STRATEGIES UNDER NON-TRANSFERABLE uTILIm ; g AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF THE EEEEOTSOF : - DIVISIBILITY OF 'PAYOFF, COGNITIVE COMPLEXITY. AND MACHIAVELLIANJSM 0N STRATEGY SELECTION IN A MIXED MOTIVE GAME ’ ’ Thesis for the Degree of Ph. ‘D. MIOIIIOAN STATE UNIVERSITY LAWRENCE H. NITZ' 1959. ‘5' _.fl.... TI." .___ 5 LED 1: AK) Michigan State University ‘fld This is to certify that the thesis entitled Strategies Under Non-Transferable Utility: An EXperimental Study of the Effects of Divisibility of Payoff, COgnitive Complexity, and Hachiavellianism on Strategy Selection in a Mixed Motive Game presented by Lawrence H. Nitz has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for Ph.D. Political Science degree in T” a r flfiM/K '74 .441.qu ( Major professor Date Hay 11+, 1969 0-169 ABSTRACT STRATEGIES UNDER NON-TRANSFERABLE UTILITY: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF THE EFFECTS OF DIVISIBILITY OF PAYOFF, COGNITIVE COMPLEXITY, AND MACHIAVELLIANISM ON STRATEGY SELECTION IN A MIXED MOTIVE GAME Game-theoretic treatments of political decision processes typically assume that the payoff of a decision is homogeneous and infinitely divisible. This assumption permits the transfer of goods to which the analytical concept "utility" may be applied. This study explores stra- tegies that may be selected in a mixeddmotive situation constructed with either easily divisible payoffs or relatively indivisible payoffs. Recent studies of strategy selection (e.g., Riker, 1967) have con- tended that personality or individual differences do not have a significant effect on processes relevant to political strategy selection. A more general question, however, has been raised (Greenstein, 1967); Under what conditions do individual differences account for political behavior? The mixeddmotive situation used in this study systematically controls conditions in which differential strategy patterns might be predicted from individual difference measures of attitudes or skills supposedly related to strategic behavior. Studies by Cole (1969), Phillips and Nitz (1968) and Nitz and Phillips (submitted for publication, Journal of Conflict Resolution) indicate that the probability of executing a strategy choice and the ease of divisibility of the payoff elicit differential strategies in mixed—motive situations. In this study a mixeddmotive coalition game known as the "political con- vention paradigm" presented subjects with a finite set of strategy options as they played the roles of faction leaders in two mock political party conventions. Each subject played the role of a faction leader faced with one opponent who could muster an equal number of convention votes and one opponent who could control a greater number of votes. The subject also played the role of a "stronger" contender in a game with two large, equal factions and one small faction. Four explicit strategies were defined on the basis of the subject's joint choices in the two types of games and the divisibility of payoff: Maximization, Competition, Security and Intra- coalition Compatibility. The following hypotheses were examined: 1. Subjects seek to maximize their share of the payoff with respect to their coalition partners, regardless of the probability of winning or the ease of divisibility of the payoff. 2. Subjects seek to form coalitions in which the division of the payoff can be negotiated with a minimum of intracoalition friction. When the payoff is only unequally divisible, the probability of choosing the unequal contender is higher than when the payoff is easily divisible. When the payoff is easily divisible, no intracoalition incompatibility is en- gendered in a coalition between unequals, so the maximization decision rule is used. 3. Subjects seek to form.coalitions that will allow maximum grounds for conflicts, that is, coalitions for which the payoff structure of the game suggest no obvious division of the payoff. 4. When the payoff to a coalition can be obtained only with some probability less than unity, subjects will seek to maximize their chances of winning by forming the largest coalition possible. Twenty-seven triads of male college students were run in each of three experimental payoff conditions: easily divisible-certain (Here the payoff was 100 patronage positions at a mid-term party convention); indivisible- certain (The payoff was nomination for either the governorship or lieutenant governorship in a one-party state); and indivisible-uncertain (Nomination for governorship or lieutenant governorship in a two—party state). Hypothesis 1, Maximization, and 2, Intracoalition Compatibility were con- firmed, substantiating the initial findings of Phillips and Nitz (1968) and Nitz and Phillips (submitted for publication) that indivisibility of payoff tends to elicit strategies that seek to reduce conflict over pay- off division. Harvey's (1961) conceptual systems theory defines four rank-ordered modes of processing information that would be expected to affect decision- making behavior. Persons with the more cognitively complex information processing skills would be expected to reject irrelevant social cues and select more task-related maximization strategies than persons with less cognitively complex information processing patterns. Tuckman's (1964) Interpersonal Topical Inventory was used to identify subjects in each complexity level. A factorial partition of contingency tables was used to analyze the effect of complexity differences on strategy selection. The hypothesis relating complexity level to strategy selection was dis- confirmed. The most complex and the third-most complex of the four groups, however, performed according to the prediction for the more complex per- sons. The second—most complex and the least complex groups selected strategies predicted for the less complex subjects. Moreover of the most and third-most complex groups of subjects, those who picked Maximization strategies perceived their opponents as likely to demand less than half of the payoff. Revisions of conceptual systems theory were suggested. Christie's (1962) Machiavellian is expected to select strategies that maximize either payoff (regardless of conditions) or conflict. No strategy choices could be predicted with the dichotomous classes of subject scoring above and below the median Mach V score. A post-hoe discriminant function analysis, however, was able to discriminate Maximization from Competition, Security and Compatibility; Security from Compatibility; but was not able to discriminate Compatibility from either Competition or Security. The extremely strong degree of association of the predicted by observed con- tingency tables for strategies (X2 = 73.09) as well as the discrimination 9df among strategies with only four Mach V items in the discriminant function equations (X2 = 27.86; .005 > p > .001) indicates that the Mach items can 9df effectively predict strategy selection in an abstract game, but not if they are taken as an additive scale. The high level of discrimination obtained among the discrete abstract strategies defined across different payoff conditions in the political convention game suggested that it may be inappropriate to assume that any particular attitude scale should pre- dict political behavior across situations. This study suggested that it may be fruitful to examine those skills that permit a political actor to select strategies appropriate to the particular situation; i.e., that per- mit discrimination among strategic situations. STRATEGIES UNDER NON-TRANSFERABLE UTILITY: AN EXPERIMENTAL STUDY OF THE EFFECTS OF DIVISIBILITY 0F PAYOFF, COGNITIVE COMPLEXITY, AND MACHIAVELLIANISM 0N STRATEGY SELECTION IN A.MIXED MOTIVE GAME by 3(VQ ‘ I Lawrence H. Nitz A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Political Science 1969 A C KNOWIE DC E ME NTS I wish to thank my dissertation committee members, Professors Rufus Browning and James Phillips and my Chairman, Frank Pinner for the patient guidance and thoughtful criticism they have prQVided throughout this study. I thank Frank particularly for proviuing the initial intellectual stimulus that led me first to lose myself in experimental and social psychology for two years, and then to find my way hack to essential issues in modern political theory. During my tenure as a graduate student he served far beyond my highest role expectations of a doctoral program chairmen. In studying social psychology 1 incurred other debts that I wiSh someday to be able to repay. Professor Donald Johnson helped me develop an appreciation for significant problem areas in the study of human cogni- tion; Professor Eugene Jacobson labored to convey to me an appreciation of thoroughness in the study of human organization. Professor Frank Marzocco helped eliminate the less elegant segments of earlier proposals. To my fellow colleagues at MSU's Human Learning Research Institute, particularly Steven Cole, Charles Kenoyer, and David Kline, I owe much of whatever skill in the study of human behavior I have acquired. The in- formal discussions I have had with them have helped me clarify my ideas. I wish to acknowledge the support of the Human Learning Research Institute throughout this project. Professors Frank Marzocco, former Director, and Ted Ward, current Director of the Institute have consist- ently supplied not only the facilities and services of the Institute, but also thoughtful advice and administrative support, without which this study could not have been done. Computer time has been generously applied by tlu:lNJlitical Sciewuleyepartment of lmnftnul the Computer Laboratory of the University of Hawaii. I have already thanked those graduate students and faculty members who Supplied subjects for the eXperiments in this study. I wish to thank thcse who have taken on the tethnical tasks of this study. Each of them has ptrformed with thoroughly professional compe— tence. Clinton Tarkoe was responsible for assembling t perimental materials and coding finished questionnaires. Mrs. Cecelia Highstreet typed the experimental materials and the Sinai manuscript--much of it from hand- writing no one should have to rtad. Duane Lawton was kind enough to put his computer program into working order well ahead of schedule so that I could complete the contingency table analyses. Steve Cole supervised production of the final copies of the dissertation. James Phillips, for intellectual stimulation, insistent attempts to force me to concentrate m' labors on rohlems that were both significant 3 P s 5' -4 C. ¥~ , C- H r-Q and manageable, cogent criticism (even when want it), and open 1 friendship, I hold responsible for much of m} prOgress toward completion of the Ph.D. Finally, this work could not have been begun without twenty-odd years of support and guidance from my parents, Mr. and Mrs. harvey Nitz. It could not have been completed in the short year it took without the con- sistent support, encouragement and sexiness of my wife, Kiyoko Kurusu Nitz. iii LIST OF LIST OF LIST OF CHAPTER TABLE OF COLTENIS FIGURES. TABLES APPENDICES Introduction The Identification of Social Contact Strategies in the Political Convention Paradigm. III Situation Structure, Cognitive Complexity, and Machiavellianism as Determinants of Strategy Selection IV. Objectives and Procedure V. Results and Discussion VI. Summary and Implications BIBLIOGRAPHY APPENDICES . iv Page vi viii 12 40 57 67 96 105 109 Figure 2.1 3.1 4.2 4.3 4.4 LIST OF FIGLRES Minimum resource predictions in Gamson's second con- veI‘lt ion. 0 O O O O O O 0 O O O O O O O O I O O O O 0 Joint choices in Type 2 and 3 triads . . . . . . . . Theoretical strategies by divisibility condition . . Experimental payoff conditions . . . . . . . . . . . Type 2 resource distribution . . . . . . . . . . . . Type 3 resource distributions. . . . . . . . . . . . Counterbalance of labels and resource values . . . . Page 19 41 43 58 64 65 65 Table 2.1 5.4 5.5 5.6 5.7 5.8 5.9 5.10 5.11 5.12 LIST OF TABLES Probability of choosing the smaller contender as a function of resource distribution and divisibility of payoff. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Tests of the difference between p(W)EXperiment I and p(w?Experiment 11 for the Type 2 Resource Distri- bution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Strategy selected as a function oi group and payoff Condition. C U C C I O C I C O O C C 0 O C O O O O . p(W) with 951 confidence intervals by payoff condi- tion, experiment and type oi triad . . . . . . . . . p(W) ’ > 3 - p(W)m, . 0 by experiment and payoff condligbn. . . . 1y?c.h. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . LP(W)Type 3 ‘ P(W)Type 21 Condition 1 ' 1P(W)Type 3 'P(w)Type 2] Condition 111 by experiment . . . . . . Strategy choice by perception in the Type 2 conven- tion by cognitive complexity . . . . . . . . . . . . Strategy choice by perception in the Type 3 conven- tion by cognitive complexity . . . . . . . . . . . . Strategy choice by perception in the Type 3 conven- tion by cognitive complexity categories I + 111 v. II + IV. C O O 0 O O O O O O O O O O O O O I O O I I Frequency of marginal strategy choices for four cognitive complexity categories. . . . . . . . . . . Strategy choice by cognitive complexity and Machia- vellianism Scores. 0 C I 0 I 0 O I O C I I O O l O O Marginal strategy choices by Machiavellianism score group. O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O I O O O O O O 0 Means and standard deviations of Mach V item scores for each strategy type . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Linear function discriminating four strategy types on the basis of 20 Mach V item scores . . . . . . . . . Page 31 69 7O 72 73 76 78 79 8O 82 84 84 86 88 Table Page 5.14 Number of subjects classified into strategy groups on the basis of Mach V scores on 20 items. . . . . . . 89 5.15 Summary table of steps in discriminant program . . . . 90 5.16 Number of subjects classified into strategy groups on the basis of Mach V scores on the eight most discrim- inating items. 0 o o I a O O O 0 0 O O o O o O I O I O 91 5.17 Number of subjects classified into strategy groups on the basis of Mach V scores on four most discriminating items. 0 O O C O I I O O O C O O O O O O I O O O O O O 91 5.18 Items for which means of the distribution of Mach V item scores differ across groupsa:b. . . . . . . . . . 92 5.19 Keyed items from the Mach V scale. . . . . . . . . . . 94 vii Appendix A B LIST OF AVPENDICES Induction for Condition 1 Induction for Condition II. Induction for Condition III Complete Questionnaire. Machiavellianism and Interpersonal TOpical Inventory Scoring Routines. Instructions for Experiment II. viii Page 109 112 115 118 136 143 ‘haptcr 1 Introduction If the process of forming a coalition to effect a political decision is conceptualized as an n-pcrson game, we would expect the mathematical theory of n-person games to shed some light on the strategies that would be in some sense ”rational” in the game. Lute and Raiffa (1957) note that the nothematical work on n-pcrson games has generally assumed that "in addition to receiving the payoffs prescribed by the rules of the game, the players are permitted to nuke additional transfers....” This provision for side-payments generally subsumes the much stronger condition "that utility is unrestrictedly transferable". (Luce and Raiffa, 1957). This assumption about utility (or in actuality, goods to which individuals ascribe value) requires the additional supposition that: there exists an infinitely divisible, real, and desirable commodity (which for all the world behaves like money) such that any reapportionmcnt of it among players results in increments and decrements of individual utilities which sum to Zero according to some specific set of utility scales for the players. This can happen when money exists, provided that each player's utility for money and that the ztro and unit of earh utility function is so chosen that the conservation of money implies the conservation of utility. When else it can realistically happen is obscure. (Luce and Raiffa, 1957, p. 168) Luce and RJiffa (1957) argue that the assumption of transferable utility is not essential to n-person game theory and that a solution function can be defined without it. Their discussion is roughly as follows: Suppose there is a lottery whose prizes are bundles of goods, services, obligations, etc. The bundles accrue to each possible winning coalition as a whole. Let C(S) denote the commodity bundle accruing to the coalition S and let J(S) denote the set of all possible physical v distributions, T, of C(S) over the members of S. A coalition S is defined to be effective for a set of utilities X:(Xl’ x;,......xn), where n is the number of actors in S, if there exists at least one distribution, T, in the set J(S) such that the utility of T is less than Xi for all players i in the coalition S. The set of utilities Y=(yl, y,,...yn) is said to dominate the SEC 4 __,_____ of utilities X=(x1, x2,...xn) if there exists a non-empty coalition S such that S is effective for Y and yi).xi for all i in S. Under these conditions, S is a solution for the game. Luce and Raiffa (1957) point out the critical mechanical problem of making side payments in units of indivisible physical commodities. Suppose the joint payoff to the coalition Sl=ll,? k and C are non-homogeneous, indivisible goods like a house, a painting and is C(Sl)={},8,d}, where A, B, \IV’”) a car. If player 3 were to join S1 to form sz{l,2,i} the payoff might be C(32)={P,Ei; where D and E are also non-homogeneous, indivisible goods such as a yacht and an antique oriental chest. The monetary equivalents for the commodities A, B, C, D, and E may differ from person to person. So long as no external market mechanism is available, there is no apparent method either S1 or S2 may employ to divide the payoff. Nor is there a clear way to decide whether it is profitable to add another player. One means of circumventing this problem is by aggregating payoffs--either by bringing a number of small issues into the negotiations, or by contributing some divisible resource, Such as money, to a common pot. Luce and Raiffa (1957) note that the problem of indivisible payoffs has neither been attacked directly, nor has it been approached through systematic deve10pment of a theory of anregdtion. This study attacks the problem of predicting strategy choices in games in which payoffs may not be infinitely divisible. The focus of the present study, however, is not the mathematical derivation of ideal solution sets, but is rather the empirical examination of the effect of nontransferable utility on the strategies different subjects select. The remainder of this introductory chapter will note several significant studies of coalition strategy that have contributed to the general design of the present research. The chapters to follow will examine several studies in detail, derive empirical hypotheses, construct a test situation, and present the findings (3f tlu: stud)n Caplow (1959) was the first empirically oriented social scientist to investigate the problem of Strategies in games with non-transferable pay- offs. He defined three kinds of competitive environments: continuous, in which the rewards of the coalition process lie in the activities of forming the coalition, as in competitive social games; episodic--in which the rewards are distributed periodically to the coalition in control at pre- determined distribution times; and terminal--in which the distribution of rewards permanently ends the game, e.g., by destroying one or more actors or by establishing an equilibrium condition. In postulating three different strategies, Caplow (1939) made two implicit assumptions. The first was that all persons perceived the sit- uation in the same way. The second was that all persons who perceived the situation in a given way would select the same strategy. Caplow's (1959) assumptions have been implicit in much contemporary research on coalition formation. (e.g., Gamson, 19613, Riker, 1967). One of the first political scientists to develop a fornwl coalition theory, William Riker (1962) also makes qualitative distinctions among types of payoff. Riker (1962) identifies one set of rewards as partic- ularly appropriate to followers, and another set as constituting the principal reward of leaders. His distinctions, though, do not lead to predictions of different strategies. Riker (1962) derived one strategy from a strictly deductive analysis of the n-person zero—sum game. This strategy assumes an infinitely divisible payoff. All rational subjects are not expected to perceive the payoff situation in the same way but they are expected to select the same strategy. Riker (1962) contends that an actor reaches a strategy decision only by comparing offers ten— dered with his own preferences and its Subjective estimation of his opponent's preferences and alternatives. he claims generality for this approach since the estimation assumption frees him from the necessity of postulating interpersonal comparisons of utility. In the derivation of the "size principle", which postulates that rational actors will choose to form the smallest winning coalition, Riker (l962) examines a situation in which a larger-than—minimal winning coalition might form. If it is possible to increase the total payoff more than proportionately by adding members to an already winning coalition, a larger than winning coalition might conceivably form. Riher (l962) examines four rules for payoff division in this situation, and finds that none of them lead to a stable coalition larger than the minimal winning coalition-—if they lead to a coalition at all. The entire analysis, though, examines payoff dis- tribution rules that operate only with infinitely divisible payoffs. Thus despite his disclaimer to the contrary, Riker (196“) limits his analysis to situations which have transferable utility. Schelling (1960) argues that if a social situation is conceptualized as a mixed-motive game-—that is, as a situation in which there is something to be gained by cooperation with some, but not all of the participants--then it is not possible to construct a totally deductive theory of coalition strategy. Cues in the environment that may be independent of the abstract characterization of the situation's payoffs may suggest strategies to actors that would permit them to coordinate their activities. Moreover, some empirical knowledge of how the actors assessed their opponent's res— ponses to sucn cues is necessary to a viable theory of strategy selection (Schelling, 1960). This argument takes the individual actor's perceptions of the competitive situation as essential elements of a theory of coali— tion strategy. Schelling's (1960) approach would suggest that intangible goods such as agreement on ideological stands, or particular sensitivity of individual actors to certain outcomes or particular prominence of specific payoff divisions, would be likely to have cue value to the actor formulating a strate y—-even if neither the actor nor an outside observer could assign an exchange value to the good or situation element that pro— vided the cue. Riker (1967) provides a contrast to Schelling's (l962) position in this introduction to an eXperimental study of bargaining in a three-person mixed motive game: The scientific expectation is that, by studying the quasi—political action of games-—where the variations among institutional, psychologi— cal, and ideological components of the behavior are minimized——one will be able to understand more profoundly the basic political ac— tivities of bargaining, forming coalitions, and choosing strategies. This more profound understanding is a consequence of obtaining an— swers to the following questions: (1) What is the mathematical sol- ution, that is, what amount of utility can players he expected to obtain, when it is assumed that players are rational and wish to maximize utility? (2) What is the strategy (or method of playing) that will ensure players of achieving the solution? (Riker, 1967) Riker (1967) found that the mean payoff to players in each playing position was not significantly different from the mathematical solution of the game. He also found that those participants who "undersold" them— selves in bargaining, that is, those who orfered their opponents a larger share of the payoff than the opponent could expect to obtain in any other coalition, won significantly more games than did participants who offer- ed less to the opponent and demanded more of the payoff for themselves. Participants tended to change their offers as they played different positions in the game, and players from different social backgrounds did differ in bargaining strategy or amount won (Riser, 1967). Riker (1967) concludes his study with the following remarks: It is often suggested that the outcomes of political events are determined by the psychological or sociological characteristics