulating them; the whole system is usually reduced to symbolic form-- Euclidean geometry is a classic example. From a slightly different point of view, a formal model comprises a set of axioms and all of the postulates of theorems that can be derived from those axioms according to the canons of formal logic. "Formality" in a model can also entail the ability to quantify parallel elements. Greer reflects this line of reasoning in his conception of a "formal" model: 8 It seems most sensible to use the term "model" to refer to a developed theory that is isomorphic to an undeveloped one. A mathematical model would then be a developed theory for which quantitative values can be stated, values for the description of both variables and relations among them. In this sense, mathematical models are of little value for social science except in those areas where variables conform to the demands of true number; otherwise isomorphism is not determinable . . . , such areas are rare. The formal model is therefore: (1) a symbolic system whose symbols, as elements, are divorced from empirical referents; and (2) often, a system whose relational aspects can be examined vis—a-vis another system only through quantification. If the scope of the usage of the term "model" were restricted to only formal models, it would hold little promise for the purposes of this research. However, there are non-formal models which are more immediately useful. Greer states: Although models, if rigorously defined, have presently a very limited use in social science, the term "model" is ubiquitous. One could dismiss this popularity as merely a fad, a new cargo cult, if there did not seem to be a common meaning underlying all the usages noted. This use of "model" would seem to indicate a config- urative concept that can be used in widely varying circumstances. It is a formal abstraction, like any complex concept, and its utility varies with the empirical nature of its referent.18 Greer, in fact, allows great flexibility in the usage of the concept: In common usage, then, we are not talking about formal models most of the time. We are really talking about something that precedes formalization, precedes axiomatic and formal theory. We are in fact using a controlling conceptual scheme, one that is purely formal and without content, one that may lead to the construction of empirical theory. Let us be clear: 9 model, as we use it in social science, simply refers to a guiding metaphor.19 Therefore, "models" in political science may assume a variety of forms. That is, to utilize Kaplan, a family of conceptions of model (including a subset of "formal models") is inherent in the concept of model. A second concern in the consideration of model building is the relationship, and possible overlap, between "model" and "theory." Kaplan contends that the use of the term "model" is often of little methodological value when one is simply Operating upon "theory."20 Kaplan states: We can now understand why the term "model" is sometimes used as a synonym for "theory," especially one which is «couched in the postulational style. The model is conceived as a structure of symbols interpreted in certain ways, and what it is a model of is the subject-matter Specified by the interpre- tation. Relations among the symbols are presumed to exhibit corresponding relations among the elements of the subject-matter. The theory is more or less abstract-—that is, it neglects certain variables-- and what it describes are certain more or less "ideal" entities, having an existence only in the context of the theory itself. What is hoped is that the system of such entities will be isomorphic, in appropriate reSpects, to the real system which provides the subject-matter for the theory.21 What Kaplan has outlined above he suggests be termed 22 rather than "model." "theory in postulational form," Kaplan is, in essence, stating that in order for a theory to be a model, only the relational aspects of the elements may be evaluated for isomorphism and there is no need for the elements themselves to be isomorphic to any degree whatsoever. This point is especially important to this 10 research because the "model" used here would lose its validity in light of Kaplan's categorization. The fault in Kaplan's treatment is that he dichotomizes theories into sets of either totally relational or other. That is, he leaves no room for degree. It might be reasonably stated that a "model" emphasizes the relational aSpects and thus "model" and "non-model" theory are end points on a continuum. In this context, the use of the term "model" in the present research is valid, since the primary func— tion of the structure is to permit extrapolation and pre— diction based upon congruity of form, and the empirical referents function merely as indicators of relevance, rather than as explanatory hypotheses. It might be added, and will be illustrated, that Kaplan's severe restrictions upon the usage of the term "model" are not generally reflected in the literature on structure of theory. A final consideration of model building is the Possible distinction between "model" and "ideal type." Ideal types come in two forms: prescriptive, and descriptive. The use of the term "model" to represent a Prescriptive ideal type is common. Van Dyke comments: . . . we should note that models sometimes represent a conception of the desirable, constituting patterns or ideal types, and so take on a normative or prescrip- tive quality. Thus one of the characters in the Pirates of Penzance claimed, "I am the very model of a modern Major-General." In this sense, there are also model professors, model wives, and model students. And there are models who diSplay dresses in fashion shops and models who pose for artists. To name them as models is to prescribe. Imitation is recommended. Those who want to excel as Major-Generals, professors, 11 wives, or students, and those who want to achieve the beauty of the fashion model or the artist's model should seek an isomorphic correSpondence of a one—to- one sort with the model.23 Although the use of the term "model" in the above sense is quite common in everyday life, in this paper the term is in no way prescriptive. A second form of "ideal-type," the Weberian form, is descriptive. It simply describes the "pure" form or what might be described as the modern equivalent of a Platonic Form. Kaplan states: An ideal type may be a construct like the limiting concepts. . . . It Specifies something "with which the real situation or action is compared and surveyed for the explication of certain of its significant com- ponents." (135:93) [Weber, M.: The Methodology of the Social Sciences, Glencoe, Ill., 1949f] As such, it is a particularly useful device for dealing with internal vagueness. No state in history has been wholly, fully, "truly" a democracy, just as no male has exhibited all the traits of masculinity in superlative degree-- Athens did not extend suffrage to slaves, and even Achilles was given to tears. But we can conceptualize perfect specimens of any species.24 It is therefore obvious that one need not choose between utilizing a model or an ideal type, since the two are separate entities and not mutually exclusive. One can construct a model gf_an ideal type. "Model" refers to the manner or style of conceptualization while "ideal— type" refers to a type of concept. Thus a model of an ideal type would be a construct primarily concerned with the elemental relations within some "pure" entity. One might also have theories about ideal types as well as models. 12 Having considered the various uses of the term "model" (as well as "ideal type") and the ambiguities of the term, it is now necessary to stipulate the use of the term in this paper. First, a model is an abstraction. As Van Dyke writes, ". . . , a model is an abstract image --a simplified and composite version-~of a class of a."25 ;ptienomen Second, a model functions via the process of analogy. Lastrucci writes: A model, as employed in scientific discussions, refers to a parallel form, simpler than the complex subject it represents but having a similar structure or organization.é And Nagel adds: In analogies of the first kind [substantive analogies], a system of elements possessing certain already familiar properties, assumed to be related in known ways as stated in a set of laws for the system, is taken as a model for the construction of a theory for some second system. This second system may differ from the initial one only in containing a more in- clusive set of elements, all of which have properties entirely similar to those in the model; or the second system may differ from the initial one in a more radical manner, in that the elements constituting it have properties not found in the model (or at any rate not mentioned in the stated laws for the model). 7 Ellird, a model, because it is an analogous structure, is \nsed for prediction and extrapolation rather than explana- Eigg. Meehan writes, ". . . , formal models can often be Used as predictors, even though no explanation of the phenomena being examined is available."28 van Dyke sim— ilarly contends, "A correSpondence is specified between attributes of the model and what is modeled. Neither explanation nor prescription enters in."29 Finally, a 13 model can encompass an "ideal-type" and, in effect, represent the pure form of a phenomenon. Lastrucci sums up this position: Science is fundamentally a particular method of achieving reliable knowledge. In pursuit of that achievement, all its knowledge is theoretical--i.e., it is an interpretation of reality, not the reality itself. This theoretical interpretation is often arranged in terms of ideal or perfect forms or con- ditions--e.g., an absolute condition designated as a "solution," a Specific and discrete entity as a "cell," or an absolutely round figure designated as a "circle." Such conceived ideal forms are termed models, whether referring to Simple concepts such as "solutions" or to highly abstract concepts such as "the law of gravity." But such models are only approximations, and hence tentative interpretations of reality. The function of science, therefore, is to endeavor con— stantly to refine and improve such models so that they may continually approximate more closely the assumed reality of form and matter in terms of increasing and more refined empirical evidence.30 Table 1 presents the model of the "pure" or "ideal" totalitarian state which will be utilized in this VVc>rk. The basic axiom of the entire model is that total- 211tarian regimes seek the totalization of power. A defini- tion of power and the derivation of the lower-level 191?opositions will be presented in later sections. But fifr‘st it is necessary that the nature of the testing be Ina-(‘le clear. Specifically, the propositions in Table 1 are 223 hypotheses, whose validity in relation to total- itarianism in general will be tested in the course of tiliis work. Rather, because they are components of a model, trlGBy are the "givens" of an equation and are axiomatically t‘?l1e. If one wishes to question their validity he must do SC) by criticizing either the basic (general) assumptions 14 Manchu 29H? moofiuomhmpsfi masosw no“ munchovnfi :OHmownnmm: Av .mHnsoa>aosa oeanmom an mast mo mononum can mpflnonpsm mo mocfia omsmsoo Am oflmfloomm xDHm mo mumpm pampmsoo m SH museum sows AN mQSOMw so>ooxm910hm Ham Honesoo no soupmon AH OOSmHHHo>hsm Hmsofi>flocfi mo masonw OpmfioosHOch pampmnoo Am hsoooasm honpmom an no SSOSOHSN hospmon AH oncoming: wcfixOOMIuosoo SOBOQ mo mcofim ow mamow Ham mpwao Icouxo o>HumufiHmno mo cofipmcaouonsm Am Hmsnowsfi cam UOQHqu AN tam o>fipmpflucmsa AH sosoo mo sofipmufiampoe Hmhococ Hooos smfinmpfiamaoe mo mofiumahOpomhmno snooze mo Ho>oq um03m2rrect). ‘3Eln bring the entire Situation into Sharper focus. may state that human beings need water in order to live, as a logically derived true prOposition of human behavior, deduced from the model of a "human being." One may also '3t353erve the activities of creature Q. If creature Q uses 11¢) 'water, assuming the method Of observation itself is v‘lilid, one can conclude that the model of "human being" Ahalfis some amount Xwater less relevance to the understanding cxf' creature Q (where the sum of X? represents the total 16 sum of human characteristics), than would be the case if creature Q had used water. For creature Q to be human, Q = xwater I Xhair I Xreproduction I + Xn' Therefore, what iS being tested is not the model of humanity, which is a given, or the reality of Q, which is a. fact of existence, but the validity of the equation. This research operates on the same principle as that outlined above. But the research is not testing a Simple equation, which is often an either/or proposition. The task is more complex. Relationships become a matter of degree. In short, this work is testing, in a very non- its actual operation. The "bases-interaction" dimen- sion is also, in general, dichotomous. That is, most 'tllteorists define power in terms of either its attributes 5332, as a relationship between elements. Of those who £3131?ess the bases of power Simon is prominent. He uses the 'tGSer "authority" but it seems to be, in effect, a substi— tute for "power." Simon writes: 19 Because the person who accepts proposals may do so for a variety of motives, there will be seen in any organization a number of different types of authority relationships, corresgonding to these dif- ferent motives for acceptance.3 :Simon goes on to discuss the various types of authority (hi.e., the bases of power). Briefly, he divides the bases cxf power in the following fashion: A . Authority of Confidence (obedience stems from the belief in another's ability) 1. Functional Status (expertise) 2. Hierarchical Status (position) 3. Charismatic Leadership 13.. Authority of Identification (obedience stems from the need to identify with a group) C3- Authority of Sanctions l. Non-hierarchical Sanctions 2. Hierarchical Sanctions (authority stems from deprivations caused by a higher position in the structure of organization) 3. Rule of Anticipated Reactions (obedience stems from threat of sanctions) - Authority of Legitimacy (obedience stems from one'S belief that he should obey)33 Nieburg, in his discussion of political violence, also ln‘atitions bases of power. He writes: Domestic, politically socialized power is transmuted into indirect forms manifested by prestige, influ- ence, property-holding, skill, class or caste, phy- sical beauty, and the like. The constituted authority 20 structure holds a legitimate monopoly of the means of physical power in order to enforce the norms of social relationships, rights and reSponsibilities, procedures for political change, conduct and media— tion of private and public bargaining, and exchange of values among individuals and groups by means of attenuated and socialized forms of indirect and de— centralized power.34 Schermerhorn, in his work Society and Power, refers to Bierstedt's discussion of the sources of power: Bierstedt is more persuasive when he declares that the source of power in human society is threefold: "(1) numbers of people, (2) social organizations, and (3) resources," particularly where intergroup relations are concerned.35 €3<2hermerhorn also presents his own set of power sources. lies contends that there are five major bases of power: (21) military, police, or criminal power with its control (:2) (:3) (‘1) (5) over violence; economic power with control over land, labor wealth, or corporate production; political power with control over legitimate and ultimate decision-making within a Specified territory; traditional or ideological power involving control over belief and value systems, religion, education, Specialized knowledge, and propaganda; diversionary power with control over hedonic inter- ests, recreation, and enjoyments.36 A-::l-‘l:hough all of the above definitions are generally use- :E‘JII, there are, on the whole, inappropriate for the I33'E‘esent research for two reasons. First, they exhibit a tendency to define power in terms of other abstract 21 concepts and are thus partially exposed to the criticism of circularity. Second, since it is a model with which the author of this paper is working, the interactional characteristics of "power" are of primary concern. To discuss power as an entity is irrelevant, to discuss it as a relationship is crucial. Therefore it is necessary to examine some defini- ‘tions of power put forth by theorists who emphasize the linteractional aSpects of the concept. These definitions Cain.be divided into four general categories: (1) those truat emphasize the role of power in structuring or moti— Vating a society; (2) those that view power in terms of a C3111sh of systems; (3) those that discuss power as it relates to conflict and/or sanctions; and (4) those that Vilew power as an actor upon the probabilities of events. The first group mentioned above consists of those definitions of power which define power as some cohesive ‘31? :motivational force acting vis-a—vis the society, geanerally, as a whole. Nieburg expresses this position: Much of philosophy and the social sciences deals with "power," "violence," "force," and the nature and function of the state and its police power. Power iS the most overworked and ill—defined word in political discourse. It can be defined most concretely in physical terms: Power is the application of energy to do work. It is the man or machine moving a mass from here to there. At a higher level of abstraction, power is the ability to direct energy to modify or control the environment, to express values (designs, goals, etc.) through intervention in the configuration of things. In terms of the social environment, power may be viewed as the ability to direct human energy (i.e., attitudes and behavior) to express or realize 22 certain values by the organization and use, modification and control of both physical and human (i.e., behavior itself) materials. . . 