§ Ens. til. 3: l Rug? 4.. a: .héil .. :3. . .9. x..:.....!!: g l‘lttf..51. s I )2. i. l. v i l f. ... (.0 .4. 21.! wit-.1... . , . 1...! pro. vll 3.1.1....»0 . . .2711}: .0 .r. , . . . . . . V .'...a:u.l......: W343}? 200? LIBRARY Michigan State University This is to certify that the dissertation entitled THE UNITY OF IDENTITY: A DEFENSE OF AN IDEAL presented by JOHN ZILLMER has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for the Ph.D. degree in Philosophy Jm, Major Professor’s Signature 00 9 Date MSU is an affirmative-action, equal-opportunity employer -a-a-o-Q-o-o-n-b-o-—-—.—-——._-_. _. _--.—-o-—.-g-o—a--n-n-a-o-u-n-o-o-n—--n-o--a-c-o—-a-.--o—.‘-.-n-o-o-o—- PLACE IN RETURN BOX to remove this checkout from your record. TO AVOID FINES return on or before date due. MAY BE RECALLED with earlier due date if requested. DATE DUE DATE DUE DATE DUE 5/08 K./Prolecc&Pres/ClRC/DateDue‘indd THE UNITY OF IDENTITY: A DEFENSE OF AN IDEAL By John C Zillmer A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Philosophy 2008 ABSTRACT THE UNITY OF IDENTITY: THE DEFENSE OF AN IDEAL By John C Zillmer The elements of one’s personal identity, including desires, projects, principles, group membership, self-conceptions, and narratives are ideally unified. Unification of identity elements is characterized by a lack of conflict between these elements. Personal identities are ideally unified since identity conflict undermines personal autonomy, moral and other sorts of integrity, and both commitment and valuing within romantic relationships. TABLE OF CONTENTS INTRODUCTION DISCOVERING OR POSULATING THE ONE ......................................... 1 CHAPTER 1 UNITY, FRAGMENTATION, MULTIPLICITY ......................................... 8 CHAPTER 2 THE UNITY OF PERSONAL IDENTITY ............................................... 48 CHAPTER 3 AUTONOMY ................................................................................. 109 CHAPTER 4 INTEGRITY ................................................................................... 165 CHAPTER 5 LOVE: VALUE AND COMMITMENT ................................................. 207 CONCLUDING THOUGHTS ............................................................. 260 BIBLIOGRAPHY ............................................................................. 263 iii — Introduction — Discovering or Postulating the One One way of dealing with the problem of diversity, of the many, is by discovering, or postulating, the one. (Why diversity is a problem is another question, one I haven’t an answer to. What’s clear is that for Western epistemology and politics it has been a problem, perhaps the problem.) - Naomi Scheman, Engenderings’ This work does not assume that diversity is the problem. The idea that there is one, or even one central, type of problem is difficult to accept; there are lots of problems, and unfortunately for those who seek universal solutions, not all problems (and not all answers) boil down to the one and the many. But in some ways diversity — the many — can be a problem. The specific sort of diversity that this work — one not in epistemology or politics but in moral psychology — takes to be problematic is that of a disunified personal identity. The overall aim in the present work is both to detail some of these ways in which certain sorts of diversity within one’s personal identity can be a problem, and to attempt to discover — rather than postulate — the solutions unity can offer. Some introductory remarks on ‘unity’ and ‘personal identity’ are in order here. One sort of unity that might characterize one’s personal identity is metaphysical. Derek ‘ Scheman (1993), p. 186. Parfit has famously argued that there is no persisting subject of experiences such that some future person is identical to the present person who is me.2 Such a view thus takes ‘personal identity’ to refer to just that thing the temporal persistence of which is tantamount to the temporal persistence of the person. Parfit takes the subject of experiences to fulfill this role; others — John Locke is typically thought to have held this position — have taken memories to do so. Parfit’s defense of the claim of diachronic disunity can be contrasted with an argument denying the existence of synchronic metaphysical unity, such as that of Roland Puccetti.3 Puccetti appeals to the behavioral split that occurs under certain conditions in callosotomy patients — persons who have had the hemispheres of their brains surgically separated — to argue that even neurally intact persons are composed of two metaphysically independent beings. Thus, whatever it is that underlies behavior (Puccetti is noncommittal as to just what constitutes this behavioral substratum), it is just this that constitutes one’s identity. The sort of unity of personal identity that the present work will take up is not a metaphysical but rather a practical unity. For example, one’s gender identity has effects on what she does, effects that are not a function of any physical characteristics that might be thought to be associated with her biological sex. To illustrate: a woman has reason to be cautious of accepting etiquette advice, since it is in virtue of her conceiving of herself as a woman as well as 3m-person attributions of this identity to her that she is vulnerable to exploitation through such channels as norms of feminine propriety. 2 Parfit (1984/1987). 3 Puccetti (1973). Each person has more than one such practical identity: one may identify as, and be identified as, a woman, and a Native American, and a mother, and a triathlete. These identities might be practically unified - that is, they might have practical effects that are concurrently realizable. More likely, though, some of a person’s identities are disunified. What is it for an identity to be practically unified? This question has only an ideal answer, since practical unification is realizable only as a matter of degree — and, thus, the claim that an identity is unified should throughout this work be taken as a relative, not absolute, claim. Just as we call a bicyclist ‘fast’ or an artwork ‘beautiful’ without thinking them the fastest or most beautiful, or perfectly fast or beautiful, we can call an identity ‘unified’ and mean by that not perfect unification (whatever that might be) but instead mean that the identity has the feature ‘unity’ to such a degree or in such a way that it is appropriate to note this feature. One indication of a practically unified identity is that an action done for reasons that flow from one’s identity will tend not to be done ambivalently. A person who is unambivalent about, say, eating organic food is wholeheartedly in favor of doing so, and as such she disregards counter—considerations (such as the greater monetary cost and relative unavailability of organic food). Talking to people who eat organic readily brings to light two points about ambivalence: it is a relative notion, since virtually everyone has some of it; and to be unambivalent is not to be single minded, as even those who are wholehearted about a goal have many other goals as well. (Talking to such people indicates that eating organic food is something that can be strongly identity—constituting, as well.) Another characteristic of a practically unified identity is that each of one’s actions that flow from reasons conferred by her unified identity will be unlikely to conflict with other of her actions. A person whose practical identities include eating organic food as well as frugality, for instance, will have regular practical conflicts, and as such her identity is disunified. One’s actions will tend to cohere over time, as well, so a person whose identity is diachronically practically unified will be less liable to undermine her past projects with her present ones.4 This sort of practical unity of identity is one that, I’ll argue, is an ideal that is desirable to hold. As an ideal, it is strictly speaking not perfectly realizable. Nevertheless, the asymptotic approaching of the ideal can improve the lives of those who do so. The argument for this claim will appeal to the ways in which the possessing of a unified identity is a precondition both of acting autonomously and with integrity, and is an important, if not strictly necessary, condition of romantic loving. These aspects of human life are the focus here for one principle reason: each is an important element of living well. Acting on one’s own principles and beliefs and motivations, that is, autonomously, is a precondition of one’s leading a good life that it often — in daily life, though not by philosophers — goes unexamined. Even Buddhist writers — those who, having examined self— governance and found it lacking — imply that the goal of no-self is to be attained only by one’s own wholehearted attention. Even those who recommend an attitude of caring for others rather than one of preserving one’s own rights and liberties endorse (one would hope) only self-motivated altruism; it would 4 It might be noted at this point that there are other reasons that one’s actions may conflict. One example is the fact of value pluralism, which virtually guarantees conflict due to incommensurable grounds for practical decisions. I will argue in Chapter 2 that the most important of such conflicts, and the values that play a role in them, are ultimately grounded in practical identities. be at the very least conceptually suspect to advocate forceful instigation of an ethic of care. In any event, the importance of autonomy goes even deeper than such axiological considerations — that being autonomous is, or contributes to, what makes a person’s life a good one. While there may be some truth in that understanding, autonomy might more clearly explain what makes someone’s life, good or bad, her own life at all. Acting with integrity is perhaps a more ideal, rather than expected, characteristic of a good life, since even those lives without excessive social and psychological barriers to acting with integrity do not feature such actions unremittingly. Nevertheless, it is axiomatic that, ceteris paribus, to act with integrity is better than not to; the term is often used synonymously with a wide range of moral praise terms such as honesty, courage, and reliability, and is sometimes used as a more general term of overarching personal approbation. Though some certain situations might well demand that integrity be forgone, the ability to act with integrity — and the regular appropriate exercise of this ability — is desirable. Loving is an especially important element of living well. The objects of our love are sources of strength, meaning and pleasure, and without them life would be impoverished. It tells a great deal about the importance of loving that a person is more likely to die after the passing of her life’s partner, and suicide is much more common among those who have recently ended a romantic relationship.5 Each of these aspects of a good life — autonomy, integrity and loving — is (and likely has always been) undermined by forces both internal and external to particular persons. Autonomy is thought to be undercut by ambivalence (arguably more prevalent 5 Kposowa (2000). now than historically), coercion and oppression. To act with integrity, that is, from one’s own moral principles in the face of pressure to do otherwise, is hampered by social norms that selectively prescribe submission, the insurmountable resistance caused by various oppressive forces, and the inability of some to act morally in certain social contexts. Resistance to the ability to love is presented by (among many other things) social pressure to value wrongly and the decline of commitment. Each of these elements —- autonomy, integrity and loving — are in what follows here the subject of a discussion that both outlines the philosophical terrain and defends a certain conception of the notion. I then explain the ways in which the unity of identity bears on the subject, showing how the possession of a unified personal identity improves the ability to act with autonomy or integrity, and to love — that is to say, how a unified identity is an ideal insofar as it underpins these elements of a good life. Before these specific arguments are launched, two tasks are in order. One is a full account of the notion of the unity of identity that will feature in the following arguments. Though there is little in the way of explicit accounts of the unification of identity in the philosophical literature, there are a range of possible forms such unity might take. But first it is necessary to set the stage by considering the opposition to the ideal of unity. In the eyes of many who are resistant to arguments for unified identities, any proffered account of unity would be, I fear, a complete non-starter. This resistance is held for understandable sorts of reasons, to be sure. Unity ideals have been implicated in an oddly a priori sort of oppression of those whose identities are multiplicitous or otherwise not amenable to reduction to a unity. The Kantian unified will and the singular Cartesian cogito are taken as representatives and even agents of patriarchy; contemporary accounts of autonomy and integrity are taken to be further marginalizing of those who, because they are already marginalized, do not fit the criteria for these capacities; given that the social world is less than unified, to advise that we inhabitants of it be unified seems to some an unattainable ideal. These are serious charges. The account defended here will be as answerable to these concerns as is possible. I believe that the notion of a unified identity can accommodate many of the concerns of those who oppose it; I believe such an account can accommodate all the most serious concerns. Nevertheless, the notion of personal unity has been heavily criticized, and as an ideal, it must be admitted that the unity of identity has a deep hole to climb out of before it can brush the dirt off and make itself presentable. _1_ Unity, fragmentation, multiplicity Do I contradict myself? Very well then I contradict myself, (I am large, I contain multitudes.) -Walt Whitman, “Song of Myself” Unlike Whitman, who in the above well-known passage admits his satisfaction with a disunified self-conception, a number of prominent philosophers have argued — or assumed — such a self-conception to be undesirable. Plato claimed that internal disunity, like disunity within political and social organizations, entails injustice. After arguing that injustice is inherent in an internally divided city, army, or family, he asks: And is not injustice equally fatal when existing in a single person; in the first place rendering him incapable of action because he is not at unity with himself, and in the second place making him an enemy to himself and the just? Is that not true, Thrasymachus?l Distinct from Plato, Kant thought it not (only) immoral but rather impossible that an underlying disunity marked a person. The condition of having one unified experiencing mind, the “transcendental unity of apperception”, is a condition he argued to be a minimal condition of conceptualizing anything at all.2 Surprisingly to some, this is intended to be even less of a metaphysical claim than that of Plato; our unity, for Kant, is ‘ Republic, 352. 2 Critique of Pure Reason, B 139-142. a matter of our subjective self-conception, for “as far as inner intuition is concerned we cognize our own subject only as appearance but not in accordance with what it is in itself.”3 If, as is sometimes claimed, philosophy is a series of footnotes to Plato, and modern philosophy footnotes to Kant, these two conceptions of unity will find their way into the present work whether intended or not. I will not explicitly address these views, though - Kant’s being more cognitive than volitional, and Thrasymachus’ ‘yes, certainly’ being offered much too easily — in favor of addressing criticisms of contemporary views of unified identity. The Received Model Of contemporary philosophers, two defend views that together draw the majority of the criticism aimed at the ideal of unity. Often taken to defend a virtually identical account, Gerald Dworkin and Harry Frankfurt hold views that are sometimes criticized as one; John Christman characterizes them as such in terming them “the received model“. Though sharing the same conceptual core, that of the hierarchical structure of the person, the two accounts diverge both in ways that will be described immediately below, and especially in ways that become apparent in responding to critics. These distinctions between the two accounts will serve as response to some of the criticisms of unified identity that this chapter will address, since certain criticisms of Dworkin’s account are answerable by components of Frankfurt’s view. The remainder will be answered in the spirit in which at least some have been intended: being corrective demands upon what is 3 Critique of Pure Reason, 8156. " Christman (1991), p. 4. (I will argue) an essentially defensible view, alterations to the influential accounts described here will be suggested. Dworkin’s and Frankfurt’s accounts share a notion of identification. Both are concerned with the effects of identification on autonomy, as well, and both have a hierarchical view of the self. Outside of these similarities, the accounts differ, as will become clear. What a person identifies with are “the influences that motivate him”, on Dworkin’s view.5 Such influences, termed first-order motivations, can be desires, wants, aims, motives, et cetera. For one’s first—order motivations to be authentic her second- order desires must “be congruent” with them.6 In this way — through wanting to be so motivated — she identifies with those first-order motivations. One is not thus identified if she is alienated from or resents her first-order influences.7 Frankfurt’s notion of identification is nearly identical. A desire that a person is moved by is her own if she has a second-order volition by which she endorses her own acting on the desire. Frankfurt admits some complexities to this simple core view, though. Not all desires are ones that a person may wish to be moved by, even though she might still identify with them and desire that she have them. For example, a person with a desire for whiskey and also a desire for sobriety may identify with both, admitting that both are desires are hers. But she may wish to act on the desire for sobriety - in light of a second-order volition - and still identify with the desire for whiskey, though not want to act on this desire. Thus the object of identification need not be something that one intends to be motivated by. 5 Dworkin ( 1988), p. 15. 6 Dworkin (1988), p. 15. 7 This latter point plays its strongest role in Dworkin (I970). 