of the participants. Such considerations seem inconsequential in these eXperiments where quite different kinds of subjects behaved in substantially identical ways and where the same sub- jects behaved differently in different positions . . . subjects did not let their psychological predispositions toward high or low aspirations or high or low feelings of dominance (or what- ever else might be said to force them to behave similarly in different positions) affect their judgement on the choice of a strategy . . . I conclude hat the crucial determinants of be- havior are the subjects' (conscious or unconscious) recognition of the abstract solution and the strategy dictated by the tem- poral circumstances. It should be noted that Riker (1967) reports no individual difference measures on his subjects other than their social group identification as political science students, randomly selected students, or businessmen in evening college. Moreover, Riker's (1967) experiment used only one form of abstract game and a monetary payoff--thus there was only one abstract solution. The contrast between Riker's (1967) argument and Schelling's (1960) approach can be sharpened by examining one of the principal objections to the study of the effects of personality on political behavior: Personality is not an important determinant of behavior because individuals with varying personal characteristics behave sim- ilarly when placed in common situations. And it is not useful to study personal variation, if the ways in which people vary do not affect their behavior. (Creenstein, 1967) Greenstein's (1967) critical review of this sort of objection rephrases it in terms amenable to scientific examination: Under what circumstances do different actors (placed in common situations) vary their behavior, and under what circumstances is behavior uniform? Two sorts of questions may be asked with this proposition in mind. The first deals with characteristics of the environment that may facilitate or hinder personal variability. Sherif (1953) notes that ambiguous sit— uations tend to leave room for personal variability. Budner (1962) elaborates the concept of ambiguity to include those environments which are completely new and offer no familiar cues, those which are complex and provide a great number of cues, and those which provide contradictory cues. Greenstein (l9b7) suggests the following proposition relating personality effects to environmental differences: The opportunities for personal variation are increased to the degree that political actors lack mental sets which might lead them to structure their perceptions and resolve ambiguities. The second sort of question one might ask to ascertain the conditions under which individual dif‘erences might lead to differential behavior is, "What kinds of individual predispositions are sensitized by various sit- uations? What kinds of skills do different situations draw upon?" These questions can be directed to those elements of the environment budner (1962) held relevant to individual variation in behavior. What kinds of skills would be useful in a situation which is novel, complex or contra— dictory? What kind of predispositions would be sensitized by such a sit- nation? This study examines several theoretical contributions of the study of coalition behavior in the light of the effects of environmental and predispositional differences. It proceeds by (l) structuring a well defined mixed—motive environment and postulating a set of strategies eXpected to be elicited by the environmental structure; (2) developing a set of systematic alterations in the environment and predicting the differences in strategy patterns resulting from environmental changes; and (3) postulating a set of strategy choices that would be expected of individuals with selected personal characteristics in specific en— vironmental situations. The Experimental Environment The "political convention paradigm" has been used extensively as an eXperimental setting for testing hypotheses based on various theories of coalition formation behavior. The political convention paradigm was first used by Gamson (l96lb). In it subjects are asked to take the roles of faction leaders or candidates in a political party convention. The purpose of the convention is to allocate an easily divisible pay- off, such as a number of patronage positions or a relatively indivisible payoff such as the nomination to an office on the party's ticket. The subjects, as contenders, must garner a majority of the delegates' votes to gain effective decision power over the payoff distribution. Their activities consist of deciding whom to contact to begin negotiations with, negotiating, and arriving at some coalition agreement with an eXplicit division of the payoff. The political conVention paradigm thus provides the opportunity to observe several forms of social and individual behav- ior. This stLdy focuses on one phase of the individual's strategy: his selection of a potential partner with whom he will begin negotiations. Abilities and Predispositions The prospect that situations which are novel, complex, or contradic- tory may facilitate the use of particular kinds of skills suggests a particular area of personality theory that may explain aspects of strategy selection behavior. Harvey's (1963) work with conceptual systems theory deals directly with Sdllls essential for handling complex situations. Harvey, Hunt, and Schroder (1961), Harvey (1903), and Schroder, Driver and Strcufcrt (1967) developed a theoretical scheme that postulates that the ability to deal with large amounts of complex or contradictory infor- mation is a basic individual skill. Individuals who can integrate large quantities of information and make accurate discriminations can generate more alternative conceptions of possible outcomes in a situation and can anticipate a larger number of consecuences of different strategies. These persons are called cognitively complex. They have been found to be suc- cessful in several forms of strategy games (Schroder, Driver and Streufert, 1967). Persons who lack these abilities are more limited in their strat- egy perceptions and thus exhibit more rigid and invariate strategy choice. The contribution of conceptual systems theory to the prospect of determining the conditions under which different situations will elicit different strategies is examined in this study. The possibility that different competitive environments might sensitize different predispositions or attitudes suggests that one would do well to examine some set of attitudes that are theoretically related to strategic behavior. The concept of the Machiavellian refers to the individual who has skill in interpersonal strategy and has no scruples about using it to . . , . _ .. . 1 his own advantage. Christie describes the ideal Machiavellian as follows: 1The develOpment of an objective scale to measure Machiavellianism was initiated by an informal workgroup at the Center for the Advanced Study of the Behavioral Sciences in 1953-54. The group consisted of Robert Agger, Richard Christie, Bruce Melnik, and Frank Pinner. (Christie, 1962) 10 (l) he is not basically concerned with morality in the convention- al sense. (2) He is basically ”cool” in the interpersonal relationships-- once one becomes emotionally involved with another person it is difficult to treat him as an object manipulated. (3) Since those who manipulate are more concerned with means than with ends, he might be of any ideological persuasion, but is more concerned with conning others than with what he is conning them for. (4) He functions successfully in the contemporary world. He is not likely to display signs of irrationality viewed as neurotic or psychotic, but is more likely to be overly rational in dealing with people. (Ceis and Christie, 1965) The Machiavellian might be eXpected to be sensitized by situations which offered a number of strategies for dealing with the environment at hand. Moreover, he might be especially sensitive to those strategies which others might avoid because of questions of the ”fairness” or ”right- ness". This study examines the effects of Machiavellianism in several competitive situations which provide such strategies as viable choices. Implications for Political Thecgy The study that follows attempts to integrate the major questions raised by two distinctly different arguments in modern political theory: One, the position that the abstract (mathematical structure of the com- petitive situation determines the participants' strategy choices; the other that the participants' perception of significant cues may lead actors to strategies not defined as mathematically optimal. The key to integrating these conflicting arguments is an examination of behavior in a situation which is characterized by non-transferable utility, i.e., in- divisible payoff. Chapter II of this study reviews four competing theories of coalition formation, Minimum Power Theory, Minimum Resource Theory, Anti-Competitive Theory, and Utter Confusion Theory (Gamson, 1964). The review poses a question suggested by Sche‘ling's (1960) criticism of purely deductive approaches to theory of interaction in mixed—motive games: how do changes in the competitive environment alter the strat- egies chosen? This question provides a means of integrating the con— flicting predictions of the four theories of coalition formation. Moreover in dealing with situations which may elicit alternative strat- egies, it becomes possible to ask if the perception and selection of specific strategies is in part the result of some particular skill or sensitization to the competitive situation. hapter II develops the theoretical basis for predicting alternate strategies in mixed-motive situations and Chapter III derives hypotheses predicting strategy selection from individual difference measures. Chapter IV restates the objectives of the study and develOps the experi- mental design. Chapter V presents results and Chapter VI summarizes the findings of the study and briefly discusses their theoretical sig- nificance. Chapter II The Identification of Social Contact Strategies in The Political ConVention Paradigm The identification of "successful” strategies in mixed—motive games is generally contingent on the assumption of a particular theory of strat- egy behavior. This is most apparent in theories of "rational" choice, such as Riker's (1962) application of a game theoretic model to the study of political coalitions. Riker (1962) defines a rational choice as a stra— tegy that would seek to build the smallest winning coalition. Any deci— sion to form a coalition larger than necessary to win the contest at hand, unless it is made in ignorance or the necessary margin or size of the min- imum winning coalition, is an irrational decision. In an empirical exam— ination of a theory which assumes a single rationality it is meaningful to ask whether subjects or respondents chose rational strategies or not. If the theoretical basis for a study of decision behavior postulates alternative strategies, that is, alternative goods that a participant may choose to maximize, then it makes little sense to ask wnether subjects in the study are behaving rationally. It does make sense, however, to ask, "With respect to what decision rule are their decisions rational?" This study investigates several distinct patterns of strategy selection, each of which maximizes a somewhat different expected utility. Each strategy pattern is in this sense a rational pattern. lhe question we may then ask is, "Under what conditions do participants in a mixed—motive game select alternate rational strategies?" This chapter reviews some of the empirical findings that have led to the development of the several theory fragments dealing with coalition for— lnation process, Shelly and Phillips' (1966) distinction between two i) o phases of action in forming a coalition provides a useful analytic tool for the discussion to follow. They distinguished a temporally prior pro- cess in forming a coalition as the "social contact process" and a later phase as the "bargaining process". The contact process will receive prin- cipal attention in this study. The social contact process is by no means a unitary event. There are at least two individual activities in the contact process. One is the in— dividual's estimation of the demands other participants will make in bar- gaining. The other is the exercise of a decision rule to select one of the other participants to contact. Several studies have examined the contact process with major emphasis on decision rules (Chertkoff, l9bb; Phillips and Nitz, 1968; Cole and Phillips, 1967; Nitz and Phillips, in preparation). Little previous research has examined the participant's evaluation process— es. This study will provide initial data on the evaluative processes in the mixed-motive game. Theoretical Background Minimum Power Theory. Minimum Power Theory is derived from a game theoretic measure of power developed by Shapley (1953). The power of any participant in a mixed motive situation is measured by counting the number of ways he can turn a losing coalition into a winning one by joining it. The theory assumes that some decision rule that specifies the total amount of resources an actor or social unit must control in order to influence the distribution of payoff in the situation. For any mixed motive situa— tion with a finite number of social actors and a fixed decision rule, it is possible to enumerate all possible orders of voting (i.e., joining a coali— tion) and count the number of times each actor holds the pivotal position. Shapley and Shubik (1954) have shown that any other internally consistent measure of power in voting bodies must be a transformation of this one. With Shapley and Shubik's (1954) simple algorithm for computing power, we can specify the relative power of each actor and the likelihood of his being the pivotal member of a coalition in a mixed motive situation. However, in a situation where resources are distributed as follows: A: 4 votes B= 3 votes C= 2 votes and a simple majority (5 votes) is required to win any contest, the Shapley-Shubik algorithm identifies two potential coalitions for each participant, such that either will become a winning coalition if it is formed. Thus the power of all participants is equal -- the probability of any participant forming a winning coalition is 1/3. In this sort of mixed motive situation where no participant has either dictatorial pow- er or veto power, Minimum Power Theory predicts that all coalitions will form with equal likelihood. So long as the probability of forming a winning coalition is equal for all actors, Minimum Power Theory neither suggests nor derives from any social contact strategy based on the payoff structure of the game. When the actors' chances of forming winning coalitions vary, though, Minimum Power Theory may suggest strategies based on order of play. There has been little experimental support for Hinimum Power Theory. Vinacke and Arkoff (1957), Vinacke (1959), Phillips and Nitz (1968), and Cole (1969), however, provide a convincing set of counter-examples. The one study (Kelley and Arrowood, 1900) that does not support Minimum Power Theory is based on an experiment that allows several confounding variables to be uncontrolled. Anti-Competitive Theory Anti-Competitive Theory was named by Gamson (l96é) in his review of coalition formation literature. This theorv assumes that participants in l»— U1 a mixed-motive situation will attempt to minimize conflict or competition within an alliance by forming coalitions along lines of least resistance. The coalitions that form with least resistance will be between those par- ticipants for whom the distribution of resources suggests an obvious and unambiguous division of the payoff.1 Gamson (leQ) further specifies that "this will occur among players who are equal in resources, because . . players with equal resources will share equally". Two types of findings can be distinguished among studies supporting Anti-Competitive Theory. The first type consists of instances of anti— competitive behavior that arise through the play of the game. Hoffman, et a1. (1934) found that achiey'ng an early lead in a game where cumula— tive scoring was important was likely to stimulate opposition. Thus subjects found it advantageous to avoid taking a commanding lead early in the game. Uesugi and Vinacke (1963) observed that females repeatedly attempted to transform a mixed motive game into a pure coordination game by rotating winners between plays and forming all-inclusive alliances. Chaney and Vinacke (1960) found that subjects high in achievement motivation were coalition members significantly less often than were those low on achieve— ment motivation. Apparently the more highly motivated subjects presented the image of a fierce competitor andxvere therefore avoided. The second type of evidence for Anti-Competitive Theory arises from the resource distribution and the formal structure in the game, rather than from the bargaining behavior occurring during the game play itself. This is substantially the argument presented by Schclling (1960). Willis (1962) found that an even distribution of resources between po- tential coalition partners tended to lead to the formation of more counter-coalitions in a four person game than did an unequal distribution of resources. Gamson (196lh) noted a prevalence of coalitions between participants with equal resources in a five man game under resource distribution conditions similar to those used by Willis. Leiserson (1966) observed that his subjects divided a monetary payoff equally more often than any other way. He interprets this as division of payoff along the lines of least resistanCe--by virtue of the prominence 0 of the strategy.h Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) further noted that subjects were less willing to form a coalition with a potential partner who had equal resources when the payoff was relatively indivisible. Under that circumstance the equal resource distribution cannot make it easier to agree on a division of the payoff. This latter set of data suggests that a careful analysis of a limited set of structural variables, such as the resource distribution and the divisibility of the payoff may provide explanations for some of the be- havior described as anti-competitive. Minimum Resource Theory Minimum Resource Theory evolved from the work of CAplow (1956), Vinacke and Arkoff (1957), and Gamson (1960, 19613, b). The theory was explicitly formulated as a sociological theory of the coalition process by Gamson I did not manage to secure a copy of Leiserson's (1966) Ph.D. disser- tation until the work reported here was substantially complete. I shall touch on his research contribution more lightly than I might have had I examined his work before independently developing a parallel theoretical framework. l7 (l961a, 1064). Camson (l9ola) limits Minimum Resource Theory to mixed motive games where no participant has dictatorial or veto power. In a three-person game with participants A, B, and C, this would mean that the distribution of resources among the participants could not be a > (B+C) or A = (5+C). That is, no one contender (here arbitrarily designated ”A”) can have sufficient resources to control or block any decision. This exclusion of situations that have participants with dictatorial or veto power limits Minimum Resource Theory to situations which are essential games: Each participant has some stake in the outcome and some possibility of exercising control over that outcome. Gamson (1961a) assumes that all participants have the same infor- mation about the initial resource distribution and payoff conditions. There is some class of payoffs among which they do not differentiate on the basis of payoff value, but among which they choose according to a "non-utilitarian” strategy. These assumptions define an explicit set of situations for which the theory is apprOpriate. The first empirical hypothesis of Minimum Resource Theory is a statement of the goals or expectations the partic- ipant perceives others to have: 1. Any participant will eXpect others to demand from a coalition a share of the payoff proportional to the amount of resources which they contribute to the coalition. This hypothesis has been referred to as the ”parity norm” (Gamson, 1964). A succinct development of the notion of parity in interpersonal exchange is found in homans' (1961) discussion of distributive justice: *4 f x A man in an exchange relation with another will expect that the rewards of each man will be proportional to his costs-- the greater the rewards, the greater the costs—~and that net rewards or profits of each man will be proportional to his investments.... (homans, 1961, pp. 75-77) Gamson's (1961a) second hypothesis specifies a decision rule for the participant. It may be expressed in both general and specific forms, depending on the nature of the payoffs in the game and the relevance of non-utilitarian strategy choices. The more general form, which applies . .. . .-. _ 3 when the payoff to each posSible coalition may ditier is: 2a. A participant will choose that coalition in which the product of the total payoff to the coalition and his expected share of that payoff is highest. He will not discriminate within payoff classes on the basis of his members have the highest mean rank in his evaluation of non—utilitarian preferences. When the payoff to all coalitions is eoual, hypothesis 2a may be rephrased as follows: 2b. When a player must choose among alternative coalition strate— gies where the total payoff to a winning coalition is constant, he will maximize his payoff by maximizing the ratio of his re- sources to the resources of the coalition. Thus he will favor his cheapest winning coalition. The final prediction of the theory is: 3. A coalition will form if and only if there are reciprocal strategy choices between two participants. This hypothesis assumes that the coalition formation process proceeds in a pairwise manner. An illustration of the theory's explicit predictions is found in Camson's (1961b) study of coalition formation in the political convention paradigm. Camson (1961b) constructed three political convention games and asked subjects from two local fraternities to play a series of the games. Two subjects from one fraternity and three from the other played in each 3 . . . . . Hypothe51s 23 and 2b are my wordings rather than Gamson's. I believe they convey the sense of Gamson's (1961a) propositions more explicitly than his original phrasing. V game. In one caperimcnt the resources or votes were apportioned among five subjects in the following amounts: l7, l7, 17, 25, 25. The payoff in this convention was 100 political jobs that would be divided among the winning coalition. The non-utilitarian strategy preferences were established by composing each group of members from two different social fraternities. The effective decision point was taken to be a simple majority of the votes. Since the payoff to all coalitions is the same in this convention, coalition preferences could be prt~o icted on the basis of the initial re- source distribution. Thc minimal winning coalition for all subjects is a coalition that includes two of the 17 vote contenders. When the cases in which both of a subject's pro-hypothesis choice options were members of the other fraternity were removed from the analysis, the choice hypo- thesis was confirmed. The minimum winning coalition was the alliance most often preferred by the three contenders with 17 votes each. The final coalitions formed as predicted one-third of the time (chance expec- tation was one-tenth). In the second convention, both resource base and payoff to the coalition varied. The Minimum Resource Theory choice prediction are illustrated in Figure 2.1. (Camson, l9bO) Figure 2.1 Minimum Resource Predictions in Camson's Second Convention 15 votes\ ’5 votes 90 jObS lOOI jobs 6 votes lOI votes 90 jobs \ no jObS 35 votes””’:’/:’ar no jobs The nwnber of jobs the coalition was able to divide was the highest of the payoffs to the members, rather than the sum of the jobs available to the members if they should win. In this convention the 6 and 10 vote participants made choices con— sistent with the prediction of the theory. The two 33 vote participants, however, chose each other more often than they chose any of the other contenders. None of the final coalition frequencies differed from chance expectancies. The latter two findings are contradictory to the prediction of Minimum Resource Theory. Gamson (1960) suggests that this tendency of the contenders with greater resources to choose each other may be a strategy of risk-reduction. Forming any winning coalition on the first negotiating round may have been preferred to taking the chances involved in a series of negotiating rounds necessary to build a 3 member cheapest minimal