37 Huntington contends that Talcott Parsons also reflects this view: Parsons says power is ". . . the ability to mobilize the resources of the society for the attain- ment of goals for which a general 'public' commitment has been made, or may be made. It is mobilization, above all, of the action of persons and groups, which is binding on them by virtue of their position in the society." 8 Ifiinally, Lynd also exhibits this society—oriented con- ceptualization of power: Organized power may accordingly be conceived as the process by which whatever is the version of order and disorder in a given society is continually defined, redefined, and maintained. Order in this sense is the way the major routines of a population's daily actions are channeled toward selected goals in the use of available institutional means.39 The consensus on this position, then, seems to be that pOwer is a force which motivates one set of elements in a ES<><3iety to accomplish some task. In a sense, power is the ability of a society to utilize its various resources in ‘51?<>ve is somewhat similar to the first. That is, it also c3<>riceptualizes power as a system-wide relationship; how— e\'er, it stresses the conflict or disruption between S‘ystems. Karl Deutsch puts forth this definition: We might say, then, that power consists in the prob- ability of preserving the inner structure of one of the systems in a clash, with little or no relevant 23 modification, at the price of bringing about rela- tively large modification in the structure of the systems which clash with it. In other words, power consists in accepting the least amount of non- autonomous change in one system while producing the largest amount of non-autonomous change in another.40 Thus Deutsch views power as a prOportional relationship, involving both change in the object of the power relation- ship and change in the wielder of power. The problem with this definition lies in its inability to conceive of power in absolute amounts. That is, one system which produces no change in another system and suffers no change itself, is equivalent in power to a system which produces total change in another system yet undergoes total transformation in the process. However, it would, by this point, seem conceptually necessary to admit that the Simple ability to produce change is somehow related to power. Thus to equate the absence of activity with the ability to produce vast change is a fruitless line of argument. In terms of a simple application, it would be stating that the Nazi regime had no more, or perhaps even less, power than a rock. Therefore, the effect of power upon the wielder of power, while perhaps useful for an understanding of power, cannot be allowed to become a determining factor. A third view of power relates the concept to sanc- tions (deprivations) and, in some cases, to conflict. Harold Lasswell presents the classical definition of this type: At this point we narrow our conception of power, using the term to designate relations in which severe 24 deprivations are expected to follow the breach of a pattern of conduct. . . . This eliminates an enormous range of relationships in which a breach is assumed to be of trivial importance. This mode of conceiving power emphasizes the crucial role of expectation. One conductor may expect to deal strictly with his men, and to impose penalties for minor as well as major deviation from the faithful following of his cues. And an orchestra may expect to deal strictly with conductors if the players are dis— satisfied. Indeed, by deliberate non-cOOperation or hostile agitation, they may get him fired.41 Bachrach and Baratz also utilize the notion of sanctions, and they also add the idea of conflict. They conceptualize power in the following manner: We can now draw together the several elements of our conception of power. A power relationship exists when (a) there is a conflict over values or course of action between A and B; (b) B complies with A's wishes; and (c) he does so because he iS fearful that A will deprive him of a value or values which he, B, regards more highly than those which would have been achieved by noncompliance.42 In fact, they insist upon conflict as a condition of a power relationship: . . . , in Speaking of power relations, one must take care not to overstate the case by saying that A has power over B merely because B, anxious to avoid sanc- tions, complies with a given policy proclaimed by A.43 Of course, one must also consider the question of what constitutes a sanction. Lasswell tackles the problem by enlarging the range of application: Manifestly, expectations may differ about what constitutes a deprivation, and what is mild or severe. When we are examining not one human asso— ciation but a whole community, or all the communities of which there is knowledge, we define severity or mildness in the light of the entire panorama of rela- tionships which are taken into account.44 . .‘IIF A Ono‘“ P‘0. ‘ A.“ 3'" Lf o—O- (Y) tn I), 25 George Orwell presents a rather extreme, though hardly viable, View of the proper role of sanctions: How does one man assert his power over another? . . . By making him suffer. Obedience is not enough. Unless he is suffering how can you be sure that he is obeying your will and not his own? Power is in inflicting pain and humiliation. Power is in tearing human minds to pieces and putting them together again in new shapes of your own choosing.45 Finally, Schermerhorn combines the notion of sanctions with that of decision-making capabilities: . . , we may define power as the processual relation between two parties modally characterized by (l) asymmetrical influence, in which a perceptible prob- ability of decision rests in one of the two parties, even over the resistance of the other party; and (2) the predominance of negative sanctions (threatened or actual) as a feature of behavior in the dominant party. . . . In summary: whatever the deviation from either of the modal characteristics, power relations are still present as long as one of the two variables, asymmetry, or negative sanctions, still remains. 45 The thrust of these arguments is fairly clear; A has power over B if, and sometimes only if, A can impose some depri- vation upon B in order to force compliance. One fault of this type of conceptualization stems from nonintercompara- bility of sanctions. One man's sanction is another man's reward, and not even Lasswell's attempt to "average out" the idea of sanctions can suffice to solve the problem. A second, and more serious, fault lies in the inability of these theories to account for changed behavior due to such "non-sanctions" as idealization and imitation, love, charisma, etc. To claim a proper definition of power by banishing the above types of behavior to other categories (e.g., influence) is merely to make a semantic victory 26 out of a conceptual defeat. The behavior of men and groups is controlled and influenced by the carrot as well as the stick, and to ignore either is unsatisfactory. The fourth View of the nature of power seems to hold the most promise. It conceives of power as the ability to change the probability of occurrences. Deutsch states: . . . , power is the ability to make things happen that would not have happened otherwise. In this sense it is akin to causality, that is, to the pro- duction of a change in the probability distribution of events in the world. And since the world is changing already, power deals with the change of change--or second-order change. Thus power involves our ability to change the changes that are already under way and would continue without our intervention. 47 Thus, the probabilistic approach avoids the major pitfalls of the earlier approaches by avoiding the almost hopeless complexities and ambiguities of what power is and focusing upon what power does. The concept is defined by its mea- surement. That is, all the earlier approaches defined power in terms of its identifying characteristics, either its bases or the features of interaction associated with it. This led to either reification of the concept of power, or the unenviable task of trying to understand a very abstract concept through a limited set of empirical characteristics. The probabilistic approach eases the Situation, and also eSpecially lends itself to use with model building, by looking only at the effects of power rather than power itself. Thus, in a very real sense, power is as power does. 27 The concept of power which will be used in this research is the probabilistic concept put forward by Dahl. Briefly stated, Dahl measures power (he never truly "defines" it) as the difference in probabilities of an entity committing or not committing some act, dependent upon either action or non-action by a second entity. That is, A's power over B with respect to B committing act x, dependent upon A's committing act w can be symbolically represented as: M (£ : w,x) = P (a, x/A, w) - P (a, x/A, W) = p1 - p2 where M is power, a and A are actors, x and w are their reSpective acts, and p is probability.48 The description presented above is the crux of Dahl's treatment. It is not necessary here to recreate his entire work, it appears in numerous places.49 Suffice it to say that for the pur- poses of this research "power" is defined as the ability of one actor to change the probability of a second actor's performance of some deed, by committing a second deed. This definition, although it may prove to contain certain Operational difficulties, is especially suited, because of its relational nature, to work with models. As stated earlier, the primary goal of a total- itarian regime is the ultimate concentration of power in the hands of the totalitarian elite. Logically this implies both a quantitative and a qualitative extension of power. Quantitative extension of power entails an GXpanSion of the amount of power held in relation to each 28 unit of the society. Qualitative extension of power refers to the expansion of power beyond the political Sphere and into every area of human activity. Hook states, ". . . , the historic tendency of all major totalitarian states, particularly when they find themselves in a world of non—totalitarian states, is towards total control."50 Arthur Schlesinger writes, "Totalitarianism, . . . , means that all social energy—-all loyalty, emotion and faith—- is focused upon a Single objective; . . ."51 Also, Malinowski contends that "Totalitarianism consists in the placing of one institution, the state, above all 52 The others, at the expense of their very existence." state, which i§_the totalitarian elite, is thus the center Of all decision making, and its decisiOns are unquestion- able. Kohn very correctly contends that ". . . , modern totalitarianism has reasserted the same claim to absolute- ness as medieval faith."53 But it is not simply the finality or absoluteness of decision making which uniquely characterizes the total- itarian regime. Many early deSpotisms and autocracies were also in possession of absolute authority. What dis- tinguishes the totalitarian state is the enormous range of its power. It endeavors to extend its power into every area of human existence. This feature distinguishes it from mere autocracies. Neumann writes: The design of modern dictatorship is essentially different from that of its nominal antecedents. Present-day autocracies are not just departures from the democratic norm. They claim to present a system 29 of government outliving their dictatorial creator and extending their sway into a totalitarian rule over practically every Sphere of human interest and activity. It is their quasi-institutional and total— itarian character, this virtually limitless extension in time and Space, that holds out the challenge to democracy. Schlesinger echoes this belief when he writes: The totalitarian state, which has risen in specific response to this fear of freedom, is an invention of the twentieth century. It differs essentially from old-style dictatorship, which may be bloody and tyrannical but yet leaves intact most of the structure of society. Totalitarianism, on the contrary, pul- verizes the social structure, grinding all independent groups and diverse loyalties into a Single amorphous mass. The sway of the totalitarian state is unlimited. This very fact is a source of its profound psycholog- ical appeal.55 In fact, the idea of the all pervasiveness of the totalitarian regime is probably the most widely held belief on the part of totalitarian analysts. This char- acteristic certainly predates Mussolini's popularization of the term "totalitarian." The imposition of the state upon the whole of society was a feature of Plato's ideal political system. Furthermore, the French Utopian Socialist St.-Simon was eSpousing the same idea in the early nineteenth century: "Like the modern totalitarian State, the Saint-Simonian doctrine demanded the total Control of all phases of society and culture, including the realm of personal life, family, religion, and education."56 These early calls for a total state control Were limited to small communities. It was only the tech— nological revolution in communications which permitted total control to be extended to a mass society. 30 Thus the modern totalitarian state transcends the simple autocratic state by its extension into all Spheres of human activity, and at the same time transcends the old-style "total" state by its utilization of the communi- cations revolution to extend its control to mass societies. Hans Bucheim supports this contention in his description of a modern totalitarian state: . . . the totalitarian claim to power is not kept within the bounds of possible governmental competence but--as the name makes clear-—is intended to dispose unreservedly over the totality of human life. The claim is not confined to the area for which the state is responsible but is allowed to encompass all areas, and to have an exclusive voice even where the political regime can at best play an ancillary role--as, for instance, in family life, in scientific research, and in art. Totalitarian rule attempts to encompass the whole person, the substance and Spontaneity of his existence, including his conscience. It does not acknowledge the primacy of society over the state as an area of freedom which, in principle, lies beyond governmental control, but rather interferes in it deliberately, to change it from the ground up according to its own plan; for the regime wishes to create--in accordance with its own ideological scheme and with social engineering techniques--a wholly new society. . . It undertakes the production of an artificial, synthetic society.57 George Sabine also professes this belief: [In a totalitarian society] Government may, indeed must, control every act and every interest of every individual or group in order to use it for enhancing national strength; government is not only absolute in its exercise but unlimited in its application. Nothing lies outside its province. Every interest and value—-economic, moral, and cultural--being part of the national resources were to be controlled and utilized by government.58 Kornhauser also emphasizes the totalitarian state's absorption of society: 31 Thus, while it is a dictatorship based on mass support, and while it is also based on elite-domination of centralized organization, its distinctive character lies in the fact that it is a permanently mobilized mass movement which seeks to control all aSpectS of life. Totalitarian dictatorships involve total domination, limited neither by received laws or codes (as in traditional authoritarianism) nor even by the boundaries of governmental functions (as in classical tyranny), since they obliterate the distinctions between state and society. Totalitarianism is limited only by the need to keep large numbers of people in a state of constant activity controlled by the elite.59 Finally, Ernest Barker states the situation very clearly when he writes, ". . . the system of single—party govern— ment is led to engulf--to absorb, or at any rate regulate-- churches, trade unions, institutions of education, chari- table organizations, and every form and phase of the activity of the community's life."60 The totalitarian regime is therefore characterized by an absolute and all-pervasive centralization of power. The ideal totalitarian state not only decides for its citizens such matters as who will govern, what major domestic policy will entail, etc., it also controls the most mundane and non—political questions of a person's life. Marriage, leisure activities, proper foods, etc., all come under the purview of the totalitarian state. Huxley's Brave New World presents a view of uniformity in even such minor things as proper dress. Those who doubt that a totalitarian regime's arm could ever reach that far Should contemplate the stress put upon the wearing of uniforms in many actual totalitarian regimes. 32 The extent of the totalitarian state's desire for centralization of power can be seen in the fact that it even surpasses human activity. That is, the totalitarian regime would seek to impose its control upon nature itself, (n'at least conceive of nature in such a fashion that it conforms to the regime. Robert Tucker discusses the Stalinist regime's projection of totalitarianism upon nature. Tucker contends the Soviets could not accept non- deterministic and non—ordered theories of science (e.g., Heisenberg indeterminancy principle, Mendelian genetics, quantum theories which hold that electrons "choose their own path"). In effect, Tucker concludes, the totalitarian cannot accept an uncontrollable nature any more than he can accept an uncontrollable social System. In conclusion, the first (and probably most basic) characteristic of the ideal totalitarian state is the drive of the ruling elite to centralize power both quali- tatively (over all aSpectS of life) and quantitatively (absolute obedience).62 The next logical question, then, is what is the nature of this totalitarian elite that strives so forcefully for total power? NOTES CHAPTER I 1Carl Friedrich and Zbigniew Brzezinski, Total- itarian Dictatorship and Autocracy (New York: Praeger, 1956), pp. 9-10. 2Robert Tucker, The Soviet political Mind (New York: Praeger, 1963), p. 4. 31bid., p. 4. 4Edmund Walsh, Total Power (New York: Doubleday, 1948), p. 242. 