10 Usually, though, a desire that a person wants herself to have is a desire that she wants herself to act on.8 It is also a usual occurrence that a person is ambivalent about whether she wants to act on a certain desire. Though we often describe such a situation in terms of conflicting reasons, the (compatible) description in terms of identification is this: some of one’s hi gher-order volitions are consistent with the desire, and some are not.9 A person might be ambivalent regarding her desire, say, to marry Jorge; she may love him, and want to legally join herself to him, but she might also desire to further the aims of a certain sort of feminism which frowns upon heterosexual marriage. Frankfurt’s intertwined notions of ‘resonance’ and ‘wholeheartedness’ are offered as ideal-case characterizations of identification. When a person identifies with a desire, (to continue the example) the desire to marry Jorge, wholeheartedly, she has no internal conflict regarding the desire. In this way, her identification with the desire resonates throughout her entire volitional economy; like striking a tuning fork in the vicinity of other tuning forks, the others return the reverberations at a harmonious pitch. She may of course have external conflict regarding the desire: her best friend may advise against her marrying Jorge, or Jorge may already be married to someone else. This conflict makes for nuptial trouble, but not for identity trouble. Also a mode of external conflict is a case in which her desire to marry Jorge conflicts with other desires that move her but with which she does not identify — Jorge is shorter in stature than she is, suppose, and while she does not want to be moved by her aversion to shorter partners 8 ‘Usually’, that is, as a matter of frequency. As a tangentially interesting matter, there is a conceptual core to the notion of a ‘desire’, though, that makes for a certain amount of tension in claims about desires that one does not desire to be moved by. In one sense, Ulysses desired to be lured by the sirens, but he did not desire to be moved by their so luring him. Ulysses desired the phenomenological experience, but the associated motivation. Thus one might truly say that Ulysses did not desire to be lured by the sirens. 9 A more complete defense of the desirability of understanding practical conflict in terms of identification rather than reasons is contained in Chapter 2, below. For the time being it should be sufficient to note that I do not deny that there are conflicting practical reasons. 11 (she realizes that her feeling is tied up in some complicated way to norms of feminine submission to which she does not subscribe), she cannot ignore the feeling. Thus, her desire to marry Jorge conflicts with a desire that is external to her, that is, a desire with which she does not identify. It is important to note the content—neutrality of both these accounts. The internal relation of a person to a desire, not the content of the desire itself, is what makes the desire part of the person’s identity. There may be some limits to the sorts of desires one can take up; the desire to thwart all of one’s own goals may be one with which one cannot identify, but this for structural reasons -— it would necessarily conflict with other desires.lo But one could, on a structural account, identify with the desire to have no self- respect, or the desire to be abused, or to be subordinate to others. Whether a desire is properly said to be one with which a person identifies is a matter of her relation to it, not a matter of the desire’s appropriateness for a person (on some explicitly morally normative conception of ‘person’) to possess. Another feature of note is the conception of the self as constructed entirely out of desires. While the locutions of Dworkin and Frankfurt include with the archetypal ‘desire’ such notions as ‘goals’, ‘aims’, and ‘projects’, it seems never to have been the intent of these original accounts to accommodate categorically different identity— constituents. This restriction seems at times to be an explicit one: Frankfurt claims, about someone who doesn’t care which of his desires he is moved by, “he has no identity apart from his first-order desires”.“ More often, though, this restriction of non-connative '0 And also, of course, with itself. ” Frankfurt (1988), p. 18. 12 elements from personal identity is made by exclusion; Frankfurt and Dworkin’s arguments and examples simply do not reach outside the category of desires. This limitation is misleading. The identities of persons, and thus the persons themselves, are more plausibly described as comprising various characteristics (‘tall’, ‘playful’), group memberships (‘Ojibwa’, ‘feminist’, ‘union worker’), principles (‘generous’) or abstracta (‘moral agent’).I2 But while I think that the idea of identity’s being only a matter of desires a possibly misleading oversimplification, structural accounts of identity need not be grounded in such a reduction. Since the accounts of Dworkin and Frankfurt are described in terms of desires I will talk about them in this way; those of the following criticisms that are cast in terms other than ‘desires’ will introduce the emendation of a basic structural view, to be completed in the following chapter. Criticisms of unified identity Neither Dworkin’s nor Frankfurt’s is explicitly an account of identity. Both have offered their account of identification in the interests of grounding a certain conception of autonomy. This fact has not prevented the accounts from being the subject of a great deal of criticism regarding their claims about identity. Because these two accounts have been so philosophically influential — positively as well as in the negative sense that will become clear in the course of addressing criticisms - to show how resilient these representative hierarchical accounts are is to begin to make plausible the ideal of unity. Criticisms cluster around four distinct issues, which I will briefly sketch here before proceeding to a deeper analysis of each. At the most theoretic level, criticisms are ‘2 These categories are not mutually exclusive; ‘feminist’ fits well into the first three groupings. Nor are they exhaustive. 13 spurred by the fact that Dworkin’s account (the specific target of John Christman, the critic I will consider here) holds the structure of desires entailed by identification to be of a hierarchical nature. Christman argues that this hierarchical form subjects the account to an unacceptable notion of ‘identification’, in two ways. ‘To identify’ involves a state of either evaluative approval or bare acceptance, neither of which characterize the range of identifications. Secondly, the temporal process by which one comes to be so identified are problematic, since endorsement on the grounds of a coercively acquired hi gher-order desire is not, Christman claims, properly called ‘identification’." The second sort of criticism is that a structural account of identity cannot accurately characterize the “adequacy of identity”‘4: adequate, that is, not only for mere self-govemance, but for self— governance over actions that aim at one’s own best interests. The quoted phrase and the language of ‘best interests’ belong to Susan Babbitt, but the concern is shared by many other philosophers.l5 All sharing this concern agree that if a person is properly said to be acting from her own identity this must entail that her actions thus motivated aim (at least fallibly) at her own well-being, not just at the satisfaction of desires she happens to have. The third sort of criticism is that the unity of identity can entail ossification or rigidity that persons neither have nor ought to have. Diana Meyers claims, “Frankfurt’s account shows how very difficult it is to explicate integration without appearing to recommend personal ossification”.16 The internally unified are thought to be obdurate and static, rather than resilient and open to change. '3 Christman (1991). ‘4 Babbitt (1996), p. 104. ‘5 Benson (1991), Christman (2004), Meyers (1989). '6 Meyers (2000), p. 169. 14 On the same subject, Amy Mullin notes, “it is important to avoid assuming that effectively unified selves must be homogeneous or integrated to the point that harmony is rarely threatened. Such a conflation of unity and homogeneity unduly limits our options for coping with diversity and has damaging political consequences”.l7 These damaging political consequences are the fourth point of criticism; these political consequences are claimed to be due to a number of distinct features of the ideal of unity. One such feature is the one that Mullin notes in the above passage: ‘unity’ is sometimes taken to be ‘perfect unity’, a pure state allowing of no conflict. Mullin uncovers another potentially problematic feature of the ideal of unity in claiming an association between the supposed unity of groups and the unity of identity: the fact that “. . .the appeal of unity is used to eliminate the disadvantaged or marginal suggests another reason why we should be uneasy about attempts to rid ourselves of inner differences or conflicts”l8 These criticisms — of hierarchical structure, inadequacy of identity, ossification, and damaging political consequences — come from different quarters: conceptual, such as the concept of autonomy and the implications of structure; and practical, as the concerns about oppression and resistance. These distinctions aside, each of the criticisms is culled from a discussion that shares the practical focus of the conception of identity the present work defends, and so the responses offered here will have this practical conception in mind. '7 Mullin (1995), p. 3. ‘8 Mullin (1995), p. 15.. 15 0f hierarchical structure The very basic conceptual feature of unified identity — structural unity of a hierarchical form — has been questioned perhaps most thoroughly by John Christman.19 Christman’s project is the defense of a certain conception of a person’s volitional economy — desires and beliefs that give one reason and motivation to act — on which she is able to be autonomous. Though Christman’s ultimate concern is for autonomy, which will be more closely analyzed in the third chapter of the present work, his criticisms focus on the notion of identity that grounds the characterization of the autonomous person. What it is for a person to identify with her desires, on the received model, is inadequate to characterize the self—determination constitutive of autonomy. Christman takes Dworkin’s hierarchical account as exemplary of the model, and in a supposition shared with other philosophers, claims that the components of, and problems with, Frankfurt’s account are the same. In light of the distinctions explained above, the criticisms Christman offers have force not against hierarchical accounts generally but only against Dworkin’s version. As I’ll go on to show, the criticisms therefore do not undermine the ideal of unity in the way they are intended. Christman argues that hierarchical models are subject to three problems.20 One is a difficulty with the “condition of identification.”21 Identification with a desire occurs when a person reflects on her desire, the desire to marry Jorge, suppose, and approves of that desire - an approval grounded in one or more of her higher-order desires. Christman offers two readings of this condition: (a) she acknowledges the fact of her possessing a '9 Christman (1991). m The tripartite taxonomy here is somewhat arbitrary; Christman’s explicit divisions between issues are not as clear, and while this is not a problem in the original presentation, the divisions make a re-presentation clearer. 2' Christman (1991), p. 5. 16 desire to marry Jorge, or (b) she both acknowledges and positively evaluates it. Both are unacceptable, Christman argues: (a) because she could acknowledge that she has a desire that she came to have with no control of her own and which she would prefer not to have, though she admits she does in fact have it. Her desire to marry Jorge, or to marry at all, might well be of this sort. This mere acknowledgment sense of ‘identification’ is problematic, for if this is all there is to identification, then “I can just as readily ‘identify’ with those non—autonomous aspects of myself as the more ‘authentic’ parts.”22 Christman’s claim is that merely acknowledging that one has a desire is not sufficient for it to be her desire. The other reading, (b), is problematic since then “I would have to be in some sense perfect (in my own eyes)” if my desires could be said to my own.23 Thus a person who reflectively takes stock of who she is would, improbably, discover no flaws, for any possible identity element with which she finds fault would not be an element of her identity. The second related difficulty Christman points out regards the conditions under which one comes to form her desires. The desire to marry Jorge might be one that she approves of, even in the stronger evaluative sense, though this in virtue of hi gher-order desires that are the result of illegitimate external forces. Again, the marriage example is apt: suppose she came to have the desire to marry because of social and familial expectation to do so, and further suppose that she positively evaluates her desire to marry because she has internalized the hi gher—order desire to agree with social norms and the expectations of her family. Thus, if a person acquires hi gher~order desires through some 22 Christman (1991), p. 5. Emphases in original. 1‘ Christman (1991), p. 5. 17 form of manipulation, the hierarchical view still takes the first-order desires of which the person approves to be her own desires. This is unacceptable to Christman, who claims, “the acts of identification must themselves be autonomous”.24 This leads to a third difficulty, which takes as its form a dilemma: either the acts of identification don’t need to be autonomous, or they are in fact autonomous. If the acts of identification don’t need to be autonomous, that is, if identification with a desire is sufficiently done just by the brute fact of approval of the desire, then identification can occur ab initio, without foundations. Christman finds it implausible that a lower-order desire can be one’s own without the process by which it came to be one’s own also itself being relevantly grounded in oneself. The other horn of the dilemma is the possibility that the lower-order desires are internalized not ab initio but are in some way autonomously acquired. If they are, then this sort of autonomy might be the same sort of autonomy that is supposed to characterize actions — that is, being the object of a hi gher-order desire. This possible fashion of desire-acquisition introduces an irdinite regress into the account, though, for every desire must then be the subject of a still hi gher-order desire. If the desires with which one identifies are acquired by some other autonomous method, then the account is incomplete, since it needs to characterize this other sort of autonomy. Thus, Christman faults the received model for both failing to give a plausible account of what it is to identify with a desire and for allowing this identification to occur via a process that must, but cannot, be autonomous. The first concern, regarding the condition of identification, is admittedly problematic on Dworkin’s description, or as 2" Christman ( 1991), p. 7. 18 Christman implies, underdescription, of the notion. At least for purposes of clarification, Frankfurt’s richly described notion of identification can serve as a remedy. When a person takes a positive volitional attitude toward a desire that motivates him, he thereby identifies with it: that he wants to have a desire that he is in fact motivated by is sufficient for his identifying with it. “Whether a person identifies with these passions,” Frankfurt writes, “or whether they occur as alien forces that remain outside the boundaries of his volitional identity, depends on what he himself want his will to be.”25 Often enough, though, honesty will require a person to acknowledge that a desire she would rather not have is indeed one for which she must take responsibility; here the attitude toward the desire is less volitional than cognitive. Having unsuccessfully resisted some desire for a long time, one might give up “this equation of the real with the ideal”26 in the understanding that her ideal self is not something she is willing, or able, to attain. Thus Frankfurt claims that the evaluation criterion for identification is sufficient but not necessary. Christman objects to this sort of identification — mere acknowledgment — calling its objects inauthentic, as noted above. But this sort of identification does not always entail inauthenticity. A person can wish she didn’t desire to run, for example, since it takes time and energy and dedication that she’d rather spend on other pursuits. But admitting that she does have this desire, and is not willing to do whatever it would take to divest herself of it, it is thus her own desire. Lots of runners are like this, and similar examples can be offered ad nauseam. 25 Frankfurt (1999), p. 137. 2" Frankfurt (1988), p. 63. 19 Nor is the criticism concerning desires acquired or identified with ab initio particularly troubling. We make all sorts of things our own in this way: that I take up the hobby of backcountry camping on a whim, that I come to appreciate the dark humor of Edward Gorey though it is grounded in none of my other literary values, that through sheer happenstance 1 have acquired possession of this wholly unlikable cat, say nothing at all against whether these things are properly mine in the various relevant senses. But more troubling is a person’s identifying with some desire in virtue of a hi gher-order desire that is not itself one with which she similarly identifies. Christman’s presentation of the problem is peculiar, however, since only actions, and not desires, are said to be autonomous. One reason for this is that desires are only very rarely (if ever) voluntaristically directly brought about, while it is a defining feature of my action that I brought it about thus. So, while I might govern the conditions for the formation of a desire (eating a favorite food while performing an unpleasant task so as to come to desire the task/treat complex), I do so though actions. The worry Christman brings out, though, is real: one’s hi gher-order desires ought to be her own in the same way (or, if not by the same method, at least with similar results) as are her first-order desires, those on which she acts. The most forceful version of the concern is this: a person can be said (on the received model’s notion of identification) to identify with some desire that she endorses with hi gher—order desires that have themselves been manipulated. This might occur through hypnosis, brainwashing or oppressive socialization. To address this concern, I’ll turn to the discussions of it by Paul Benson and Susan Babbitt. 