winning coalition. The results of Camson's (l9blb) first conVention game tend to support Minimum Resource Theory. The results of the second game suggest that Gamson's empirical hypotheses capture only a portion of the substance of a viable coalition theory. The three theoretical approaches disvussed all appear to be faulted. Nonetheless, they provide a sufficient basis for formulating an integrated explanation of strategy selection. Identification of Strategy Selection Propositions The most fruitful place to begin an examination of unexplained strategy selection patterns is with the most clearly articulated theory frag- ment, Minimum Resource Theory. There are stveral ways in which Gamson's (19613) Minimum Resource Theory hypotheses may not have been adequate for the task. The empirical hypotheses assumed (l) a particular distributive maximization decision rule, and J b.) t"; H. P-f, *- 0 justice expectation, (Z) a (3) required reciprocal choice as a prerequisite to coalition formation. In the eXperiment subjects chose partners intil reciprocal choices were made, so no test of the latter hypothesis was possible. The subjects' evaluations or estimates of their opponents' eXpectations were not measur— ed, but were inferred from their partner preference choices. Since the partner preferences did not contirm the theoretical predictions in Gamson's second experiment we must assume that either (1) the subjects did not enter— tain parity expectations, or (2) the subjects did not maximize according to the parity principle, or (3) both. Finally, Minimum Resource Theory predicts coalition outcomes on the assumption that all participants use the same decision rule and have the same estimate of other's eXpectations. This assumption is not upheld in Gamson's (1960, l9blb) second game. The absence of any significant pattern in the coalitions formed in the second game, combined with consistent partner preferences in the oppo- site direction from the theoretical predictions challenges the adequacy of Minimum Resource as a sociological theory. The significant, though not necessarily pro-hypothesis, patterns of partner preferences in both the first and second games indicate that Gamson's (lQhU, lfihla) formulation may provide a model for a viable theory of strategy selection or individual choice in coalition formation situations. Gamson's (1961a, 1901b) work suggests several elements of a strategy selection model. The first is a prediction that an individual will tend to hold a parity expectation: A. Any participant will expect others to drmand from a coalition a share of the payoff preperticnal to the amount of resources which they contribute to the coalition. w r r\/‘ Since little previous research on expectations and social judgments is directly related to coalition processes, I will not elaborate upon this hypothesis at this point. Its purpose is essentially exploratory in nature. "e se ox v o n sis su oes co 5 ithsoi , o 's ' ' ' Tn’ c id hyp tle‘ _g“ t ’ *y (an 1's w rk l‘ a modification of his maximization decision rule. Bl. Individuals seek to maximize r share of the payoff with 1' A. 9 . ii t e respect to the coalition partner The remainder of this cnapter will explore the effects of two factors that appear to be systematically related to coalition partner selection strategies; multiple resource dimensions and differential divisibility of payoff. Multiple Resource Dimensions Three studies of coalition processes involving multiple resource dim- ensions may suggest what sorts of mechanisms may contribute to a viable theory of individual choice in coalition formation. Chertkoff (1966) exam- ined the effect that differing probabilities of success would have on coalitions formed in the political convention paradigm. The payoff or pur- pose of the convention was to award a nomination and to apportion 100 pa“ tronage positions among the coalition members. The distribution of votes among three contenders was 40—30-20. The distribution corresponds to Caplow's (1956) Type 5 resource distribution. The essential characteristic of the Type 5 distribution is that the resources be distributed among the contenders such that: A > B > C A < (B+C) Here A represents the number of votes pledged to contender A; B, the number F.) \a.‘ J I pledged to Contender h; and c, the number pleugeo to candidate C. The se- cond resource dimension, the probability of winning the election if nomina- ted, was also varied. Four conditions were used. In condition one the pro— bability of winning the election was not introduced. In condition two each candidate had a probability of .50 of winning the election if he were nomin- ated. In condition three contender A bad a probability of .70, while con- tenders B and C had probabilities of .50 each. In condition four candidate A had a probability of .90 of winning the election if nominated, while con- tenders B and C had each probabilities of .30. The bargaining period began only if two subjects made reciprocal choices. The subjects were allowed to bargain for a fixed period of time. If they reached no agreement within the time limit, the process of choice and bar- gaining was repeated until a coalition formed. Chertkoff (1966) found that Minimum Resource Theory predictions of coalitions formed held for condition one, the condition with no probability manipulation. When the probability of winning was introduced, the frequency of BC coalitions decreased as the probability of A's winning the election in— creased. The BC coalitions were replaced by AB and AC coalitions. Stryker and Psathas (1960) and Kelley and Arrowood (1060) contend that misperception of the real power relationships in coalition situations generates the frequent coalitions observed between weaker contenders. Under Kelley and Arrowood's (1960) hypothesis the decrease in frequency of BC coalitions Chertkoff (1966) "correction" of such a misperception of the observed could be attributed to a power relationships. An explanation of Chertkoff's (l96b) data that does not resort the mechanism of subject error has been proposed by Cole (1969). Cole (1969) examined coalition formation in a truel (three person duel) under two conditions of certainty. In the deterministic condition, any attack a coalition or an individual directed at an opponent was executed with a trobability of 1.0. In a probabilistic condition, coalitions or indi- vidual actors were successful in their attacks with a probability of .50. Since no coalition in the probabilistic condition could be successful with certainty, no minimum winning coalition could be defined. To gen- erate predictions comparable to thase of Minimum Resource Theory, Cole (1969) suggested the following proposition: Participants in a probabilistic situatimn will prefer to form that coalition which will maximize their chances of winning. Cole (1969) then predicted that the stronger contender would be the coalition choice preferred by all subjects in the probabilistic condition. The weaker contender would be the preferred coalition choice in the deter- ministic condition. Cole's (l9b9) first hypothesis was confirmed, while his second was not. He attributes subjects' choice of the stronger con- tender in tne probabilistic situation to the operation of a desire for security. This desire is seen as a by-product of the same structure. It becomes salient when subjects cannot be certain of executing chosen game strategies (Cole, 1969). Cole's (1969) concept of a desire for security is quite different from Homans' (1961) distributive justice and Gamson's (1900, l96la) parity principle. The parity principle is an eXpectation the subjects have of others' desires. Cole's (l969) desire for security is actually a decision rule the subject uses to select a coalition partner. it would be consis- tent with this discussion to rephrase Cole's (lQbQ) security norm as a decision rule alternative to the Gamson's (l9blb) maximization rule: 2c. When the payoff to any coalition cannot be obtained with certainty, but only with some probability, individuals will seek to maximize their chances of winning by forming the coalition that will maximize that probability of winning. r J b" When the probability of winning is perceived as a function of the total weight or combined resources of the coalition members, persons will attempt to form the coalition with the greater resource weight. Phrased in this way, the security role describes a strategy found by Leiserson (1966), namely an urgency on the part of some subjects to get the benefits of a winning coalition no matter how small a share one had to accept. Chertkoff (l9b6) noted that the contact prOCess served as a sensi- tive indicator of a large portion of a liance forming behavior. In every position the probability of picking the weaker competitor was greater than the probability of picking the stronger. The difference from the _ - 2 , null hypothes1s P(N) = .3 was highly significant (X = 18.32, p < .001). df Not all subjects, however, followed this Minimum Resource Theory strategy. A minority favored the stronger competitor. SeVeral types of behaviors may be represented by these non-minimal winning coalition choices. The Kelley and Arrowood (1960) hypothesis is that these few subjects correct- ly perceived the real power of all three contenders to be equal and that the majority misperceived this power distribution. A positive hypothe- sis, though, can postulate a decision rule to explain this behavior. Two possible explanations are snéacsted by these data. Each is con- sistent with a different interpretation of bamson's (1964) Anti-Competi- tive Theory. First, the occurrence of a plurality of 33-33 coalitions may simply be an unintended consequence of the pair-wise negotiating pro— cedure. Forming a three member coalition requires two rounds, forming a two-man coalition requires only one. A 33-33 coalition may simply be the "security" strategies. result of mutual Gamson's (l96la, b) origi al study of the convention paradigm sheds some light on one sort of alternative decision rule that some subjects may be using here. Camson (lfioA) notes that the number of unexpected large 35-}5 coalitions formed in his second game suggests that some form of anti-competitive behavior may have occurred. Second, coalitions be- tween equally matched contenders suggests an obvious division of payoff-- fifty-fifty. Schelling (1960) noted that psychologically salient out- comes may suggest distinct Strategies. The saliency of some set of possible outcome allocations may affect subject's choices in this situation. The remainder of this chapter will review research developing this line of argument. Phillips and Nitz (1968) conducted owo studies of the decision rules used in the contact process that Suggest an explicit set of alternate decision rules. The method used was a paper-and-pencil measure called the Political Decision Questionnaire, or PDQ. The PDQ has taken various forms, the first of which reads as follows: Assume that you are the manager for a candidate in a political party convention. There are a total of 300 votes among the dele- gates and at least a majority (151) of these are required to win the nomination. Your man, Candidate A, has votes pledged to him. Candidate B has votes pledged to him, and Candidate C has votes pledged to him. Which of the other two candidates, B or C, will you approach first to try to make a deal? (Phillips and Nitz, 1968) The following scheme was used to distribute the convention votes among the three candidates. The Subject always played the role of the Faction A representative. One of the two remaining factions, B or C, was designated w, the weaker faction, and the other was designated S, the strong- er faction. The subject always had the same number of convention votes as either W or S. The following relationships then existed in the resource distribution: I») \J A + H + S = Total number of votes 5 ((A + la") and either A = W (Caplow's type 2 triad) or A = S (Caplow's type 3 triad) The probability that the subject will choose the weaxer candidate can be designated p(W). The probability of choosing S, the stronger candidate can be designated 1 - p(W). Minimum Resource Theory predicts that A will choose the weaker candi- date, w, with a probability greater than .50 in both the Type 2 and Type 3 triad resource distributions. Phillips and Nitz's (l908) data confirmed this prediction. The data also showed that the p(w) was greater when A = S than it was when A = W. Phillips and Nitz (l908) hypothesized that this shift in preference toward the smaller contender was the result of the operation of some kind of anticomnetitive norm. That is, some subjects sought to reduce intra-coalition competition over division of the relative— ly indivisible payoff-—a nomination—-by choosing the man whose resources were not equal to his own. This hypothesis was examined more rigorously in a study by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation). The difference between [p(K), A=W1 and [p(W), A=S] observed in the Phillips and Nitz's (1968) study was seen as a function of the subject's perceptions of the divisibility of the payoff. The experimental manipulation in Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) varied the nature of the payoff or outcome of the convention. Three conditions were used: an easily divisible payoff, a payoff that could be divided only unequally, and a payoff that could be divided only extremely 28 unequally. Each PDQ began as follows: A political party is divided into thrEe factions or groups. These groups are designated Fa tion A, Faction B, and Faction C. The party is having a convention. There are 300 delegates to this convention. Each delegate has one vote. Faction A has delegates (votes). Faction B has delegates (votes) and Faction C has dele— gates TUBIés). In approximately half of the forms Faction A had 83 votes, Faction B or C had 85 votes, and the third faction had 130 votes. The subject's group, Faction A, was thus equal to the smaller of these two competitors. In the other half of the forms, Faction A had 115 votes, either B or C had 115 votes, and the third faction had 70 votes. The subject thus had resources greater than those of the weaker opponent. The three forms continued as follows: Form 1. Easily divisible condition. The major business of the convention is to decide how many of lOO political jobs each faction will receive. Each faction would like to get as many of these 100 jobs as possible. It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on some division of these jobs. If these two factions have a maj- ority of the votes of the convention (at least 151 votes) be- tween them, then the jobs are divided acttrding to their agree- ment. An alliance between Faction A and Faction B would have votes. An alliance between Faction A and Faction C would have votes. An alliance between Faction B and Faction C would have votes. Assume that you are the representative of Faction A( votes). Which of the other two factions would you try to contact first to try to make a deal for the political jobs? Form 2. Unequally divisible condition. The text of Form 2 was much the same as that for Form 1, with the ex» ception of the following critical passage: The major business of the convention is to nominate a candiv date for governor and a candidate for lieutenant governor. Bach faction would like to have its man nominated for governor, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if he received only the lieu— tenant governor nomination. Form 3. Very unequally divisible condition. The critical passage in Form 3 was: The major business of the conVention is to nominate a candidate for governor and a candidate for lieutenant gover- nor. The governor's office is a very powerful position. The post of lieutenant governor, however, has generally been a political dead end for the candidates elected to it. (Nitz and Phillips, in preparation). The three conditions above provided the experimental situation to test the operation of four different decision rules in the contest phase of the political convention paradigm. The subjects were assumed to eval- uate others' expectations on the basis of the parity principle. Four al- ternate decision rules the subjects might use are described by the follow— ing general hypotheses: 1. Maximization Subjects seek to maximiZe their share of the payoff with respect to their coalition partners, regardless of the divisibility of the payoff . 2. Dominance Subjects prefer to he the dominant member of any coalition, regardless of the divisibility of the payoff. 3. lntra-Coalition Compatibility Subjects seek to form coalitions in which the division of the payoff can be negotiated with a minimum of intra-coalition friction. When the payoff is unequally divisible, the pro- bability of choosing the unequal contender will be greater than when the payoff is easily divisible. When the payoff is easily divisible, no intra-coalition incompatibilitv'will be engendered in a coalition between equals or in a coali- tion between unequals, so the maximization principle will be expected to hold. 4. Equalitarianism If the payoff is equally divisible, subjects seeking to minimize intra-coalition Competition will prefer to form coalitions with equals more than with unequals-—regard- less of whether he is equal to the stronger or the weaker competitor. These hypotheses are not totally independent. it was anticipated that the majority of the subject population would choose a maximization strat— egy in all payoff conditions--but that the divisibility of payoff would determine the size of that majority and the prevalence of the latter three marginal strategies. The results of the Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) study are shown in Table 2.1. These data support the maximization and the compatibility hypotheses above. The maximization hypothesis assumption predicts that p(W) would be greater than .50 for any resource distribution. The data show that this is the case. The dominance hypothesis is not conditional on divisibility of payoff. it predicts p(W) will be high-—and constant across conditions of payoff divisibility. The difference between p(W) for the easily divisible condition and p(w) for the unequally divisible con— dition at the point A=85 disconfirms the eXpectation that there will be no difference. Hypothesis three, intra—coalition compatibility, predicts that p(W) for easily divisible condition will be greater than p(w) for the un- equally divisible conditions at A=85. This hypothesis is confirmed by the data presented in Table 2.1. Finally, hypothesis four assumes that an equal division is the most easily negotiated division and predicts that when the payoff is easily divisible, p(w) will be higher if A=N than if A#W. That is, it predicts an effect exactly the Opposite from the effect observed: p(W) at A=83 should be greater than p(W) at A=llS. The observed difference is in the opposite direction. The data in Table 2.1 indicate that the intra—coalition compatibility hYpothesis is the most reasonable explanation of the deviation from the Strict maximization observed in the Philliws and Kitz (l9o5) data. Table 2.1 Prohahility of resource lypv Payoff Divisibility Conditions [(W) l. Easily divisible 49 2. Moderately non- equally divisible 36 3. Extremely non- equally divisible 48 letween divisibility conditions c1 c. / , ” of choosing 2 Triad = W fiS) pVW) l0 .830 19 *333 Ql .676 I) . X‘ comparisons t, c1 #.Ubl -- .06 Type 3 Triad {(W) 31 56 Azs f(S) 9 10 the smaller contender as a function distribution and divisinility of payoff P(W) X .850 .08 .833 .4 -ntegration of Strategy Selection hypotheses F The findings of the Gamson (l9hlh), Chertkoff (1966), Phillips and Nitz (1963) and hitz and Phillips (in preparation) studies suggest the importance of the contact phase in the process of alliance formation. Phillips and Eitz (1968) and Nitz and Phillips (In preparation) have demonstrated the viability of tne maximization assumption strategy of Hinimum Resource Theory for social contacts in the Type 2 and Type 3 resource distributions. They have also shown that perceived indivisibil- ity of the payoff causes some persons to make contacts that would tend to minimize eventual intracoalition conflict (Nitz and Phillips, in prepar— ation). heir conclusion that the maximization strategy of Minimum Re- source Theory explains most coalition partner choices and that the major deviations from the maximization choice can be interpreted as strategies that would reduce intra—coalition competition is subject to three strong limitations. In this section I will examine these limitations, suggest means of dealing with them, and present the elements of a theory of strategy se— lection whose major purpose is to eXplain those marginal strategies not predicted by the simple maximization hypothesis of Minimum Resource Theory. The first limitation of Phillips and Nitz (lane) and Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) theoretical interpretation is related to Cole's (1969) security principle. The security principle asserts that when strategies can succeed with probabilities less than unity, individuals will choose Coalition partners so as to maximize their chances of winning. The politi— Cal convention paradigm can be interpreted as either a probabilistic or a deterministic game. If subjects conceive of a coalition formed in a Convention to nominate a candidate as a necessary compaign force for 33 an impending general election, then the security principle would be rele- vant to their coalition choices. If they placed higher value on winning the general election than on attaining the top spot on the ballot, they would attempt to build the largest coalition possible. In the Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) PDQ such a strategy would be indicated if p(K) = p(K) Type 2 Type 3 < l/2 in the unequally divisible nomination condition. This security strategy asserts a preference for the smaller contender le:s than half of the time. Another finding might be attributable to security strategies in the indivisible payoff convention situation. If some subjects perceived the uncertainty of a future general election as more salient when they are relatively weak than when they are relatively strong, they might choose security strategies when in a position of weakness and compatibility strategies when in a position of strength. This combination of strategies would lead to predictions like this: P(W) > P(W) Type 3 Type 2 That is, subjects would tend to choose the different (smaller) man in the Type 3 situation, where they were equal to the larger opponent. In the Type 2 situation, they would tend to cheese the larger man (who controlled 3 different amount of resources). Moreover, if both of these strategies were found in a population that predominantly used Maximization strategies, the data would take the form: p(W) > p(fi) > l/Z Type 3 Type 2 But this is exactly the effect Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) identified as Intracoalition Compatibility! Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) pro- Vide no means of distinguishing the alternative individual strategies that 3:. might account for this aggregate statistic. This failure to discriminate between security and anti-competitive strategies is in part due to an inadequate conceptualization of the nature of these strategies. Thus the theoretical implications of the intracoalition Compatibil— ity hypothesis proposed by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) are not clear. A replication of Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) eXperiment with alternate unequally divisible payoff conditions would provide a test of the conditions under which the Intra-coalition Compatability hypothesis identifies a form of Security strategy and the conditions under which it identifies a strategy that is independent of security motivation. Three critical convention situations for a test of the distinction between Security and Compatibility strategies can be constructed. Condi- tion I would be identical to the easily divisible payoff condition used by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation). Condition 11 would be identical to their unequally divisible condition, with nominations for the ballot positions for a state governorship and lieutenant governorship. This condition would represent a probabilistic payoff condition. While this condition does not directly manipulate the probability of winning, it replicates the ambiguity about the probabilistic dimension found in Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) PDQ. Condition Ill would remove this am- biguity by presenting a convention in a one-party state. Thus the success- ful nominee need not be concerned about organizing support for a general election campaign. If he wins the nomination in the convention, he is virutally assured of the office itself. All three conditions will provide tests of the Maximization hypothe- sis: 35 l. Maximization Subjects seek to maximize their share of the payoff with respect to their coalition partners. Their choices are not altered by the divisibility of the payoff or the pro- bability of winning in a subsequent contest. This strat— egy is expected to occur with a probability of .50 or more under all three experimental conditions. The following strategies are essentially marginal strategies. These strat- egies may or may not be independent of each other, but are not generally independent of the maximization strategy. They are defined so as to ex— plain a portion of the subject population's behavior that is not accounted for by the Maximization hypothesis. The proportion of non—maximization strategy choices they explain is expected to vary as a function of the ex- perimental condition. 