5Sydney Hook, Political Power and Personal Freedom (New York: Collier Books, 1959), P. 182. 6A. James Gregor, Contemporary Radical Ideologies (New York: Random House, 1968), pp. 20—21. 7Boris Meissner, "Totalitarian Rule and Social Change," in Zbigniew Brzezinski (ed.), Dilemmas of Change in Soviet Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969), PP. 71-75. . 8N. S. Timasheff, "Totalitarianism, Despotism, Dictatorship," in Carl Friedrich (ed.), Totalitarianism (New York: Grosset & Dunlap, 1954), p. 39. 9Karl Deutsch, "Cracks in the Monolith: Possibil- ities and Patterns of Disintegration in Totalitarian Systems," in Friedrich, Totalitarianism, p. 309. 10Barrington Moore, Jr., Political Power and Social Theory (New York: Harper & Row, 1958), p. 31. 11Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Meridian Books, 1958). 12Bronislaw Malinowski, Freedom and Civilization (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1944), p. 305. 13Scott Greer, The Logic of Social Inquiry (Chicago: Aldine Publishing Company, 19697. P. 140. 14Vernon van Dyke, Political Science: A Philosophical Analysis (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1960), p. 104. 33 34 15Kaplan would not be in agreement with this distinction; see Abraham Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry (San Francisco: Chandler Publishing Company, 1964), p. 264. 16Eugene Meehan, Contemporary Political Thought (Homewood, 111.: The Dorsey Press, 1967), p. 292. 17Greer, p. 140. 1312;g,, p. 141. 19£pgg., pp. 141-142. 20Kaplan, p. 264. 21;p;g., p. 264. 2219;g., p. 264. 23Van Dyke, p. 107. 24Kaplan, p. 83. 25Van Dyke, p. 106. 26Carlo Lastrucci, The Scientific Approach (Cambridge, Mass.: Schenkman Publishing Company, Inc., 1963), p. 130. 27Ernest Nagel, The Structure of Science (New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World, Inc., 1961), p. 110. 28Meehan, p. 294. 29V’an Dyke, p. 106. 3OLastrucci, pp. 61-62. 31R. H. Tawney, Equality (London: Allen & Unwin, 1931), p. 228. 32Herbert Simon, Donald Smithburg, and Victor Thompson, "Why Men Obey," in John Kessel, George Cole, and Robert Seddig (edS.), Micropolitics (New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, Inc., 1970), p. 580. 33Ibid., p. 580. 34H. L. Nieburg, political Violence (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1969), p. 11. 35 35Richard Schermerhorn, Society and Power (New YOrk: Random House, 1961), p. 16. 36Ibid., p. 17. 37Nieburg, p. 10. 38Samuel Huntington, Political Order in Changing Societies (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1968), p. 143. 39Robert Lynd, "Power in American Society as Re- source and Problem," in Calvin Larson and Philo Washburn (edS.) , Power, Participation, and Ideology (New York: David McKay Company, Inc., 1969), p. 58. 40Karl Deutsch, Nationalism and Social Communica- tion (Cambridge: The M.I.T. Press, 1953), p. 73. 41Harold Lasswell, Power and Personality (New York: The Viking Press, 1948), p. 12. 42Peter Bachrach and Morton Baratz, "Decisions and Non-decisions: An Analytical Framework," in Roderick Bell, David Edwards, and R. Harrison Wagner, Political Power (New York: The Free Press, 1969), p. 102} 43Ibid., p. 102. 44Lasswell, p. 13. 45George Orwell, 1984 (New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World, 1949), p. 270. 46Schermerhorn, p. 12. 47Karl DeutSch, Politics and Government (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1970), p. 24. 48Robert Dahl, "The Concept of Power," in Behavioral Science, II, No. 3 (July 1957), 205. 49Ibid., pp. 201-215. 50Hook, p. 183. 51Arthur Schlesinger, The Vital Center (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1949), p. 77. 52Ma1inowski, pp. 305-306. 53Hans Kohn, Political Ideologies of the Twentieth Century (New York: Harper Torchbooks, 1966), p. 65. 36 54Sigmund Neumann, Permanent Revolution (New York: Praeger, 1965), p. 3. 55Schlesinger, p. 53. 56Georg Iggers, The Cult of Authority (The Hague: Nbrtinus Nijhoff, 1958), p. 103. 57Hans Buchheim, Totalitarian Rule: Its Nature and Characteristics, trans. Ruth Hein (Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1968), p. 14. 53George Sabine, A History of Political Theory, 3rd ed. (New York: Holt, Rinehart, E Winston, 1937), p. 916. 59William Kornhauser, The Politics of Mass Society (New York: Free Press, 1959), pp. 122-123. 60Ernest Barker, Reflections on Government (London: Oxford University Press, 1942), p. 289. 61Tucker, p. 98. 62For an interesting counter-example to the total- itarian concept of unlimited power, the reader might con- sult Schlesinger's discussion of the extremely circumscribed nature of political power-seeking in the United States; in Joseph Schlesinger, Ambition and Politics (Chicago: Rand McNally & Co., 1966). CHAPTER II A TOTALITARIAN MODEL A second characteristic of a totalitarian regime, based upon its drive for power, is the unique nature of the political elite. It is generally the case, at least at the level of actual historical regimes, that the total— itarian society has been dominated by a single individual. Daniels' statement is typical of the conclusion of many totalitarian scholars, "They [totalitarian regimes] have all been dominated by individual dictators. In every case, one man was the creator and director of the country after the party took power."1 Similarly, Friedrich and Brzezinski state that Goering once remarked to the then British ambassador, Neville Henderson, "When a decision has to be taken, none of us count more than the stones on which we are standing. It is the Fuhrer alone who decides."2 Friedrich and Brzezinski conclude that the individual totalitarian dictator: . . . possesses more nearly absolute power than any previous type of political leader, that he is com- pletely identified with his actual following, both by himself and by them, in a kind of mystical union, that he is able to operate on both these levels as he does because he is backed by mass propaganda and terror--coercive cohesion-—and that therefore his 37 ,-1._-_ 11- 38 leadership is not to be confused either with tyranny, or des otism, or absolutism in their historical forms. It is obvious, then, that the ideal totalitarian state can be ruled by a single individual. It is also possible, however, that there may be a totalitarian elite composed of a limited number of individuals who Share this power, so long as this elite acts only as a unit. Some form of oligarchy is possible, but only so long as this elite is small enough to operate entirely on the basis of inter—personal and entirely non-formal interaction. The reason for this restriction is plain; should the elite become too large or too formalized it will begin to adopt some meaningful bureaucratic administrative procedures. Thus, once power is institutionalized it must necessarily become fragmentized. Any group, even if it is a segment of the totalitarian elite, will tend to accumulate power and loyalties once it is allowed to become a legitimate institutional organization. Bureaucratization entails Specialization of function (Weber) which in turn encour— ages fragmentation of power. Hannah Arendt writes: A hierarchically organized chain of command means that the commander's power is dependent on the whole hierarchic system in which he operates. Every hier- archy, no matter how authoritarian in its direction, and every chain of command, no matter how arbitrary or dictatorial the content of orders, tends to sta— bilize and would have restricted the total power of the leader of a totalitarian movement. Sabine contends that ". . . bureaucratic qualities, which far more than political liberalism had been principles of \ 39 Cbrman constitutionalism, were in fact destroyed by the rise of national socialism to power."5 What Sabine and Arendt point up is that bureau- cratization, institutionalization, in effect the estab— lishment of any lines of authority and/or the granting of legitimacy to any group is a challenge to the total control of the ruling elite. Why, therefore, should a totalitarian elite court such a threat by establishing rules, lines of authority, differentiated groups, within itself? It can thus be seen that the totalitarian elite (when it is more than a single individual) must be a group small enough to function on the basis of non-formal and totally inter-personal relations. Neumann characterizes this operation as "oligarchic democracy." That is, democracy only within the elite; and he adds, "Brutal and merciless as the lieutenants usually are toward their enemies, strutting like the gods of vengeance, they had better not play the boss within the circle of their 0 6 associates." In conclusion, the totalitarian model is dominated by either a single individual in whom all power resides, or an elite small enough to operate without the necessity of formalized rules. The final characteristic of totalitarian regimes, stemming from its power-seeking, is the tendency to sub— ordinate any and all societal goals to the desire for the total concentration of power in the hands of the elite. ‘ " r-‘r-rmcmi ' I __-Jx=:....-. 40 This characteristic is crucial in differentiating the ideal totalitarian state from other forms of political organization, some of which may possess totalitarian characteristics to one degree or another. A true Communist state, for example, will always strive for the attainment of the final Marxist utopia whereas a totalitarian state which makes use of Marxist ideology will abandon Marxist goals when they become a threat to the power of the ruling elite. Similarly, other societal goals can fall by the wayside when they conflict with the drive for power. In this sense, the totalitarian is strangely like the demo- cratic state, that is, they both place the method of governing (absolute power in one case and self-determina- tion in the other) above any Specific end-point for the society. They are both more concerned with the means than the end, even though their respective means are polar opposites. Thus, the totalitarian regime will not let any goals interfere in its drive for power. Obviously, the elite will not sacrifice power in order to attain goals to which the elite itself is not committed. For example, one finds it hard to imagine the Nazi regime striving for the goal of meaningful mass suffrage at the expense of its own power. There is, however, a more difficult problem. What happens when a totalitarian regime must choose between surrendering power and the attainment of goals to which it is publicly committed? This is a point in dispute 41 among totalitarian analysts. They do agree that the totalitarian state possesses an ideology. The question then becomes: does power seeking take precedence over ideological goals or not? Many theorists contend that the heart of a total- itarian regime is its commitment to an all inclusive ideology. Kohn, for example, writes that "The totalitarian certainty of victory is based on an eschatological cOnfi- dence free from all moral contexts."7 Ernst Nolte contends that, "Every totalitarian dictatorship must be founded on some necessary, incontestable factor which it perhaps merely annexes, perhaps exceeds to a dangerous degree, but which for the time being disarms the objections of its opponents and elicits the approval of the masses." Waldemar Gurian presents the classic example of this posi- tion. He writes: Montesquieu remarks that religion works a check in despotic regimes which do not have any institutional or traditional checks against the arbitrary actions of the despot. An essential feature of totalitarianism consists in the disappearance of this factual, though neither legal nor institutional, limiting power of religious habits and customs. On the contrary, energies and forces which formerly had their outlet and expression in religion, limiting the old despotic ruler, are now driving forces behind and in the new deSpotic regimes of the 20th century. The totalitarian ideologies replace and supersede religion.9 What Gurian is saying is that ideology replaces religion as the check upon the otherwise unchecked regime. Thus, for Gurian, ideology (i.e., ideological goals) takes precedence over the total centralization of power. He goes on to contend that: cm 42 In the pure forms of totalitarianism-—which are not only an expression of methods by which the "new prince" of Machiavelli must operate in the world of the twentieth century--the ideology is the driving force (and not primarily oratory) determining the reality of the movement. The formal structure of the ideology can be filled with various contents and permits great flexibility. But it would be a decisive error to conclude that therefore the ideology—-Marxism and Leninism on the one hand, the racial Weltanschauung of the Fuehrer on the other hand--is unimportant, only a cover—up of a drive for power and control without sense of limits and moderation, as required by existing conditions and power relations.10 Many theorists tend to replace Marxism or Racism with Modernization and Industrialization as the ideological goals of the contemporary totalitarian state. The content of the ideologies varies; what remains throughout is the idea that there is some set of ideological goals which is of greater importance to the regime than the Simple drive for total power. This paper is diametrically Opposed to the contentions of Gurian. It asserts that in the ideal totalitarian state ideology is a Sham, a control device. Furthermore, the totalitarian elite will in every instance abandon an ideological goal if such a goal becomes a threat to the drive for total power. Of course, since no real regime absolutely conforms to the totalitarian model, this will not always be the case in the real world. How- ever, there are numerous historical events supporting this assertion. Joseph Nyomarky, in his discussion of the Nazi state points out the following instances: "Those people who wanted to attach some programmatic content to National ._--_._._..__,_ if! 43 Socialism were called by Hans Frank the 'objectivists' as Opposed to the 'totalitarians' for whom National Socialism' remained an 'infinitely interpretable Weltanschauung,‘ or "11 an 'empty faith' Nyomarky continues: . . . in that year [1934] rose the "Order State," which was more concerned with the solution of existing problems ("the principle of the execution of orders at any price") than with the utopian future. In the years after 1934 it became clear to all willing to see and listen that the Nazi state was not to be a socialist state, nor a state based on traditional ideas of authority, but a state based on the concept of order! Order became sacred regardless of its sub- stance, and loyalty became equated with obedience.12 Nyomarky also discusses the roles of the Sturmabteilung (S.A.--Storm Troopers) and Schutzstaffel (S.S.—-Elite Guard) in the Nazi state. The S.A. made demands upon Hitler in return for its support, and was thus a block to his total control. The S.S., however, was an entirely different type of organization: The S.S. was based on the sanctity Of orders regardless of substance; its code was unconditional obedience. . . . In their oath, S.S. men swore unqualified loyalty to the person of Adolf Hitler. . . . The S.S. was an organization of men who broke with all traditions and who followed their superiors blindly without questions or reservations . . . ; it was the ideal political expression of the Nazi state. The motto of its members, "My honor is my loyalty," revealed the emptiness of their fanaticism and made them ideal mercenaries of the totalitarian leader.13 The same assertion has been made about the Chinese regime by Lucian Pye. He writes, "Now, however, it seems relevant to ask in simple accounting terms whether the Chinese have not been paying an excessively high price Simply for main- taining their political, that is, their control system, and whether control has not increasingly become an end in h.— J. 44 itself and not a means."14 Barrington Moore states the general case: Today the insistent demand for a commitment-- commitment for its own sake--is part of a pervasive totalitarian atmosphere. In my city the trolley cars carry placards urging parents, "Give your child a faith to live by." Apparently any reSpectable faith will do. Its content does not matter.15 Basically, for the totalitarian regime, ideology is a "tool" of control much like a police System or an educational network. The content of the avowed ideology has little relevance to the primary goal of the leadership elite, the centralization of power. It may well be the case, some may suggest, that the ideology represents a set of secondary goals, which may be pursued only when they do not challenge the regime's power. But even this is anathema to the totalitarian elite; for if the elite allows some set Of goals (even secondary ones) to exist legiti- mately they could potentially supply a framework for rea- soning, a yardstick against which to measure the actions of the regime. Therefore the ideology must be kept ever meaningless, ever shifting and changing so that it becomes an instrument for total obedience rather than a set of 3 positive goals. This is the essence of Orwell's "double; think." The world of 1284 is characterized by the lack of a real ideology; in that world "War is Peace, Freedom is Slavery, Ignorance is Strength."16 In The Trial, Kafka's hero obeys seemingly irrational orders, and he obeys them not because of a reasoned commitment to an ideology, but 45 because of a compulsion to obedience that not even he can rationally comprehend. As has been stated earlier, no actual regime can fully satisfy the requirements of the totalitarian model and therefore no real regime has ever totally subjugated every pragmatic and utopian goal to the drive for total power. Perhaps this is why the works of Orwell, Kafka, Huxley, and others touch more closely upon the soul of totalitarianism than do the works of social scientists. In any case, the third basic characteristic of the ideal— type totalitarian regime is its subordination of all goals to the goal of centralization of power. Therefore, the degree to which any actual regime follows this course is an indication of the degree to which it approximates the totalitarian model. This section has been concerned with general characteristics of the totalitarian regime (centralization of power, informal nature of the elite, and subordination of all ideological goals). In the next section, a set of lower-level propositions about the totalitarian model will be presented and discussed. I The discussion thus far has concerned three basic characteristics of the totalitarian model. Based upon these generalizations, several more Specific characteristics of the totalitarian model can be deduced: (l) in order to insure total control, the totalitarian regime will attempt to keep a close and constant 46 surveillance of all activities of each of its citizens; (2) the totalitarian regimes will strive to destroy the autonomy of the individual; (3) the totalitarian regimes will strive to destroy the autOnomy of all intermediate groups in the society. The totalitarian regime can never feel absolutely secure in its desire to attain and retain total power. The mere possibility that somewhere, someone may be escaping the control of the regime is almost neurotically abhorent to the regime. What iS more, the fear of opposition grows rather than diminishes as the regime gains greater power. Most analysts of the totalitarian phenomenon have noted the tendency of such regimes to reach a state of near- paranoia as its real opposition is destroyed and it is faced with the task of finding new enemies. Because the fear of opposition is not terminal with the attainment of stability, the need for a surveillance network lasts for the life of the regime. Of course, the regime desires to observe more than simple opposition. Since the regime seeks to control every aspect of life, it must observe everyone in all activities, in order to be sure that its control does not erode. Thus the need for an elaborate surveillance net— work, penetrating all areas of society. Rather than a Single network, in fact, the totalitarian regime must maintain a set of surveillance networks, each separate from the others. These networks spy not only upon the masses, ~_ra~ now—"ml! . 