20 The adequacy of identity Paul Benson has influentially addressed the oppressive effect of socialization on women’s self-conceptions. He writes, In leading women to internalize gravely mistaken conceptions of themselves from a very early age, such socialization systematically prevents many women from recognizing more adequate views of their real strength and value; it renders them unable to take seriously reasons there are for them to regard their appearance differently.27 Benson is making two distinct points here, one psychological and one normative. The normative point is that the socialization of women is often oppressive, this partly in virtue of its encouraging the acceptance of incorrect values. Women are exhorted to find their personal value in their physical appearance (of a certain virtually unattainable type) or in submission to men. These preferences — the preference to be submissive, or to find one’s value solely in one’s own appearance — are normatively incorrect, Benson rightly maintains. I’ll bracket the normative claim in favor of first addressing the psychological claim. In internalizing mistaken self-conceptions, women are endorsing the desires they have, to take one example, to act in sexually submissive ways.28 Such a desire can easily be understood to be the product of socialization: advertisements portray submissive women as typical or admirable, and these images are reinforced by everyday interactions with men (and women) who expect such submission as a matter of course. 27 Benson (1991) p. 396. 1’ Though the subjects of the discussion are oppressively socialized women, Benson realizes both that men are subject to similar sorts of socialization, and also that non-oppressive socialization works in much the same fashion. The focus on women is based on the particularly oppressive nature of the socialization of women. 21 It is relevant that not only does such a woman have a desire to act in these ways. Many of us have, as a matter of socialization, desires to act in certain self-harmful ways: to eat unhealthy snack foods, or to forgo a college education are both supported by certain social and cultural expectations. But the systematic inculcation of femininity notably (though not uniquely) involves the manipulation not only of first-order desires, but also of those of the second order. Women are instructed not only to possess a mere urge — as the urge to eat snack foods — to be submissive, but further to identify with submission; that is, they not only desire to be submissive, but also want that desire itself. In this way, “feminine socialization has insinuated its lessons into their most stable views of what they are and ought to be as persons.”29 It is this argued shortcoming of Frankfurt’s structural account of persons that grounds Benson’s critique, ultimately aimed at the implications for autonomy. The charges that structural accounts are unable to ground autonomy will be taken up below, in chapter 3, and so for the time being I will bracket this specific concern. But the indictment that in certain sorts of situations the structural account of identity yields false self-conceptions is a serious one, which I will now address. The indictment might hold, too, but not in the sorts of situation Benson describes, and not, I think, in any situation that is not so pathological that our theory of identity, indeed our theory of anything, need be held to answer. The situations Benson is justly concerned about are those very common ones in which social norms are given uptake and endorsed by women whose betterment those norms do not promote. This socialization takes place from many quarters — from the 2" Benson (1991), p. 388. 22 mass media, from friends, from family members, from persons in positions of authority — and from a very early age.30 But one relevant strength of a structural account of identity is that it accurately characterizes the fact that, virtually always, not all of the grounds on which one might endorse her lower level preferences are manipulated (at least, not all toward the same end). For this to be the case, all of the sources from which one acquires her norms, beliefs and values would have to conspire to give the same message. On certain interpretations of various historical eras, such homogeneity of cultural pronouncements is said to have existed. I do not know whether such unified societies have ever existed; if perhaps they have, ours is not now one of them. Oppression is indeed systematic, but this does not entail that it is perfectly pervasive. It is because oppression is not perfectly pervasive that structural views of identity explain how it is that some (whether few or many) people escape certain of its damaging effects, as I’ll explain. Consider just one example, mentioned above, of a particularly injurious effect of oppressive socialization: a self-image disorder such as anorexia. Sometimes claimed to be the only potentially fatal psychological condition, anorexia is widely believed to have strong ties to social norms advocating low body weight as the standard for feminine beauty. The fashion model images of the 1970’s were extremely thin, especially compared to the mid-century’s so-called sweater girl models. But — and this is the point that has gone unnoticed -- at the same point in history, alternative social norms became available, advocating the unimportance of the physical in favor of mental, social, and psychic growth. If hippies were thin, it was because they refrained from eating meat, not 3° Indeed, even prenatally: see Scheman (1997) on being “perinatally pinked”. 23 because they emulated Twiggy. While it is undeniable that oppressive social norms play a causal role in self-image disorders; it is similarly undeniable that not all culturally- mediated statements advocate (then or now) extreme thinness as an ideal for women. Indeed, one of the defining elements in the development of the disorder of anorexia is a stage of resistance — resistance, that is, to the perceived conspiracy against being thin.31 Contra Benson, then, a structural view of identity illustrates a way in which many women in fact escape some of these more damaging effects of oppressive socialization. Even if a woman has a hi gher—order preference such that she endorses her desire to be extremely thin, she has other hi gher-order preferences as well. From a theoretical standpoint, then, structural views have the benefit of descriptive accuracy, at least in the ways just mentioned. From a more practical standpoint, structural views show how a number of hi gher-order desires in concert could tip the scales against a person’s oppressive upbringing; this is what I take to happen in such situations as organized consciousness raising. This also occurs when a person enters into a new social group and comes to substantially reorganize her commitments as a function of the support she garners from membership in that group. On a hierarchical account, there is no need to think that one or another higher-order preference (or even some set of them) will define a person’s life in such an encompassing manner as Benson suggests. To be sure, there are cases in which a person’s life is controlled in a totalizing fashion. Such Orwellian society has been reported to have characterized some of the concentration camps of the Second World War, for example. In such circumstances, the only self-conception possible (or, at least, perceived to be possible) is one to which there 3' Levenkron (2000). 24 is no alternative.32 Against such atrocities, though, we should not expect some certain account of personal identity to defend. Thus a structural account of identity does have resources to address the ways in which harmful socialization exploits the process of identification through hi gher-order endorsement of desires. But still unanswered is the normative concern: the sort of identity that would acceptably ground one’s actions must, the claim runs, be characterized by an account which has an essential normative element. Thus any structural account of identity, such as Frankfurt’s hierarchical account, is unsatisfactory insofar as it is consistent with a person’s identifying with anything, no matter how normatively undesirable this object of identification. Benson’s repeated references to ‘the reasons that there are’, to which a satisfactory identity is supposed to lead its bearer, are echoed by the claims of Susan Babbitt. Babbitt argues that structural accounts of identity are unable to capture the sense of self that is adequate for autonomy, integrity and rationality: one that aims at one’s own best interests, interests that may not be the goal of the desires that one happens to have. She accuses as being “too simple” a view quite similar to Frankfurt’s, at any rate a structural view: the “popular conception of individuals according to which the autonomous individual is one who possesses the capacity to reflect on her preferences and alter them in the light of information.”33 It is not just this relation that one has to her preferences that constitutes identity, Babbitt argues, but rather it is the content of those preferences that makes for an adequate identity. And though only explicitly demanding that the adequacy of identity be an adequacy for the exercise of autonomy, it is clear ’2 Some survivors of such extreme violence report their self—conception having been reduced to that of a mere physically existing being (Brison, 2002, chapter 3). ’3 Babbitt (1996). p. 103. 25 enough that Babbitt’s target is much more broad. She takes to be “equivalent” a number of human capacities that seem, to this reader at least, to sum to personhood: personal integrity, autonomy, rationality, identity, and even, minimally, a self.“ Further, without an adequate identity, Babbitt argues that goods such as self—respect and dignity are unimaginable and in fact impossible.” Her proposed solution to these inabilities of certain persons is to require that one’s sense of self be one that directs her to realize her own best interests. This is as much a social as a theoretic demand. The social environment must be altered so that it allows persons with inadequate identities the social resources needed to improve their self- conceptions. Options for actions that make possible dignity, integrity, et a1, must be available and be perceived to be available; minimally, such actions must be imaginable, for it is the lack of possibilities not only in the world but especially in the range of possible thought that makes for the capacities that concern Babbitt. This much — that social changes should be promoted that open the range of opportunities so that self-respect and the goods that accompany it are available to all — is indisputable. The theoretic dimension of Babbitt’s demand, though, is less tenable. Part of the problem here stems from the intended reconceptualizations of the central ideas: ‘identity’, ‘integrity’, ‘autonomy’, and ‘rationality’.36 The somewhat conflationary redefinitions make it difficult, unfortunately, to get a clear grasp of the theoretically intended suggestions. For example, “the term “personal integrity” is taken to refer to the 3“ Babbitt (1996), pp. 6 (on rationality), 8 (on autonomy), 43 (on the self), and 105 (on integrity and identity). 35 Babbitt (1996), p. 8. 3" As pointed out in Walker (1998). 26 ”’7; an adequate identity, in turn, just is that identity which leads one adequacy of identity to pursue her own real interests, not merely the ones she perceives herself to have. But this is just autonomy: “a special kind of agency, the capacity to take control of one’s life and to realize one’s best interests?”8 And each of these definitions is hardly distinguishable from that of ‘rationality’, which is a matter of “whether a person’s choices and actions constitute the best means to her most important ends.”39 There is a practical aim that comes through more clearly, though: Babbitt intends a central normative element to be present in each of these concepts. This is quite contrary to structural views, on which sufficiency is judged by the degree of unification of the constitutive elements whatever their content. Babbitt’s account thus leaves no room for judging any of the central notions (identity, autonomy, integrity, rationality) on structural grounds. For each of these notions, unity is just as preferable as disunity, so long as one’s best interests are promoted. Depending on just what we take the philosophical purpose of an account of identity to be, though, it is not clear that Babbitt’s normatively-constituted view is preferable. Babbitt’s motivation for making a certain content a requirement of a plausible account of identity is that she wants to explain how identity leads a person to pursue her own best interests. This is fine, to a point; since the notion of identity at hand is one of practical identities, if a person’s actions lead to her own well-being this will be, in part, a matter of the content of her identity. ’7 Babbitt (1996), p. 104. 3" Babbitt (1996), p. 45. Interestingly, ‘control’, being “the realization of real interests” (ibid.), has the same normative component shared by the other concepts at hand. 3" Babbitt (1996), p. 6. 27 But someone’s identity can be her identity without it grounding her own well- being. Thomas Hill’s deferential wife, who through oppressive socialization has come to completely identify with, and even gain pleasure from fulfilling, her subservient role in relation to her husband, surely does not aim at her own well-being. She is worse off for who she is, and would be happier and more self-respecting had she an identity that did not cast her as essentially and completely subservient. But the (hypothetical) fact of the matter is that this improved identity is not hers. Would that it were. She is subservient, on her own sincere appraisal as well as judging from the subservient actions she regularly engagesin. Nor does the fact that one’s identity can fail to be self-beneficial change in light of the fact that identities are socially constructed, that first-personal as well as third- personal forces affect identity. Indeed, it is sometimes because one’s identity is not purely self-constituted that a necessary normative element is implausible: it would be inaccurate to deny that someone - a black slave in the antebellum South; an elderly person assumed by her family to be incapable of making her own decisions because of her age —- whose identity prevents her from promoting her own well-being is not in fact the possessor of just this identity. Because of the social environment, the slave is a slave; similarly the elderly woman is unable to make her own decisions. To say that these identities do not belong to the people to whom they are attributed is to deny the sometimes unjust power that others have in the creation of identity. Attributing to Babbitt the claim that a person’s identity can fail to be her own is not entirely easy to support textually. Babbitt’s repeated phrasing of the problem of identity as one of the adequacy of identity can often be interpreted as either or both the 28 adequacy of accuracy or that of self-interest; her claim that an identity can be “wrong’”0 might be epistemic or moral. But one discussion of the Deferential Wife and why exactly she is “falling short of her interests” involves a distinction between her actions being “a result of mistaken beliefs about her self” and their being “the realization of her actual self 1‘” In being subservient, the Deferential Wife acts on an inaccurate identity, one that does not correspond to her actual self. Another similar discussion contains the claim that the Deferential Wife is “improperly self-defined”, suggesting, like other improper definitions, not moral impropriety but epistemic inaccuracy. In perhaps the clearest claim Babbitt makes on the matter, she discusses philosophers who “have not attempted to answer the question. . .of what sort of person one should be — the more robust sense of identity that is at issue when we aim at self-understanding.”42 If the aim of self- understanding is not the aim of understanding who one in fact is, but rather who one should be — if self-understanding takes as its object someone who one currently is not -- then it seems one’s identity can fail actually to be her own. Now, it may be that, as in the case of the slave, the elderly woman and the deferential wife, the identity that a person has is (simply) not adequate to lead to self- benefiting actions. Even if we assume that this fully characterizes Babbitt’s point here, this is not itself a fault of an account of identity so much as a problem with the specific identities that persons possess. An account of identity ought accurately to characterize the sort of identities that people do in fact have. With this even Babbitt agrees, arguing that it is only her own normative account of identity that accurately accounts for a person’s best interests (those she actually has), rather than her perceived interests (ones 4° Babbitt (1996). p. 30. 4' Babbitt (1986), p. 44. Emphasis added. 42 Babbitt (1986), p. 106. Emphasis added. 29 she only believes she has). And the fact of the matter — that some people (perhaps many people; perhaps all of us) have identities that are inadequate — is not only captured by a structural account but, as the present work has promised to take up, allows for an ideal that promotes two of Babbitt’s concerns, autonomy and integrity. OSSIfication For some, ‘unity’ and ‘rigidity’ are nearly synonymous, a unified thing being inevitably rigid. A unified identity is assumed to be one that is inflexible, ossified into one rigid unalterable structure. So rigid is such an identity, this assumption continues, that it becomes homogeneous: lacking in internal diversity, each constitutive element has become so wedded to its co-constituents that each is indistinguishable. Likely a visual representation of such an identity would be an unbroken field of dull gray; the implication is that a life founded on such an identity would be the same dreary hue.