2. Intracoalition Compatibility Subjects seek to form coalitions in which the division of the payoff can be negotiated with a minimum of intracoali- tion friction. 'hen the payoff is unequally divisible, the probability of choosing the unequal contender is higher than when the payoff is equally divisible. When the pay- off is easily divisible, no intracoalition incompatibility will be engendered in a coalition between equals or in a coalition between unequals, so the maximization decision rule will be used. Here Condition III provides a clearly non-probabilistic form of an unequal— ly divisible payoff. To the extent that Phillips and Nitz' (1968) and Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) subjects perceived the payoff as simply a larger or a smaller nomination and ignored the probabilistic aspect of the nomination, their results should be replicated in this condition. Conditions 11 and III test the independent hypotheses that the security strategy is elicited by a probabilistic payoff situation: 3. Security When the payoff to a coalition can be attained only with some probability less than unity, subjects will seek to maximize their chances of winning by forming the largest coalition possible. 36 SubjeCts are expected to choose Candidate W less often in Condition 11 ‘than in Condition III in both the Type 2 and Type 3 triad, indicating a tendency to form larger coalitions under conditions of probabilistic pay- off. An indication of the contribution of security strategies to the occurrance of lntra-coalition Compatibility behaviors is given by the difference p pm) -p('w') \ Type 3 Type 2) Condition 11 / ,. .. ’kaw) -p(w) Type 3 Type 2 Condition III The test of this difference, moreover, is independent of the two hypothe— sis tests discussed above. If the difference given by the above equation is positive and significantly different from zero, it will indicate that the Intra-coalition Compatibility strategies identified by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) can be attributed more correctly to Security choices. Otherwise, it will suggest that the effect observed by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) is entirely the result of subjects' compatibility strategy choices. These tests should resolve the ambiguity between the Security and the Intra-coalition Compatibility strategies identified by Cole (1968) and by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation). Three additional marginal strategies may now be presented. All three are marginal to the simple Maximization strategy, but two are closely related to lntra—coalition Compatibility. 4. Equalitarianism If the payoff is equally divisible, subjects seeking to min— imize intra—coalition competition will prefer to form coali- tions with equals more than with non-equals. (No stipulation will be made here as to the effect of probabilistic outcome on this decision rule.) This hypothesis provid“s a plausible counter-proposition to explain the strategy choice Phillips and hitz (1968) designated as weak anti-competi- tive behavior. Choosing Candidate K more often when the payoff is easily divisible may be a result of situational cues suggesting an equal split. Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) argue that an Lqualitarian Strategy would be indicated by POW?) > PU‘D > l/2 Type 2 Type 3 for the equally divisible condition, and p(w) > p(w) > 1/2 Type 3 Type 2 for the unequally divisible condi ion. Yet the Equalitarian prediction for the equally divisible condition differs from the prediction of the Intra-coalition Compatibility hypothesis only insofar as Compatibility predicts p(W) = p(W) Type 3 Type 2 A more general strategy that incorporates both would be defined: P(W) 2 D(W) > l/2 Type 2 Type 3 for the equally divisible Condition l, and p(W) >p(w) >1/2 ) Type 3 Type L for the unequally divisible condition, Condition Ill. The second strategy related to lntra—coalition Compatibility is not a subset of Compatibility behaviors, but rather is the complement. The Competition strategy can be defined: 5. Competition Subjects will seek to form coalitions that will allow maximum grounds for conflict; that is, coalitions for which the struc- ture of the resource distribution suggests no obvious division of the payoff. 1 Tue Competitive strategy hypothesis predicts behavior exactly opposite of Compatibility behavior: p(l~') > p(l~’) > 1/2 Type 3 Type 2 for Condition 1, and p(M) > p(N) > 1/2 Type 2 Type 3 for Condition III. The Competition strategy is obviously not independent of Compatibility. One is necessarily accepted if the other is rejected. The final strategy pattern to be examined here is the Dominance Strat- egy: 6. Dominance Subjects prefer to be toe dominant member of any coalition. Their choices are not altered by the divisibility or the payoff or by uncertain prospects of final attainment of the payoff. The Dominance hypothesis is dependent on all of the preceeding marginal hypotheses. If any of the other hypotheses are Confirmed, then the con- ditions of the Dominance hypothesis are not met. These conditions are as follows: PW) 4' pW) .. 1/2 Type 3 Type 2 for Conditions I, II, and Ill. The second limitation to the generality of Nitz and Phillips' (in prep- aration) findings is in a sense methodological. Camson (19613), Chertkoff (1966), and Cole (1969) gathered their contact data in an experimental sit- uation in which subjects played in each others' presence. The PDQ studies gathered data in a classroom situation in which subjects were asked to imagine their opponents. A high degree of similarity between the induction 39 of the PDQ studies and the eXperimental induction in other studies of coalition formation in the political convention paradigm is insufficient grounds to justify the assertion that the PDQs and the political conven- tion paradigm experiments yielied the same sort of social contact data. The comparability of the data from these two forms of the political con— vention paradigm must be demonstrated empirically. It is therefore nec- essary to introduce two experimental conditions, one in which subjects are given PDQs, and another in which they make essentially the same types of choices in an interactive three person political convention game. The third restriction on the generality of the Phillips and Nitz (1968) and Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) hypotheses is that the identifica- tion of marginal strategies is essentially the identification of strategies selected by only a portion of the subject population. The development of an experimental paradigm that will permit positive identification of indi- vidual strategies is the t0pic of the next chapter. Chapter III Situation Structure, Cognitive Complexity, and Eachiavellianism as Determinants of Strategy Selection The Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) study was among the first to examine a set of systematically related coalition strategy hypotheses under alternative experimental conditions. Their use of two convention resource distributions (Type 2:8 <(A+W) A=w; Type 3:8 <Type 3) l/; for Condition 1, and pTVp€ 3:> pTVp8 2:. 1/2 for Condition III. Another marginal strategy is closely related to the Intracoalition Compatibility strategy hypothesis. This is the Competition hypothesis: . . '3 B3. Competition Subjects will seek to form coalitions that will allow maximum grounds for conflicts, that is, coalitions for which the payoff structure suggests no obvious division of the payoff. The Competitive hypothesis thus predicts behavior that is the complement of Compatibility behavior: pO‘DType 3 > p(w)Type 2 > 1/2 for Condition I, and pType 2 > pType 3 > 1/2 for Condition III. These two hypotheses are not independent, but are completely dependent. A single test will determine which of these two marginal strategies is a plausible explanation for non-maximization strategy choices. The final strategy hypothesis examined here is the Security hypothesis: B4. Security When the payoff to a coalition can be attained only with some probability less thin unity, subjects will seek to maxi- mize their chances of winning by forming the largest coalition possible. 3 - _ Tests of hypotheses A, 5 and 6 were shown to be dependent on the tests of hypotheses l, t and 3 in Chapter ll and have been omitted here. The original numbering system has been retained here to permit cross referencing. bl A comparison between probabilistic Condition II and non-probabilistic Condition 111 provides the data to test this hypothesis. The hypothesis predicts the following relation: p(W)Type 2> Murry},e 22 1/2 Condition III Condition II These tests constitute the examination of the theoretical hypotheses at the level of population behaviors, the level of behavior that has been observed in almost all previous studies of coalition formation. The next two sections of this chapter will deal with the comparability of the PDQ to interactive group games and the prediction of individual strategy choices. The PDQ and the Political Convention Came The comparability of the social contact data obtained with the PDQ to the contact data obtained from a group of subjects sitting in the same room choosing a potential partner is examined quite simply. The second strategy experiment was administered to another group of subjects. Exper- iment 11 consists of two parts; the first is a political convention game similar in content to the Type 2 distribution PDQ of Experiment I. The subjects choose a potential partner to bargain with, bargain and divide the payoff. The first choice of a potential partner provides the social contact data for the Type 2 triad. The second part of the experiment was a Type 3 PDQ. The payoff conditions were identical with those in Figure 4.1. A comparison of Subjects' choices in the Type 2 triad conventions of Experiments I and II examines the iSomorphism of the contact data of the PDQ and the interactive political convention paradigm experiment. Individual Differences and Individual Strategies An individual playing the two political convention games of Experiment I or II can make four possible rcSponses: Kw, RE, SW, and SE, that is, he 62 may choose the equal contender in the Type 2 triad and the weaker in the Type 3 triad, etc. The t er oi strategy selection presented above maps four mutually exclusive strategies onto these reSponse patterns. The mapping (Table 3.2) is a function of the divisibility of the payoff. By defining the strategies associated with specific choice patterns differ- ently for Condition I and for Conditions 11 and III, the divisibility variable is incorporated into the strategy definitions, rendering the strategies independent of the competitive environment. Each strategy pattern represents individual behavior consistent with the theory of strat- egy selection, regardless of the subject's experimental condition. These individual strategy choices can thus be predicted from individual differ- ence measures alone. Cognitive Complexity Harvey's (l96l) constructs of the four conceptual systems suggest patterns of strategy selection different from the patterns of social per- ception. The Maximization strategy selection pattern predicted is: Cl. System 11 and IV subjects will select more Maximization and fewer marginal strategies than System I and III Subjects. EXplicit predictions are also made (or the marginal strategies selected by each System. C2. A larger preportion of System I subjects will choose Security strategies than will choose any other marginal strategy. C3. A larger proportion of System 11 sukjects will choose Compe- titive strategies than will choose any other marginal strategy. C4. A larger prOportion of System III subjects will choose Intra— coalition Compatibility strategies than will choose any other marginal strategy. C5. System IV subjects will choose all three marginal strategies with equal frequency. Machiavellianism An orientation toward the exercise of power or toward competition leads to a maximization and a marginal strategy prediction: C6. The proportion of High Mach subjects who choose Maximization strategies will be larger than the proportion of Low Mach persons who choose Maximization strategies. C7a. A larger proportion of Low Mach subjects will choose Security strategies than will choose any other marginal strategy. C7b. A larger proportion of High Mach subjects will choose Com- petitive strategies than will choose any other marginal strategy. Method Subjects. Subjects for Experiment I were 226 male undergraduate social science and political science students who participated in classroom groups.4 Subjects for Experiment 11 were 243 male volunteers from introductory psycho- 10gy and political science courses. These volunteers participated in 1-4 hours of experiments for extra credit toward their class grade. Procedure Experiment I. Each subject took a questionnaire in a classroom situa- tion. The questionnaire included: (I) a brief statement of the American Psychological Association Code of Ethics relevant to individual difference and opinion measures; (2) a Type 2 PDQ; (3) a Mach V Scale revised for machine scoring;5 (4) Tuckman's ITI Scale, revised for machine scoring, and (5) a Type 3 PDQ. 4Two hundred-thirty females also took the questionnaire for Experiment I. Since female strategy behaviors have not been discussed in this study, these data will be analyzed at another time. 5The Mach V Scale is found on pp.121-l26 and the ITI is found on pp. 142 of Appendix E. The answer sheets for these two measures are also found in Appendix D. FORTRAN scoring subroutines are found in Appendix E. 64 Three payoff divisibility conditions were used in the PDQS. Condition I had an easily divisible payoff, 100 political jobs or patronage appointments. It is essentially the same as the easily divisible condition used by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation). The experimental induction is found in the PDQ of Appendix A. Condition 11 has a payoff which was divisible only unequally, the nomi- nations for the governor's and the lieutenant governor's places on the party ticket. This condition is also the same as Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) indivisible condition. Condition 11 may also be considered a probabilistic payoff condition, since some subjects will attend to the expectation of an impending election. An example of this condition is found in Appendix B. Condition Ill offered the same payoff as Condition 11, but explicitly discounts the importance of the impending general election by Specifying that the party holding the convention has been in control of state govern- ment for several years. Subjects are told that any candidate who secures the nomination is virtually assured of winning the general election. The text of the Condition Ill induction is found in Appendix C. Within each payoff condition, subjects received both a Type 2 and Type 3 PDQ. The resource distributions for the two PDQs have been selected so that the difference between the odd man and the other two is equal for both types. Two counterbalanced forms are used in each PDQ. The distri- bution for the Type 2 resource distribution is as follows: F igure 4 . '2 Type 2 Resource Distributions B C la 100 150 100 lb 113 124 113 23 113 124 113 2b 113 113 124 65 The distribution for the Type 3 triad is given in Figure 4.3. Figure 4.3 Type 3 Resource Distributions A B C 1a 134 134 82 1b 13 82 134 2a 120 120 110 2b 120 120 120 Subjects receive one PDQ of each form number; e.g., la, Type 2 and la, Type 3. Each form asks for the subject's first contact choice, the minimum bargaining share of the payoff he will accept, the reasons for his choice, what he expects the other faction leader to demand, and his estimate of his own bargaining ability. Since the length and quality of responses to these questions have been highly variable in the past, no explicit hypo- theses will be formulated at this point. Experiment 11. Subjects were told they would participate in a series of mock political conventions. They actually participated in two acti— vities, but only the first was an interactive convention. Each subject played in only one of the three payoff conditions in the convention. With- in each payoff condition, the labels assigned to the subjects were counter- balanced according to the following scheme: Figure 4.4 Counterbalance of Labels and Resource Values Subject Designation X Y 2 Resource (1) 150 100 100 Distribution (2) 100 150 100 Order (3) 100 100 150 66 Within each condition, seven triads were run in each of the three assign- ment orders. Twenty-seven triads comprised one experimental condition. The second activity consisted of a Type 3 PDQ and the Mach V Scale and Tuckman's (1964) ITI. The PDQ administered to the EXperiment 11 Subjects contains an in- struction to treat the factions in the PDQ as essentially different from and not identified with the people in the live experiment. The order of play in the political convention game was as follows: Instructions were read to the subjects.7 Subjects were randomly assigned to candidate positions. Subjects were asked for their written choices of contender with whom they wish to start negotiations. If two subjects made reciprocal choices, these two bargained (in the presence of the experimenter, but out of the presence of the third subject) for three minutes. The bargaining session was recorded but is not analyzed in this study. If an agreement was made, it was to be written and given to the experimenter. If no agreement was reached, the subjects were asked again to make choices. If no reciprocal choices were made, the subjects were also asked to choose again. After completing the questionnaire, subjects filled out the questionnaire described above. 6(me subject in each triad, the odd man, was lost because he had no meaningful choice. The number actually used was smaller than 54 in some cases because of subject errors. 7 The experimental instructions are found in Appendix F. Chapter V Results and Discussion The hypotheses presented in the previous chapters deal predominantly with marginal strategy choices. These are expected to be minor strategies, that under Specifiable circumstances account for a portion of coalition formation behavior. The hypotheses are relatively easy to test; most call only for comparisons among proportions. The conditional nature of the hypotheses, though, would pose a problem of interpretation if these were the only analyses performed. We would have no indication of the conditions under which individual difference measures predict strategy selection, the relationship between Subject's perceptions and strategy selection, or of any of the interaction effects among subsets of variables if only tests for differences were used. The principle dependent variable, strategy choice, is a nominal level measure. Thus, most interval level statistics are inappropriate for this dependent variable. Contingency tests, however, are applicable. The major analysis used here will be a factorial partition of a contingency table (Sdtcliffe, 1957). Since this method does not permit the use of an observation which has incomplete data, such as an unanswered question, the numbers used in the tables will decrease slightly as the number of levels in the factorial design increases. It will be possible to examine fairly complex interaction patterns, but most fourth level interactions will have many cells with expected values less than 5.0. To avoid the X2 estimation problems encountered in such cases, some variables will be collapsed into 67 68 a smaller number of categories. In most cases, only the collapsed tables for lower order interactions will be shown, since the entire table is generally too large to interpret visually. Popula t ion Behavior Comparison of the PDQ and the Political Convention Game. The most direct indication of the comparability of the PDQ social contact data with that of the political convention game is a test of the difference p(w)Experiment 1 ' p("Ulixperiment II for the Type 2 triad, the resource distribution for which administration conditions differ. Table 5.1 presents the results of this test. The observed differences were not statistically significant under any payoff condition. Another indication of the comparability of the PDQ and the political convention game is provided by a comparison of the distribution of strategies selected in Experiment 1 with those selected in ExPeriment II. Table 5.2 gives these distributions for the three payoff conditions. The Group X strategy effect is clearly significant, indicating that subjects in the two experiments did not select identical distributions of strategies. The Condition X strategy effect is also significant, but the Group X Condition X Strategy effect is not. The payoff condition, then, does affect the strategy distribution, but has no significant differential effect on the two experimental groups. The inconsistency between the Croup X Strategy effect in Table 5.2 and the lack of effect in Table 5.1 indicates that the two experiments elicited different distributions of individual strategies. These differ- ences in individual strategies are masked in the population statistic p(W). 69 Table 5.1 Tests of the differences between p(W). , and P(W) hxperiment 1 , for the Tv a 2 Resource Distribution. hxperiment II ‘ -p“ 5 Condition p(W) p(W) Difference Pooled df t Experiment I EXperiment ll Sp 1 .797 .722 .075 .0747 93 1.00 * II .711 .588 .121 .0628 115 1.92 111 .605 .500 .105 .0621 117 1.69 k .05:p_<_ l0 70 Table 5.2 Strategy selected as a function of group and payoff condition Strategy Type Group Condition 1 2 3 4 Maximization Competition Security Compatibility Experiment I 1 38 6 6 9 II 52 7 12 12 III 45 4 13 19 EXperiment II I 21 7 3 5 II 19 1 2 11 Ill 17 2 l 18 1 r a a w . . . a Group X Condition X Strategy Factorial Contingency Ana1y81s 2 Effect X df p A Group Fixed 0 B Condition Fixed 0 C Strategy Fixed 0 AxB 2.15 2 ns AxC 11.53 3 5 .01 BxC 13.53 6 5 .05 AxBxC 9.08 6 .25< p: .10 Total 36.34 17 < .005 8The method of computation is from Sutcliffe (1957). Lawton (1968) programmed the analysis routine. 71 B1. Max1mization: The Maximization hypothesis asserts that p(W) will be greater than 1/2 for all experimental conditions. The observed value of p(W) is pre- sented, for each experimental condition, in Table 5.2. The .95 confidence interval has been computed for each point. Table 5.3 indicates that three experimental conditions have .95 confidence intervals that include the point p(W) = .50. In Experiment I, Condition III, the lower bound of is .498; in Experiment ll, Conditions II and III, the lower bounds of pType 2 are .416 and .334, reSpectively. In all other con- ditions, the lower bounds of the confidence region exclude p(W) = .50. Thus the Maximization hypothesis is supported in all easily divisible Condition I groups and all unequally divisible Condition II groups except for the Type 2 triad in Experiment II. Maximization is supported in the Type 3 triads of both Experiment I and II in Condition III, but is not supported in either Type 2 or Type 3 triads in Condition III. B2. Intracoalition Compatibility: The Compatibility hypothesis predicts that p(w)l‘ype 3 : p("DType 2 1/2 in Condition 1, and pType 3 , P(W)Type 2 1/2 in Condition III. Table 5.4 presents tests of the difference p(W)Type 3 - p(W)Type 2 for payoff Conditions I and III in Experiments 1 and II. There are no significant differences in Condition I of either experiment, as predicted by the Compatibility hypothesis. The differences in Condition III are significant for both experiments, again in accord with the Compatibility hypothesis. 