47 but on each other. The reason for this is plain: a unitary observation network can easily acquire a will of its own and become a rival power center in the society. The networks must be strong enough to perform their func- tions vis-a-vis the masses, yet weak enough to pose a minimal threat to the totalitarian elite. Since an observation or police organization is itself an inter— mediate organization, the means used by the elite to both utilize and control it are the same as the means for uti- lizing and controlling all intermediate organizations. These procedures will be discussed in detail later in this chapter. The point to be made here is that the regime §2§§ maintain such a set of networks, and does strive to be informed about all activities. Ignazio Silone's Bread and Wine portrays this system: It is well known (says Minorca) that the police have their informers in every section of every big factory, in every bank, in every big office. In every block of flats the porter is, by law, a stool pigeon for the police. In every profession, in every club, in every syndicate, the police have their ramifications. Their informers are legion, whether they work for a miserable pittance or whether their only incentive is the hope of advancement in their careers. This state of affairs Spreads suSpicion and distrust throughout all classes of the population. On this degradation of man into a frightened animal, who quivers with fear and hates his neighbor in his fear of discovery, the dictatorship is based. The real organization on which the system in this fountry is based is the secret manipulation of fear. Thus, even in Fascist Italy, generally considered quite far removed from the ideal totalitarian state, the 48 pervasiveness of the watchful eye of the regime was a major factor of the system. Silone's passage also bears upon the second characteristic mentioned above, the totalitarian regime's desire to destroy the autonomy of the individual. As will be seen later, the totalitarian elite seeks to destroy the possibility of an individual relating to a societal group and thus acquiring a different set of perSpectives than those supplied by the elite. Therefore, there are only two sources of direction for the individual left, his own self-reliance and the regime. What the regime desires is the destruction of the individual's self-reliance. Thus stripped of both inner dependency and the support of non- regime controlled social group relationships, the individ— ual becomes totally dependent upon the elite for all direction and purpose in his life. The ideal totalitarian citizen lacks any critical capacities, any self-reliance, any ability to function away from the regime's control. Else Frenkel—Brunswick discusses this psychological attack upon self-reliance: For those who have fallen within the grasp of total- itarianism, rational argument is overshadowed by the image of an all-powerful, superhuman leader whose aura of strength, superiority, and glory afford sur- cease from feelings of isolation, frustration, and helplessness and whose doctrines provide an absolute and all-embracing answer to the conflicts and confusions of life and relief from the burdens of self-determina- tion. These solutions, presented in a dogmatic, apodictic, and Often inarticulate and unintelligible way, are formulated for the explicit purpose of by- passing the process of reasonable consideration and of finding their mark in those emotional and instinctual 49 processes which prompt to precipitant action. Reason, deliberation, and a manysided orientation toward objects, situations, or toward life itself then appear as irrelevant and thus as morbid.18 Thus the totalitarian man is as dependent upon the regime for his mental sustenance as a baby is upon its mother for physical sustenance. The first goal of a regime is there- fore to break the individual loose from his old ties and frameworks for analysis. Moore states, "A totalitarian ‘ movement tries to acquire a considerable mass clientele, eSpecially from individuals turned loose upon the world by 19 the destruction of prior social bonds." Furthermore, as 20 21 22 Hoffer, Ortega y Gasset, and Fromm point out, the masses may not be committed to preserving their individual autonomies. Dostoievsky writes in The Brothers Karamazov, "Man is tormented by no greater anxiety than to find some one quickly to whom he can hand over that gift of freedom with which the ill-fated creature is born."23 And Arthur Schlesinger adds, "Man longs to escape the pressures beat- ing down on his frail individuality; and more and more, the surest means of escape seems to be to surrender that individuality to some massive, external authority."24 Furthermore, Schlesinger realizes how totalitarianism feeds upon this need of some in society to relinquish their autonomy: ". . . the essential dynamism of totalitarianism is toward the unlimited domination and degradation and essential obliteration of the individual; . . ."25 Hans Bucheim agrees that ". . . the totalitarian claim to power, . . , is said to insist on treating peOple like objects, 50 never establishing a relationship with them but eager to rob them of their independence."26 Thus, for those who seek to surrender their indi— viduality, the totalitarian regime fills a need; but the regime itself must seek to destroy the autonomy of all its citizens, not merely those who are in agreement. In a democratic society, persons who seek this type of direction often find it in religion or in some other form of group which does not encompass the entire society. Therefore, those who prize individual autonomy are allowed to, in effect, live their lives outside the system. But the totalitarian state, in its drive for total power, cannot afford such a luxury. William Kornhauser states: The non-elite also needs to form and maintain hyper— attachments to the elite in totalitarian society, for Since people are given no other choice as to objects of attachment, they must find psgghological sustenance in this manner or do without it. John Kautsky adds, "The goal [of a totalitarian regime] is, again, to turn the population from a potential threat to the regime into its pliant tool. The insecure, powerless individual is to be satisfied by having himself and his interests associated with, and indeed submerged in, a large and powerful community."28 What then is this human end product which the totalitarian regime works to produce? What is the "total- itarian man" in his ideal state? Schlesinger states: The totalitarian man denies the testimony of his private nerves and conscience until they wither away before the authority of the Party and of history. He is the man persuaded of the absolute infallibility of 51 the Party's will and judgment, the agent who knows no misgivings and no scruples, the activist who has no hesitation in sacrificing life to history.2 And Adorno presents a classical psychological profile of the totalitarian citizen: Totalitarian society produces a psychological type that is self-alienated, like the mass man, but group- centered, like the tradition—directed person. Total- itarian society engenders this combination by denying any reSpect to the individual and by attaching all meaning to the group (eSpecially the party in conjunc- tion with the state). Possessing no legitimate privacy and few personalized models of conduct, the individual in totalitarian society sheds an unwanted sense of individuality and submits psychologically as well as behaviorally to the group. He does not regard himself as distinct from the group. Since the group is dom— inated by an elite possessed of a monopoly of power, submersion in the group entails submission to the elite. Extreme submission to the elite and extreme hostility toward outsiders are characteristics of the Totalitarian man.30 Finally, Szamuely casts light upon the totalitarian man in his commentary upon the Soviet Union (whether or not his comments are actually true in the case of the Soviet Union, they are relevant to the totalitarian model): Indeed, Lewis Carroll is an invaluable guide on a Sovietological expedition: a journey to a land where, for instance, a memory that only works back— ward is regarded as a pretty poor memory, and where most people have acquired the practice necessary to believe as many as Six impossible things before breakfast.31 Thus the totalitarian man is self-alienated, insecure, lacks self-confidence; in short, his only source of mental strength is the regime. Of course, the goal of the regime is to Spread this state of dependency to all its citizens, no one must even consider opposing the directions of the elite. Furthermore, simple obedience is not enough. 52 Acquiesence is a characteristic of the authoritarian and not the totalitarian regime. The regime demands whole- hearted and enthusiastic support from its citizens because grudging obedience indicates that the individual has suf— ficient internal resources to arrive at a conclusion not identical with the regime's. If an individual can reach independent conclusions, even though he does not act upon them, it indicates that the control and power of the regime is not total. John Weiss states, "Totalitarian dictator- ships must manufacture approval, not merely outlaw dis- approval."32 Szamuely illustrates the difference between autocratic obedience and totalitarian support in his description of one aSpect of de—Stalinization in the Soviet Union: In other words, the striking difference between the present-day USSR and Stalin's Russia is that today if one keeps one's nose clean and one's mouth shut and does nothing then one is guaranteed (barring a genuine misunderstanding) not to go to gaol--whereas under Stalin millions of people were sent to slave labour camps literally for "doing nothing."33 Finally, Deutsch quips that "In a democracy, . . . , everything that is not forbidden is permitted; under an authoritarian regime, everything that is not permitted is forbidden; under totalitarianism, everything that is not forbidden is compulsory."34 The totalitarian regime is not willing to accept the grudging obedience of its citizens. It strives for the active enthusiasm of each individual in every venture. Simply accepting the dictates of the state may indicate 53 that the individual believes that he himself "knows better" but can do nothing about it. This potential willingness to rely upon one's own judgment is a threat to the total authority of the elite. Thus, the ideal total- itarian citizen is an individual who makes no decisions for himself, but supports every elite decision as if it were his own fondest wish. The third and final characteristic to be discussed is the desire of the totalitarian regime to destroy the autonomy of all intermediate groups in the society. Korn- hauser supplies an excellent description of what consti- tutes an intermediate group. He states: We can conceive of all but the simplest societies as comprising three levels of social relations. The first level consists of highly personal or primary relations, notably the family. The third level con— tains relations inclusive of the whole population, notably the state. The second level comprises all intermediate relations, notably the local community, voluntary association, and occupational group. These intermediate relations function as links between the individual and his primary relations, on the one hand, and the state and othernational relations, on the other hand. It muSt be emphasized that voluntary associations are not the only kind of intermediate relation; all organized relations that mediate between the family and the nation, such as local government and the local press, are classified as intermediate structures in the present study.35 For the purposes of this paper, Kornhauser's conception of intermediate structures will be extended. Specifically, an intermediate structure or group is any structure or group that stands between the isolated individual and the totalitarian elite. Governmental units (even the state structure), voluntary associations, family units, and even 54 the totalitarian party itself are intermediate structures. In fact, any association of humans, except for the total— itarian elite, is an intermediate group. The reader may be taken aback by such an inclusive definition, and may well wonder how a model totalitarian system can operate without these organizations. First, one must consider the totalitarian leader(s) (one may assume that a Single dictator presides over the system, but the case holds just as well for an elite such as was described earlier). The citizen would receive all inputs from the leader and direct all outputs to the leader. Physical isolation of the individual would be unnecessary; he would simply not be cognizant of other humans around him. The leader would experience no difficulty in issuing directives to all the citizens; modern mass media can cope with that task. The problem is one of surveillance and decision making. How can the leader monitor the activities of all the citizens, learn of the objective needs of the system, or be sure that his orders are followed? What this system calls for is some sort of gigantic input-communica- tions net. A super-computerized system which can collect and collate all incoming information and process it in accordance with the wishes of the leader without either burdening him with masses of details or adding any judg- mental factor of its own. This is the ideal totalitarian state, each individual tied completely and exclusively to the leader. 55 Of course, the whole idea is a bit farfetched given the present level of technology, and some may suggest it is more political science—fiction than political science. Perhaps it is, but imagine a person attempting to explain the modern state and its reliance upon mass communications to an eighteenth-century audience. Pictures that float invisibly through the air would seem a bit Speculative to a citizen of that era. Technology has a habit of over- taking speculation. But if one leaves the world of speculation and returns to the present technological age, a different situa- tion awaits him. Given the present level of technology, no leader or elite can possibly keep tabs on an entire society. Thus, unfortunately for the totalitarians, intermediate groups are necessary evils. They are necessary for surveil- lance, passing information up to the elite, and handling countless decision-making tasks too menial to warrant the attention of the elite. But they are evil because each one is a potential rival for power in the totalitarian system. This is the dilemma of the modern totalitarian state. To meet this dilemma the totalitarian state has devised a set of means to aid in utilizing these intermediate groups while minimizing their threat to the system. The desire of the totalitarian regime to destroy the autonomy of intermediate organizations is a common fea— ture of almost all conceptualizations of the totalitarian model. Friedrich and Brzezinski discuss the various 56 "islands of separateness (family, church, university, and military)" with which totalitarian regimes must cope.36 They then conclude that "the dictatorship seeks to divide and rule in the most radical and extreme way: each human being Should, for best effects, have to face the monolith that is the totalitarian rule as an isolated 'atom'."37 In Specific reference to Germany, Walsh states: "The Church [in Nazi Germany] was an obstacle in the way of totalitarianism; hence it had to go. Total power cannot tolerate divided allegiance."38 Sabine also discusses the totalitarian need to subjugate or destroy intermediate groups in Germany: Except by permission of government there could be neither political parties, labor unions, industrial or trade associations. Except under its direction there could be neither publication nor public meeting. Education became its tool and in principle religion was also, . . . Leisure and recreation became agen- cies of propaganda and regimentation. No area of privacy remained that an individual could call his own and no association of individuals which was not subject to political control. . . .39 Sabine then continues: Totalitarianism undertook to organize and direct every phase of economic and social life to the exclusion of any area of permitted privacy or voluntary choice. But it is important to observe What this type of orga- nization concretely meant. First and foremost it meant the destruction of great numbers of organizations that had long existed and that had provided agencies for economic and social activities. Labor unions, trade and commercial and industrial associations, fraternal organizations for social purposes or for adult educa- tion or mutual aid, which had existed on a voluntary basis and were self-governing, were either wiped out or were taken over and restaffed. Membership became virtually or actually compulsory, officers were selected according to the "leadership principle," and their procedures were decided not by the membership 40 but by the outside power that the leader represented. 