“3 Two philosophers have taken up this charge against the ideal of unity. Diana Meyers’s critique focuses on two elements of Frankfurt’s account: the notion of wholehearted endorsement that is peculiar to his particular view, and the rank ordering that is a fundamental component of a hierarchical view. Amy Mullin, offering more of a warning than a criticism, is also concerned with the possible association of unity and homogeneity. I will explain Mullin’s warnings and agree that they are apt, but first I will answer Meyers’s criticisms. Meyers pits her reading of Frankfurt against the fact of intersectional identity, finding Frankfurt’s account to inaccurately characterize the authentic self. Intersectional identity, on Meyers’s usefully broad characterization, is “an identity drawn from diverse ‘8 As in Meyers’s (2000) description of “the autonomous individual as an isolated, plodding planner, wholly lacking in panache and merriment...” (p. 168) 30 sources that may give rise to conflicting desires and rival allegiances?”4 Identity elements from these diverse sources — race, gender, economic class, sexual identity, employment roles, and so on — can intersect in distinctively harmful ways. For example, one harm of racial oppression is that African-Americans are expected to pull themselves up by their bootstraps and take the initiative to improve their collective situation, while people in lower socioeconomic classes are expected to be humble in the face of those who hold societal power; the conflicting identity of a poor black person should be apparent. It is the authentic self of persons possessing this conflicting sort of identity that Meyers claims Frankfurt’s view fails accurately to account for. Meyers’s notion of the authentic self has been developed and somewhat altered over the course of her writings, but nowhere does she give it an explicit and complete definition. In a work earlier than the one critical of Frankfurt, she characterizes the authentic self as a “repertory of skills” in conjunction with “a collocation of attributes”45 which are not merely a static set but are “dynamic“. Unsurprisingly synonymous with possession of “the true self’“, to have an authentic self is incompatible with “regard[ing] one’s self as alien’m’. In her later work, the repertory of skills is cast as a necessary precondition of, but not a constitutive part of, the authentic self.49 Meyers’s earlier notion of the integrated personality, argued to be a necessary facet of the autonomous person, plays no role in her discussion of intersectional identity, consistent with expectations. \ 44 Meyers (2000), p. 154. ‘5 Meyers (1989), p. 92. 4" Neyers (1989), p. 61. ‘7 Neyers (1989), p. 20. “8 Meyers (1989), p. 73. “9 Meyers (2000), p. 166. 31 She gives a clearer definition of what she takes Frankfurt’s view on the authentic self to be.50 Frankfurt argues that when a person wholeheartedly identifies with a desire, she identifies with it in such a way that she cuts off any ambiguity or further internal conflict regarding the desire. This identification is done by excluding from one’s self the desires she does not want to satisfy, and by establishing a rank ordering of the retained desires that establishes one’s priorities. Meyers concludes that on Frankfurt’s view “to have an authentic self is to be wholeheartedly committed to a rank ordering of the desires one has decided to satisfy and to be wholeheartedly dissociated from those of one’s ”51 Thus the authentic self is an integrated desires that one has decided against satisfying. self. Meyers points out that persons with intersectional identities do not fit this model. On a broad but plausible view, the set of possessors of intersectional identities includes virtually everyone. We are each the possessor of multiple identities, and whether the notion of intersectionality essentially includes the sort of notable conflict and interactive harm as in Crenshaw’s crash metaphor of intersectionality, many pe0ple do exemplify intersectionality.52 The lack of fit is both descriptive and normative, Meyers contends. Frankfurt’s view fails to accurately characterize the authentic self that intersectional subjects do possess. It is in the interest of resistance to oppression that intersectional subjects do Come to an understanding of their authentic self — that is, that they are indeed \ 5° The following paragraph is from Meyers (2000), p. 169. 5' Neyers (2000), p. 169. 52 The crash metaphor is a view of intersectionality that focuses on both the most harmful elements of ide mity — race and gender insofar as persons are oppressed vis-a-vis them - and the “sinister synergy” that characterizes their interaction: since intersectional persons are harmed in virtue of multiple elements acting in concert, no elements are blamed individually (Meyers 2000, p. 154). 32 intersectionally identified, and to know this is to possess knowledge of one’s authentic self. This knowledge, in turn, can motivate resistance to oppression: when a person comes to realize that she is not only a woman (a subordinate identity) but also white (a dominant identity that few white people are consciously aware of), she thereby gains resources with which to resist her subordination. But the view of the authentic self as an integrated self is in direct contradiction to this fact, as made clear by considering such non-integrated identities. Normatively, a view holding as ideal an integrated self is unattainable by many persons, and is in any event not as ideal for multiply oppressed persons as it is for others; Meyers notes that for someone to identify wholeheartedly with “her victimization” would be foolhardy, as would wholeheartedly disidentifying with it, thus foreclosing the possibility of resistance.” Ambivalence, in some cases, is the proper attitude to take up. In summary, Meyers faults Frankfurt’s view for what she sees as an ideal of unity that above all is unresponsive to the reality of intersectional subjects, who are in fact internally divided and also stand to be harmed by taking wholehearted attitudes toward their identities. There are a number of elements of Meyers’s critique that put a great deal of pressure on Frankfurt’s account. The observation that intersectional subjects are motivated to resistance in virtue of self-knowledge of their own internal division should give pause to the proponent of unity. But one might wonder if the two accounts are so divergent on this matter; indeed, Meyers preempts the defense: Now, it might seem that Frankfurt’s idea of identification and integration gives these individuals a technique for coping with this predicament. 53 Meyers (2000). P. 169. 33 They can disidentify with the harmful attributes they have internalized, for example, self-doubt, servility, or submissiveness, and they can identify with the empowering attributes they have internalized, for example, a mordant sense of humor, persistence in the face of adversity, or a love of convivial gatherings.54 This, though, would lead to the damage noted above: to wholly deny or to wholly embrace, for example, one’s servility, is either to accept it and thus fail to resist it, or to deny it with the same effect. There are at least three misleading inaccuracies in Meyers’s reading of Frankfurt. The first is remediable, but still worth noting. It is not at all apparent in what way Frankfurt’s account would absorb the attributes, such as servility, that Meyers is concerned with. On Frankfurt’s view the basic constituents of identity are desires. Desires with which a person identifies are associated with the things she cares about — principles, ideals, political causes, other persons, her own projects — things she identifies with. Thus, unless the case involves a person who cares about being servile — that is, like Hill’s Deferential Wife has a desire to be servile that she wants to persist — Frankfurt’s account is simply silent regarding such attributes. Meyers’s misreading, then, is the simple substitution of ‘attributes’ for ‘desires’ in Frankfurt’s account. But on this point, Meyers’s characterization of identity, as including more than just desires and objects of care, is more accurate than Frankfurt’s. While a person may sometimes feel like nothing more than a bundle of desires, identity is more broadly 55 constituted, and includes, inter alia, attributes such as servility. While a person could 5‘ Meyers (2000), p. 170. 55 It could be argued that such attributes reduce to or ground in desires; ‘servility’ is just a term to characterize a certain set of desires, and reference to these desires is ineliminable when explaining the volitional, practical nature of personal identity. 34 have a desire to be servile, this is distinct from the notion of servility as an attribute. What is the relation between the desire and the attribute? The relation hinges on the second distinction. For Meyers, to identify with something is to embrace it, to disidentify is to eschew.56 These suggestive terms (the only characterization of ‘to identify’ that Meyers offers) obscure the difference that can be drawn between desires and attributes. To identify with a desire, Frankfurt has claimed, is sometimes to want to be motivated by it.57 The simple (and simplistic, as this notion of identification becomes more rich in his later writings) distinction here is from those desires one does not want to be motivated by. A person disidentifies with her desire for a sports car if she does not want to be motivated by the desire she has for such a car. She may realize that she has the desire only because she saw an advertisement and does not want to be swayed by advertising, or because her friend recently bought a sports car and she realizes her desire is mere envy. She, in what amounts to a process of self-constitution, makes unwanted desires external to her, and makes a desire with which she identifies internal to her. The desire with which she identifies becomes not a force moving her, but she moving herself.58 In later works the notion of identification, and especially the radical freedom of self—constitution the earlier notion included, Frankfurt admitted to be less a matter of approval than of acceptance. One who identifies with a desire not only wants it but also “takes responsibility for the fact of having the desire”59 If our advertising victim finds ¥ :Meyers (2000), p. 170. :Frankfurt(l988), p. 18; (1999), p. 105. :,Frankfurt (1988), p. 170. 59,Frankfurt (1988), p. 170. 35 herself unwilling to distance herself from the desire for a sports car she may (again, if she is honest with herself and others) admit that the desire is hers. The desire may be so trivial that it does not merit the energy needed to expunge it (some of us have a strong desire to put on our shoes either left-first or right-first, for example). And about all of this, the person is satisfied: lacking the intention, desire, or motivation to identify differently, one who is satisfied with her identity (or with certain elements of it) is in “a state constituted just by the absence of any tendency or inclination to alter its condition.”"0 On this view of the process of identification, there appear to be more nuanced options than either embracing or eschewing an attribute. A person who has internalized the attribute of servility, on this view, does accept that she is motivated by this attribute; she takes responsibility for her servility, not because she imposed it on herself and not because she embraces it. She may identify with it as a matter of self-honesty, and with a lack of resources to change this element of her identity. On Meyers’s more hopeful narrative, the servile woman is imagined to possess resources, other identity elements, in the light of which she might disidentify herself from the attribute of servility. Because the woman identifies with her persistence in the face of adversity, she need not be satisfied with her servility. But this is not, as Meyers assumes, to deny that the woman has the attribute of servility forced upon her. What Frankfurt’s notion of identification accurately shows about this sort of case is that a person can be affected by something - the attribute of servility, which no matter how persistent the woman, she will still be affected by to some degree - without her identifying with it. ‘ 60 Frankfurt (1999), p. 104. 36 Thus a structural account need not lead to the sort of ossification that Meyers claims, for a number of reasons that we have just seen: it is not the case that Frankfurt’s view entails that the authentic self is a unified self, nor are the options for a person’s stance toward various elements of her identity exhausted by either complete acceptance or total denial. Further, as I will now explain, any worry about the ossification of identity is not unique to a structural view. While ‘ossification’ is not a philosophical term of art (and so has no specifically relevant definition), it does suggest an array of synonyms: ‘crystallization’, ‘immobilization’, ‘rigidity’, and ‘inflexibility’. Something that is ossified has all of its constituent parts locked together in a certain unchanging, unchangeable pattern, an assembly that might be thought to break under force, rather than bend. To become ossified is to lose one’s resilience. To be sure, a structurally integrated identity would lend its possessor a certain degree of steadfastness in her actions and projects: she tends to know what she wants, and how much she wants it in relation to other things she wants. She is not apt to be ambivalent, and so will not be easily swayed from a decision to pursue a goal with which she wholeheartedly identifies. Suppose a person identifies with a desire to eat organic food. Suppose further that the desire is one with which she identifies wholeheartedly; this desire coheres with her other desires — to attend to her health, to minimize the amount of chemicals produced, to shop at that little co-op down the street that her friend is an owner of — and she Wholeheartedly identifies with no conflicting desires, such as the desire to be frugal. But 37 after she and her partner adopt a child, she finds (contrary to her earlier calculations) that she cannot afford to feed herself and her child with organic food. Now she may continue to identify with the desire to eat organic, even though she cannot act on the desire. This would likely cause her a fair amount of distress, and so she might well disidentify with the desire by a process of internal restructuring.“ Lower on the rank-ordered scale would go her desire to attend to her health (she knew she’d get less sleep and exercise while raising a child, anyway) to make room for the whole set of desires that accompanies caring for a child. This example is of a familiar sort. A person has all of her priorities organized, and a change in the world — even a positive change — spurs a reorganization in response. A structural account of identity, further, explains why a person presented with an external change undertakes internal changes. Desires carefully ordered may be free of conflict, but such a set is always subject the addition of desires caused by changes in the world.62 Desires may atrophy, too, for reasons external to their possessor, and this is well characterized by the negative notion of satisfaction described earlier. To be satisfied with one’s desires is not to experience some positive feeling (like the satisfaction one gets from eating a favorite food). If this were the notion of satisfaction in play, it would be unclear how a desire might fall out of one’s internal economy; the lack would be noticeable, and even painful. But satisfaction defined as the lack of internal conflict is R 6' She could, and we sometimes do, continue to identify with desires that she knows cannot be satisfied. To do this to a large extent, though, limits the practical nature of one’s identity; one who identified only with impossible-to-pursue desires would be unable to act at all. 62 This is more consistent with Frankfurt’s actual claim regarding ‘rank ordering’. He explains that when “the issue is which desire to satisfy first [. ..| the competing desires are integrated into a single ordering” (1988, p. 170, author’s italics), a set that would need to be reordered when a novel desire presents itself at some point in the prioritization. 38 consistent with the loss of desires with which one was satisfied, so long as the loss of the desire does not itself bring about a conflict. Through the foregoing discussion it can be seen that the unity of identity can be characterized in such a way that is attentive to the practical contingencies of the lives of real persons. This is due in large part to the practical criteria on which structural unity is based. The manner in which desires are moved around is not voluntaristic, at least not primarily so; thus even to acquire, expunge or reorder desires involves a practical move, not merely a mental one. The conflict on which unity itself is judged is often a practical one as well. Amy Mullin’s warning that “it is important to avoid assuming that effectively unified selves must be homogeneous or integrated to the point that harmony is rarely threatened,”"3 which she takes proponents of unity to have done, is thus a useful one. That the ideal sort of unified self is an efiectively unified one, rather than absolutely unified, is consistent with the present project. Unity, oppression, resistance Cui bono fuerit? (Whom did it benefit?) - Longinus Cassius Tracing the steps the present chapter has taken shows that the concerns have been primarily, though not entirely, theoretical. The notion of ‘identification’ itself and the related hierarchical process by which one comes to identify were questioned for their conceptual plausibility. The suggestion that structural accounts support ossification was ‘53 Mullin (1995), p. 3. 39 made in the interest of alternative philosophical theory. Paul Benson’s appeal to oppressive socialization is best taken to be predominantly a counterexample used to illustrate theoretical problems within hierarchical accounts. One with an interest in the social effects of the ideal of unity and who agrees with Babbitt’s practical demands might wish them to be grounded in less opaque conceptualizations. That philosophical discussions of personal identity have, like the sorts outlined above, been largely ignorant of the practical effects of our conceptualizations is clear. But the matter of personal identity is much more than conceptual; the way in which identity is characterized has real effects on the persons it purports to describe. That the ideal of unity is just that — an ideal — straightforwardly suggests that those who fail to attain it have fallen short. What is more, since the ideal of unity is an ideal not so much about behavior (as, say, a utilitarian sort of moral ideal) as it is about the sort of person one ought to be, those who fail to achieve or even to pursue the ideal may be thought of as personally deficient, even defective. The ideal of the unity of identity does appear to be an ideology, in the pejorative sense of the term — what Charles Mills characterizes as theory with a “reliance on idealization to the exclusion, or at least marginalization, of the actual.”"4 Meyers’s reference to intersectional identity was made in order to point out that real people have disunified identities, and often face great practical barriers to altering that state. An account advocating identity unification must be responsive to these facts so as not to marginalize those who do not attain the ideal advocated by the theory. 6“ Mills (2004). p. 166. 