72 .uouuo wawvasou can uwumaumum u mamamm Hausa ou one ecumsaumouu>on .oom. deuce use muesaoea unwoa menu you ~m>houaH mofievamdoo mm. 058 m noao.a Nam. mmeo. Ham. poao.a omm. cmao. m~a. mam. has. mace. was. mass .HHH .axm mm am on com. memm. Name. cow. ooh. mode. «awe. wwm. «mm. cum. memo. «mm. maze .HH .axm 0mm. go“. quo. ooh. New. owe. moqo. an“. wmm. «no. memo. man; came .H .axm Hm mm mm was. mama. demo. moo. mom. mac. oaao. Han. oom. ace. ammo. mom. oa>e .H .axm venom venom venom page - venom venom noun: neaoa a Home: ~03 a Home: HoBQA a IIIIIL a 2:335 m z 9: 3535 m 2 96¢ Jaime: m z Azj _ moaopwmcoo eocenamcou oucopfiueoo esoouso awmuumo ofinwmw>ua maamsvmcs HHH :Oauwvcoo eeoouso :kuumona manama>aa saamsame: HH coauaeeoo manama>ao magnum H coauaeaoo pmwua mo make new uCeEwuwmxm meoauaeeoo «Cosme pmwuu mo memo cam usesfiuoaxo .aofluflvcoo wwozma mp mam>hmuaw mocovwwcoo Nmm so“: A3Va m.m essay 73 .emwsuonuo o .3 ma moaono m mama m.x ma H u .xx x mom .omw3uonuo o .3 ma mowono N mama m.x oomnnsm «H H I «xx paw m Anxxuaxxv w n e mecca . e u u a a .I _I So; as. ammm.¢ mm mmm. Hma. summ.m am cam. awn. Nun. cm can. omo. HH .axm *Nam.m Hm mmm. me. qu.H mm mum. coo. Nam.ou mm 0mm. fine. a H .axm unfit du z um> Na3vanmA3va «mac au 2 um> NA3vaumA3va wmwc ea 2 Hm> NA3valma3va .ucmafiumaxm mEOUUso samuumo osoouao cwmunmoca waHmH>fia Adawsvoc: oabwma>aa xafimsamc: manflmfl>wo maammm cofiufiecoo HHH :oHqucoo HH coauaeeoo H coauaeeoo muchmm coauaeeoo uuosam cowufiecoo muchma cam uaosHuoaxo an N enhemzva u m mamHflzva a.m magma 74 The Competition hypothesis predicts that PW) p(W) 1/2 Type 3 > Type 2 > for Condition 1, and p (W) (W) Type 2 > p Type 3 > 1/2 for Condition III. Since this prediction contradicts the prediction of the Compatibility hypo- thesis, which received strong support, the Competition hypothesis must be rejected as an explanation of marginal strategy choice. Conditions I and II provide a test of the Compatibility hypothesis designed to replicate the conditions of the Nitz and Phillips study (in preparation). Table 5.4 indicates that the critical difference Type Type 2 is significant for eXperiment II, the interactive group game, but is not significant for Experiment I, which most closely replicates Nitz and Phillips (in preparation). Thus, the Intracoalition Compatibility hypothesis has received strong support, but not under Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) origional conditions. B3. Security An alternate interpretation of the finding Nitz and Phillips' (in preparation) interpreted as a compatibility effect is that the effect they observed was in part the result of a form of Security strategy played by subjects in the Type 2 triad who sought to build a larger coalition in the face of an uncertain outcome. A test of the plausibility of this interpretation of the operation of a Security strategy is found in the difference between the effects observed in Condition II and those observed in Condition III. If the quantity - p(W)Type 2)Condition II - (p(W) - p(W) e 2)Condition III (p (W)Type 3 Type 3 Typ 75 is positive, the difference identifies the pr0portion of the Intracoalition Compatibility effect observed by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) that can be explained as a function of Security strategy choices. If the differ- ence is zero or negative, it suggests that subjects in Conditions II do not perceive a greater value in minimizing conflict within the coalition than the subjects in Condition III. Table 5.5 indicates that there are no signi- ficant differences between the Compatibility effect observed in Condition II and that observed in Condition III. The differences observed (t - -l.57 p.i .13 and t = -.53, p >.50, EXperiments I and II, reSpectively) are negative, and do not support the Security hypothesis. ‘_£ediction of Individual Behaviors Behaviorgpredicted from cognitive complexity. The subjects perception of their Opponent's payoff expectations were obtained as written answers to the question, "what do you expect the other faction leader to demand?" These answers were coded into one of three classifications: (a) The opponent would demand less than 1/2 of the payoff. (b) The opponent would demand 1/2 of the payoff. (c) The opponent would demand more than 1/2 of the payoff. Category b also included several answers that opponents would demand some- thing in a range of outcomes, such as 40-60%. The cognitive complexity measures were scored according to Tuckman's (1964) recommended procedure: A subject was classified into the category in which he scored above the 75 percentile, provided he scored lower in all other categories. If a subject scored at or above the 75th percentile in more than one category, or below the 75th percentile in all categories, he was classified into category 0. Category 0 subjects were not used in analyses which used complexity as an independent variable. 76 Amzv M On. A M mm. . mo moa. moo.- Mme. eNm. HH .oxm M Amzv n ma. em.a- Nos eoeo. mNH.- mma. ooo. H .oxm Anoaaoo NV W so i HHH eoaoaoeoo Ha eoaoaoooo a H o up oocmpoMWHQ unmawuoaxm wOO . s a n Nisan - Mason Nixon - mason unmaauoaxo up HHH noaoaoooo HH ooaoaoeoo mam max duh oak N e Axon- m sxzvni MN aAsvou n aflzvo_ m.m oases 77 The distribution of cognitive complexity categories, perceptions, and strategies chosen is given in Tables 5.6 and 5.7. Table 5.6 presents subject's perceptions on their first (Type 2 triad) choice and Table 5.7 represents their perceptions on the second (Type 3 triad) choices. Cogni- tive complexity appears to be unrelated to strategy choice or to perception of the opponent's expectations in either political convention game. The only effect that approaches significance is the interaction between com- plexity, perception in the second game (Type 3 triad) and strategy choice. Hypothesis Cl. predicts that cognitively complex System III and IV persons will choose a greater preportion of Maximization strategies than will cognitively simple System I and 11 persons. Tables 5.6 and 5.7 pre- sent data relevant to this hypothesis. There is no difference in the proportion of Maximization strategies selected by the complexity groups (X23df = 5.65, .25 >p>.10). Moreover, controlling for perception of opponent's expected demands does not render a significant Complexity X Strategy effect. Table 5.7 suggests, though, that there may be differences in strategy as a function of Complexity and Perception or differences in perception in the Type 3 game as a function of Complexity and Strategy in the preceding_(Type 2) game. The complexity X Perception in the second (Type 3) game X Strategy effect approaches significance (Xzédf = 11.39, .10:>p:>.05). Table 5.8 indicates the source of the effect observed above. The data here are those of Table 5.7 collapsed over complexity Systems I and IIIv. II and IV. The perception information in this table comes from the subject's second game which had a Type 3 resource distribution. There is no signi- ficant difference here in the perceptions of the two complexity groups (x22df = .588, ns). Of those who perceive the opponent's payoff demand to be less than half of the total payoff, four times as many System II and IV subjects select a Maximization strategy as choose a Marginal strategy. 78 Table 5.6 Strategy choice by perception in the Type 2 convention by cognitive complexity Cognitive Perception Strategy, Choice of Opponent's Complexity, Demands Maximization Marginal System I < 1/2 17 18 2 1/2 5 9 > 1/2 20 9 System II < l/2 18 5 2 1/2 4 4 > 1/2 14 8 System III < 1/2 3 6 Z l/2 3 3 > 1/2 5 4 System IV < 1/2 13 8 I 1/2 9 3 > l/2 9 4 Factorial Anal sis for Strategy Choice x Perception x Cognitive Complexity 2 Effect X df p A Cognitive Complexity Fixed 0 B Perception .1 Fixed 0 C Strategy Fixed 0 AB 3.47 6 ns AC 5.65 3 .25 >p >.10 BC 2.08 2 ns ABC 6.39 6 ns Total 17.61 18 ns 79 Table 5.7 Strategy choice by perception in the Type 3 convention by cognitive complexity ———--“_. Cognitive Perception Strategy Choice of Opponent's Complexity Demands Maximization Marginal System I < 1/2 18 22 I 1/2 15 8 > 1/2 9 6 System II < 1/2 24 6 I 1/2 10 6 > 1/2 2 5 System III < 1/2 4 7 2 1/2 6 5 > 1/2 1 1 System IV < 1/2 20 6 I 1/2 6 6 > 1/2 5 3 Factorial Analysis for Strategy Choice x Perception x Cognitive Complexity Effect _§__ _£§;_ __2__' A ,Cognitive Complexity Fixed 0 B Perception 2 Fixed 0 C Strategy Choice Fixed 0 AB 4.36 6 ns AC 5.65 3 .25 >p >.1O BC .75 2 ns ABC 11.39 6 .10 {p >.05 Total 22.15 18 ns 80 Table 5.8 Strategy choice by perception in the Type 3 convention by cognitive complexity categories I + 111 v. II + IV Cognitive Perception of , . . Strategy Ch01ce Complex1ty Opponent S Maximization Mar i a1 System Demands ' g n I + III (4% 22 27 *% 21 13 >% 10 7 II + IV < % 44 11 I l6 13 :>% 7 9 Factorial Analysis of Strategy Choice x Perception in Type 3 Triad x Complexity Category I + III v. II + IV Effect x2 df p A Complexity Fixed Effect 0 B Perception Fixed Effect 0 C Strategy Choice Fixed Effect 0 AB .558 2 ns AC 4.736 1 <.05 BC 1.223 2 ns ABC 11.392 2 <.OOS Total 17.909 7 <.025 81 The System I and III subjects who see the opponent as demanding less than half of the payoff chose Maximization strategies less often than they chose marginal strategies. Hypotheses C2. through C5. predict specific marginal strategies for each of the conceptual system types. Each hypothesis assumes as its null hypothesis that each marginal strategy will be chosen with equal probability. Table 5.9 presents the observed marginal strategy choices for each con- ceptual system along with the test of the deviation of the observed distri- bution from that predicted by the null hypothesis. Hypothesis C2. predicts that System I subjects will choose more Security than any other marginal strategy. The observed strategies for System I per- sons differ from the null hypothesis slightly (X2 = 4.75; p‘: .10), but 2df this difference is in the wrong direction. The Security strategy is not the most frequently chosen. Hypothesis C2. thus lacks support. Hypothesis C3. predicts that System II subjects will tend to choose Competitive strategies. The observed distribution is significantly differ- ent (X22df = 18.0; p < .001) from the null distribution, but in the opposite direction from that predicted by C3. Hypothesis C3 is thereby disconfirmed. Hypothesis C4. predicts that System 111 persons will select more Com- patibility strategies than any other marginal strategy. Table 5.11 indicates that this prediction is confirmed (X22df = 6.71, p < .05). Hypothesis C5. predicts that System IV subjects will select all three marginal strategies with equal probability. Since this prediction is equiv- alent to the null hypothesis, a goodness-of-fit test rather than an indepen- dence test is required. The observed distribution fits the prediction of the null hypothesis moderately well (.90:> p > .75). Table 5.9 Frequency of marginal strategy choices for four cognitive complexity categories Complexity , System Strategy Ch01ce Competition Security Compatibility 1 6 10 16 II 1 4 16 III 5 3 12 IV 6 4 ' 4 Contingency Tests Against the Null Hypothesis p(Sl) = p(Sz) = p(S3) 2 Confirmation Complexity X df p of System Hypothesis I 4.75 2 .10) p) .05 NO 11 18.00 2 <.001 Opposite Direction III 6.71 2 <.05 Yes IV .43 2 .90 >p> .75 Yes Total 29.89 Strategy Main Effect 18.83 2 <.001 Overall Com- plexity x Strategy 11.06 6 .10> p> .05 a J'll-CI W 83 Only one of the four marginal strategy hypothesis received support here. The overall Complexity X Strategy effect is given by partitioning the data of Table 5.9 to remove the main effect for Strategy. The Come plexity X Strategy effect approaches significance (X26df = 11.06; .10 > p > .05). Behavior Predicted from Machiavellianism Scores Hypothesis C6. predicts that High Mach subjects will choose a larger F‘ proportion of Maximization strategies than will Low Mach subjects. Table 5.10 presents strategy selections by cognitive complexity groups and High- . Low Mach score groups. Machiaevellianism is not significantly related to selection of Maximization or Marginal strategies (ledf = 1.26, ns). This finding disconfirms hypothesis C6. Nor is Machiavellianism related to cognitive complexity (X23df = 4.90; .257’ p>'.lO). The interaction of Machiavellianism, complexity and strategy choice is in the predicted direc- tion but is not significant (X23df = 1.01, ns). The total effect in Table 5.10 is not significant (leodf = 12.83; .25 > p >.10). Hypotheses C7a. and C7b. predict that High Machs will tend to prefer Competitive Marginal strategies. Table 5.11 presents the distribution of marginal strategy choices by Machiavellianism groups. High and Low Mach subjects do not differ in their preferences among the marginal strategies (x22df = .512; ns). Hypotheses C78. and C7b. are not supported by these data. The data in Tables 5.10 and 5.11 indicate no differential strategy choices attributable to Machiavellianism. The studies by Geis (1963), Geis, Christie and Nelson (1963), and Blumstein and Weinstein (1967) though, lead us to expect High Machs to behave differently from Low Machs in com- petitive situations. The finding above raises two questions about the 84 Table 5.10 Strategy choice by cognitive complexity and Machiavellianism scores Strategy Choice Complexity Mach Maximization Marginal System I Lo 23 22 Hi l9 14 11 Lo 13 8 Hi 23 9 111 L0 5 5 #1 Hi 6 8 IV Lo 13 8 Hi 18 7 . Factorial Analysis of Strategy Choice x Complexity x Machiavellianism. 2 Effect X df p A Complexity Fixed Effect 0 8 ' B Machiavellianism Fixed Effect 0 C Strategy Choice Fixed Effect 0 AB 4.90 3 .25>;)>.10 AC 5.65 3 .25 >p >.10 BC 1.26 1 ns ABC 1.01 3 ns Total 12.83 10 .25 >p >.lO Table 5.11 Marginal Strategy Choices by Machiavellianism score group Strategy Choice Machiavellianism Competition Security Compatibility Lo 16 17 34 Hi 10 15 29 X = .512 df ll N I'lS 85 nature of Machiavellianism. First, does the construct measured by the Mach V scale identify an ability to select appropriate abstract strategies or does it identify a nonstrategic ability to deal with others only in close interpersonal situations? Second, does dichotomizing the Mach V scale scores or does the operation of summing the item scores mask the dimensions of the scale that predict behavior most effectively? These questions can be answered with an additional multivariate analysis. If it is possible to predict strategy choices in these data from some weighted combination of Mach item scores, then it will be clear that the Mach scale can predict abstract strategy choices. If a differ- ent prediction equation is necessary for each of the four strategies, however, the utility and appropriateness of summing the item scores and assuming a unidimensional scale must be questioned. The UCLA BMD program for stepwise multiple discriminant analysis provides a simple means for making these tests (Dixon, 1967). Table 5.12 presents the means and standard deviations of the Mach V items for each strategy type. The analysis program fits a linear regres- sion equation to each of the strategy categories in such a way that the function constructed maximizes the discrimination of subjects falling into each category. The program adds one predictor variable (Mach item) to the regression equations on each iteration, always selecting that item on which the mean item score across strategies differs most. During the addition process the effects of the variables previously added to the prediction equations are partialled out. The resulting discriminant function weights for 20 predictor variables are presented in Table 5.13. Each function is of the form Strategy(j) : a.qxj2 + ... + . 4.. r O . ajO + ajlle . J“ ameJm “A .001). An indication of the nature of the ”Machiavellianism” underlying each of the strategies can be seen by examining the items on which the strategies differ most markedly. Table 5.18 summarizes a series of tests which identify (r (I Table 5.13 Linear function discriminating four strategy types on the basis of 20 Mach V item scores Linear Coefficients for Each Strategy Type I II 111 IV Mach Item No. Maximization Competition Security Compatibility 1 1.87703 1.95503 0.99802 1.26568 2 1.44775 2.22581 1.59916 1.25567 3 2.12372 2.94689 1.08141 2.10734 4 0.79066 1.86258 0.72249 0.91590 5 0 98275 0.59006 1.15272 0.51356 6 1.54095 1.23982 1.00355 1.75744 7 1.00361 0.01019 1.21310 0.91430 8 1.37535 1.14201 0.91424 0.70363 9 1.92810 0.86398 1.77829 1.18258 10 1.06840 1.49766 1.40395 1.33324 11 1.53996 1.73637 2.42302 2.16943 12 2.87590 2.82723 2.86919 3.05498 13 2.16363 2.12922 2.27833 2.51544 14 1.00424 0.55182 1.28434 1.29258 15 1.29153 1.89076 1.23761 1.48925 16 -0.42412 -1.39225 -0.14017 -0.82861 17 10.45706 11.45313 10.84952 10.51994 18 1.62254 0.85477 1.33652 1.82874 19 3.23176 3.35551 3.09557 3.20752 20 2.24840 1.95887 1.60844 2.45587 Constant -13.25240 -l4.06542 -12.75385 -l3.52576 89 Table 5.14 Number of Subjects classified into strategy groups on the basis of Mach V scores on 20 items Predicted Strategy Group Observed I II III IV Strategy Maximization Competition Security Compatibility Group Maximization 76 41 38 35 Competition 3 18 2 4 Security 6 3 19 8 Compatibility 8 20 19 29 2 x 9df = 73.09 p< .001 90 OH. ca. m0. mo. 25. as. ”o. Ho. #0. Ho. Ho. so. Mo. 2c. #3. so. Ho. Ho. no. 0H. qmm 0H3 ram Amy mm: mmo 0mm wma mm: mmo mmo owa nmm 0H0 n00 owm mmw cwm was mmm .oe .Nm .qm .am .mq .ma .Na qfim. .OM .mm .on .am .am .sm .ma .ma .Na .0 .o .m Eopeoum WC moepmoo U a:3«ucEax0pagm~n~ m to. cg. mm.m Om.m wM.N aq.N nm.m f\ o A‘OJNI—‘HHHI—‘i—Jy—‘l—‘HHH-fl Emuwoua osmcfiefiuomfln an maeum mo eapmu unmeasm Hmwm.o cmwm.o ewwm.o mmmm.o moom.o waow.o mNow.O wman.o mflmw.o qo«w.o mmmm.o noqx.o chm.o ofimm.o acmw.o omom.o ~®H©.o mom©.o ammm.o Nam©.o sa.mxaa2 .AwoaHV axooum cam cease can Aaoaav coxao umuuau .pmuouce xawsofl>oua meabmfipm> ecu Se>fiw .eeuomaem oHanuo> ecu mo :oHusnfluumflp Hmcowowpcoo ecu mo .masouw xwmumuum use“ “Hm uw>o .moflamsvo wo momma oflomu woonflaexfla ego mum emmzan .peuooce :moo uo: m>m£ once emozu mo msfim> m umecwwz ecu Lows manmfium> ecu pause cu uem coflueufluom WC WC m5 m5 WC m5 II. mm. mm. mm. mm. OH. OH. OH. Eocovum mo mmepmea n nannana menmfi-Ommfiméefirnmmmmmmmm A h a H A a a H G I a I mooo.o HHM~.0 mmw¢.o wamm.o quo.o odom.o Acmm.o qoqa.o OHNH.H wmwa.fi noom.H mo~¢.~ Rcwo.a mxwm.H maoc.m wmfim.a mwao.w weqa.m wOm¢.N qawm.m ueocm ou oaam> e mH.m waan tn~7<31\lwcurw HH—‘r—c—I—a—l N 00 m \o N v—4 r-fi imrmr\.4sa'n~o.q'3 F4 peueucm manmflno> ponesz amum 91 Table 5.16 Number of subjects classified into strategy groups on the basis of Mach V scores on eight most discriminating items Predicted Strategy Group Observed I II III IV Strategy Maximization Competition Security Compatibility Group Maximization 68 43 45 34 Competition 3 l6 2 6 Security 7 l 19 7 Compatibility ll 19 21 25 X29df = 49.88 p< .001 Table 5.17 Number of subjects classified into strategy groups on the basis of Mach V scores on four most discriminating items Predicted Strategy Group Observed 1 11 III IV Strategy Maximization Competition Security Compatibility Group Maximization 66 53 '48 23 Competition 6 17 3 1 Security 8 7 16 5 Compatibility 19 30 15 12 ngdf = 27.86 .005. p> .001 Table 5.18 Items for which the means of the distrigugions of Mach V item scores differ across groups ’ Strategy Type Maximization Competition Security Competition 9,3,7,16,4,20,2,18, 5,6,15,10,17,13,12 3.7.1.16,4,20,2, Security 8,11,16,20 18,5,6,15,17, 13,12,19 Compatibility 9,8 None None 8This table represents those sets of k items for which the sum of Euclidean distances between strategy groups on items included was significantly different from zero. (p = .05: Actual F and df vary as the number of items increases.) Items listed in order of decreasing variance explained. \I 1 Table 5.19 identifies the strategies each Mach V item differentiates. the keyed Mach V items represented by the item numbers in the discussion that follows. Because of the number of items involved that discriminate with relatively low probability, only the first four in each cell will be discussed here. Competitive subjects were less likely than Maximizing subjects to view flattery as a useful tactic (9), more likely to tell real reasons only if they are useful (3), less likely to give real reasons for asking a favor (7), less likely to feel honesty is always the best policy (16), and more likely to believe that the best way to handle people is to tell them what they want to hear (4). Subjects who chose Security strategies differed from Maximizing sub- jects as follows: Security subjects are more concerned about morally right action (8), humility and honesty (11), honesty as the best policy (16), and believe in trusting others (20). Subjects who made Compatibility choices differ from Maximizing subjects by feeling flattery an inappropriate tactic (9), and are more concerned about morally right action (8). 1The test is based on the statistic: F = (n-g-r+1) nm “k r _. _ mk \. it (ami - aki) (xm - Xk) r(n-g)(nm+nk) i=1 df = r, r, n-g-r+l where = number of groups n = number of subjects nm= number of subjects in group m r = number of variables included at time of test 10. ll. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. Table 5.19 Keyed items from the Mach V scale Most men forget more easily the death of their father than the loss of their property. People suffering from incurable diseases should have the choice of being put painlessly to death. Never tell anyone the real reason you did something unless it is useful to do so. The best way to handle people is to tell them what they want to hear. Most people are basically good and kind. Most people who get ahead in the‘world lead clean, moral lives. When you ask someone to do something for you, it is best to give him the real reasons for wanting it rather than giving reasons which might carry more weight. One should take action only when sure that it is morally right. It is wise to flatter important people. The biggest difference between most criminals and other people is that criminals are stupid enough to get caught. All in all, it is better to be humble and honest than to be impor- tant and dishonest. There is no excuse for lying to someone else. Generally Speaking, men won't work hard unless they are forced to. Most men are brave. It is hard to get ahead without cutting corners here and there. Honesty is the best policy in all cases. It is possible to be good in all respects. Barnum was probably right when he said that there's at least one sucker born every minute. It is safest to assume that all people have a vicious streak and it will come out when they are given a chance. Anyone who completely trusts anyone else is asking for trouble. Indicates a Machiavellian item. Indicates a reversed item. Finally, the competitive subject can be distinguished from the Security strategy subjects by their preferences for never telling the real reasons for actions unless useful (3), for giving reasons that carry more weight than the real reasons (7), their beliefs that most men value their prOperty more than the death of their father (1), that honesty is not always the best policy (16), and that the best way to handle peeple is to tell them what they want to hear (4). The preceding analysis of the relationship of the Mach V items to the strategy patterns defined in Chapters 11 and Ill Suggests that Machi- avellianism is not a useful concept so long as it is thought of as a unitary scale. If the items that predict Specific strategies are iso- lated, however, distinct subsets of items effectively discriminate be- tween alternative behaviors even when these behaviors are highly abstract strategy choices. Chapter VI Summary and Implications The major objective of this study was to examine the effects of one of the conditions of nontransferable utility, namely indivisible payoffs, on coalition formation strategies selected in a mixed motive game. Two distinct analytical approaches were used. The first probed for evidence of consistent social contact strategies across the population of subjects as a function of experimental manipulation of divisibility and certainty of payoff. The second examined individual social contact strategy patterns and sought to predict them on the basis of individual difference measures that could be eXpected to have a bearing on strategic behavior. In addition, two different experimental measures were designed to identify social con- tact strategies, the Political Decision Questionnaire and an interactive political convention game. Differences between these two measures suggest an important consideration for future strategy research. Payoff Conditions as Determinants of Strategy Selection The analysis of social contact strategies in the subject population provided support for the Maximization and the Intracoalition Compatibility hypotheses: Under all conditions of payoff the most frequently chosen strategy is a maximization strategy; but under conditions of indivisible payoff, deviations from the Vaximization strategy can best be attributed to a strategy that seeks to reduce conflict within the coalition about to be formed. Intracoalition Compatibility, however, was not supported in all eXperimental conditions. In a condition that replicated Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) identification of the Compatibility strategy, support was lacking. 