57 Thus the totalitarians begin their rule by destroying or capturing old forms of intermediate organization. This attitude of totalitarianism does not end with the seizure of power, however; the regime is constantly obsessed with these groups. Weber states: "If the community is an organic whole, deviations are corrupting and cannot be tolerated. All must act as one, shunning dissensions as intrinsically harmful, seeking a unity which alone can "41 Intermediate save in the providential person of one man. groups are potential Spawning grounds for just such dis- sensions. Alex Inkeles goes so far as to suggest that the preeminent goal of the totalitarian regime is not to sub— ordinate the individual per se, but to subordinate the human associations of a society.42 He states: . . . totalitarianism, in contrast to liberalism and pluralism, leaps over the individual to give full recognition and weight to the role of social institu- tions in the structure and functioning of society. It recognizes that one of the important aspects of social organization in the large-scale society is that the individual is related to the total social system primarily through the institutional networks in which he is enmeshed and it has therefore given Special and primary emphasis to the subordination of the traditional human associations, the organizations and institutions, of which the individual is a member. This becomes the chief tool for its ultimate subordination of the indi- vidual to the state. Totalitarianism recognizes that so long as certain of its crucial membership units are not themselves subordinated to the demands of the central authority, the individual himself may to that degree be immune to full subordination.43 John Kautsky also recognizes the vital need to control intermediate organizations. He states that "The new organizations, all run by the regime, thus become organs of supervision."44 The regime in fact encourages the 58 individual to participate in these controlled organiza— tions in order to keep him "out of trouble." This, of course, relates to a point made earlier; the totalitarian regime cannot accept grudging obedience; the citizen must actively demonstrate his support. These organizations become the channels through which such activity is directed. Barker similarly recognizes this use of organizations. He writes: The absolute on which it [a totalitarian government] is based must be carried into every domain of life-- the social no less than the political: religion, education, economics, the methods of sport and the uses of leisure, as well as politics proper. Any form of group for any activity is a potential rival; it is a possible magnet of loyalty, which, however insignificant it may seem in comparison with the great loadstone, may none the less succeed in deflecting the quivering point of allegiance. From early life, the individual must be taught to point true: he will be enlisted early in the Octobrists or the Balilla or the Hitler Youth: his games, his holidays, the very life of his family, will be drawn into the field of the party the party-State, the leader, the ultimate absolute.45 Several societies have attempted to construct the type of organizational system outlined above. John Weiss discusses the Italian experience: The Italian Fascists created a vast network of ideological and paramilitary leisure-time organiza- tions, including the famous Depolavaro (after-work) paralleling the Nazi Strength Through Joy. Only so could they frustrate the development of spontaneous cultural and leisure activities. Such activities would, if allowed to arise freely, express the inde— pendent and hence dangerous varieties of individual, group, or class experience. Normally, each group or sub-group in society can draw upon its own social or work experience as a model from which to judge and accept or reject what it is told or taught by outsiders.46 59 The same holds true for the Nazi regime. Neumann describes the Situation of non-central governments: The totalitarian theory was also the instrument for cO-ordinating all public activities. Absolute con- trol from the top--the famous Gleichschaltung (syn— chronization) of federal, state, provincial, and municipal activities--was justified in the doctrine of the state's total right and total power. In con- trast to the pluralistic and federalistic Weimar Republic, the new state could not and would not brook the efi%stence of autonomous public bodies within it; Kornhauser writes, in relation to the Soviet Union, that: The intermediate structure of a totalitarian society, on the other hand, helps to prevent access to the elite by virtue of its domination by the elite. By means of intermediate groups instituted and controlled from above, the totalitarian regime is able to keep the population in a state of mobilization. Such orga- nizations as Soviet trade unions have the primary function of activiating and channelizing the energies of workers in directions determined by the regime. If there were no controlled intermediate organizations in all Spheres of society, people would be free to re— group along lines independent of the regime. That is why it is of the utmost importance to totalitarian regimes to keep the population active in these con- trolled groups. Totalitarian regimes search out all independent forms of organizations in order to trans- form them or destroy them. In certain other societies, the natural decline of independent forms of associa- tion prepares the way for the rise of totalitarian movements. The preceding discussion has attempted to high- light the role of the intermediate organization in a totalitarian state. That is, it is necessary as a tool for the control of society but it is dangerous as a potential opponent of the totalitarian elite. Ionescu puts it directly: In an ideal Apparat, or for that matter_totalitarian state, the function of all these bodies {intermediate groups] is that of "transmission belts" and of agencies of state-control. But then it can be said that the 60 history of any "ideal" Apparat or totalitarian state is precisely the history of the failure of the central "monolithic" power to prevent institutional checks from being reformed.49 This is the basic dilemma of totalitarian states: how to use intermediate groups but yet retain complete control over them. It is the contention of this paper that the total— itarian state has an arsenal of weapons to use in order to try and alleviate this dilemma, Since by its very nature it cannot be completely solved. These procedures or weapons for both utilization and control are the tests by comparison to which this paper hopes to gain some insight into the usefulness of the totalitarian model for studying Communist China. They are, furthermore, the least general of the propositions thus far presented and are therefore the most useful measures against which the behavior of a regime can be empirically tested (although the reader must keep in mind that they are but a Single set of totalitarian characteristics and there are many other sets which deal with different relations.and activities of the totalitarian regime). These procedures of the totalitarian regime for dealing with intermediate structures are presented below. A. Upon gaining control, the totalitarian elite will: 1. Destroy the old-style intermediate organizations which cannot be utilized by the regime; 2. Infiltrate and control the old-style intermediate organizations which are of some use to the regime; 61 3. Create a new set of organizations which are totally thecmeatures of the totalitarian elite. The totalitarian elite will attempt to prevent orga- nizations from becoming identified with specific interests in the society and thus being a potential focus for individuals who share that interest. The elite will do this by: 1. Attempting to prevent institutionalization. Huntington defines institutionalization as, ". . . the process by which organizations and procedures acquire value and stability."50 He goes on to state that the level of institution- alization is defined by the adaptability, com- plexity, autonomy, and coherence of an organiza- tion.51 The totalitarian regime attempts to minimize the level of all four of the above mea— sures by constantly keeping organizations in a state of flux; that is, organizations will be created and destroyed rapidly because the longer an organization exists the more likely it becomes that members of the organization will develop a vested interest in it; therefore, the life expec— tancy of an organization will be very brief as compared to that of another society; 2. Attempting to separate leadership from expertise in intermediate organizations--1eadership will be vested in persons politically loyal to the regime 62 rather than persons who possess the necessary expertise to run the organization or who represent an area of knowledge which that organization was created to Speak for (in China, of course, this is subsumed under the "red-expert" controversy). The totalitarian regime will seek to keep organizations weak and insecure by maintaining confused lines of authority: 1. Various organizations will all be charged with the same area of operation and thus the organizations will act as a check upon each other (this is, in effect, a totalitarian twist to the Madisonian argument of Federalist #10. That is, since groups cannot be abolished, they should be diverse enough to check one another); The regime will periodically and arbitrarily Shift the locus of activity and/or authority from one organization to another in order to prevent any one organization from acquiring a sense of legitimacy born of past performance, in the eyes of the citizens; also, it helps perpetuate the totali- tarian atmosphere by denying to citizens sure knowledge of where authority lies, thus helping to keep the citizen in a perpetual state of flux and insecurity as well as adding to his general feeling of helplessness; 63 3. The regime will constantly set up a gallery of figureheads--this will serve many of the same purposes as (2) above, but also the figureheads are available as scapegoatsfor the failures of the regime, thus preserving the "infallibility" of the elite; these figureheads are usually placed in positions of prominence in intermediate orga- nizations, often as a direct prelude to their disgrace. D. The regime will try to base organizations on a fictional Shared interest rather than a real one. Thus, Sports and leisure clubs are fabricated to replace real orga- nizations. Mass groups based on characteristics such as "motherhood" are encouraged as replacements for organizations which are centered about an actual and immediate felt need of its members. This lessens the attachment which the member will build for the group. This section has attempted to analyze the dilemma of totalitarian regimes in their relations with interme— diate groups (i.e., utilization vs. control). It has further presented a set of propositions outlining the pro— cedures which the totalitarian regime uses in order to ease this dilemma. Now the research will focus upon a set of intermediate groups in Communist China vis—a-vis their adherence to these procedures and by doing so hopefully will help determine the usefulness of the totalitarian model for understanding Chinese activities. NOTES CHAPTER II 1Robert Daniels, The Nature of Communism (New York: Vintage Books, 1962), p. 305. 2Carl Friedrich and Zbigniew Brzezinski, Total- itarian Dictatorship and Autocracy (New York: Praeger, 1956)} p. 23. 31bid., p. 26. 4Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Meridian Books, 1958), pp. 364-365. 5George Sabine, A History of Political Theory, 3rd ed. (New York: Holt, Rinehart, & Winston, 1937), p. 917. 6Friedrich and Brzezinski, p. 20. 7Hans Kohn, Political Ideologies of the Twentieth Century (New York: Harper TOrchbookS, 1966), p. 57. 8Ernst Nolte, Three Faces of Fascism, trans. R. Piper & CO. (New York: Holt, Rinehart, & Winston, 1963), p. 222. 9Waldemar Gurian, "Totalitarianism as political Religion," in Carl Friedrich, Totalitarianism (New York: Grosset & Dunlap, 1954), p. 122. 101bid., p. 125. 11Joseph Nyomarkay, Charisma and Factionalism in the Nazi Party (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1967), p. 38n. 121bid., p. 52. 13Ibid., p. 140. 14Lucian Pye, The Spirit of Chinese Politics (Cambridge, Mass.: The M.I.T. Press, 1968), p. 237. 15Barrington Moore, Jr., Political Power and Social Theory (New York: Harper & Row, 1958), p. 195. 16George Orwell, 1984 (New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World, 1949), p. 17. 64 65 17Friedrich and Brzezinski, p. 147. 18Else Frenkel-Brunswick, "Psychological Aspects of Totalitarianism," in Friedrich, Totalitarianism, p. 172. 19Moore, p. 26. 20Eric Hoffer, The True Believer (New York: Harper & Row, 1951). 21Jose Ortega y Gasset, The Revolt of the Masses (New York: W. W. Norton & Co., 1932). 22Eric Fromm, Escape from Freedom (New York: Holt, Rinehart, & Winston, 1941). 23F. Dostoievsky, The Brothers Karamazov, Book V, Chapter 5. 24Arthur Schlesinger, The Vital Center (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1949), p. 53. 25Ibid., p. 87. 26Hans Buchheim, Totalitarian Rule: Its Nature and Characteristics, trans. Ruth Hein (Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1968), p. 16. 27William Kornhauser, The Politics of Mass Society (New York: Free Press, 1959), p. 62. 28John Kautsky, Political Change in Underdeveloped Countries (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1962), p. 95. 29Sch1esinger, p. 56. 30Kornhauser, p. 111. 31Tibor Szamuely, "Five Years After Khrushchev," in Survey, No. 72 (Summer 1969), p. 59. 32John Weiss, The Fascist Tradition (New York: Harper & Row, 1967), p. 96. 33Szamuely, pp. 57—58. 34Karl Deutsch, "Cracks in the Monolith: Possi— bilities and Patterns of Disintegration in Totalitarian Systems," in Friedrich, Totalitarianism, p. 309. 35Kornhauser, p. 74. 36Friedrich and Brzezinski, pp. 239-280. 66 37121g., p. 281. 38Edmund Walsh, Total Power (New York: Doubleday, 1948), p. 100. 39Sabine, p. 916. 49121g., pp. 918-919. 41Eugen Weber, Varieties of Fascism (New York: van Nostrand, 1964), p. 36. 42Alex Inkeles, "The Totalitarian Mystique: Some Impressions of the Dynamics of Totalitarian Society," in LFriedrich, Totalitarianism, p. 90. 43Ibid., p. 90. 44Kautsky, p. 94. 45Ernest Barker, Reflections on Government (London: Oxford University Press, 1942), p. T66. 46Weiss, p. 98. 47Franz Neumann, Behemoth (New York: Harper & Row, 1966), p. 51. 48Kornhauser, pp. 82-83. 49Ghita Ionescu, The Politics of the European EEEEEEBJnist States (New York: Praeger, 1967), p. 166. S SOSamuel Huntington, Political Order in Changing _£!E£E13313§ (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1968), p. 12. 