40 Even if the ideal of unity does not ignore the actual, it may further oppression by contributing to the advantage of the dominant, in this way. If it is true that the ideal is virtually unattainable by the socially subordinate, then the ideal will, to borrow another of Mills’s characterizations of ‘ideology’, “reflect and contribute to perpetuate illicit group privilege”"5 insofar as only the dominant will be able to attain the goods that are associated with reaching the ideal. Who benefits? The members of dominant groups. Maria Lugones has, in advancing similar criticisms, provided a set of concepts under which different sorts of unity can be understood. I will adopt her nomenclature, and in describing it, draw out her associated criticisms and the responses that can be offered. Lugones argues that each human being — she uses the term ‘incarnate being’ — is composed of multiple persons. This admittedly (and I think excusably) “ontologically problematic”66 view flows from a phenomenology peculiar to the oppressed. She appeals to “examples of people who are very familiar with experiencing themselves as more than one: having desires, character, and personality traits that are different in one reality than in the other,”67 people who are not just of two minds about an issue, or who tend to be more understanding with their children than with their colleagues (or vice versa, as the case may be). The oppressed find themselves in different realities, different ““worlds””"8. In one “world” such a person may be playful (to use Lugones’s example), while in another it is impossible for her to be so. She is two persons: one playful, one not. 65 Mills (2004), p. 164. 6" Lugones (2003), p. 89. 67 Lugones (2003), p. 57. ‘8 Lugones (2003), ch 4; internal quotation marks Lugones’s. 41 That these two situations are different realities and not merely different contexts or environments is a feature not just of the altered subject who inhabits it. That the characteristics, abilities and desires are different in different “worlds” is a function of the different interpretations that are given, not only by the subject herself, in the various “worlds”. “If one can remember the intentions of the person one is in the other world and tries to enact them in the other, one can see that many times one cannot do so because the action does not have any meaning or has a very different sort of meaning that the one it has in the other reality.”"9 Regrettably familiar examples illustrate this claim well. A black man who intends friendliness is interpreted as friendly in some realities, but in other realities his actions (because of the interpretations given them by others) take on an aggressive meaning. A woman’s ‘No’ in one “world” is defiant, while in another it is insubordinate, and in yet another, coquettish. An incarnate being leading a life (of a very common sort) marked by such shifts in meanings and self—characterization is multiplicitous, on Lugones’s view. One of Lugones’s central projects is to depict the ways in which such multiplicitous subjects can resist the fragmentation that is alleged to characterize them. Thus Lugones’s target is the ideal of unity: arguing that such internal discontinuities undermine one’s ability for agentic action, or one’s bare personhood, or some other ability or status, is tantamount to fiagmenting such persons. Such fragmentation — simply by making attributions of fragmentation — that is the interpretation of multiplicity made by members of the dominant group is itself oppressive. Thus, “the negotiations of the relation between ‘9 Lugones (2003), p. 57. 42 fragmentation and multiplicity by resistant subjects become central to an understanding of resistant subjectivity.”70 Lugones’s recommendations for resistance introduce another valuable concept, ambiguity. Actions can be intended ambiguously: instead of intending either a resistant or an oppressed action — that is, acting from either a resistant or oppressed identity — one can issue an action from both, intending that the action be interpretable as either resistant or oppressed or both." For example, a black housekeeper might fail to arm the security system, an action that she intends to be both oppressed (as when her employer attributes the failure to her perceived ineptitude) and resistant (since it indicates disdain for her employer’s possessions). A person can also (in a distinct, though still ambiguous, sense) ambiguously inhabit an identity that has been externally imposed. To do so is to “block identification” with an oppressed identity, while still acknowledging it; Lugones does not intimate that such an identity can be cast aside simply by refusing to acknowledge it, but does offer this sort of ambiguity as a defense against bald uptake of oppressive identities.72 As an example illustrating the notion in his second sense of ambiguously inhabiting a certain identity, consider a lesbian couple who, on being publicly slurred for their sexuality, engage each other in an openly passionate kiss.73 The act is oppressed: after being accused of being lesbians (which is often what slurs partially entail), they prove it, so to speak. It is also an act of resistance, openly acting in a way that is 7" Lugones (2003), p. 32. 7' Lugones (2003), p. 13. 72 Lugones (2003), p. 74. 73 This example is borrowed from Mason (2002), who discusses the conditions under which such acts of resistance can be intended as such. 43 proscribed. In intending ambiguously, these women can inhabit an identity while not giving it, and especially its oppressive aspects, full uptake. It is the first sense of ‘ambiguity’ that is especially interesting for the present project. This sense of the concept requires a slightly different example, since it regards ambiguity between, rather than within, identities. 74 A woman who is both a mother and a wife might ambiguously intend her refusal to tolerate her son’s and husband’s collective disrespectful sloth. As a mother, the act is authoritative; as a wife, it is insubordinate. In intending ambiguously she intends the act to be interpreted in both ways, and the act flows from both of her identities. Though this tactic would likely take substantial psychic resources, and likely carry the same risks as any other resistant actions, it is an important observation that an action need not be, to use another of Lugones’s terms, “monosensical”.75 The notion of ambiguity explains how multiplicity can be retained without entailing fragmentation, the fragmentation that is supposed to follow from internal diversity. Ambiguous intending makes it possible for one to retain her moral and agentic standing in the face of “mainstream, institutionalized morality” that presupposes the unification of the self, since she acts in a way that makes sense to such a morality, but also retains her integrity. 76 And though resistant actions, even those ambiguously intended, open one up to substantial risks, the motivation to perform such socially and personally valuable actions might well be found in ambiguous intending. 7" Lugones’s own example of an act intended as both incompetence and sabotage (p. 13) is inadequate to fully illustrate the notion of intent, since incompetence is more clearly a matter of ability rather than intent. 75 Lugones (2003), p. 7. 7" Lugones (2003), p. 14. The notion of ambiguity, then, is valuable, as is its practice. Further, ambiguity is not inconsistent with the ideal of unity. The notion of unity as a practical rather than metaphysical unity is able to take up this element of multiplicity on which one brings her internal economy into some sort of order through a harmony of action. Recall the lesbian couple in the earlier example - each has conflicting reasons for action (to express herself through a display of affection, as well as to refrain from doing so). Lugones advocates a practical reconciliation of this conflict by intending ambiguously, a reconciliation that entails a practical unification: whatever the state of one’s identity, the actions that issue from it are not in practical conflict. The agreement between ambiguity and unity may be the result of a misrepresentation or inaccurately narrow characterization of unity. At times (though rarely) Lugones appears to take a specifically Kantian conception to task. “Reason, including its normative aspect, is the unified subject. It is what characterizes the subject as a unity.”77 But this ‘reason’, especially its normative aspect, is a practical notion: reason — practical reason — is said to unify the subject so that she can act. This is the same accomplishment as that of ambiguous intending: the practical (not metaphysical) unification of an agent. If practical unification is problematic, ambiguous intending can hardly be an acceptable alternative. It is in the recurring claims about the fragmented subject’s supposed “inconsequential or attenuated sense of agency”, without the appeal to ‘Reason’, that Lugones suggests her target to be perhaps a more contemporary defender of unity, such as Frankfurt, Dworkin, and even Benson and Chri stman, who each takes as central to the 7’ Lugones (2003), p. 129. 45 exercise of autonomy some variant of unity.78 Much the same criticism holds here: that contemporary defenders of structurally-based accounts of autonomy advocate a unity that is not necessarily based in rationality does not distinguish their projects from Lugones’s as regards unification in action. The sort of unification at which Lugones might ultimately be directed is the supposed unification of groups. “If the person is fragmented, it is because the society is itself fragmented into groups that are pure, homogeneous.”79 Since group identity is an important constituent of one’s overall identity, the sort of structure that characterizes these groups might be thought to mirror the internal structure of those who gain their identities from membership in these groups. As Amy Mullin writes, the fact that “. . .the appeal of unity is used to eliminate the disadvantaged or marginal suggests another reason why we should be uneasy about attempts to rid ourselves of inner differences or conflicts.”80 The same sort of reasoning on which recalcitrant elements of a social group are excluded, the worry runs, functions to exclude certain elements of a person from herself. Even if assumptions of group essentialism were the only or even the primary cause of personal fragmentation, it is not at all clear how ambiguous intending could constitute a remedy. To intend that one’s actions flow from, and be interpretable in the light of, more than one identity - identities that are each supposed to be homogeneous — does nothing to undermine or even deny the purported homogeneity. The sharp distinction between oppressive and resistant intendings that is a feature of ambiguity can X : Lugones (2003), p. 5. so Lugones (2003), p. 141. Mullin (1995). p. 15. even be seen to reinforce one’s self-conception as a member of two essentially and radically different groups. It seems, then, that the weak point in Lu gones’s critique of the ideal of unity is the imprecise characterization of ‘unity’. Though this may make the account of unity that is being defended here perhaps too resilient, it is clear that at the heart of an account of an identity that motivates action, enables one to act with integrity and to love — all practices that require subtle and varied abilities, sensitivity to contingencies, and an appreciation of the complexities both of the world and especially of the persons who inhabit it — one will find multiplicity without fragmentation. If this is indeed the goal of both those who lack unity as well as those who are better placed to realize it, that is, the goal of both the subordinate and the dominant, then the answer to Cassius’s question is ‘everyone’, at least everyone with a direct and immediate interest in these goals.8| In this way will the account of unity presented in the next chapter and defended in those following be attentive to the oppressive possibilities of marginalizing conceptualizations. 3‘ That is, I don’t take the ideal of unity to be relevant to the severely cognitively disabled, for example. That this excludes a certain (perhaps large) set of people is true but unavoidable, since there are vanishingly few substantial claims that are true of every human person. 47 _2_ The Unity of Personal Identity The criticisms of the ideal of unity addressed in the last chapter were criticisms of the unity of identity as conceived quite generally. That is to say, opponents of the ideal of unity tend to take up arms against an underdescribed adversary. Having shown that the criticisms of unity (conceived of generally) can be answered, the next task is to outline the specific sort of unity of identity to be defended. The unity of personal identity is a twofold notion, composed, of course, of ‘personal identity’ and ‘unity’. I will address these two concepts first separately, and then draw from these separate analyses in outlining the specific form of the ideal of the unity of personal identity that I have in mind. I will explain — and defend as plausible — various points of compatibility between views of identity including narrative, group identification, self-conception, and desire-endorsement views. That is, certain of the issues on which competing views do not conflict (whether explicitly or implicitly) are, for the present purposes at least, the most philosophically interesting issues (rather than, as is usual, the points of contention). I will not here construct a theory of personal identity de novo, though I do maintain that the views of personal identity on offer sum to a credible if understandably incomplete account. To look ahead: the main point of agreement between the accounts is as follows. All the views of personal identity that will be discussed (which I take to be illustrative of the range of major approaches), on a plausible reading of each, accommodate Harry Frankfurt’s notion of endorsement as underlying the relation 3 person has to elements of her identity. Just what counts as an identity element is what distinguishes the various views that I will defend as compatible and complementary: narratives, desires, group membership, practical self-conceptions are each elements of a person’s identity. Roughly, for a person to endorse some element with which she identifies is for her to be satisfied with it, that is, for the element to be part of her psychic and practical life without conflict or resistance from her. Following from this, I will describe a conception of unity as freedom from conflict between one’s identity elements. I now turn to a critical explication of major contemporary accounts of personal identity. 0n personal identity Philosophical discussions of personal identity have primarily addressed one of two only indirectly related questions, which Marya Schechtman has termed the reidentification question and the characterization question.1 The reidentification approach to personal identity, which this work is concerned with only indirectly, aims to discover the criteria in virtue of which some person is identical with some temporally prior person. Reidentification accounts are thus concerned with the diachronic identity of persons. This discussion of reidentification has dominated the philosophical literature, spawning a wide variety of accounts of personal identity over time — memory‘, consciousness’, psychological traits generally", character’ and other features of human ' Schechtman (1996). 2 Commonly attributed to John Locke. 3 What Locke more plausibly took to ground personal identity. He in fact denied the relevance of memory explicitly: “being interrupted always by forgetfulness [. . .and] even the best memories losing sight of one part whilst they are viewing another [...] concerns not personal identity at all.” (Locke 1690/1964, 2, XXV II, 10.) See Schechtman (1996), pp. 107ff for an argued denial of Locke’s holding of a memory view. 4 Parfit (1984/ 1987). 5 In the somewhat peculiar sense of “projects and categorical desires with which the person is identified” (Williams 1981, p. 14) 49 life have been adduced as the ground of personal identity. The most important reason for noting this conception of personal identity — a conception that takes as central the ‘identical to’ sense of ‘identity’ — is to distinguish it and the philosophical literature that addresses it from the characterization understanding of personal identity that is at issue here. Characterization accounts of personal identity, on the other hand, aim at explicating the features in virtue of which a person is the person she is. The sense of ‘personal identity’ that is sought in the stereotypically adolescent or midlife question ‘who am I?’ is the sense such accounts address. (Preempting some misplaced criticism is the reminder that personal identity is not automatically equivalent to biological identity, historical identity, racial identity, and so on. That is to say, though ‘being a bipedal mammal’ is, in everyday experience, an identifying criterion for persons, this characteristic is not (typically) an element of personal identity.) The question of what makes a person the person she is can seek two sorts of answers. One regards the features of personal identity generally: of what elements is a personal identity constituted? Call this ‘the general characterization question’. This question assumes that identities are distinguishable entities — that they exist, have causes and effects, and that true and false claims may be made about them. Similar assumptions have been made - and questioned — in related discussions of the self, and in reidentification accounts of personal identity" I will not question the assumption here, as I take it to be correct. Nor will I be centrally concerned with determining precisely what features constitute a personal identity. I wish the arguments in defense of the ideal 6 Dennett (1989) questions the assumption that the self exists; Parfit ( 1984/ 1987) argues that whether in a certain instance the relation of diachronic identity holds is indeterminate, and thus it is neither true nor false that the relation holds. 50 of unity, the thesis I am supporting here, to be applicable to as wide a range of conceptions of personal identity as possible. The second question of characterization, which I will call the ‘specific characterization question’, is, given some account of what features constitute identities generally, whether specific instances of these features are to be attributed to a given person. So, for example, imagining as Hume did that persons “are nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions”7 , this second question of characterization asks, regarding a given person, which perceptions belong to (or more in accordance with Hume, are) her? In defending the unity of identity, the specific characterization question will be the most important characterization question. Since the unity of identity regards the unity of the specific features of a given person’s identity, the question of which features specifically characterize her will need to be answered prior to a determination of their state of unity. But since, as noted above, I intend the following arguments to be applicable to the range of answers to the general characterization question, I will briefly outline the most prominent established accounts of characterization. Given that I do not expect agreement between all answers to the specific characterization question, I will address specific views separately. Narrative views In order to illuminate the essential ideas of a narrative view of identity, 1 will Concurrently discuss two recent accounts, those of Marya Schechtman and Hilde Lindemann". I choose these two for a number of reasons. The approaches of both writers \ 1: Hume (1739/1978), Book 1, Part 4, section 6. Then writing as Hilde Lindemann Nelson. 