96 97 This condition, the indivisible uncertain Condition II in Experi- ment I differed from the corresponding condition in the Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) study in one major reSpect: both Type 2 and Type 3 choices were obtained from each subject in this study. Although the two PDQ forms were separated by about 20 pages of questionnaire, the value of Pearson's contingency coefficient for the two PDQ choices in Experi- ment I is a = .41 (X2=35.18, p <.001). The degree of association between the Type 2 and Type 3 contact choices in Experiment II is insignificant (X2=.1O, ns). This lack of independence would account for the reduced effects in the Experiment I PDQ. The experimental manipulation of certainty of the payoff did not induce security strategies in either experimental pOpulation. Moreover, the fact that p(W) 3-p(W) is larger for the indivisible certain Type Type 2 Condition III than for the indivisible uncertain Condition II in both experiments suggests that the Intracoalition Compatibility strategy iden- tified by Nitz and Phillips (in preparation) is the result of the relative indivisibility of the payoff rather than the uncertainty of obtaining it. The fact that the differences observed in Table 6.4 are in the opposite direction from a Security prediction suggests that the indivisible-uncertain Condition II subjects may not have attended to the uncertainty cues in the experimental inductions. An analysis of the comparability of two means of assessing social contact strategies identifies a critical shortcoming of coalition strategy research that has relied on pepulation statistics to test strategy hypo- theses. A test of the difference[ p(W)EXp I - p(W)EXp II] for all three experimental payoff conditions and both resource distributions yields no 98 significant differences between p(W)s in the two experiments for corre- sponding conditions. A factorial analysis of the individual strategy distribution across experiments and payoff conditions indicates a strong Experiment X Strategy effect and a strong Payoff Condition X Strategy effect. There is no significant three-way interaction. It is clear that by defining strategies based on multiple bits of information for individual subjects it is possible to detect effects due to experimental presentation and payoff conditions. These results suggest that the results of a whole series of studies notably, Riker (1967), Gamson (1961b), Vinacke and Arkoff (1957), Vinacke (1959), Vinacke, Crowell, Dien, and Young (1966), and others may be suSpect--since they aggregate behavior over games and subjects. This study finds that simple aggregation across subjects (without adding together non-independent successive games) masks significant behaviors. Moreover, the behaviors that are masked are the Marginal Security and Compatibility Strategies. Table 5.2 indicates that Security strategies appeared only in the indivisible conditions of the PDQ, and were chosen as frequently as Compatibility strategies, but marginal strategies were chosen only half as often as Maximization strat- egies. In indivisible Conditions II and III of the interactive game, however, Security strategies do not appear, but Compatibility, alone accounts for about half of all strategies chosen. The above observations suggest that an essential element in the study of strategic behavior is a highly cautious approach to the possibilities of confounding effects. Identification of individual strategies as joint behavior on separate critical tasks, conditional on experimental manipulation of the payoff permitted positive identification of the Intracoalition Com- patibility hypothesis as a descriptor of a meaningful strategy elicited by 99 a condition of nontransferable utility, i.e., indivisible payoff. Were the identity of the experimental tasks neglected, the joint aspect of the subjects' behavior would be lost and so would be the opportunity to crit- ically test any hypothesis about the individual's strategy behavior other than Maximization. In light of this consideration, it seems crucial to ask whether the study of exclusively divisible payoffs, i.e., transferable utility situations may do more to hinder the development of political theory than to facilitate it. Certrainly Maximization cannot be taken on apriori grounds as the only viable political strategy. Individual Differences as Determinants of Strategy Selection Cognitive Complexity. The major complexity hypothesis predicts that cognitively simple System I and II persons will choose fewer Maximization strategies than cognitively complex System 111 and IV persons. This hypo- thesis was disconfirmed. The combinations of categories I + III and II + IV, however, do select the strategies predicted for cognitively simple and cognitively complex persons, respectively. An even stronger effect is found in the interaction among complexity, perception of the opponent's demands in the second game, and strategy choice. System II and IV persons select more Maximization strategies than do System I and 111 subjects; but the System II and IV subjects who do so are those who perceive their oppo- nents as likely to demand less than half of the payoff (See Table 5.8). This effect cannot be attributed to the interaction between complexity and perception, since that effect is minute (x22df = .558gns). The two com- plexity groups, then do not perceive the situation differently, but act differently given equivalent perceptions. An alternative explanation of this effect can be prOposed. Since ‘the perception measures were taken after the subject made his strategy lOO choice, they could be a result of his choice rather than a cause. More- over, the greatest Perception X Complexity interaction effect occurs in the second game played. This interpretation cannot be dismissed on the basis of these data. The effect observed here suggests that it may be fruitful to design a study that controls for the reactive effect of social perception questions on subsequent strategy choices and of strategy choices on subsequent perceptions. The marginal strategy hypotheses for cognitive complexity received at best only Spotty support. Hypothesis C4 predicted that System III persons would select more Compatibility strategies than any other marginal strategy. The test against the null hypothesis indicates that they did so (XZde = 6.71; p< .05), but the Complexity by strategy interaction over the entire marginal strategy table (Table 6.10) was not significant (x26df = 11.06; .lO> p> .5). The distribution of strategies for System 111 persons is thus not significantly different from the distributions for the other three systems. In light of this observation and in light of the fact that the reverse ordering of the System 11 prediction is highly significant (X2 = 18.0; p< .001), it seems reasonable to reject 2df this entire set of marginal strategy hypotheses. 0f the five conceptual systems theory predictions, only a post hoc hypothesis predicting Maximization strategies for System II and IV persons was strongly supported. These two pairs of systems that show the most nearly equivalent strategy selection behavior, though, are not closely ordered in level of complexity to Harvey's (1961, 1963) theoretical con- structs of cognitive complexity. Systems I + III and II + IV do not differ in the distribution of their perceptions of their opponents but 101 they differ in the way these perceptions are related to strategy selection. This behavior cannot be attributed to a greater or lesser degree of ab— stract abilities within the context of conceptual systems theory. This observation suggests that conceptual systems theory should be revised, since the predictions we can make in the political convention paradigm are not related to the presumed level of complexity or abstract- ness of the four Systems. The conceptual system theorist, though, might challenge this conclusion by citing an important construct in his theo- retical framework. The basic conceptual ability that is the referent of the concept of cognitive complexity is the ability to deal with large amounts of information. That is, to be cognitively complex is to be able to work effectively under an information overload or in a complex environ- ment. The political convention paradigm used here could be described as an information underloaded or simple environment. The conceptual system theorist does not expect cognitive complexity to predict differential behavior in an environment that does not overload even the most concept- ually simple subject. This sort of argument does not clarify the ambi- guities we have noted in the concept of complexity. We have observed differential behavior in a simple environment, and we have predicted this behavior on the basis of a measure of cognitive complexity. If cognitive complexity predicts differential behavior only under information overload conditions, then what we have measured must not be the cognitive com- plexity originally intended. If we have measured cognitive complexity, then information overload must not be necessary for the prediction of individual behaviors from complexity information. One suggestion as to what Tuckman's (1965) Interpersonal Topical Inventory may have measured is provided by Harvey's (1966) review of 102 complexity studies. Harvey (1966) notes that System 11 and IV persons tend to score low on the EPPS Deference subscale and high on the Autonomy subscales. Moreover, System 115 score high on Aggression. System I persons were high on EPPS Deference, and low on Change and Autonomy. System III persons were high on Affiliation and also low on Autonomy and Change. Not only do System I and III persons choose fewer Maximization and more Marginal (predominantly Security and Compatibility) strategies than System II and IV persons, but they achieve similar scores on measures of affiliation, deference and autonomy. It would be reasonable to hypothesize that Tuckman's ITI provides a measure comparable to certain subscales of the EPPS. These considerations confront the student of political strategy with a major problem in the study of cognitive behavior. How does one identify patterns of cognition? How does one select a measure of these patterns appropriate to the behavior he wishes to predict? In the long run it would be fruitful to replicate Vannoy's (1965) study of the comparability of cognitive complexity measures, but to replicate it with a primary focus on identifying patterns of perceiving competitive situations and patterns of strategy selection. In the short run, though, the problems raised in this report suggest a project of narrower scope: a discriminate function analysis of ITI items as predictors of strategy patterns. Machiavellianism. Hypotheses C6 and C7 predict that High Machs will select Maximization strategies more often than Low Machs, and that the High Machs will tend to select Competition strategies when they do select uarginal strategies, while Low Machs will tend to select Security strategies. Both of these hypotheses were disconfirmed. The possibility that the Mach Scale might contain subscales which predicted specific strategies led to 103 a discriminant function analysis of the Mach V Scale items. This analysis identified items which discriminated among the four strategies. The two strategies most clearly distinguished were Security and Competition. Subjects who had responded with these strategy selections could be pre- dicted with quite high accuracy on the basis of only four Mach V items-- items that deal with mores and tactics for dealing with people. The dis- criminant functions for the Machiavellianism Scale did not permit proper classification of subjects into all strategy categories, however. While it was possible to distinguish Maximization from Competition, Maximization from Security, and Security from Competition, only two items lent to dis- criminating Maximization from Compatibility and no items discriminated Compatibility from either Competition or Security. It is apparent that some Mach Scale items predict some behaviors-~what is important is that the behaviors the Mach items predict are the strategies that could not be predicted on the basis of divisibility or certainty of payoff. Problems for Further Analysis Lawton's (1968) program of Suttcliffe's (1957) factorial partition of contingency tables made the three-way interaction analyses in this report possible. The cell expected values decrease rapidly for four dimensional analyses and lend to unstable approximations to X2. Thus several desirable analyses could not be performed. The technique of using dummy variables to represent discrete independent variables in regression equations, how- ever, offers promise of completing additional analyses. The dummy variable technique can be extended to discriminant function analysis to obtain the joint effects of eXperimental conditions and individual difference item measures on discrete strategy behaviors. This particular extension, though, 104 Irequires prior knowledge of the pairwise interaction effects of individual (difference items and the dummy variables representing discrete experimental condition. 1 The discriminant function analyses of Machiavellianism items and Specific strategy choices suggests that a similar analysis including ITI items and dummy variables for experimental conditions would not only be ‘highly enlightening, but may be a step toward answering Greenstein's (1967) questions about the effects of personality variables. Under what condi- tions will which personality measures predict what kinds of political be- havior? The present analysis has identified four distinct political strategy behaviors and the conditions under which Maximization and Compat- ibility strategies are elicited. It has also demonstrated a relationship between particular individual difference measures and strategies. Reanal- ysis of the data presented here may contribute to an understanding of the relationship between payoff conditions and individual difference measures and the interaction among environmental conditions, personality variables and strategy selection. 1These analyses must be temporarily deferred until an efficient inter- éiction program, such as Morgan and Sondguist's (1965) AID, is operational éit the University of Hawaii. BIBLIOGRAPHY Adorno, T. W., Frenkel-Brunswik, E., Levinson, D. J., and Sanford, R. N. The Authoritarian Personality. New York: Harper, 1950. Asch, S. B. Social Psychology. New York: Prentice Hall, 1952. Blumstein, P. W., and Weinstein, E. A. The redress of distributive in- justice. American Sociological Association meeting, San Francisco, August, 1967. Bond, J. R., and Vinacke, W. E. Coalitions in mixed-sex triads. Sociometry, 1961, 33, 61-71. Budner, S. Intolerance of ambiguity as a personality variable. Journal of Personality, 1960, 22, 30. Caplow, T. A theory of coalitions in the triad. American Sociological Review, 1956, g1, 489-493, Caplow, T. Further development of a theory of coalitions in the triad. American Journal of Sociology, 1959, 63, 488-493. Chaney, M. V., and Vinacke, W. E. Achievement and nurturance in the triad. Journal of Abnormal Social Psychology, 1960, pg, 175-181. Chertkoff, J. M. The effects of probability of future success on coalition formation. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 1966, 3, 265-2770 Christie, R. Impersonal Interpersonal Orientations and Behaviors. Mimeo- graphed research proposal, Columbia University, 1962. Cole, S. C. An examination of the power inversion effect in three person mixed-motive games. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1969,_11, 50-58. - Cole, 3. G., and Phillips, J. L. A note on verbalized strategies in a three-person political convention situation. East Lansing: Human Learning Research Institute, Report No. 10, May 1967. Dawson, J., and Phillips, J. L. Machiavellianism and manipulative strategy in a mock political convention. In preparation. Dixon, W. J. (Ed.) BMD Biomedical Computer Programs. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1967. 105 106 Driver, M. J. Conceptual structure and group processes in an inter-nation simulation. Part OnE: The perception of simulated nations. Ed. Test. Serv., April 1962, Report RB-62-15. Edwards, A. L. Manual for the Edwards Personal Preference Schedule. New York: Psychological Corporation, 1954. Felknor, C., and Harvey, O. J. Some cognitive determinants of concept formation and concept attainment. Technical Report No. 10, Contract Nonr 1147(07), University of Colorado, 1964. Gamson, W. A. An experimental test of a theory of coalition formation. American Sociological Review, 1961, 26, 565-73. Gamson, W. A. A theory of coalition formation. American Sociological Review, 1961,.26, 373-82. Gamson, W. A. A Theory of Coalition Formation. Unpublished Dissertation, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, 1960. Gamson, W. A. Experimental studies of coalition formation. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 1. New York: Academic Press, 1964. Geis, F. L. Machiavellianism in a three-person game. Ph. D. Dissertation, Columbia University, 1963. Geis, F. L. Machiavellianism and the manipulation of one's fellow man. Paper read at American Psychological Association, Los Angeles, 1964. Geis, F. L., and Christie, R. Machiavellianism and the tactics of manip- ulation. Paper read at the American Psychological Association, Chicago, September 1965. Geis, F. L., Christie, R., and Nelson, C. In search of the Machiavel. Paper presented at American Psychological Association meeting, Chicago 1963. Gillmore, C., Kline, D. K., Anderson, J., Lawton, D., and Phillips, J. L. A 3400/3600 Fortran program for computing chi-squares and exact probabilities of all effects in a factorial design. Technical Report No. Human Learning Research Institute, Michigan State University, in preparation. Cough, H., and Sanford, R. N. Rigidity as a psychological variable. Unpublished Mss. University of California, Los Angeles, Institute of Personality Assessment and Research, 1952. Greenstein, F. I. The impact of personality on politics: an attempt to clear away the underbrush. American Political Science Review, 1967, -6__1_, 629-6410 107 Harvey, O. J. Cognitive determinants of role playing. Technical Report No. 3, Contract Nonr 1147(07), University of Colorado, 1964. Harvey, O. J. Experience, Structure and Adaptability. Chapter 6, New York: Springer, 1966. Harvey, O. J., Hunt, D. E., and Schroder, H. M. Conceptual Systems and Personality Organization. New York: Wiley, 1961. Homans, G. C. Social Behavior: Its elementary forms. New York: Harcourt Brace and World, 1961. Kelley, G. A. The Psychology of Personal Constructs. New York: Norton, 1956. Kelley, H. H., and Arrowood, A. J. Coalitions in the triad: Critique and experiment. Sociometgy, 1960, 23, 231-244. Nitz, L. H., and Phillips, J. L. The effects of divisibility of payoff on confederative behavior. In preparation. Phillips, J. L., and Nitz, L. H. Social contacts in a three-person "polit- ical convention" situation. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 1968,.12, 206-214. Riker, W. H. Bargaining in a three-person game. American Political Scientific Review, 1967,.61, 642-656. Riker, W. H. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale Univer- sity Press, 1962. Rokeach, M. The Open and Closed Mind. New York: Basic Books, 1960. Rulon, P. J., and Brooks, W. D. On statistical tests of group differences. In D. K. Whitla (Ed.), Chapter 2 Handbook of Measurement and Assess- ment in Behavioral Sciences. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1968. Schelling, T. C. The Strategy of Conflict. New York: Oxford University Press, 1963. Schroder, H. M., Driver, M. J., and Streufert, S. Human Information Pro- cessing: Individuals and Groups Functioning in Complex Socia1 Situations. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1967. Schroder, H. M., and Streufert, S. The measurement of four systems of per- sonality structure varying in level of abstractness. (Sentence Com- pletion Method.) Princeton University: ONR Technical Report No. 11, Nonr 1858(12), 1962. Shapley, L. S. A value for n-person games. Annals of Mathematical Studies, 1953,'g§, 307-317. 108 Shapley, L. S., and Shubik, M. A method for evaluating for distribution of power in a committee system. American Political Scientific Review, 1954,.48, 787-792. Shelly, R., and Phillips, J. L. A social contact model for coalition form- ation. East Lansing: Human Learning Research Institute, Report No. 6, September 1966. Sherif, M. The concept of reference group in human relations. In M. Sherif and M. W. Wilson (Eds.), Group Relations at the Crossroads. New York: Harper, 1963. Suttcliffe, J. P. A general method of analysis of frequency data for multiple classification designs. Psychological Bulletin, 1957, 21, 134-137. Tuckman, B. W. Personality structure, group composition, and group function- ing. Sociometry, 1964, 21, 469-487. Tuckman, B. W. Integrative complexity and attitudinal orientation. Perceptual Motor Skills, 1965,_gl, 838. Tuckman, B. W. Integrative complexity: its measurement and relation to creativity. Educational Psychological Measurement, 1966,.26, 369-382. Tuckman, B. W. Personal Communication. 1968. Vannoy, J. S. Generality of cognitive complexity-simplicity as a personality construct. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1965, 2, 385-397. Vinacke, E. A. Sex roles in a three-person game. Sociometry, 1959. Vinacke, W. E., and Arkoff, A. Experimental study of coalitions in the triad. American Social Review, 1957, 22, 406-475. Witkin, H. A. Individual differences in the perception of embedded figures. 'ggurnal of Personaligy, 1950, 12, 1-15. A ppend ix A Induction for Condition I Form I-la PDQ 12 POLITICAL DECISION QUESTIONNAIRE This questionnaire is part of a study of some basic political abilities. There are several parts to the questionnaire and each part has its own instructions. Since various forms of this questionnaire will be given in a number of different classes, we would like the following information. Name Class in which this questionnaire is given Year in college Major Sex M F In keeping with the American Psychological Association's Code of Ethics, no information given on this questionnaire will be released at any time except as part of a statistical average which cannot be identified with a person. The answers you give will not be available to your instructor, administrative officers of this university or to investigative agencies for any reason. PART ONE A state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. The party is having a convention. Assume that you are the representative, that is, the floor leader of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the delegates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leadership. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representative of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has 100 delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has 150 delegates (votes), and Faction Z has 100 delegates (votes). The major purpose of this convention is to de- cide how many of 100 political jobs each faction will receive. Each faction would like to get as many of these jobs as possible. 110 111 Form I—la Cont. It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the jobs. If these two factions control a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the jobs are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have 250 votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z would have 200 votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have 250 votes. Assume that you are the floor leader of Faction X (100 votes). Which of the other two factions Y or Z, will you contact first to try to make a deal for the division of the jobs? Faction Y Faction Z (150 votes) (100 votes) (Circle one) What portion of the jobs are you prepared to offer? What is the smallest portion of the jobs you would be willing to accept in a coalition with this faction leader? (That is what is your rock-bottom low?) Why did you choose to contact the faction your chose? What do you expect the other faction leader to demand? What is likely to be the outcome of the bargaining session? What portion of the jobs do you think you can realistically obtain? GO ON TO PART TWO. Append ix B Induction for Condition II Form II-la PDQ 12 POLITICAL DECISION QUESTIONNAIRE This questionnaire is part of a study of some basic political abilities. There are several parts to the questionnaire and each part has its own instructions. Since various forms of this questionnaire will be given in a number of different classes, we would like the following information. Name Class in which this questionnaire is given Year in college Major Sex M F In keeping with the American Psychological Association's Code of Ethics, no information given on this questionnaire will be released at any time except as part of a statistical average which cannot be identified with a person. The answers you give will not be available to your instructor, administrative officers of this university or to investigative agencies for any reason. PART ONE A state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. The party is having a convention. Assume that you are the representative, that is, the floor leader of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong all of the delegates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leader- ship. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representative of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has 100 delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has 150 delegates (votes), and Faction Z has 100 delegates (votes). The major purpose of this convention is to nominate a candidate to run for the office of governor and a candidate for the office of lieutenant governor. Each faction would like its man to receive the nomination for the governorship, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if its man received only the lieutenant governor's place on the ballot. 113 114 Form II-la It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the nominations. If these two factions have a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the nominations are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have 250 votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z would have 200 votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have 250 votes. Assume that you are the floor leader of Faction X (100 votes). Which of the other two factions, Y or Z, will you contact first to try to make a deal for the division of the nominations? Faction Y Faction Z E (150 votes) (100 votes) (Circle one) Which nomination are you prepared to offer them? Which nomination would you accept as a rock-bottom bargain in a coalition with this faction's floor leader? Why did you choose to contact the faction you chose? What do you expect the other faction leader to demand? What is likely to be the outcome of the bargaining session? What nomination do you think you can realistically obtain? GO ON TO PART TWO. Appendix C Induction for Condition III Form III-la PDQ 12 POLITICAL DECISION QUESTIONNAIRE This questionnaire is part of a study of some basic political abilities. There are several parts to the questionnaire and each part has its own instructions. Since various forms of this questionnaire will be given in a number of different classes, we would like the following information. Name Class in which this questionnaire is given Year in college Major Sex M F In keeping with the American Psychological Association's Code of Ethics, no information given on this questionnaire will be released at any time except as part of a statistical average which cannot be identified with a person. The answers you give will not be available to your instructor, administrative officers of this university or to investigative agencies for any reason. PART ONE A state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. The party is having a convention. Assume that you are the representative, that is, the floor leader of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the delegates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leader- ship. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representative of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has 100 delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has 150 delegates (votes), and Faction Z has 100 delegates (votes). The major purpose of this convention is to nominate a candidate to run for the office of governor and a candidate to run for the office of lieutenant governor. Each faction would like its man to receive the nomination for the governorship, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if its man received only the lieutenant governor's place on the ballot. Since this party has effectively controlled State government for several years, any man who receives the nomination is virtually assured of winning the general election against the opposition party. ' 116 117 Form III-1a It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the nominations. If these two factions have a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the nominations are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have 250 votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z would have 200 votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have 250 votes. Assume that you are the floor leader of Faction X (100 votes). Which of the other two factions, Y or 2, will you contact first to try to make a deal for the division of the nominations? Faction Y Faction Z (150 votes) (100 votes) (Circle one) Which nomination are you prepared to offer them? Which nomination would you accept as a rock-bottom bargain in a coalition with this faction's floor leader? Why did you choose to contact the faction you chose? What do you expect the other faction leader to demand? What is likely to be the outcome of the bargaining session? What nomination do you think you can realistically obtain? GO ON TO PART TWO. Appendix D Complete Questionnaire Form II-Zb PDQ 12 POLITICAL DECISION QUESTIONNAIRE This questionnaire is part of a study of some basic political abilities. There are several parts to the questionnaire and each part has its own instructions. Since various forms of this questionnaire will be given in a number of different classes, we would like the following information. Name Class in which this questionnaire is given Year in college Major Sex M F In keeping with the American Psychological Association's Code of Ethics, no information given on this questionnaire will be released at any time except as part of a statistical average which cannot be identified with a person. The answers you give will not be available to your instructor, administrative officers of this university or to investigative agencies for any reason. PART ONE A state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. The party is having a convention. Assume that you are the representative, that is, the floor leader of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the delegates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leader- ship. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representative of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has 113 delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has 113 delegates (votes), and Faction Z has 124 delegates (votes). The major purpose of this convention is to nominate a candidate to run for the office of governor and a candidate for the office of lieutenant governor. Each faction would like its man to receive the nomination for the governorship, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if its man received only the lieutenant governor's place on the ballot. 119 120 Form II-2b It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the nominations. If these two factions have a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the nominations are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have 226 votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z woul have 237 votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have 237 votes. Assume that you are the floor leader of Faction X (113 votes). Which of the other two factions, Y or Z, will you contact first to try to make a deal for the division of the nominations? Faction Y Faction Z (113 votes) (124 votes) (Circle one) Which nomination are you prepared to offer them? Which nomination would you accept as a rock-bottom bargain in a coalition with this faction's floor leader? Why did you choose to contact the faction you chose? What do you expect the other faction leader to demand? What is likely to be the outcome of the bargaining session? What nomination do you think you can realistically obtain? GO ON TO PART TWO. 121 PART TWO: MACH V. ATTITUDE SCALE Instructions: Below are twenty groups of statements. Each group contains three state- ments labeled A, B, and C. Each statement refers to a way of thinking about people or things in general. The statements reflect opinions, not matters of fact, and different people have been found to agree with different items. Read the three statements in each group. First decide which of the three statements, A, B, or C, comes the closest to describing your own beliefs. On the red answer sheet, make a mark in the plus (+) space for that statement. This is the way you would indicate that statement B was the closest to what you believe. + _ A— __ .B‘ —_ C—— Then decide which of the remaining two statements is farthest from your beliefs. Mark the minus (-) space next to this letter: 4. .. A——— .13-:- C‘: - Here is a set of example statements. On the questionnaire you might find these statements: A. It is easy to persuade people but hard to keep them persuaded. B. Theories that run counter to common sense are a waste of time. C. It is only common sense to go along with what other people are doing and not be too different. 0n the answer sheet you will find the answer space next to the circled question number. 3> ||+ II' B 122 If you agreed with A, you would mark your answer sheet like this: + - A- —_ B —— — C Then, out of the remaining two statements, if you disagreed most with B, you would finish marking the question like this: + _ A-':_ g B '-. C Be sure that you have marked one plus (+) and one minus (—) space in every group of three statements. Do not omit any group of statements. 123 Please answer all of the sets of statements on your answer sheet, not on the questionnaire booklet. 1. A. It takes more imagination to be a successful criminal than a successful business man. The phrase, "the road to hell is paved with good intentions" contains a lot of truth. Most men forget more easily the death of their father than the loss of their preperty. Men are more concerned with the car they drive than with the clothes their wives wear. It is very important that imagination and creativity in children be cultivated. People suffering from incurable diseases should have the choice of being put painlessly to death. Never tell anyone the real reason you did something unless it is useful to do so. The well-being of the individual is the goal that should be worked for before anything else. Once a truly intelligent person makes up his mind about the answer to a problem he rarely continues to think about it. People are getting so lazy and self-indulgent that it is bad for our country. The best way to handle people is to tell them what they want to hear. It would be a good thing if people were kinder to others less fortunate than themselves. Most people are basically good and kind. The best criteria for a wife or husband is compatibility-- other characteristics are nice but not essential. Only after a man has gotten what he wants from life should he concern himself with the injustices in the world. Most people who get ahead in the world lead clean, moral lives. Any man worth his salt shouldn't be blamed for putting his career above his family. People would be better off if they were concerned less with how to do things and more with what to do. 10. 11. 12. 124 A good teacher is one who points out unanswered questions rather than gives explicit answers. When you ask someone to do something for you, it is best to give the real reasons for wanting it rather than giving reasons which might carry more weight. A person's job is the best single guide as to the sort of person he is. The construction of such monumental works as the Egyptian pyramids was worth the enslavement of the workers who built them. Once a way of handling problems has been worked out it is best to stick with it. One should take action only when sure that it is morally right. The world would be a much better place to live in if people would let the future take care of itself and concern them- selves only with enjoying the present. It is wise to flatter important people. Once a decision has been made, it is best to keep changing it as new circumstances arise. It is a good policy to act as if you are doing the things you do because you have no other choice. The biggest difference between most criminals and other peOple is that criminals are stupid enough to get caught. Even the most hardened and vicious criminal has a spark of decency somewhere within him. All in all, it is better to be humble and honest than to be important and dishonest. A man who is able and willing to work hard has a good chance of succeeding in whatever he wants to do. If a thing does not help us in our daily lives, it isn't very important. A person shouldn't be punished for breaking a law which he thinks is unreasonable. Too many criminals are not punished for their crime. There is no excuse for lying to someone else. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 125 Generally speaking, men won't work hard unless they're forced to do so. Every person is entitled to a second chance, even after he commits a serious mistake. People who can't make up their minds aren't worth bothering about. A man's first responsibility is to his wife, not his mother. Most men are brave. It's best to pick friends that are intellectually stimulating rather than ones it is comfortable to be around. There are very few people in the world worth concerning oneself about. It is hard to get ahead without cutting corners here and there. A capable person motivated for his own gain is more useful to society than a well-meaning but ineffective one. It is best to give others the impression that you can change your mind easily. It is a good working policy to keep on good terms with everyone. Honesty is the best policy in all cases. It is possible to be good in all respects. To help oneself is good; to help others is even better. War and threats of war are unchangeable facts of human life. Barnum was probably right when he said that there's at least one sucker born every minute. Life is pretty dull unless one deliberately stirs up some excitement. Most people would be better off if they controlled their emotions. 19. 20. A. 126 Sensitivity to the feelings of others is worth more than poise in social situations. The ideal society is one where everybody knows his place and accepts it. It is safest to assume that all people have a vicious streak and it will come out when they are given a chance. People who talk about abstract problems usually don't know what they are talking about. Anyone who completely trusts anyone else is asking for trouble. It is essential for the functioning of a democracy that everyone vote. Now check over your answer sheet to see that you have answered every set of three statements. You should have a total of 20 marks in the plus (+) columns, and 20 marks in the minus (-) columns. Write your name on the line provided on the answer sheet and mark the appropriate space to indicate your sex. 127 PART THREE: Topical Inventory Form N INSTRUCTIONS This inventory gives several tapics or situations and a number of different ways that people react to them. The reactions are presented in pairs. Your task here is to choose the one member of each pair that most closely fits your Opinion or feeling about the general topic. Some of these choices will be easy to make, while others may be rather difficult. All of the choices are statements of opinion or feeling, so there is never any "right" or "good" choice in any pair. If you do not agree with either of the responses in a pair, choose the one that is least disagree- able of the two. The items in the inventory will be presented like this: Pair Number 1. When I am confused - - - a. I try to find a solution and end the confusion. b. I completely ignore the fact that I am confused. ii. When I am confused - - - a. I break out into a nervous sweat. b. I remain completely calm at all times How to respond: Find space on your purple answer sheet with the same number as the pair number. It will look like this: Then decide which response, g_or b, you agree with most. If you agree most with response a, mark your answer sheet like this: Make your mark heavy and dark. When you have finished the first item go on to the next. Decide which response most fits you. For example, on pair two if response b, "I remain completely calm at all times" best 128 describes your behavior, you would mark your answer sheet like this: ii a b c d e Be sure to choose only one of the responses in each pair. Do not skip any pair, even if it is difficult to make a decision. Once you have marked your choice for an item, don't go back to it; first impressions are usually the most reliable in this inventory. There are six situations or topics in the inventory. Each situation or topic his six pairs of responses. Be sure to pick one and only one response from each pair. When you have finished, you should have 36 marks on your answer sheet. Before you begin, put your name and indicate your sex in the appro- priate place on the answer sheet. Work at your own speed, but work straight through the inventory without stopping. Once you have completed an item do not return to it. 129 Questions 1-6: Imagine that someone has criticized you. Choose the response from each pair that comes closest to your feelings about such criticism. Indicate your choice by marking either the A or the B space on your answer sheet. 1. When I am criticized - - - a. I try to take the criticism, think about it, and value it for what it is worth. Unjustified criticism is as helpful as justified criticism in discovering what other people's standards are. b. I try to accept the criticism but often find that it is not justified. PeOple are too quick to criticize something because it doesn't fit their standards. 2. When I am criticized - - — a. I try to determine whether I was right or wrong. I examine my be- havior to see if it was abnormal. Criticism usually indicates that I have acted badly and tends to make me aware of my own bad points. b. It could possibly be that there is some misunderstanding about some- thing I did or said. After we both explain our viewpoints, we can probably reach some sort of compromise. 3. When I am criticized - - - a. I listen to what the person says and try to accept it. At any rate, I will compare it to my own way of thinking and try to understand what it means. b. I feel that either I'm.not right, or the person who is criticizing me is not right. I have a talk with that person to see what's right or wrong. 4. When I am criticized - - - a. I usually do not take it with good humor. Although, at times, constructive criticism is very good, I don't always think that the criticizer knows what he is talking about. b. At first I feel that it is unfair and that I know what I am doing, but later I realize that the person criticizing me was right and I am thankful for his advice. I realize that he is just trying to better my actions. 5. When I am criticized - - - a. I try to ask myself what advantages this viewpoint has over mine. Sometimes both views have their advantages and it is better to com- bine them. Criticism usually helps me to learn better ways of dealing with others. b. I am very thankful. Often I can't see my own errors because I am too engrossed in my work at the time. An outsider can judge and help me correct the errors. Criticism in everyday life usually hurts my feelings, but I know it is for my own good. 130 When I am criticized - - - a. It often has little or no effect on me. I don't mind constructive criticism too much, but I dislike destructive criticism. Destruc- tive criticism should be ignored. b. I try to accept and consider the criticism. Sometimes it has caused me to change myself; at other times I have felt that the criticism didn't really make much sense. Questions 7-12: Imagine that you are in doubt. Choose the response from each pair that comes closest to your feelings about such doubt. Indicate your choice by marking either the A or the B space on your answer sheet. 7. 10. 11. When I am in doubt - - - a. I become uncomfortable. Doubt can cause confusion and make one do a poor job. When one is in doubt he should ask and be sure of himself. b. I find myself wanting to remove the doubt, but this often takes time. I may ask for help or advice if I feel that my questions won't bother the other person. When I am in doubt - - - a. I don't get too upset about it. I don't like to ask someone else unless I have to. It's better to discover the correct answer on ,your own. b. I usually go to someone who knows the correct answer to my question. Sometimes I go to a book which will set me straight by removing the doubt. When I am in doubt - - - a. I first try to reason things out and check over the facts. Often I approach others to get ideas that will provide a solution. b. I think things over, ask questions, and see what I can come up with. Often several answers are reasonable and it may be difficult to settle on one. When I am in doubt — - - a. I realize that I'll have to decide on the correct answer on my own. Others try to be helpful, but often do not give me the right advice. I like to judge for myself. b. I usually try to find out what others think, especially my friends. They may not know the answer, but they often give me some good ideas. When I am in doubt - - - a. I look over the problem and try to see why there is a doubt. I try to figure things out. Sometimes I just have to wait a while for an answer to come to me. b. I try to get some definite information as soon as possible. Doubt can be bad if it lasts too long. It's better to be sure of yourself. 131 12. When I am in doubt - - - a. I consider what is best in the given situation. Although one should not rush himself when in doubt, he should certainly try to discover the right answer. b. I act according to the situation. Sometimes doubt can be more serious than at other times and many of our serious doubts must go unanswered. Questions 13-18: Imagine that a friend has acted differently toward you. Choose the response from each pair that comes closest to your feelings about such an action. Indicate your choice by marking either the A or the B space on your answer sheet. 13. When a friend acts differently toward me - - - a. I am not terribly surprised because people can act in many different ways. We are different people and I can't expect to understand all his reasons for acting in different ways. b. I am usually somewhat surprised but it doesn't bother me very much. I usually act the way I feel towards others. People worry too much about others' actions and reactions. 14. When a friend acts differently toward me - - - a. I find out why. If I have doen something wrong I will try to straighten out the situation. If I think he's wrong, I expect him to clear things up. b. I feel that I may have caused him to act in a different way. Of course, he may have other reasons for acting differently which would come out in time. 15. When a friend acts differently toward me - - - a. I first wonder what the trouble is. I try to look at it from his viewpoint and see if I might be doing something to make him act differently toward me. b. It is probably because he has had a bad day, which would explain this different behavior; in other cases he may just be a changeable kind of person. 16. When a friend acts differently toward me - - — a. It is probably just because something is bothering him. I might try to cheer him up or to help him out. If these things didn't work I would just wait for him to get over it. b. I try to understand what his different actions mean. I can learn more about my friend if I try to figure out why he does things. Sometimes the reasons may not be very clear. 17. When a friend acts differently toward me - - - a. There has to be a definite reason. I try to find out this reason, and then act accordingly. If I'm right I'll let him known it. If he's wrong, he should apologize. b. I usually let him go his way and I go mine. If a friend wants to act differently that's his business, but it's my business if I don't want to be around when he's that way. ,ilftlrlli Ir I‘l ‘Ill: all. Ills! I." III... all! 132 18. When a friend acts differently toward me - - - a. I don't get excited. People change and this may cause differences. It is important to have friends, but you can't expect them to always be the same. b. I like to get things back to normal as soon as possible. It isn't right for friends to have differences between them. Whoever is at fault should straighten himself out. Questions 19-24: Think about the topic of people in general. Choose the response from each pair that comes closest to your thoughts about people. Indicate your choice by marking either the A or the B space on your answer sheet. 19. This I believe about people - - - a. Whatever differences may exist between persons, they can usually get along if they really want to. Although their ideas may not agree, they probably still have something in common. b. People can learn from those who have different ideas. Other people usually have some information or have had some experience which is interesting and can add to one's knowledge. 