51See Huntington, p. 12., for a complete discussion. CHAPTER III MINOR PARTIES In Chapter II it was stated that an intermediate group was one which existed in the area between the isolated individual and the ruling elite. In China this includes the state apparatus, the army, voluntary associations, family, the party itself, etc. It is obviously beyond the Scope of this research to investigate all of the above forms of intermediate-organization. Therefore, this work Will focus upon only a Specific subset of these intermedi- ate organizations, consisting of three separate types. The first two of these three types of organizations are "ha-1: Townsend refers to as "secondary associations." They constitute ". . . the secondary association which is orga- Iii-Zed, at least theoretically, on the basis of the common interests, occupations, or class viewpoints of its members. with no significant exceptions, these organizations are national associations with branches at various local levels and operate again theoretically, on the principle of VOIUntary membership."1 The types of secondary associa— tions to be examined are the democratic (or minor) parties and the mass organizations. The third type of group to be 67 68 examined in this work is the mass campaign, which is an extremely ephemeral form of mass organization. There are several reasons for choosing these three types of groups. First, most of these organizations are outside what is commonly considered, in Western govern— mental systems, the political or governmental Sphere of activity. The minor parties, which would play a political role in a democratic state, play a non-political role in China. These groups are referred to as minor parties or democratic parties. They are, in fact, neither parties, in the Western sense, nor democratic. However, they theoretically represent the continuation of pre-Communist political parties and are also theoretically part of a United Front Government with the Communist Party. The Communist regime itself invariably refers to them as minor or democratic parties and the author feels it unwise to create new terminology for these groups since such ter— minology would only confuse the reader as to the object of references. Furthermore, this chapter will make amply clear the "true" nature of these groups. Therefore, the regime's behavior towards these groups illustrates the Spread of elite activity, in a totalitarian state, beyond the limits of normal political or governmental roles. It illustrates the extension of the elite's desire for control over all areas of human activity. Because these groups are, in this sense, far removed from the regime, an analysis 69 of them should demonstrate most clearly the operation of those characteristics presented at the end of Chapter II. These three types of groups can, in effect, be arranged along a continuum of totalitarianism. That is, the groups can be rank ordered so that each group more closely conforms to the totalitarian demands than the preceding group. The analysis begins with the democratic, or minor, parties which existed in China from the inception of the regime (or earlier) until the onset of the Cultural Revo- lution. There were eight democratic parties which, along with the Communist Party itself, formed the United Front which was the "official" governmental ruling coalition from 1949 until the Cultural Revolution. The majority of these parties pre—dated the Communist takeover and thus had an existence independent of the ruling elite.2 Many of the parties represented entrenched and vested interests. Because these parties represented interests which were independent of the regime, it was necessary for the regime to remold the organizations so that they would no longer be representative of special groups, but rather would be channels for control of these groups. That is, they would be a tool for the elite's domination of that segment of society which they supposedly represented. It is primarily because the parties represented "real" interests and had power bases which pre-dated the regime (thus they could be viewed by some as legitimate 70 sources of authority, independent of the ruling elite) that they, of all the groups being considered here, were furthest removed from the ideal totalitarian intermediate organization. Chapter IV will discuss how the minor parties were successively co-opted, dominated, totally controlled, and finally discarded by the ruling elite of China. The second type of organization which will be discussed in this work is the mass organization. These organizations are closer than the minor parties to the type of intermediate organization preferred by a total- itarian regime because they are creatures of the ruling elite. Specifically, they were constructed by the regime to serve its ends and thus have a lesser claim to legiti- macy as an actual representative group than do the minor parties. Furthermore, the mass organizations themselves can be broken down into two major types: (1) those organizations which ostensibly represent some real and immediate interest of a group of persons in the society (e.g., one of the trade unions); (2) those organizations which represent a Sham interest because the bases upon which they are organized are either (a) too broad to include immediate interests (e.g., the Women's Federation of the People's Republic of China), or (b) the bases are totally fictional and created by the regime (e.g., the Chinese People's Association for Cultural Relations with Foreign Countries)- 71 These organizations all served the regime as channels of communication, information, and control. FUrthermore, as Chapter IV will indicate, they were more "totalitarian" in their nature than the minor parties because they were more diffuse in their interests, more the creatures of the regime, and more transient. At the time ofthe initiation of the cultural revolution there were 120 mass organizations and minor parties in Communist China.3 Table 2 divides these orga— nizations along the lines outlined above. TABLE 2 MINOR PARTIES AND MASS ORGANIZATIONS Minor Parties China Assn. for Promoting Democracy China Democratic National Construction Assn. Chinese Peasant's and Worker's Democratic Party Revolutionary Committee of the Kuomintang Taiwan Democratic Self-Government League China Democratic League China Chih Kung Tang Chiu San Society Mass Organizations "Real" Basis All-China Federation of Handicraft Cooperatives All-China Federation of Literary and Art Circles, includes: Union of Chinese Artists Union of Chinese Cinema Workers Union of Chinese Drama Workers Union of Chinese Musicians Union of Chinese Photographers Union of Chinese Writers Union of Chinese Chuyi Artists China Dancing Research Assn. 72 TABLE 2 (cont'd.) All-China Federation of Supply and Marketing COOperativeS All-China Federation of Trade Unions, includes: China Agricultural and Forestry Workers' Trade Union China China China China China Coal Miners' Trade Union Construction Workers' Trade Union Education Workers' Trade Union Engineering Workers' Trade Union Financial and Commercial Workers' Trade Union China China China China China Geology Workers' Trade Union Heavy Industry Workers' Trade Union Light Industry Workers' Trade Union Petroleum Workers' Trade Union Postal and Telecommunications Workers' Trade Union China China China China Workers' All-China China Scientific and Technical Assn., China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China Railway Workers' Trade Union Seamen's Trade Union Textile Industry Workers' Trade Union Water Conservation and Electric Power Trade Union Journalists Assn. includes: Aeronautical Engineering Society Agricultural Mechanization Society Agronomy Society Anatomy Society Animal Husbandry and Veterinary Society Anti-Tuberculosis Society Architectural Society Astronomy Society Automation Society Bacteriology Society Botany Society Chemistry and Chemical Engineering Society Civil Engineering Society Crop Research Society Dynamics Society Electronics Society Entomology Society Forestry Society Geodesy and Cartography Society Geography Society Geology Society Geophysics Society Horticulture Society Hydraulic Engineering Society Mathematics Society Mechanical Engineering Society 73 TABLE 2 (cont'd.) China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China China Medical Society Metallurgy Society Meteorology Society Nursing Society Oceanography Society Paleontology Society Pedology Society Pharmacy Society Physics Society Physiology Society Plant Pathology Society Shipbuilding Engineering Society Silicate Society Textile Engineering Society Water Conservation Society Zoology Society China Welfare Institute for the Blind and Deaf Mute National Red Cross Society of China Political Science and Law Assn. Religious Organizations, "Broad" of China includes: Chinese Buddhist Assn. Chinese Catholic Patriotic Assn. Chinese Islamic Assn. Chinese Taoist Assn. National Committee of Protestant Churches in China for Realization of Self-Administration Based All-China All-China All-China All-China All-China China Philosophy Society China Welfare Institute Chinese People's National Committee in Defense of Children Chinese People's Relief Assn. Women's Federation of the People's Republic of China "Sham" Basis Athletic Federation Federation of Industry and Commerce Returned Overseas Chinese Assn. Students' Federation Youth Federation Afro-Asian Solidarity Committee of China China Asia-Africa Society China Committee for the Promotion of Inter- national Trade China Welfare Institute Chinese People's Assn. for Cultural Relations with Foreign Countries 74 TABLE 2 (cont'd.) Chinese People's Committee for World Peace Chinese People's Institute of Foreign Affairs Friendship Assns., includes: China-Albania China-Africa China—Bulgaria China-Burma China-Cambodia China-Ceylon China-Cuba China-Czechoslovakia China-Germany China—Hungary China-India China—Indonesia China-Iraq China-Japan China—Korea China-Latin America China-Mongolia China-Nepal China-Pakistan China-Rumania China-United Arab Republic China-Vietnam Sino—Soviet For complete, but undifferentiated, listing, see Vincent King, "Propaganda Campaigns in Communist China," M.I.T. Center for International Studies Monograph, January 1966, Appendix. The third type of intermediate organization which will be discussed is the mass campaign. These campaigns have been a feature of Chinese politics throughout the Communist period. They have, however, become more refined as time passed. Similarly, as the techniques of utilizing the mass campaign developed, the regime began to rely more heavily upon them, generally as a replacement for other forms of intermediate organization. 75 The mass campaigns have several features which make them singularly desirable for a totalitarian regime. First, they lack a strict and formalized hierarchy, thus discouraging the entrenchment of power. Second, they are extremely transitory. Therefore, they do not have the ability to acquire a sense of legitimacy, in perhaps a Burkian manner, in the eyes of the public. Furthermore, the campaigning flits from topic to topic at a moment's notice, thus decreasing the citizen's sense of security and his ability to build a stable set of priorities, upon which he can make rational decisions outside the framework of regime control. In effect, the use of the mass campaign in China comes the closest to any actual regime's utiliza- tion of an intermediate group in an advanced totalitarian fashion. Chapter V will focus upon the role of the mass campaign in China. The minor parties, the mass organizations, and the mass campaigns all are vital (or were vital) in the Chinese governmental framework. Each represents a type of orga- nization which is distinct in its relation to a totalitarian regime. The following three chapters will be devoted to studying these three types of groups and evaluating their positions vis-a-vis the Chinese ruling elite. Not only will each be evaluated in terms of its own relationship to the totalitarian principles outlined earlier, but arguments will be put forward to support the contention that they may be rank ordered in terms of their approximation to the 76 ideal totalitarian intermediate organization (culminating, theoretically, in the elimination of all such groups what- soever). Also, evidence will be presented to indicate that the Chinese regime has been moving, over time, to replace "less totalitarian" groups with "more totalitarian" groups. The Cultural Revolution is a watershed event in this movement and will be examined as such. Of course, the intermediate groups mentioned above were not the only ones subjected to elite controls during the 1949-1965 period. The governmental bureaucratic system underwent drastic revision after 1949. In the Party's control of the bureaucracy one can see the use of many control devices applied in other areas. Barnett discusses several of the control devices used for the purpose of guiding the bureaucracy: (l) The Party hierarchy itself has functional units parallel to the government, almost a "shadow govern- ment." These units exert leadership over their coun- terparts in the bureaucracy; (2) Party members almost monopolize key leadership posts at all levels of bureaucracy. Furthermore, they are subject to Party orders as well as governmental directions; (3) All major central governmental bodies have "Party Fractions." That is, the high ranking Party members- bureaucrats comprise a clique which is responsible for assuring that Party directives are implemented; 77 (4) Party branches and committees exist within all levels of the bureaucracy; (5) Party directed intermediate mass organizations (Young Communist League, Labor Union, and Women's Association) serve as "transmission belts" and monitoring agencies for non-Party workers at all levels of the bureaucracy; (6) The use of political study sessions which all workers attend. These meetings present the Party line to non- members and also provide group criticism and self- criticism for non-Party workers who are not performing adequately.4 Many of the above techniques will appear again as they operate vis-a-vis the other intermediate organizations. The Army was also subjected to reorganizations, and control 5 and devices were installed in it. Alexander George Samuel Griffith6 discuss these devices and the subsequent conflicts which arose in the army between the forces of professionalism and those of control. Similarly, the Cul- tural Revolution was, at least in part, directed against entrenched interests in the Party itself, and was an attempt by the totalitarian elite to reimpose controls over some organization (the Party) which had become a viable separate power-base. The Bureaucracy, the Army, and the Party were traditionally the three major control organizations in Communist China and they were all subject to intermediate group controls. However, it is far beyond the scope of 78 this research to discuss at length the development of each. Therefore, although all of these organizations are related to the research, this paper will focus upon the three types of intermediate organizations mentioned at the outset: minor parties, mass organizations, and mass cam- paigns. By studying these groups one can discover rela- tionships to the elite which will be of benefit in studying the Party, Army, and Bureaucracy. Finally, it is necessary to discuss the types of evidence to be utilized in this investigation. AS noted earlier, reliable quantitative data about the functions of the Chinese system are all but impossible to obtain. There are two basic types of evidence that will be used in this research. First, the pronouncements of the Chinese government itself may be examined for clues to activities within the regime. The American Consulate General in Hong Kong publishes a Survey of the China Mainland Press five times weekly, as well as Extracts from China Mainland Magazines at irregular intervals. Various other govern- mental agencies also publish translations of Chinese documents.7 Also, the Chinese regime itself puts out foreign language material, such as the Peking Review. Analyses of these types of materials must be somewhat cautious. The regime (and sometimes the American trans- lators) have their own axes to grind. Furthermore, the regime writes in a jargon all its own and one cannot always take things at face value. Also, the Chinese system is so 79 large and often diverse that sometimes the provincial organs lag behind the central regime in their pronounce- ments. This is an especially important consideration since much of the information passed to the West comes through Hong Kong and is overly influenced by the nature of the southern provinces. Whenever such material is used, the circumstances surrounding its release will be kept in mind by the author. Another source of evidence, especially important to this type of study, is secondary sources. This paper is not an attempt to conduct an overall investigation of the Chinese system. It is concerned with relating the operations of a small part of that system to a theoretical model. Thus the opinions and evaluations of individuals who are primarily committed to studying the Chinese system are to be weighed heavily. Also, the preponderance of useful material on China is in the form of reportage. Out- siders' eyewitness accounts of the system in operation can be extremely valuable. In conclusion it is necessary to emphasize three points. First, it is the relevance of the model and not the model itself that is being examined. Second, only a Specific subset of intermediate organizations in China will be discussed. Third, the evidence to be used is often fragmentary because of the nature of the Chinese regime. With these points in mind, one can proceed with the actual investigation. 80 The first section of the research will deal with the role of the minor parties, as intermediate organizations, in Communist China. As indicated in the preceding section, the Chinese elite has progressed from the utilization of "less" totalitarian organizations to the reliance upon organizations which more closely conform to the dictates of a totalitarian regime. The minor parties, in this con- text, represent a starting point from which to begin the analysis. That is, they represented, at the time of the Communist takeover, the greatest acceptable locus of power outside of the regime itself. AS stated earlier, they were founded and initially organized by persons outside the elite. It will be demonstrated that the objective skills and talents which these persons possessed were necessary for the operation of the regime and thus they had to be utilized while at the same time these persons could not be allowed to build a separate power base. As stated in Chapter II, the intermediate organization in a totalitarian state is a necessary evil. It is necessary for the opera- tion of the state at this stage of technology, and yet it inherently possesses the potentiality for the proliferation of power, the greatest threat to the regime itself. The Chinese regime, in order to cope with this problem, utilized some of the control devices outlined at the conclusion of Chapter II. Specifically, they infiltrated the leadership of these organizations, they attempted to keep the parties insecure by Shifting and confusing their respective roles 81 in the society, they severely regulated the membership policies of the parties, and they generally maintained an atmOSphere of unease within the minor parties. In Short, rather than serving as representatives of the societal groups which they ostensibly represented, the minor parties served, as is necessary in a totalitarian regime, as con- trol devices through which the ruling elite could monitor and direct the activities of certain elements of the society while at the same time preventing these elements from collecting the means to function as a legitimate power base. The analysis will be broken into time periods which correspond to qualitatively different historical epochs. The first period (1949—1955) was the period during which the Communist regime most critically felt the need for the services of the members of these minor parties and thus encouraged their existence and relative stability. The second period (1956) was that of the "Hundred Flowers" campaign, during which the restrictions were eased and the active and unencumbered support of the members sought. The third period (1957) witnessed the severe rectification campaign which, as theoretically postulated in this paper, demonstrated the inability of a totalitarian regime to tolerate a proliferation of power. The fourth period (1958-1965) was one in which the role of the parties was "normalized." That is, the controls placed upon them were tightened while utilization of their members was increased. 