51 are more social than metaphysical — that is, the accounts aim to explain the ways in which narrative and identity shows how people fit into the social world, rather than defending a certain view of what persons essentially are.9 Relatedly, the accounts share with the present work an interest in the effects of identity on agency. Schechtman and Lindemann also disagree in revealing ways, showing chief points of dispute between narrative views. Schechtman defends what she calls a narrative self-constitution view of personal identity. On this view, “a person creates his identity by forming an autobiographical narrative — a story of his life.”10 By virtue of inclusion in such a narrative, actions, experiences and personal traits come to belong to the person whose narrative it is. The converse is said to hold as well; ”When a person is unable to explicate part of her narrative, some set of her actions and experiences are incomprehensible to her and, hence, not properly under her control.”ll This claim brings out at least two important features of Schechtman’s narrative account. One is that a the elements of a person’s identity must be comprehensible to her, in the way that narratives lend such understanding — that is, by interpreting certain elements in the light of others, and in the more overarching light of a meaningful, temporally unfolding progression of events. Also suggested by the cited passage is the importance of self-understanding to agency, a recurring topic in discussions of characterization, and one that I will return to shortly. The core of the account — self-constructed narrative — carries with it seemingly contradictory elements. One element is the plausible allowance that a person’s self- narrative need not be entirely explicit (here I will follow Schechtman’s equivalent use of 9 The metaphysical-narrative foil 1 have in mind here is Dennett (1992), the central argument of which is that selves, narratively constituted, are entirely abstract fictions. '0 Schechtman (1996), p. 93. ” Schechtman (1996), p. 118. 52 ‘to make explicit’ and ‘to articulate’). Another, contradictory demand is that it must be a story in a recognizable form. If the story must be in such a form — what Schechtman calls standard (alternately, traditional) linear narrative — it is not clear how it could be anything other than explicit, since that is just what narratives are.‘2 One way to relieve the tension caused by these claims is to note that Schechtman’s standard linear narrative criterion, though given a fair amount of attention by Lindemann, isn’t a demanding one. The notion of ‘standard narrative’ is described as accommodatingly indefinite and as such is an ineffective criterion for judgment. The notion allows almost anything to be considered standard, even something of a completely novel form. In addressing “the question of just how different a narrative must be before it is removed from the family of narratives making up the standard form,” Schechtman allows that both “brilliant moments in fiction” and analogously “brilliant lives” may expand the notion.‘3 Thus what is standard is indeterminate, making it unclear just what ‘standard’ means if not ‘usual’ or ‘common’ or the like. Further, the criterion is not ultimately a criterion for judgment at all. Since future cases determine just what is standard, we can’t use that concept to judge a certain narrative; on Schechtman’s description, narratives (“brilliant” ones, anyway) help us to ascertain what is standard, not the other way around. '4 ‘2 Even accepting that there is more to a narrative than just words (or even just images, as in narrative film), the other elements of narrative (characters, actions, meanings) are ultimately directly dependent on explicit discourse (Barthes and Duisit, I975). '3 Schechtman (1996), p. 105. '4 And perhaps expand the concept to the point at which it does not do the work that Schechtman intends. For example, the novel Life of Pi (Martel, 2001) is the story of a young boy, Pi, adrift on a lifeboat which also happens to be carrying a Bengal tiger, a hyena, a zebra and an orang-utan. The story primarily revolves around the plight of the castaways and Pi’s ultimate survival. What undermines the use of this book’s specific sort of narrative in providing a model of a person’s life history is this: Pi offers not one but two equally internally coherent, equally explanatory but radically distinct and incompatible accounts — narratives — of his experience on the lifeboat. 53 It should be clear that the story of one’s life does not need to be fully articulated. To make such a narrative completely explicit would be practically impossible.” A narrative identity does, though, need to be locally articulable. On this issue, Schechtman claims that a person must, for the most part, be able to explain her actions, thoughts, feelings and desires with reference to the narrative that constitutes her identity. But Schechtman also realizes that there are identity elements that an outside observer can see are attributable to a person who flatly denies their presence. She gives an example of a man who claims only affection toward his brother but tends to ““forget” his brother’s birthday, “unwittingly” serve his least favorite foods when inviting him to dinner, “inadvertently” say things that humiliate him, and so on.”"’ A sharp observer can see that the man has hostility toward his brother. On the narrative self-constitution view, is this hostility part of the man’s self-conception — the story he tells about himself? According to Schechtman, somewhat surprisingly, it is. The hostility is motivating his behavior and affecting his emotions, and so is aptly ascribed to him. She concludes that while “the hostility is not part of the story this person tells of himself, then, it can still be part of his self-conception in a very real way.”'7 If this is true, though, it is not clear that the l"-personal narrative is the root of personal identity. A plausible criterion of local articulatibility, then, is that for some action, feeling, belief, or the like to be attributable to a person requires that some advantageously placed observer — perhaps an outside observer — be able to explain the way in which the trait fits into its possessor’s '5 As well as impossible in principle. In Jorge Luis Borges’s story “Funes, the Memorious”, Ireneo Funes sustains a head injury that destroys his ability to forget. Ireneo thus sets out to catalogue the entirety of his experiences, which the reader comes to realize is futile: he must, of course, catalogue his cataloguing, thus condemning him - nightmarishly - to a life of infinite regress. ‘6 Schechtman (1996), p. 116. ‘7 Schechtman (1996), p. 116. 54 life story. This might be more in line with Schechtman’s thought that whether or not people ever do formulate an explicit narrative about certain elements of their identity, they have “a general set of background assumptions about themselves and their lives to guide the unfolding of experience.”'8 Given that unconscious self-assumptions ground identity, though, casting the view as one of self-constructed narrative seems a bit misleading. Lindemann’s view does not attempt to defend such a first-personal advantage in the construction of identity. She maintains that an identity is a number of stories, both first- and third-personally given. As might be expected, stories from different sources will not always agree. Lindemann claims, “some of the stories that constitute a person’s identity may be deeply at odds with one another.”19 This is in direct contrast to Schechtman’s demand that “in order for a narrative to be identity-constituting, it must have a high degree of coherence.”20 While I maintain (and continue to argue) that there are important reasons to think that a person’s identity ought to have a high degree of coherence, it is another matter entirely to assert (as Schechtman does) that the lack of such coherence is tantamount to the lack of an identity itself. There are many persons who simply are unable to tell a coherent story about their lives. Have such persons no identity? A powerful example of such a failure of narrative ability and its effects on identity is given by Susan Brison in her philosophical and personal exploration of her own survival of sexual violence." Brison does not offer a distinct account of narrative '8 Schechtman (1996), p. 116. ‘9 Nelson (2001), p. 76. 2° Schechtman (1996), p. 98. 2' Brison (2002). 55 identity; her project is an analysis of the destruction of the identity of victims of violence. Telling a narrative, she explains, requires accurately descriptive words, concepts and metaphors, as well as an audience willing to listen and able to understand; both of these prerequisites, necessary for making coherent sense of one’s experiences, are often unavailable to victims of violence. Brison argues that this failure of narrative ability undermines the remaking of the self that is destroyed by violence. Such an example might be taken in support of Schechtman’s implicit claim that an incoherent narrative identity is no identity at all. Brison, though, fails to distinguish between diachronic and synchronic identity, seemingly taking identity over time to encompass the whole of personal identity. She claims, inaccurately, that the narrative understanding of personal identity “is a version of the view that psychological continuity constitutes personal identity.”22 What is true on narrative accounts of the sort Schechtman defends is that a person is characterized with reference to elements that are interpreted and understood with relation to temporally distant elements — thus, an important part of the story of who I am is the story of my childhood. But neither a continuity theory nor a narrative theory of personal identity would plausibly hold that a person is characterized either by the connections she has with temporally distant elements nor by any specific examples of those elements themselves; indeed, one ability of a narrative is to make comprehensible the changes in a person over time. Thus the most that can be concluded from Brison’s argument is the discontinuity of identity over time, which is not equivalent to an identity destroyed. There may indeed be effects of violence that involve the destruction of person’s identities, but these effects 2" Brison (2002), pp. 40-41. 56 are not due simply to a temporal discontinuity (a condition which is commonly caused, for example, by certain insomnia medications which induce a short period of anterograde amnesia). Brison’s claim that the victims of violence are in some sort of undesirable identity state is certainly true, but the claim that they have no identity is not. While I am not claiming that Schechtman is herself failing to distinguish synchronic from diachronic identity (this is clearly not the case), it may be that Schechtman’s single-story understanding of identity — rather than Lindemann’s multiple- story conception — is committing her to an overly unitary account of what an identity has to be for it to be an identity at all. If this is the case, then the multiple-story understanding is much more acceptable. The multiple-story understanding is more plausible for other reasons, as well. Each person has at least two sorts of stories that constitute her identity — her own, and the ones others tell about her. These are the two basic elements of Lindemann’s conception of identity: “By ‘identity’ I mean the interaction of a person’s self-conception with how others conceive her: identities are the understandings we have of ourselves and others.”23 Indeed, this is consistent with the earlier example of the man who harbored unconscious hostility, which was part of his identity but only from the third-person point of view. Lindemann explicitly addresses the crucial role that other’s narratives play in a person’s identity. One important avenue through which other’s understandings become part of a person’s identity is the set of stories Lindemann terms master narratives. These stock roles are culturally mediated, oppressive or uplifting, and sometimes caracaturish: ‘dirty 23 Lindemann (2001), p. 6. 57 old man’, ‘Renaissance man’, ‘absent-minded professor’, ‘princess bitch’, ‘thieving nigger’, and so on. Master narratives are one important route through which one’s own stories are affected by those stories others tell about her; master narratives form much of the framework around which one’s own identity narratives are constructed. From a practical standpoint, master narratives are not only of use in explaining and justifying one’s own actions, but they function to oppress as well. The professor can appeal to a master narrative to explain and justify her lack of concern for trivial matters, while the ‘thieving nigger’ master narrative explains and purportedly justifies excessive police presence in predominantly black neighborhoods. Lindemann takes identity to have two basic elements — one’s self-conception and the conception others have of her. I agree with Lindemann that a third—personal attribution is part of one’s identity if she accepts it, through simple agreement or through infiltrated consciousness (as in Hill’s description of the deferential wife who takes up wholesale an inaccurate self-conception as a stable and value-conferring self-conception). But what of narrative attributions that are both inaccurate and not taken up by the person to whom they are attributed? Lindemann argues that such attributions are a part of the identity of the person to whom they are attributed in virtue of the phenomenon of deprivation of opportunity, damage that occurs when third-personal attributions unjustly prevent certain persons “from occupying roles or entering into relationships that are identity-constituting.”24 The damage, Lindemann argues, is caused to a person by others’ denial of her moral status in light of a negative identity attribution. So, in one of Lindemann’s examples, an emotionally sensitive Latina identified by others as ‘an 2" Lindemann (2001) p. 20. 58 overexcitable Hispanic’ might be viewed as morally incompetent and denied the role of caregiver.25 Another point of distinction between the two accounts is not unique to narrative accounts. While Schechtman claims that one’s identity is who she is, Lindemann takes an identity to be rather is a representation of who she is. Such claims — which I’ll show to be less merely metaphysical than they first appear - are usually made only implicitly. Sometimes the assumption that a person’s identity is who she is appears in an equivalent use of ‘identity’ and ‘self’ or ‘person’. Maria Lugones takes “the shift from being one person to being a different person” the core of “an account of identity”.26 More often a distinction between the self and identity is maintained, but the relation between the two is not specified. The likely motivation behind the notion of identity as representation is the thought that a person can be incorrectly identified. If identity and the self were one and the same, this disconnect between identifier and identified would be impossible in principle; a person cannot have an inaccurate self, though she be the subject of inaccurate identity- attributions. A narrative view of identity clearly explains the common phenomenon of misidentification: the story that is told about a person (either by others or by herself) simply fails to characterize the plain facts. If my earlier claim that inaccurate attributions are not part of a person’s identity is true, though, the notion of identity as representation is not bolstered by the phenomenon of misidentification Standing against such a notion of identity as representation — and in favor of a tight conceptual link between identity and the self — is a recognition of the power that 2’ Lindemann (2001), p. 27. ‘6 Lugones (2003), p. 89. 59 identities have in our lives. First-personal intemalizations of incorrect identities - as through infiltrated consciousness — can radically undermine agency. But if personal identities are merely representations, such effects would be difficult to explain in terms of identity. Some might see such claims as merely conflating or confusing ‘self’ and ‘identity’. The close conceptual relation I imply here, though, is not without reason. To explain, it seems a helpful analogy to consider the relation between ‘art’ and two types of works of art, as exemplified by, say, Pollack’s Full Fathom Five, and the more familiar and less abstract The Thinker by Rodin. Lindemann, for example, insists that the self is that thing that is represented by one’s personal identity; thus the relation between one’s personal identity and her self is the same as the relation between The Thinker and a person engaged in cogitation. There are two interesting problems with this line of thought. One is that not all art (vis, Full Fathom Five, one of Pollack’s most striking pieces of so-called ‘drip art’) is representational; I’ll return to this issue. Another problem is that while it is easy to imagine that there was some (human) model to whom The Thinker stands as a representation, it is less easy to conceive of the ‘self’ to which one’s personal identity stands as a representation. This is in large part because identities create (affect, modify, and constitute) selves.27 Indeed, whatever constitutes some self is either going to be something with which I identify or something with which others identify me. Now, an element unknown by me or by others — my as-yet unrealized interest in promoting socialism, say — if it affects my life or my actions, is as a force moving me 27 The other reason why a self cannot be conceived of prior to personal identity is that the description of a self (either the type or a token) will necessarily appeal to identifying elements, either general or specific. 60 from without. Lindemann’s claim that “how others identify me has a direct bearing on how freely I can exercise my moral agency”28 is indubitable — if, say, others inaccurately identify me as a transsexual based only on my androgynous outward appearance, my actions might be restricted and I would then experience what Lindemann calls deprivation of opportunity: I won’t be allowed to hold certain positions, or join certain organizations, or live in certain neighborhoods. As Lindemann writes, “a personal identity thus requires social recognition.”29 But all such considerations establish is that in some cases there are third-personal effects on the agential efficaciousness of personal identity. What these considerations do not establish — and more, what is false — is that a personal identity requires social recognition (or any other third-personal input) in order for it to be someone’s personal identity.30 Sometimes (often?) others are wrong about or just ignorant of certain elements of a person’s identity. Also, an element of a person’s identity need not necessarily be causally efficacious. Exemplifying both these claims is a person who neither acts on, nor allows others to know of, his pedophilic desires (desires which, to simplify the example, we can suppose he in fact wants to have). Now, there is a clear disanalogy between art and personal identity, a critic might notice: a piece of art, if it is a representation, is a static representation. Though the objects that art represents change, the work itself (typically) does not; for instance, though Rodin’s mistress Camille Claudel grew old, she is young in his F ugit Amor. ”8 Lindemann (2001), pp. 22-23. 