20. This I believe about people - - - a. People can act in all sorts of ways. No single way is always best, although at certain times a particular action might be wiser than others. b. Each person should be able to decide the correct thing for himself. There are always a few choices to be made and the individual himself is in the best position to pick the right one. 21. This I believe about people - - - a. Some people think they know what's best for others and try to give advice. These people shouldn't make suggestions unless asked for help. b. There are certain definite ways in which people should act. Some don't know what the standards are and therefore need to be straight- ened out. 22. This I believe about people - - - a. I can tell if I am going to get along with a person very soon after meeting him. Most people act either one way or another and usually it is not difficult to say what they are like. b. It's hard for me to say what a person is like until I've known him a long time. PeOple are not easy to understand and often act in unpredictable ways. 23. 24. 133 This I believe about people - - — a. People have an outside appearance that usually isn't anything like what can be found on the inside, if you search long and hard enough. b. Each person is an individual. Although some people have more good or bad points than others, no one has the right to change them. This I believe about pe0ple - - - a. People can be put into categories on the basis of what they're really like. Knowing the way a person really is helps you to get along with him better. b. People are unlike one another in many respects. You can get along with people better and better understand them if you are aware of the differences. Questions 25-30: Think about the general t0pic of leaders. Choose the response from each pair that comes closest to your thoughts about leaders. Indicate your choice by marking either the A or the B space on your answer sheet. 25. 26. 27. 28. Leaders - - - a. Leaders do not always make the right decisions. In such cases, it is wise for a man to look out for his own welfare. b. Leaders are necessary in all cases. If a leader cannOt make the right decisions another should be found who can. Leaders - - - a. Leaders cannot provide all the answers. They are like other people --they have to try to figure out what action is necessary and learn from their mistakes. b. Leaders make decisions sometimes without being sure of themselves. We should try to understand this and think of ways to help them out. Leaders - - - a. I like a leader who is aware of how the group feels about things. Such a leader would not lead any two groups in exactly the same way. b. A person should be able to put his confidence in a leader and feel that the leader can make the right decision in a difficult situation. Leaders - - - a. There are times when a leader shouldn't make decisions for those under him. The leader has the power to decide things, but each man has certain rights also. b. A leader should give those under him some opportunity to make de- cisions, when possible. At times, the leader is not the best judge of a situation and should be willing to accept what others have to say. 134 29. Leaders - - - a. Some leaders are good, others are quite poor. Good leaders are those who know what is right for the men under them. These leaders deserve the respect of every man. b. Leaders cannot be judged easily. Many things go to make up good leadership. Most people fall short in some way or another, but that is to be expected. 30. Leaders - - - a. Leaders are needed more at certain times than at others. Even though people can work out many of their own problems, a leader can some- times give valuable advice. b. Some people need leaders to make their decisions. I prefer to be an individual and decide for myself, when possible. Most leaders won't let you do this. Questions 31-36: Imagine that someone has found fault with you. Choose the response from each pair that comes closest to your feelings about such a situation. Indicate your choice by marking either the A or the B space on your answer sheet. 31 When other people find fault with me - - - a. It means that someone dislikes something I'm doing. People who find fault with others are not always correct. Each person has his own ideas about what's right. b. It means that someone has noticed something and feels he must speak out. It may be that we don't agree about a certain thing. Although we both have our own ideas, we can talk about it. 32. When other people find fault with me — - - a. I first wonder if they are serious and why they have found fault with me. I then try to consider what they've said and make changes if it will help. 33. When other people find fault with me - - - a. They have noticed something about me of which I am not aware. Al— though criticism.may be hard to take, it is often helpful. b. They are telling me something they feel is correct. Often they may have a good point which can help me in my own thinking. At least it's worthwhile to consider it. 34. When other people find fault with me — - - a. I may accept what is said or I may not. It depends upon who is ypointing out the fault. Sometimes it's best to just stay out of sight. b. I accept what is said if it is worthwhile, but sometimes I don't feel like changing anything. I usually question the person. 35. 36. 135 When other people find fault with me - - - a. I like to find out what it means; since people are different from one another, it could mean almost anything. A few peOple just like to find fault with others but there's usually something to be learned. b. There is something to be changed. Either I am doing something wrong or else they don't like what I'm doing. Whoever is at fault should be informed so that the situation can be set straight. ' When other people find fault with me ... - a. I don't mind if their remarks are meant to be helpful, but there are too many people who find fault just to give you a hard time. b. It often means that they're trying to be disagreeable. People get this way when they've had a bad day. I try to examine their re- marks in terms of what's behind them. Please count the marks on your answer sheet to see that you have made 36 choices, one from each pair. Illl“: Ill-lil- Appendix E Machiavellianism and Interpersonal Tapical Inventory Scoring Routines Form II—2b PART FOUR This part of the Political Decision Questionnaire is a convention problem somewhat different from the first one. Please work through it without referring to other portions of the questionnaire. There are 350 delegates to the convention and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the delegates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leadership. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representative of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has 120 delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has 110 delegates (votes), and Faction Z has 120 delegates (votes). The major business of this convention is to nominate a candidate to run for the office of governer and a candidate to run for the office of lieutenant governor. Each faction would like its man to receive the nomination for the governorship, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if its man received only the lieutenant governor's place on the ballot. It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the nominations. If these two factions have a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 178 votes, then the nominations are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Z would have 240 votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have 230 votes. Assume that you are the floor leader of Faction X (120 votes). Which of the other two factions, Y or 2, will you contact first to try to make a deal for the division of the nominations? Faction Y Faction Z (110 votes) (120 votes) (Circle one) Which nomination are you prepared to offer them? Which nomination would you accept as a rock-bottom bargain in a coalition with this faction's floor leader? What do you expect the other faction leader to demand? What is likely to be the outcome of the bargaining session? What lumnination do you think you can obtain for your faction? THIS IS THE END OF THE POLYTICAL DECISION QUESTIONNAIRE. Thank you for Your cooperation. If you wish to find out the results of studies similar to fills one, you may get a c0py of one of the reports from the Human Learning ReSearch Institute, 202 Erickson Hall, M.S.U. 137 all! 138 Three coding procedures are presented here. SUBROUTINE MACH counts the number of Machiavellian orderings of the items in each of the 20 triplets of Mach V items. AM is an N by 60 array of subjects' responses to each item, where N is the total number of subjects, and the entries are 8.0 for "Agree" and 9.0 for "Disagree". (This coding is dictated by the position of the Mach V response spaces on the machine-score sheet.) BM is an N by 20 array of individual item Mach scores. Sum is an N element vector of total Mach responses. SUBROUTINE TUCK counts the number of items the subject has endorsed from each of the four complexity system domains. Here AC is a l by 36 array of one subject's item responses, BC is a l by 4 array of the number of items in each category he endorsed, and M is a 2 by 36 matrix containing the scoring Key-the number identifying the complexity system each item represents. SUBROUTINE CATAG determines whether a subject has any system score which is in the upper 25% of the population distribution. If he has one and only one such score, CATC is set equal the number of the complexity category in which he has the high score. 1' (3061(3065 C L C 139 SUBROUTINE MACH‘IvA”.EM.SLF'Nbe1 DIMENSICN5V1196J198V1ltZCloSUMiVl RCAD FACH DATA, SUBJECIS TAKEN If BE ARRAY Bra; CL 5 KZ=1920 5 BMII.KZ)=C.O REAC‘5298121(Aplloleleoégl 312 FORVAT1/6X.oCF1.3/) DC 10 J=lv63 1F lA”(IyJ).NL-O.Cl CC 1C 10 AN119J138.5 1C CUNIIVUE THE ABOVE CPLRATICN FILLEL 1N ALL NC? RFQPFN't VDACiS WITH THE MIUPUINI PREFERENCE RANKING IMPLIED BY THE RANK 4 CUT Cf ‘ PHLC‘DURE th FCLLCHINC CPERAIICNS WILL GtNEKaTL a», Ihi vaca SLPRFS FOR E'Ch IRIPLET 0F IIEMS. A HIGH MACH RtSPCXSt WILL ME scwxan 1.3. A LOW P'CH RESPLNSE nR AN INCCRRECTLY MARKED RtSPLUL. WILL tr SCORED o. 21 IF IAMII.II.GI.AMII.S)I sMII.II=I.: 22 1F (AM‘I,71.GT.AM(I'11)1 BN11921=103 24 IF (AMII.I3I.LI.A~II.I?II BMII. 3)=1.. 25 IF‘AMl [.19).GI.AP(I.21)) 9M1194131.3 28 [F (AMII.25I.GI.A~II.27II erI.5I=I.¢ 38 IF (AMII.3II.CI.AM(I.35II BMII.6I=I.. 32 1F (AM(1937).LI.AN(1'3911 “~(117,;lo£ 54 IF (AM(I,45).LT.AN(I.47D) BF(I.8)=1.C 36 [FIAM(I.51).LI.A“(I.53)) thI. 9I=I.: 38 1F IAMII.55I.GT.A~II.57II BP(I.101=1.; 4: IF (AM(I.2).GT.AM(I.4)) RNI I.III=I.- 42 IFIAMII.10I.LI.AMII.12)I sNII.12I=I.: 44 IF(AMII.I4I.LI.AMII.I&II 8N(I.l3)=1.c «e IFIAVII.22I.GI.AMII.24II BH(I,14)=1.£ as IF(AM(I .28).LT.AP(I.3011 s~II.ISI=I.: 5C IF(AMII.34I.LI.A~II.3¢II sHII.IsI=I.t 52 IFlAM(I'38).GI.AM(I.4c)) BM(I.17)=1. 54 IFlAMlI.44).LI.ANiI.46)) s~(1.18I=1.c 56 IF(AM(I.521.GT.AM(I.54)) sMII.19I=I.c 58 IF (AMII.5¢I.cI.AMII.58II BP(1.201=1.C ac CONTINUE THIS COMPLETtS IHE RECCCE FCR SUBJECTS I. lbt wyxr ovIRATION u'LL SUM THE MACH SCORES. SUMINVI=C.C DC 70 JJ=I.20 7C SUMINVI=SL~INVI+BMII.JJI l‘-Is COMPLETiS THE Macs RtCCCt nun SCCRr LUNLLAIILN Eta SUBJ. I. h"IIE ROUTINE TC STCRE PACH SCORES ON TAPE HRIIE‘5119(BMlloJleJJ=11291 RtTLRN END 1. Li L l i1 815 816 99 140 SUBRUUIINE IUCK (IoACoBCthtn) DIMENSION AC‘lv3blvBC119419M12936) REAC152’81611AC110K19K31936, FURNAT‘I/llxv36Fl.OI33X1 BC(I.HT)=C.O THIS CLEARS THE TEMPORARY COUNTER 101 102 20C 201 DC 200 K=1v36 MT=C IFlAClIoK 1-1.0) 200'10191C2 HT=NlltKl BC‘IgHT138C119HT1 *loC GO TO 200 MT=P129K1 BC‘IvHT138C11vHT1 +1.0 CONTINUE HRIIEIS3).(BCII.MI).FI=1.4) HRITE‘6222511NVy13C111M119H131v4’ FCRFAT11594F1000’ RETLRN END I‘ll-ll 1“ mill I'i’il 1" 1‘1! 141 SUBROUTINE CATAGIBCoCATCoNIZvIoIT) DIMENSION 8C!IIQIICATCINI,ITIN.4).AVB(4) 1 ’TESTI4) REHIND 53 DC 400MT3194 SUMEC=0.0 SSQBC=0.0 SDBC=0.0 AVBIHT)=O.C DO 300 NV=I,N CATCINVI=C.O REACIS3IQIECII’MSI'M5=194) SUMBC=SUMBC +8C‘I’MT, SOC SSQEC=SSCBC+I8C(I,"TI1092.0 VARBC=SSQBC/(N-II-(SUPBCG'ZIII(N-1)'N) SDBC=SQRTIVAR8CI REWIND 53 C THE FCLLCWINC STATISTIC PROVIDES A STES tOR THE C UPPER 25 PERCEAT CF EACT BCIHTI DISTRIBUTION. C THIS TEST WILL IDENTIFY PERSONS CF EACH SYSTEM TYPE. C TESTIMT)=Z'SDBC AVBIMTI=SLV8CIN 400 PRINT 5000, VARBC: SDBC: AVBIHTI. MT 500C FURFATISHOVAR= ,F7.3,IOX,3H SD.F7.3,2X.10HAVERAGE 8= 9 1F7.3'7HSYSTEM 913) C C C THE FCLLCHING PROCESS IS THE TEST ITSELF REHIND 53 DC 600 NV=1.N READID319IHCII'MZ)9”Z=194) DC 500 MT=194 ITIRVyMTI=C IF!(BCII.FTI-AV8(MT)).GT.TEST(PT)I ITINV,NT)=I 500 CONTINUE ITS=O DO 601 HT=194 601 ITS=ITS+ITINV9MTI IFIITS.E0.11 602:603 602 DU 604 MT=1o4 IFIITTNV,FT).EQ.II 6109604 603 CATCINV)=C.O GC TO 600 610 CATCINVI=FT 604 CONTINUE 600 CCNTINUE RETLRN END I. T I I- I‘ll-III I ' 1'1 III l 1 III" 142 ITI SCORING KEYa some areas Pair First Item Second Item Pair First Item Second Item at... A .B. 219.1. A I: 1. 3 2 l9. 3 4 2. l 4 20. 4 2 3. 3 1 21. 2 1 4. 2 l 22. 1 4 5. 4 3 23. 3 2 6. 2 4 24. 1 3 7. 1 3 25. 2 1 8 2 1 26. 4 3 9 3 4 27. 3 l 10. 2 3 28. 2 4 11. 4 1 29. 1 4 12. 2 4 30. 3 2 13. 4 2 31. 2 4 14. 1 3 32. 3 1 15. 3 2 33. 3 4 16. 3 4 34. 1 2 17. 1 2 35. 4 l 18. 4 1 36. 2 3 aThese items are read in row order into array M of SUBROUTINE TUCK, where they provide a basis for classifying responses. Append ix F Instructions for Experiment II CONDITION I INSTRUCTIONS The experiment you will participate in today consists of a series of competitive games. The game you will play will be a political convention game. In this game, a state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. Each of you will be the representative, that is, floor leader, of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the delegates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leadership. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representative of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has __delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has __de1egates (votes), and Faction Z has __delegates (votes). The major business of this convention is to decide how many of 100 political jobs each faction will receive. Each faction would like to get as many of these jobs as possible. It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the jobs. If these two factions control a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the jobs are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have __ votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z would have __ votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have __ votes. 144 CONDITION II INSTRUCTIONS The experiment you will participate in today consists of a series of competitive games. The game you will play will be a political convention game. In this game a state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. Each of you will be the representative, that is, floor leader, of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the dele- gates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leadership. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representa- tive of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has ____delegates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has____ delegates (votes), and Faction Z has ___ delegates (votes). The major business of this convention is to nomin- ate a candidate to run for the office of governor and a candidate to run for the office of lieutenant governor. Each faction would like its man to receive the nomination for the governorship, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if its man received only the lieutenant governor's place on the ballot. It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the nominations. If these two factions have a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the nominations are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z would have votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction Z would have votes. 145 146 These cards list the votes controlled by each faction leader. The second card indicates the faction assigned to you. (Pass out vote distribution and identification cards.) The convention will proceed like this: First, each of you will fill out a "choice form" to indicate the faction you wish to negotiate with in the first round of negotiations. The form also asks some questions about what kind of offer you are willing to make, and what you think they will accept as a final agreement. This information is for use in the analysis of the study. It does not constitute an actual opening offer or any part of the bargaining process. I will not disclose these answers, but I will tell you if any two of you have chosen to bargain with each other. If two of you have chosen each other (regardless of what offers you intend to make) you will have three minutes to verbally negotiate the division of jobs. The third man will leave the room during the bargaining session. If the two bargainers reach an agreement about the division of the jobs, they will fill out an "agreement form." The third man will be called back, the jobs will be divided according to the agreement, and we will go on to the next game. If the two bargainers do not reach an agreement during the negotiation period, the third man will be called back and all three of you will fill out another set of choice forms. Another round of negotiation will then follow. Do you have any questions before we begin? If not, here are the choice forms. Please pass the form back through the slot in the divider when you have filled it out. (If a reciprocal choice has been made.) Factions ___and ___have chosen to negotiate with each other on the first round of negotiations. Faction leader __3 would you please step 147 across the room to 201D. When you shut the door we will begin the three-minute bargaining session. I will come and get you at the end of three minutes. (To the remaining subjects) Your task now is to come to some verbal agreement, if you can, on the division of the 100 jobs. Please remain seated while bargaining. You have three minutes. (Upon reaching anagreement) Have you reached an agreement? Would you please fill out these forms to record your agreement while I call the other man back. (With third man present) As I mentioned before, we will go on to another game when an agree- ment has been reached. Since you have already played this game, and since two of you have had some bargaining experience, this is likely to affect the way you play the next game. To control for this, we have constructed a questionnaire that presents you with a convention situation somewhat different from the one you just played. We would like you to fill out this questionnaire visualizing your opponents as people you have never met. Don't take them to be the people you played with today. The questionnaire is in three parts. The first is the convention situation, and the second two are attitude scales like others you have taken before. You should finish it with enough time left in the hour to talk a bit about some of the purposes of this study. (Assign them to different rooms.) CONDITION III INSTRUCTIONS The experiment you will participate in today consists of a series of competitive games. The game you will play will be a political convention game. In this game a state political party is divided into three strong factions or groups. These groups are designated Faction X, Faction Y, and Faction Z. Each of you will be the representative, that is, floor leader, of one of the three factions in the convention. There are 350 delegates to the convention, and each delegate has one vote. Since the factions in this party are quite strong, all of the dele- =a. gates in each faction have pledged their votes to the faction leadership. This enables the floor leader of each faction to bargain as the representa- T tive of his entire faction. The faction will then vote as a bloc, in line 1 with whatever agreement its floor leader may make. Faction X has ____dele- gates (i.e., votes). Faction Y has ____delegates (votes), and Faction Z has ____delegates (votes). The major business of this convention is to nominate a candidate to run for the office of governor and a candidate to run for the office of lieutenant governor. Each faction would like its man to receive the nomination for the governorship, but would not be extremely dissatisfied if its man received only the lieutenant governor's place on the ballot. Since this party has effectively controlled state government for several years, any man who receives the nomination is virtually assured of winning the general election against the opposition party. It is standard procedure for two factions to get together and agree on the division of the nominations. If these two factions‘have a majority of the votes of the convention, that is, 176 votes, then the nominations are divided according to their agreement. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Y would have votes. An alliance between Faction X and Faction Z would have votes, and an alliance between Faction Y and Faction 2 would have votes. 148 149 These cards list the votes controlled by each faction leader. The second card indicates the faction assigned to you. (Pass out vote distri- bution and identification cards.) The convention will proceed like this: First, each of you will fill out a "choice form" to indicate the faction you wish to negotiate with in the first round of negotiations. The form also asks some questions about what kind of offer you are willing to make, and what you think they will accept as a final agreement. This information is for use in the analysis of the study. It does not constitute an actual opening offer or any part of the bargaining process. I will not disclose these answers, but I will tell you if any two of you have chosen to bargain with each other. If two of you have chosen each other (regardless of what offers you intend to make) you will have three minutes to verbally negotiate the division of nominations. The third man will leave the room during the bargaining session. If the two bargainers reach an agreement about the division of the assign— ment will fill out an "agreement form." The third man will be called back, the nominations will be divided according to the agreement, and we will go on to the next game. If the two bargainers do not reach an agreement during the negotiation period, the third man will be called back and all three of you will fill out another set of choice forms. Another round of negotiation will then follow. Do you have any questions before we begin? If not, here are the choice forms. Please pass the form back through the slot in the divider when you have filled it out. (If a reciprocal choice has been made) Factions ___ and ___ have chosen to negotiate with each other on the first round of negotiations. Faction leader , would you please step 150 across the room to 201 D. When you shut the door, we will begin the three- minute bargaining session. I will come and get you at the end of the three minutes. (To the remaining subjects) Your task now is to come to some verbal agreement, if you can, on the assignment of the nominations. Please remain seated while bargaining. You have three minutes. (Upon reaching an agreement) Have you reached an agreement? Would you please fill out these forms to record your agreement while I call the other man back. (With third man present) As I mentioned before, we will go on to another game when an agreement has been reached. Since you have already played this game, and since two of you have had some bargaining experience, this is likely to affect the way you play the next game. To control for this, we have constructed a questionnaire that presents you with a convention situation somewhat differ- ent from the one you just played. We would like you to fill out this question- naire visualizing your opponents as people you have never met. Don't take them to be the people you played with today. The questionnaire is in three parts. The first is the convention situation, and the second two are attitude scales like others you have taken before. You should finish it with enough time left in the hour to talk a bit about some of the purposes of this study. (Assign them to different rooms.) 151 CHOICE FORM I represent Faction X Y Z. (circle one) I wish to negotiate with Faction X Y Z. I am prepared to (circle one) offer them I of the jobs as my Opening offer. I expect him to demand I of the jobs on a final agreement. AGREEMENT FORM Factions and agree to pool their resources and form a coalition. It is agreed that Faction will get jobs as its share of the convention outcome and Faction will get jobs as its share. I “““““ i I I fl 1' ll L" H T” III E“ H H Will” I 169 0138