82 In this period they moved in the direction of becoming more the creatures of the totalitarian state. The final period commenced with the Cultural Revolution and will be discussed in a separate section. This period can be dis— tinguished not by the role that the parties played, but rather by the fact that they passed Silently from scene, with hardly a bit of debris. Significantly, this period marks the replacement of the minor parties with other forms of intermediate organization more suitable to a totalitar— ian regime. The Early Period: 1949-1955 Between 1949 and 1964 China was theoretically governed by a coalition of parties consisting of the Com- munist Party and eight democratic parties. These demo- cratic parties were by no means "mass" organizations, as the membership figureslmesented in this chapter will indi- cate, but were, in effect, representative groups for cer- tain non-revolutionary elements in Chinese society. Even the most naive of political observers could not mistake the utterly subservient role which these parties played. Thomas states, "In contrast [to the CPC] . . . , the other parties associated with the Peking regime are none of them mass parties, nor do they control any of the real sources of power in China today."8 Before embarking upon a discussion of the develop- ment of these organizations, it is perhaps advisable briefly to acquaint the reader with each of the eight 83 democratic parties. The most important of the parties was the China Democratic League. This party represented mainly cultural and educational elements, primarily the bourgeoise intellectuals. The Kuomintang Revolutionary Committee was composed largely of disaffected KMT Party members and was a vehicle of the Communist Party in attempts at converting Nationalist Chinese both on the mainland and on Taiwan. The China Democratic National Construction Association was representative of the "national bourgeoisie" and was an instrument of the CPC in the socialization of industry and commerce. The China Association for the Pro— motion of Democracy was the organization of teachers, editors, publishers, and cultural workers in general. The China Peasants' and Workers' Democratic Party was not at all representative of peasants and workers. Rather, it was composed largely of persons in the medical and public health fields. The China Chih Kung Party was organized Specifically to enlist the aid of overseas Chinese in the development, primarily economic, of the mainland. The Chiu San Society was composed of scientists and scientific workers. Finally, the Taiwan Democratic Self-Government League was a group which was dedicated to convincing the native Taiwanese to support the CPC and oppose the Nationalists.9 Although there were a few other minor democratic parties during the very earliest years of the Communist regime, they were soon disbanded or amalgamated into one 84 of the above eight parties. It is the nature of these democratic parties and their changing roles in the "United Front" government which will be discussed in this section. Origins of the Democratic Parties Most of the democratic parties were initially organized during, or immediately following, the conflict with Japan in the 1930—40's. For example, the China Demo- cratic League (CDL) was founded after the New Fourth Inci— dent of 1941.10 It was originally named the League of Democratic Political Groups (or Federation of Chinese Democratic Parties, depending upon translation) and was, in fact, an amalgamation of several separate political organizations, including: (1) Comrades Association for National Unification and Construction (founded in January 1940), (2) National Salvation Association, (3) Third Party, (4) All-China Professional Educational Society, (5) Rural Construction Group, (6) Northeast Revolutionary Comrades Association, (7) National Socialist Party (orga- nized by Chang Chun-mai in 1931),11 and the Youth Party.12 Its leader and organizer was Chang Lan, President of Chengtu University.13 In 1944, it was more tightly orga— nized and renamed the China Democratic League. Of its early role, Thomas states, "Representative chiefly of liberal and leftist intellectuals and other middle-class elements, it had attempted to function as a 'third force' between the Kuomintang and the Communist Party, and had 85 called for a coalition government and for political and economic reforms."14 With the outbreak of civil war in 1946, the CDL moved further to the left. The more right-wing elements of the party separated themselves, the Youth Party break— ing away in October 1945, and the National Socialist Party leaving in early 1947. Finally, in October-November 1947, the CDL was officially outlawed by the Kuomintang for allegedly being an accessory to "bandits." The official Nationalist history states, "The China Democratic League . . . composed mostly of petty—bourgeoise intelligensia who, dissatisfied with the Nationalist rule and instigated by the Communists, secretly collaborated with the Communist Party and did whatever possible to weaken the prestige of the National government."15 The CDL, now led by Chang Lan, Lo Lung—chi, and Shen Chun—ju was reorganized in Hong Kong and became publicly avowed supporters of the Communist Party. With the victory of the Communists on the mainland, the CDL was invited to participate in a new "United Front" government. The Kuomintang Revolutionary Committee was organized in January of 1948 in Hong Kong by Marshal Li Chi—Shan and Feng Yu-hsiang. Closely allied to this party were the Kuomintang Association for Promoting Democracy and San Min 16 This group consisted of Chu I Comrades Association. critics of the KMT leadership who had been expelled from the party. The KRC was later to serve as an organizing 86 "magnet" for remnants of the KMT who chose not to flee the mainland following the Communist victory. The other democratic parties had either also been organized during the anti-Japanese period (except for the Chih Kung Party, which dates back to the nineteenth century), or were quickly "discovered" by the CPC upon its assumption of power. When the Communists took over the government they were already somewhat committed to a United Front Policy. This had been their slogan for over a decade "in the course of their criticism of the one-party government of the Kuomintang, and it had a powerful emotional appeal in Chinese politics."17 This is not to suggest, however, that the CPC did not wish to construct a united front government for such was definitely not the case. The CPC had many valid reasons for desiring the assistance, voluntary or otherwise, of the democratic parties, and these reasons can be uncovered by examining the roles and duties of the democratic parties during this early era. The Roles of the Democratic Parties: 1949-1955 During the period from 1949 to 1955, the democratic parties in China were used by the CPC for three major pur- poses: (l) to obtain support for the CPC from elements of society which would not usually be considered sympathetic to communist goals, (2) to "control" certain elements of society which might be dangerous to the regime, and (3) to 87 utilize bourgeois and white-collar, bureaucratic elements without contaminating the Communist Party by offering them membership, especially in the caSe of government employ- ment. Of course, the third CPC desire was probably the origin of the "red and expert" controversies which were to trouble the regime for many years. However, this problem lies beyond the scope of this work. Suffice it to say that the possibility of such a conflict either did not occur to the Chinese, or the costs of the conflict were insufficient to outweigh the advantages to be gained by the Party from making use of the democratic parties in this manner. As stated above, the CPC used the democratic parties as a means of obtaining support from nonrevolutionary ele- ments of the society. Thomas states: . . in the early stages of political and economic stabilization, calling as it did for the broadest possible collaboration of the former Nationalist governmental bureaucracy, and the co-operation of business and intellectual elements generally, a government containing these middle parties could more readily attract and reassure, as well as give a sense of participation in the government, to such groups, than could a purely Communist regime.18 Barnett comments upon this Communist ability to enliSt the support of these parties, and consequently of the social elements which supported the parties, "The members of these groups are given an Opportunity to participate in political affairs, and although they have little authority or power, the mere fact that they are put on 88 committees and called upon for consultation makes many of them feel they are playing an important political role."19 Clubb also notes this role of the democratic parties and he asserts that "the democratic parties are to assist the CCP line, educating and guiding the people the way the CCP wants them to go, mobilizing their enthusiasms and energies for the work of 'socialist construction.'"20 Of course, in order to use these parties as bases for support, the CPC had to be sure of its control over the parties. Aside from the obvious and heavy-handed physical controls available, the CPC depended mainly upon control by means of introducing its own members into the democratic parties' organizations. The China Peasants' and Workers' Democratic Party, in demonstrating its loyalty to the Communist leadership of the United Front, requested, "An appropriate number of Chinese Communist Party members and New China Youth League members . . . should be won over to our party in order to strengthen the leadership of our party."21 During the 1949-1955 period, the CPC encouraged the democratic parties to expand (although the CPC Speci- fied from which elements of society each party could draw its new members) while it increased its control over the parties. In doing so, the CPC built "organized support and Share reSponsibility for implementing its current program on a broadened basis, at the same time reserving to itself a decisive policy-making role-—a combination 89 which cannot help but be a source of great strength to the regime."22 The second function which the democratic parties performed for the CPC during the early period of Communist rule was that of utilizing the services of the bourgeoisie and the ex-Kuomintang bureaucrats, without allowing them to join and somehow "contaminate" the CPC itself. In 1950 the Party was attempting to purify its membership and "proletarianize" itself. However, it still needed the c00peration of the bourgeoisie if it desired to retain any "new democratic" features, such as limited private enter- prise. Therefore, instead of incorporating these persons into the Party, the CPC preferred to work through the democratic parties. In 1951 The Economist reported that the Communists "need to retain and consolidate the support they had during the civil war from these classes, who were inSpired by disgust at Kuomintang corruption and fiscal incompetence and also by nationalist motiveS-—but they do not want them in large numbers inside the Communist party."23 The third duty of the middle parties during this period was to serve as a controlling device for elements of society which had the ppssibility of becoming trouble- some to the regime. Once again, the Communists were unwilling to incorporate them into the Party itself and they therefore made use of the middle parties as super- vising agents. Clubb states that the minor parties were 90 "something in the nature of isolation wards for leading members of different social groups who, deemed unsuitable for CCP membership because they might infect that pure organization, nevertheless could not safely be left to go their own way Since they might provide focuses for trouble— some dissent."24 The "Hundred Flowers" Period: 1956 In 1956 the CPC launched a campaign to permit, and even encourage, all elements of Chinese society to submit constructive criticism of the regime. Boorman writes: "An interlude of liberalisation in ideological controls came during the 'hundred flowers' campaign launched in mid-1956 with the explicit aim of giving intellectuals and 'cultural workers' a greater sense of participation in the tasks of 'Socialist construction' and of leavening the literary scene with the fresh forms of expression."25 In the realm of political affairs, the democratic parties became a rallying point for anti-administration commentary. Lo Lung-chi, vice chairman of the China Demo- cratic League, came forth very early in the movement and questioned the good faith of the CPC. Lo proposed the formation of a United Front organization to "inSpect excesses during . . . past [anti-rightist] movements; this was to provide a guarantee that people who dared to 'bloom' and 'contend' would not be subjected to attack and retali- "26 ation. It will later be evident that Lo's questioning of the government's intentions was extremely insightful. 91 However, Lo continued to criticize the CPC during the period, in Spite of any doubts he might have entertained. Lo questioned the role of the democratic parties in the CPC dominated governmental framework. He acknowledged that these parties had participated in government work, but he stated: "How to make their positions real, and not merely nominal, is a question. What embarrasses the democratic parties and groups most is the lack of informa— tion required for the study of policies." He continues: At the Standing Committee of the National People's Congress and the Chinese People's Political Consulta— tive Conference, the democratic parties and groups cannot voice any effective Opinion on matters under discussion because they are not informed in advance of the matters to be discussed, and at the moment of discussion they have no time to study them. This is a problem of making the democratic parties and groups really, and not only nominally, consultant.27 Another middle party figure, Yen HSin—min, also criticized the CPC and complained that "the democratic parties today still do not possess the material basis for equality (with the CPC); all they have is political and legal equality, 28 Franklin which is not genuine and actual equality." Houn, in an analysis of this period, states that much of the minor party criticism was directed at the aloofness of the Communist bureaucracy; and the criticism seemed to "reflect a sense of frustration, on the part of the former leadership group, over their exclusion from the conduct of public affairs."29 Of course, the minor parties were not the only centers of governmental criticism; student groups, 92 scientific, literary, and academic elements also voiced their often extreme displeasure with certain aspects of the CPC. The Party was taken aback by the volume and vehemence of the criticism, and the CPC leadership decided to "clamp the lid down" on the non—revolutionary elements and therefore launched a major rectification campaign. An important factor of the "hundred flowers" period is that during this time, the democratic parties, and eSpecially the CDL, attempted to act as true intermediate organizations by articulating the demands of the societal groups which they represented. Their failure to perform this function for an extended period illustrates the inability of a totalitarian regime to allow multiple centers of power, no matter how weak, to arise. The Rectification Campaign: 1957 In 1957 the CPC launched a major rectification campaign aimed at suppressing the critics who had come forth during the "hundred flowers" period. A great portion of this campaign was directed at the democratic parties, who were viewed as a major source of support for the anti— regime critics. In 1957 Teng Hsiao-p'ing delivered a "Report on the Rectification Campaign" to a session of the eighth Central Committee in which he stated: The rightists in the various democratic parties and groups functioned as the core of the rightist attacks, because the people have granted them a certain polit- ical status and they could make use of their legal positions to issue orders and enlist followers. The democratic parties are the product of the period of 93 democratic revolution and although a number of their members have moved to the left during the socialist revolution, most of them have not yet changed their bourgeoise standpoint for that of the proletariat. Therefore, the rightists at one time got the upper hand in many organizations of the democratic parties.30 A pro-Nationalist publication, discussing the attack of the CPC upon the parties and rightists, states: "Wild animals can become dangerous as they did in 1957; the bulk of those who were then branded rightists came from the ranks of the minor parties. They were buffeted, kicked at, and beaten down, and when tamed put back again in the show to give better performances than ever."31 Even putting the colorful rhetoric aside, it is fairly obvious that the CPC was committed to new measures designed to provide further control, and to provide retribution, over the democratic parties. The CPC moved in three areas to achieve these goals. First, they moved against individuals in the middle parties who had voiced criticism of the regime. Second, they took measures concerning the organi- zation of the parties designed to prevent any increase of political power on the part of the parties. Third, they instituted a "self-rectification" campaign which was designed to force the parties to purge themselves of right- ist elements. The CPC first attacked individual members of the democratic parties who had been outspoken in their criti- cisms of the regime. A number of minor party leaders were accused of being rightists and were subjected to psycho- logical pressure which served to produce "confessions" of 94 guilt. Three of the