2” Lindemann (2001), p. 81. 3" Except, it should be noted, in the somewhat trivial sense that any conceptualization requires a shared language. In this sense, then, while it is true that George Washington could not have been a pervert — the very concept post-dates Washington’s life — this is much less clearly a claim about Washington’s behavior and self-conception than it is a claim about personal identity. The Marquis de Sade was paradigmatically a sadist — that is, those characteristic behaviors lead to and were supported by his identification with them — even though the term post-dates his life. 61 Perhaps a better analogy, then, is one that takes the relation between the self and identity to be like that between time and a clock — the clock tracks the change in time. The serious difficulty in conceptualizing ‘time’ without ineliminable reference to those material changes that track time, though, only lends support to my argument here." Perhaps the critic might think a better analogy provided by the example of a security video camera. The image provided by the camera represents the ongoing activities of whatever or whomever is being filmed. As the subject changes, the representation changes (that is the point of security cameras, of course — when the subject changes in certain ways, the camera tracks those changes). To be sure, this analogy supports Lindemann’s argument that third-personally attributed identity elements can (through deprivation of opportunity) affect the lives of those to whom the elements are attributed (another feature of the typical use of security cameras). Besides the subject-relative nature of security camera images, this example corresponds to the narrative theorist’s conception of identities as essentially propositional, or at least similar to propositions in being truth-apt.32 This is not to say that video is composed of verbal claims, but rather that video is often used as a claim about some fact: the video can (in court, say) be used as a claim that she forcibly entered the locked storeroom. As such, it can be true or false, just as, the claim runs, personal identities can be true or false. 3' The difficulty is: assuming a very plausible sort of minimal physicalism with regards to epistemic beings, the claim that there is this thing ‘time’ that can be in principle disconnected from the physical world (that is, that there could be a period of time during which nothing happens) is an essentially empty claim, there being no evidence for it in principle. The knower-relevance of time is at any rate essential to the regnant scientific world-view (Einstein, 1961, ch 8, “On the Idea of Time in Physics”). 32 Lindemann, pers.comm.. 62 This understanding is if not strictly incorrect at least deceptively limiting. This is because, as will become clear through the investigations of the present chapter, personal identities are not composed of only propositional elements (narratives). Personal identities include as their various elements desires and group membership, to mention two examples. But neither a desire, such as the one that Chavez win the election, nor membership in a group such as ‘technogeek’, have truth—value. That such things as desires serve as constituent parts of identity also undermines the idea that identity is a representation, for desires are not representational. To return to the art/artwork analogy, consider the remaining option: that a personal identity is no more a representation than are many works of art.33 But this is not to say that a particular artwork just hangs there (except, of course, in the most literal sense), arbitrary and disconnected from anything else — artworks are about something, namely art. In a related manner, personal identities are about selves — that is, about persons. (What else would they be about?) Further, just as the only conceptual distance between ‘a work of art’ and ‘art’ is the distinction between type and token (an irrelevant distinction here), there need be thought no great conceptual distance between selves and identities. Though I’ve defended a particular stance on the matter, the question of the relation between identities and selves is in large part terminological, yielding no more practical knowledge, the sort with which I am primarily concerned here. With this practical goal in mind, I would like to turn to a primarily phenomenological denial of the plausibility of narrative understandings of identity mounted by Galen Strawson. 3’ Another striking example is given by DuChamp’s Fountain, which does not represent a urinal — it is a urinal. 63 Strawson has criticized narrative views of personal identity as being both factually and normatively incorrect. He argues that not only is it false that people generally understand themselves narratively, but it is also not wholly desirable that they do so. Since I take a narrative view of personal identity overall to be a plausible one, and take my views in the present work to be compatible with such a view, a rebuttal of Strawson’s arguments is in order here. I will first explain how Strawson’s claim that he is arguing against narrative accounts of personal identity is misleading in a way that undermines the applicability of many of his arguments to narrative characterization views. Second, I will address a few concerns about the overall plausibility of his own view. Strawson’s central distinction is that between persons who understand themselves as persisting through time — such people are Diachronic — and those who do not — Episodics. (It is important to keep in mind that this distinction regards the subjective experiences of persons rather than some physical or metaphysical fact.) Strawson claims to be Episodic himself, and as such does not experience a connection, in terms of stories or otherwise, between himself and some past or future self. He writes, “. . .I know perfectly well that I have a past [although] I have absolutely no sense of my life as a narrative with form, or indeed as a narrative without form. Absolutely none. [. . .] Another way is to say that it seems clear to me, when I am experiencing or apprehending myself as a self, that the remoter past or future in question is not my past or future, although it certainly is the past or future of GS the human being.”34 Thus, even though understanding oneself as (inhabiting) a temporally persisting body, the Episodic understands himself as not having a past and future (the same past and future that the corporeal body does have). 3" Strawson (2004), p. 433. Insofar as the point of contention is between Diachronicity and Episodicity, Strawson is not clearly arguing against the truth or desirability of any distinctly narrative conception of personal identity. What he is denying is the fact and ideal of a diachronic self-conception, a view of oneself as importantly connected to some past and future person in such a way that that past and future person is oneself. But, contrary to Strawson’s claims, Diachronicity is not equivalent to Narrativity, nor is being Episodic tantamount to being Nonnarrative. One consideration in support of this claim is that Strawson is not arguing against a narrative characterization view of personal identity, in spite of the fact that he somewhat misleadingly offers Schechtman’s account as an example of a narrative view of the sort he is discussing. Explaining how this is misleading will involve further elaboration on Strawson’s claims, as follows. Strawson explicitly claims that Narrativity is a “way for human beings to experience their being in time.”35 That is, one might have the temporal experience of herself as Diachronic, taking a special interest — self-interest — in the person she has been and will become. Strawson plausibly claims that many people whose self experience is of this sort, that is, people who are Diachronics, have a narrative view of the temporal connections, their temporal continuance taking the form of a story. In a related vein, Strawson offers a reply to the possible concern that Episodics have a dysfunctional connection with their own past, a past that is part of the Episodic’s life but not her own experience of it. This reply indicates the distance of his conception of narrative identity from that of many others. He writes, 3’ Strawson (2004), p. 429. 65 “the past can be present of alive in the present without being present or alive as the past. The past can be alive — arguably more genuinely alive -— in the present simply in so far as it has helped to shape the way one is in the present, just as musicians’ playing can incorporate and body forth their past practice without being mediated by any explicit memory of it.”36 Thus the musician can, consistent with being Episodic, not identify explicitly with her past self though that past self is in part an element of her present self. Now, one implication of this is that identity-constituting narrative, at least in the sense of it that Strawson is concerned to deny, is first personally explicit - that is, the connection with one’s past that Episodics are supposed not to have is a consciously admitted connection. This leads to another reason to think that Strawson’s arguments put little pressure on the claims of narrative identity theorists: neither Schechtman nor Lindemann deny that a person can have narrative connections that fail to be “mediated by any explicit memory” or thought. Now, these accounts might be thought to hold that at least some narrative connections are explicit; what Strawson is ultimately denying is that any such connections need be explicit. Lindemann allows, though, that the narrative identity of, for example, infants, is constructed of entirely third personal elements, and as such is not first-personally explicit.37 Infants are thus not Diachronic (very young infants, at least), though their identity is a narrative one, constructed out of the stories of family and caregivers. Invisibly to Strawson’s account (since it is entirely concerned with the person’s subjective experience), these narrative elements are explicit. Again, Strawson’s claims fail to fit their target. "6 Strawson (2004), p. 432. 37 Nelson (2002). Aside from the inapplicability of the discussion of Synchronicity, some elements of the notion beg for further defense. For example, the proffered case of the musician does conform to a plausible intuition — that many elements of a person’s past are a part of, and connected with, her present in perhaps more important ways that simply through her explicit awareness of it. But the thought that a person’s past might be connected with her present only in non—explicit ways is less plausible. It suggests that a person might think of herself (as a person embodied or otherwise) and/or her personal characteristics as coming into being very recently and ex nihilo (or at least, ex nihilo temporalis). While this sort of self understanding seems psychologically possible, consistent with Strawson’s denial that all persons do in fact conceive of themselves as diachronic, it would be at least factually inaccurate since both physically and socially a person is causally dependent on her past.38 It should be noted that even if it is the case that some persons experience themselves as Episodic, and even if it is defensible to claim that the Diachronic life is no morally better than the Episodic life, none of this undermines the claim that the Narrative life is not or should not be the sort we experience. This is because a narrative identity view need contain no distinctively temporal content. Much of Strawson’s argumentation appeals, largely implicitly, to the intuition that narratives (those of identity as well as literary fabulae) are essentially in the business of tracking events over time. In this context, this intuition is misleading. While Strawson admits that “the Narrative outlook clearly involves putting some sort of construction — a unifying or form-finding 3" This is not to say that all elements of a person’s causal past need be explicitly apprehended or even epistemically available to her. My claim regards a person’s denial (or failure to apprehend) that she has a causal past at all. 67 construction — on the events of one’s life, or parts of one’s life,”39 he takes the form to be a necessarily temporal one. But while many narratives draw connections between events on the basis of their position in a chronology, such chronological progression is neither necessary nor sufficient for narrative. Narratives can contain flashbacks (either in the minds of characters or in the story lines themselves), be conveyed in reverse chronological order,40 or radically rewrite the past.4| Narratives, in their role of form-findin g, also appeal not only to temporally distinct events as Strawson notes, but also to concurrent events (‘I love her because she loves me’) or phenomena that do not, strictly speaking, occur at some point in time (Lindemann’s master narratives neither happen at some certain time, nor do they even need to be understood as historical products for them to shape one’s identity). Thus the purported close link between subjectively-experienced Diachronicity and Narrativity is not close at all, and Strawson’s arguments against the former have little traction against the latter. Returning now to the earlier cited passage in which Strawson avers, “when I am experiencing or apprehending myself as a self, that the remoter past or future in question is not my past or future,”"2 we can uncover a problem with Strawson’s defense of Diachronicity itself. Sometimes the ‘form-finding construction’ is necessary for appropriate (I dare say ‘accurate’) interpretations of events and actions. If a person understands herself (as Strawson’s explicit definition of ‘Episodic’ has it) as one “who does not figure oneself, considered as a self, as something that was there in the (further) ’9 Strawson (2004), p. 440. 4" As in the clearly narrative films Memento (Nolan, 2000) and Irreversible (Noe, 2002). 4‘ As in Martel (2001). ”2 Strawson (2004), p.433. 68 past and will be there in the (further) future“, we cannot, for instance, correctly interpret her timorous demeanor as a reaction to her abusive childhood; there is no self-understood past self who was the subject of abuse. Though some may take this to be a liberating sort of self-conception, avoiding a Sartrean bad faith assimilation to one’s facticity, it seems more troubling than emancipatory — at the very least, it closes off an avenue of explanations of one’s less than desirable characteristics, putting the burden of responsibility entirely on oneself. Perhaps even more striking is the fact that, for an Episodic, certain common and familiar feelings and actions would be in principle impossible. While an Episodic might feel, for example, whatever is phenomenologically distinct about regret (since there is nothing psychologically impossible in doing so), whatever she feels wouldn’t be regret — there is (for her) no past self for whose behavior she feels bad. In fact, most if not all of the morally interesting of what we might call the ‘again-feelings’ (resentment, regret, remorse) and the ‘again-actions’ (react, revenge, recant, reconcile, redress) make ineliminable reference to past events. Remorse that does not refer to some past event is simply pathological guilt; it is wrong, of course, to take revenge for something that did not happen, and incoherent to do so for something that is not even believed by the avenger to have happened; and so on.44 Non-retrospective but still narrative constructions are relevant here as well. Looking forward in time is necessary for a goal to be a goal, that is, a goal aims at some future state of affairs. Non-temporally, there is a narrative on which the distinction between, to take just one example, the stealthy murder of an enemy and the merciful ‘3 Strawson (2004), p. 430. 4" Strawson promises to address these sorts of criticisms in his upcoming book Life in Time. 69 euthanasia of a loved one can only be made — the raw data (two people, one sleeping and the other injecting the first with morphine) are inadequate to the distinction. Narrative gives the tools for the understanding of and, indeed, the existence of such actions and feelings, though these tools need not be temporally grounded. Thus Strawson’s criticisms do not apply to distinctly narrative views of personal identity, nor to they seem to offer a plausible alternative view. Though we’ve seen no reason to think a narrative view incorrect, and many reasons to think such a view useful, the goal of characterizing all the major views of personal identity with which I take the ideal of unity to be compatible recommends that we consider non-narrative accounts of identity. The first of these that I will discuss is that of Christine Korsgaard. The importance of self-conception A physician of my very close acquaintance recently related to me a hospital case she was involved in, and quite troubled by. The absolute horror (her description) of the parents of the patient caused her no small amount of agitation for days after the incident. The patient was a lS-month old boy. As his father was pulling out of the drive in his truck, to leave for work, or to do the shopping, or whatever it is that parents so often must quickly and distractedly do, the child ran out to happily wave goodbye to his father. The truck, backing up, struck the boy, and ran him over; he died at the hospital. Though I was not witness to the emotional and personal disintegration the parents experienced, I doubt that those present, or even the parents themselves, could find words adequate to characterize it. For it is a terrible thing for anyone to cause harm to a child, even accidentally; fatally to harm one’s own child is quite beyond terrible. It is in a very 70 real sense impossible. It is impossible not because such things do not in fact happen (they do). It is impossible because being a parent just is being a person who protects her child. In failing to do so, this child’s parents failed to be parents; they failed, that is, to be who they were. ‘Parent’ is an example of what Christine Korsgaard calls a practical identity. Each of your practical identities - each person has many — is “a description under which you value yourself, a description under which you find your life to be worth living and your actions to be worth undertaking?” ‘Philosopher’ is a practical identity, as is ‘socialist’, ‘Jennifer’s husband’, ‘American’, ‘mountaineer’, and so on. Much of Korsgaard’s argumentation is aimed at defending a certain (Kantian constructivist) conception of norrnativity against other (more straightforwardly realist) conceptions. Since this is a project that is tangential (though not irrelevant) to the one in the present work, I won’t reconstruct all of the arguments supporting Korsgaard’s more contentious conclusions here. Starting, rather, with a fairly uncontentious observation (being one of simple moral psychology rather than complex moral metaphysics), a person’s self-conceptions ground the grasp that practical reasons have on her. This claim is perhaps most clearly supported by a negative sort of example: when you cease to think of yourself as her friend, certain reasons that used to move you no longer do; you no longer are motivated to call her on her birthday, for example.