leading figures who were singled out for retribution were Lo Lung-chi, vice-chairman of the CDL and Minister of the Timber Industry; Chang Po-chun, vice-chairman of the CDL (of which there were five), and Minister of Communications; and Chang Nai-chi. These men were deprived of their party offices and, by a cabinet re-organization approved by the People's Congress in 1958, they were removed from their government positions. Hsieh Hsueh-hung, who was chairman of the Taiwan Democratic Self-Government League,was deprived of her post and expelled from the Communist Party. In 1958 twenty demo- cratic party "rightists" were suspended from the Chinese PeOple's Consultative Conference and fifty were suspended f.32 In removing from the National People's Congress itsel these leaders, the CPC felt that "these men, who were all leaders in their reSpective parties, had evidently permitted or even encouraged their members to raise heretical ques- tions concerning such matters as the need for the Communist Party dictatorship, the amount of compensation to industri- alists whose property had been expropriated, and the posi- tion of the democratic parties."33 Lo Lung-chi, who ironically had earlier been con- cerned with the prevention of retribution on the part of the CPC, and Chang Po-chun were eSpecially made into targets by the CPC. The "Chang—Lo" conSpiracy became the major CPC excuse for the avalanche of political criticism in 1956. Lo was shown the error of his ways and he subsequently 95 confessed to almost every crime but the great train robbery which, fortunately for him, had not yet occurred. He con- fessed to having attempted to separate the intellectuals from the CPC and lure them into the CDL. "There was, he said, within the League an 'invisible organization' of people who had undergone American or British education, an organization which had been crushed in 1952 and revived in 1957."34 In a public confession by Lo, he stated: . . . as a vice-Chairman of the China Democratic League, I had for over a year endeavored, in collab- oration with Chang Po-chun, to divert the League to the rightist course, depriving it of its role as assistant to the Party and throwing into confusion backward members of the League in the face of rampant attacks by rightist elements. This was unfavorable to the Party's leadership and the socialist cause. Lo and Chang presented a number of these public confessions, as did almost all the accused rightists. It is entirely possible that these men felt that they had indeed been rightists and had led the mass of the membership astray. Whether the confessions were genuine, or were dictated by expediency, the CPC succeeded in discrediting the leader— ship of the democratic parties and, having done so, were in a position to move against the organizations themselves. Rectification of the Democratic Party Organizations The middle parties had been encouraged to expand during the 1949—1955 era, and by 1957 the eight parties 36 had a combined membership of 110,000, of whom 30,000 37 belonged to the China Democratic League. The CPC took several steps to weaken the parties and prevent any 96 possible future increase in political strength. First, the parties were reorganized at all levels. Second, all rightists or suSpected rightists were replaced with left— ists. Third, previously abandoned restrictions on the parties were restored, and the parties were forced to expel all members who had joined during the period when these restrictions had not been enforced. Fourth, all membership expansion was specifically prohibited.38 The CPC was now in firm control of the democratic parties and they made use of this control to launch a major effort to reform the membership of the parties. The parties were required to abandon their bourgeois attitudes and move with new deter- mination in acquiring a socialistic outlook. The CPC desired that this change in attitude be a result of efforts on the part of the parties themselves, and so the "self- rectification" campaign was launched. Self-Rectification in the Democratic Parties The Chinese Democratic League launched this cam- paign with a statement recognizing the need for reform within the party. Part of the statement announced: After the rectification campaign of the Chinese Com- munist Party began, a group of anti-socialist right- ists, under the pretext of airing views, spoke various sorts of things against the Communist Party and socialism in an attempt to sabotage the socialist enterprises and destroy the people's democratic dictatorship and the unity between the party and the people, hoping to drag the wheel of history backward. What is even more striking and astonishing is that, among our democratic parties, and particularly among the leading personnel and members of our own League, there have been discovered some rightist anti—Communist and anti-socialist erroneous speeches.39 97 The CPC was quick to emphasize the importance of self rectification as a cure to the self—diagnosed illness indicated above. On September 17, 1957, Li Wei-han, Director of the Department of the United Front Work of the Chinese Communist Party, delivered a Speech at a gathering of representatives of the minor parties and the All-China Federation of Industry and Commerce. He said that the "minor parties and groups in China were still bourgeoisie in character, in spite of the elimination of their orig- inal economic base that resulted from the socialist trans— formation of industry, commerce, and agriculture in 1955 and 1956. They must therefore effect a self-transforma- tion in order to become a political force truly dedicated to socialism."40 An official self-reform campaign was initiated by the middle parties in February of 1958. "The China Democratic National Construction Association, com- posed mostly of industrialists and businessmen, even Specified a time-limit of three years."41 A joint rally of over 10,000 prominent minor party members and indepen- dents was held on March 16, 1958, at T'ien-an Square and was presided over by Shen Chun—ju, the 85-year-old Chairman of the CDL. At this rally a "Charter for the Socialist Re-Education of Democratic Parties and Non-Party Democrats" was adopted.42 This charter proclaimed the goals of the democratic parties to be: (1) to reform their political standpoint in order to more devotedly strive for socialism under the leadership of the CPC; (2) to be loyal to 98 the socialist system, "faithfully carrying out the state's policies and laws and wholeheartedly contributing our knowledge and strength to the nation's construction. .";43 (3) to learn from the workers and peasants, "through practical work, establishing a proper attitude toward physical labor and actively developing the doctrine and sentiments of the working people; . . .";44 (4) to study Marxism-Leninism and the examples of the Soviet Union; (5) "to carry through the policy of letting one hundred flowers bloom, one hundred schools of thought con- tend; . . ."45 (6) to provide re—education so that long- term coexistence and mutual supervision are possible; and (7) to "firmly . . . carry out the United Front policy in the service of socialism."46 The minor parties held another rally on April 10th which, as Tang states, demon- strated "the public capitulation of the minor parties and groups to the Communist demand for thorough self-transfor- mation. . . ."47 This rally launched a "dedication of hearts to the Party" movement. Wu Han (who was in the center of the Cultural Revolution and was purged due to it), Director of the Peking Municipal Committee of the CDL, stated that the major goal of the bourgeoisie was "to faithfully surrender their hearts to the Communist party and the people."48 This "dedication of hearts" was pursued throughout the country and was the cause of a great many self-enlightenment meetings, at which the bourgeois ele- ments attempted to criticize each other and develop a 99 socialist outlook. These meetings became known as "meetings of immortals" and were still being held as late as 1961.49 By means of these three measures, the CPC succeeded in disciplining the democratic parties and cutting off the flow of criticism. Tang speculates that the CPC may have used this campaign, . . more as an object-lesson than as a real drive to enforce conformity, even though the conversion of such groups is one of their avowed goals. They may not have had too much faith in the new pledges of loyalty, but they accepted the outward submission as a suitable compromise for the time being. Presumably, after the letting off of steam in the "contending and blooming" period, the lid was now firmly back on.50 The attempt of the democratic parties to act as non— totalitarian organizations was firmly suppressed by the CPC. After this initial outburst of CPC control and retri— bution, a gradual return to "normalized" roles for the democratic parties took place. The return of the demo— cratic parties to their normal role in the government during the 1958-1964 period, which included their role in the "Great Leap Forward," is the topic of the following section. Normalization of the Democratic Parties: 1958-1965 In late 1957 the CPC began to ease the pressure on the middle parties. The Party had successfully squelched the outright criticism on the part of these groups and was now satisfied to allow these parties to resume their earlier 100 roles. The China News Analysis, although it is hardly an unbiased observer and must be considered with this in mind, stated: "In 1957-58 one would have thought that the recal— citrant satellite parties would have been wiped out of existence. On the contrary, Peking, in its typical dia- lectical way, promotes and expands them. The CPPCC serves for a close checking on the middle class."51 One suspects that the regime was more motivated by a desire to return the middle parties to their proven useful roles than by a desire to be dialectical. But for the CPC, power-seeking had replaced avowed ideology. The important factor, how- ever, is that the CPC chose to attempt to stabilize its relationship with the democratic parties rather than obliterate them. Evidence of the CPC'S lessening of pres- sure was contained in a "Report on Government Work" given by Chou En—lai in 1959 to the National People's Congress. He stated at that time: Through study work and partici ation in manual labor, many of them [the minor parties have made varying degrees of progress. Except for a handful of right- ists, most of those democratic party members and other democrats who take part in state work have fulfilled their duties at their posts. During the rectification campaign, the democratic parties tidied up their orga- nizations. They still play a positive role in rally- ing the various social forces to serve socialism. In the future, it is still necessary in our country to continue to consolidate and develop the people's democratic united front on the basis of serving socialism. Under the premise of accepting the leading position of the Communist Party, long—term co—existence and mutual supervision between the Communist Party and the various democratic parties and groups is still beneficial to the people's cause.52 101 The willingness of the CPC to reinstate the minor parties into its favor can be seen in the membership figures. In 53 or 1961 there were 100,000 members of the minor parties, only 10,000 fewer members than immediately before the rectification campaign, when the parties were at the peak of their importance. Thus, by 1959, the minor parties had resumed a role in Chinese government and the "anti-rightist" campaigns were toned down. This is not to say, however, that all CPC rectification activity ceased. As late as 1963 Chang Nai-chi, who was at that time (1) Minister of Food in the State Council, (2) Vice-Chairman Of the China Democratic National Construction Association, (3) Vice- Chairman of the All-China Federation of Industry and Com- merce, (4) a member of the Standing Committee of the Chinese People's Political Consultative Conference, and (5) a member of the National People's Congress, was purged and had to undergo rectification for alleged rightist inclinations.54 Chang, however, was more an isolated example than evidence of a general trend. From 1959 to 1964 the CPC was willing, and almost eager, to use demo- cratic party members in governmental roles. Democratic Party Members in Governmental Positions During this period, members of the minor parties held some Significant governmental positions. Direction of the entire United Front Operation was supplied by the United Front Department, headed by Li Wei-han. This department was a section under the Central Committee of 102 the Communist Party. Below this department was the Chinese People's Political Consultative Conference, chaired by Chou En-lai. This organization included members from all the middle parties and "from all those in the middle-class who count."55 In the area of government operations, the minor parties were also represented. In 1959, 14 of 49 ministries of the central government were headed by members of the minor parties.56 These ministries were often the more Specialized ministries, usually subsidiary to the planning industries; and they included such ministries as the timber industry, posts and telegraphs, justice, food industry, light industry, textiles, forestry, communications, marine products, and city services.57 Members of the democratic parties also held numerous lesser posts throughout the government. These government Officials were usually chosen for their technical Skills and not for any policy-making abilities. "They hold these posts at the pleasure of the Party, for whose policies they act as administrators."58 Thus, the CPC utilized the Skills of the middle party members while preventing any rightist tendencies from entering the government. Of course, no administrator is absolutely objective, and the biases of the administrators must have at least implicitly slipped into their work; however, this was kept at an absolute minimum by the Party cadres, who permeated the government. 103 The Role of the Democratic Parties During the 1959-1964 period the democratic parties revived their duties of the pre-"hundred flowers" era and even expanded their sphere of operations, under proper CPC supervision of course. In 1963 the role of the democratic parties was described: To insure national survival, the co—operation of the educated middle class, particularly of the leading scientists, is sought today. At the same time the Party endeavors to keep them safely under its thumb, hammering into their ears incessantly the Marxist truth. This ambivalence, a very important feature today when something must be done to revive the half- paralysed national economy, is seen in this issue under a different aSpect, the middle—class tempered in organizations adapted to this double purpose.59 In order to perform their duties, the democratic parties operated under the direction of the CPPCC, described above. The CPPCC during this period had 1,086 local branches and conducted 430 political schools which pre— sented political courses to over 140,000 persons.60 The most outstanding of the schools constructed to educate the bourgeoisie was the Central College of Socialism. For example, of the 285 students enrolled there in 1961, there was one president of an institution of higher learning, 33 professors, 16 members of the Academy Of Science, 36 engineers, 5 doctors, 11 literary figures, 18 members of national minorities, 3 religious leaders, 5 overseas Chinese, and a number of teachers.61 Actually, the CPPCC performed two major tasks. First, it "controlled" the parties. Che'n Shu-t'ing stated in 1963 that the purpose 104 of the CPPCC was "to unite the democratic parties and all other people under the leadership of the communist party and Chairman Mao, and to see that these people in the CPPCC undertake political study and self-reform."62 Second, the CPPCC provided propaganda for communist activity abroad. "The international friend, often a sym- pathizer but not a communist, is impressed by the broad spirit of tolerance he imagines he finds in Peking when it honours non-communists."63 Under the direction of the CPPCC, the democratic parties have been called upon to define their goals and duties. From December 1962 to January 1963, all eight parties held national conventions to settle upon their proper tasks. As a result of these meetings, they decided upon the following goals: (1) "To continue to uphold the three red banners of the socialist general line, great leap forward, and people's communes; to contribute more to socialist reconstruction, to the campaign for austerity and increased production, and to the development of science, culture and education; and to work for a bumper harvest in agriculture and new triumphs of socialism."64 (2) "To support wholeheartedly the general line of foreign policy and to participate without reserve in the struggle against imperialists, reactionaries, modern revisionists and for world peace."65 (3) "To study diligently Marxism-Leninism and Mao Tse—tung's 105 works; to undergo ideological education in patriotism, internationalism and socialism; and to push ideological reform of party members and the masses."66 Aside from these general goals, each of the demo- cratic parties was assigned Specific tasks. The China Democratic National Construction Association, in conjunc— tion with the Federation of Industry and Commerce, was given the task of helping to improve "the managerial system and supply to the market, and in general in the readjust- ment of the national economy."67 The party of the intel- lectuals, the China Democratic League, the Association for Promoting Democracy, and the Chui San Society, along with the Chinese Peasants' and Workers' Democratic Party, were given the task of adjusting scientific techniques for the aid of agriculture. Several of the parties were asked to ‘work on industrial and technical questions. In Taiwan, Inembers of the CPPCC were instructed to contact 210 "upper- <31ass" people in order "to explain to them the policy of ‘the Party and of the government and to solicit their co-