“5 The specific ways in which such identities are of practical significance are virtually unmentioned by Korsgaard, but are well worth noting. For one, identities ‘5 Korsgaard (1996), p. 101. I will follow Korsgaard in taking ‘value’ to refer only to positive value (as in ‘I value your life’); I will use the term ‘evaluation’ in contexts where negative and positive degrees of value are at issue (as in ‘Having evaluated the painting, she found it lacking’). 4" This point about motivation is made at p. 120 (Korsgaard 1996). 71 structure reasons and put them on offer in a way that enables them to be a routine, accessible, helpful part of real lives. A mother does not have to identify, out of the innumerable reasons that there are, the reason that should motivate her, say, to take time off work to care for her ill child. As a mother, she simply does this; at the very least, she has reason to do this.“7 Her practical identity gives her a usable view of herself and how she fits into the world of possible actions. Identities provide interpretive schema, as well, so that a person can see a reason ascribed to her from an outside source as a reason, rather than seeing it merely as moralized browbeatin g. That is to say, for a reason to be my reason, for it to have authority over me, I have to conceive of myself as being a person to whom that reason applies. For example, though it may be true that any suitably placed person has an obligation to replace her car with a bicycle, only if she conceives of herself as an environmentalist (or a bicyclist, or a responsible citizen — the relation between identities and reasons is not one-to-one) will this obligation be seen as an authoritative reason for her. The intractability of the moral skeptic (the philosophical problem, that is; the skeptical person is intractable in a different sort of way) might usefully be understood in terms of these reason-giving features of personal identity.48 The skeptic, demanding a reason to be moral, insinuates that she does not identify as a moral person, or in Korsgaard’s Kantian phrasing, as a Citizen of The Kingdom of Ends. This is why no ‘7 ‘Mother’ in a certain sense; ‘female biological parent’ is compatible with ‘a mother does not abandon her child’, a statement I take to be false. ‘8 This situation might be usefully understood in a number of incompatible ways, of course. The point here is not to establish some thesis about what is really going on with the skeptic (one reason for this is that there are different sorts of moral skeptics), but that Korsgaard’s account has something interesting to say regarding this ancient issue. 72 answer will satisfy the skeptic: for her to take anything as a reason to be moral, she needs already to identify as a moral person, one who values herself as moral — or, if the answer involves connecting morality essentially to, say, religion, then the skeptic needs already to identify as religious. In this way the moral skeptic can be seen as exemplifying a global dependence of practical reasons (at least moral reasons) on identity.“9 Korsgaard argues that the reasons that flow from practical identities express obligations. To be sure, the way in which obligatory reasons are expressed sometimes implies that they are a function of one’s identity: A soldier never lays down his rifle; a Christian always leaves vengeance for God. This source of obligation is sometimes explicitly exploited, as in the Department of Transportation’s ad campaign using the slogan ‘friends don’t let friends drive drunk’. This is a very binding — categorically binding -- conception of obligation. For if practical identities are (the) sources of self-value, and if the committing of certain actions is tantamount to not possessing a certain practical identity, then certain actions entail a loss, sometimes substantial, of self value. That this is sometimes the case should be clear from the story of the parents that began this section. To violate your practical identity is to lose the self-conception on which your life is worth living. Thus reasons that flow from practical identities — at least one’s most important practical identities -- are unconditional in the sense that acting on them is the condition on which a person continues on at all, ‘9 There is a stronger claim about reasons that Korsgaard makes: the very existence of a reason depends on one’s practical identity; for example, in order for‘ it is the moral thing to do’ even to be a reason, the person for whom it is a reason has to conceive of herself as a morally-bound agent I don’t address this sort of claim here in part because it would take another book-length work even fully to describe the current state of the debate, and also because (as 1 see it) none of the claims I make here depend on the truth of the reasons- claim. 73 for to violate them is to lose [. . .] your identity, and to no longer be who you are. That is, it is to no longer be able to think of yourself under the description under which you value yourself and find your life to be worth living and your actions to be worth undertaking. It is to be for all practical purposes dead or worse than dead.50 This is certainly an extreme claim. It is not unique to Korsgaard, though. S.I. Benn presents a discussion of tragic dilemmas, in which no available option is acceptable without substantial and intolerable moral damage, but in which the agent nonetheless must act. “The kind of person one is,” he writes, “will be reflected in — or perhaps constituted by — the orderings manifested in decisions of this kind.”51 But the future tense — ‘will be reflected’ — is not necessarily apt; “Suicide may be an option, too, and could be chosen, rationally and deliberately, as an act expressing one’s uncompromising commitment to both [of two incompatible options] and one’s indignation at a world that offers only such intolerable alternatives.”52 To be forced into an intolerable ordering that shows “the kind of person one is” might recommend the self-termination of being a person at all. Examples supporting of the strong connection between identity and reasons to continue one’s life are available as well. Consider Kostas Georgakis, who in 1970 responded to the rising political power in Greece of a military junta by immolating himself. His hometown of Corfu has erected a monument to him, inscribed with his own words, ‘I cannot but think and act as a free individual.’ Georgakis’s conception of himself as a free individual gave him what he took to be a decisive reason for suicide. 5" Korsgaard ( 1996), p. 102. 5‘ Benn (1984), p. 35. 52 Benn (1984), p. 34. 74 Philosophy has its own paradigm instance of the value of a life determined by one’s practical identity. Socrates, to Crito’s pleading offer of escape from his pending execution, replied in what he claimed to be the words of his conscience as it spoke to him: ...if you go to one of the nearby cities — Thebes or Megara, both are well governed — you will arrive as an enemy to the government. [. ..] Or will you avoid cities that are well governed and men who are civilized? If you do this, will your life be worth living? Will you have social intercourse with them and not be ashamed to talk to them? And what will you say? The same as you did here, that virtue and justice are man’s most precious possessions, along with lawful behavior and the laws?” Socrates submitted to an execution that he, as a practical matter, could easily have avoided. He submitted in the realization that since he would no longer be able to propound his beliefs, no longer be able to be a philosopher, his life was not worth living. While accepting the implications of these and other similar examples, as well as accepting the tenor of Korsgaard’s arguments, I will dissent on two interrelated points. One point focuses on the categorical nature of identity-conferred reasons, the other on the claim that one’s identities always bring value to their possessor. I am, that is, going to accept (in light of the discussion immediately above) Korsgaard’s account as plausible and thus subject to the unity of identity ideal, but I am going to dispute two points within it. If a person conceives of herself as, say, a mother, and this conception contributes to the value that she takes herself to have, it is not necessarily the case that acting against the obligations derived from this identity leads to a loss in self-value. One way in which 5’ Plato, Crito, 53c. 75 persons maintain perception of their own value even when they act against their self- perceived identities is common enough: hypocrisy. The hypocrite continues to conceive of herself as living under a valuable description, but fails to act in accord with that description. A straightforward way to understand hypocrisy is as a cognitive failure to see the dissonance between what one is doing and what those acts show about who she is. This invisibility might be caused by erroneous interpretation of actions (‘That wasn’t a lie, just a harmless fib’) or of the requirements of certain identities (‘Yes, I’m a peace officer, but I don’t have to protect those people’). Some hypocrites, then, are simply the victims of their own interpretive incapacity. Others deserve at least some of the moral scorn heaped on them -— those whose hypocrisy is rooted in their narcissism, explicit double standards, or disregard for living up to anyone’s expectations, including their own. But whether hypocrisy is a cognitive or moral flaw, the hypocrite can continue to view herself as valuable even under the description that in fact fails to characterize her. The second point of dissent looks to the opposite end of the evaluative scale; while sometimes an identity can provide value no matter what actions accompany it, it might seem that some identities fail ever to provide value. Consider first an example in which a person’s identity does fairly clearly contribute to her self-valuing: a person one of whose practical identities is ‘philosopher’. Because she values herself as a philosopher, she is pleased when she does philosophical things — like publishing papers, giving lectures, talking to others about philosophical issues — and because she is thus pleased she is motivated to continue to do such things. She sometimes justifies her actions with reference to her identifying as a philosopher (‘You spent the whole weekend at the library?’ ‘Well, that’s what a philosopher does!’). 76 It is readily observable, though, that not all identities contribute to self-valuing. Some identities are (typically) unwanted: being homeless, for example, is an undesirable and undesired situation. Judging from the number of ‘I’m Homeless’ websites, forums and weblogs emerging on the Internet, it is a situation that leads a substantial number of people to identify as homeless (contrast this with other undesirable traits that only relatively rarely do people self-identify with: hypocrisy, narrow-mindedness, or miserliness). I speculate, though, that very few homeless people take ‘homeless’ to be a description under which they value themselves (though some do). Other identities are similar: ‘obese’, ‘lonely’, ‘member of an oppressed minority group’. In spite of this disconnect of identity from self-value, these identities are still practical in ways similar to the paradigm examples of practical identities. Even unwanted identities that the possessor admits she possesses (like ‘homeless’) motivate behavior: though the mere fact of homelessness can motivate behavior such as the seeking out of a shelter, the undesired identification as homeless can motivate behavior as well — perhaps behavior that serves to cover up the fact of being homeless. These observations undermine the necessity of a practical identity contributing to self-value. Turning away from explicitly philosophical lines of argument for a moment, certain observations of sociological theorists are relevant in explicating the connection between undesired identities and self-value. The terminology is a bit different, but the concepts are very similar. What Arnold Birenbaum calls a ‘social identity’ is constituted of roles, sets of expectations that constrain and obligate agents. 5“ Birenbaum takes as exemplary of roles ‘mother’, ‘senator’, ‘president’, ‘ex-convict’, and ‘scholar in 5‘ Birenbaum (1984). Here the focus is on the source of identity, which Korsgaard agrees is overwhelmingly social. 77 residence’ — the same sorts of categories that are practical identities. In an interesting merging of practical identities and (a certain conception of) narrative identities, he notes, “roles are associated with orderly accounts of the events that produced or were connected with [them]”55 In studying the disabled, Birenbaum reports that identifying as disabled, like other undesired or stigmatized roles, does contribute to self-valuing, though in a more roundabout way than Korsgaard suggests. Since disabled persons are stigmatized, taking up an identity that offers a narrative of how it is the person came to be so identified can reduce self-blame. The identity, as an account of events, explains and excuses negatively-perceived attributes. Thus identifying as disabled does contribute to a person’s sense of self-worth. Likely this phenomenon is generalizable; in a discussion of the nature of the identifications that play a role in hate crime, Michael Blake draws similar conclusions about the socially ostracized who take up their negatively-perceived identities a matter of pride.56 Similar mechanisms may well be involved, though at a more local level, in the process of terminological reclamation.57 Thus, there is empirical evidence to suggest that not all the elements of a person’s identity need contribute to her self-value in any direct or even indirect way. A person can gain value from her identity (hopefully this is the most common situation), but she may merely admit to possessing a certain identity, and only be minimally satisfied with it. This is an important point to bear in mind as the present discussion continues, since this fact of identification is central to the notion of endorsement. We will continue to see this 55 Birenbaum (1984), p. 322. 5" Blake (2001), p. 130. 57 As, famously, in Ensler (1998), “Reclaiming Cunt”. 78 importance in a look at another view of the source of personal identity, group identification Group identification Korsgaard explicitly claims the elements of identity to be descriptions. They are, though, descriptions of a broad sort. Virtually every example of practical identities she mentions refers to membership in some group — psychologists, parents, Christians. Only rarely does Korsgaard characterize practical identity in terms of anything like a specific description — e. g. ‘the first woman to walk solo to the North Pole’, or ‘Jennifer’s husband’ (the most specific example she gives is “someone’s lover or friend”). Though the notion of ‘a description under which you value yourself’ seems to imply relative specificity (I take ‘description’ to suggest more rather than less specificity), the claim that practical identities give practical reasons is most strongly supported with reference to descriptions of group membership. While the description ‘the first woman to walk solo to the North Pole’59 is most certainly one under which a person could value herself, it is not clear how it would confer obligations — since she has already done the thing that characterizes the identity. A description that is more useful in understanding the practical aspect of identity, such as ‘woman adventurer’, describes many - that is, a group — of women."0 That claim that identities are grounded at least to a significant extent in group membership is made explicitly in some characterization accounts. Diana Meyers reminds that “who we are — what we are like and how we think and act — is significantly ’8 Korsgaard (1996), p. 101. 59 Helen Thayer did this in 1988 at age 50, solo so long as one does not count the assistance of her canine companion, Charlie. 6" Such a large group that a number of companies make a business out of outfitting its members, and Women’s Adventure magazine provides a journalistic and advertising venue. 79 influenced by social systems of domination and subordination.”"l Personal identity — who one is - is thus significantly influenced by one’s memberships (or ascribed membership) in social groups, since social groups are the avenues for domination and subordination, at least in those forms of domination and subordination that are properly considered oppressive."2 The abovementioned article of Michael Blake’s makes connections between oppression and identity as well. He notes that for “membership [to] give rise to feelings of identification [. . .] it is not just the case that we recognize our membership in such groups - we also understand such membership as an essential part of our place in the world.”63 This claim is made in an analysis of hate crime — a category of offense that depends not merely on the victim’s group membership, but on a certain sort of membership: being a member of a group with which she is identified. Many of us are members of the group of people with brown eyes, but this is not a (type of) group with which we tend to identify. For our purposes, ‘feelings of identification’ will not help in explicating what it is for someone to identify with something, since feeling as if you are identified with some group is neither necessary nor sufficient for being identified with it. Nor is it clear why felt identification with a group must be essentially connected to our self-understood social position. It is odd to think that someone would consider themselves essentially homeless. Being homeless is plausibly thought of as an accidental characteristic of a 6‘ Meyers (2000), p. 153. 62 “If an individual is oppressed, it is in virtue of being a member of a group or category of people that is systematically reduced, molded, immobilized.” (Frye, 1983, p. 8.) (’3 Blake (2001), p. 129 80 person, and is nonetheless able — as many other accidental characteristics -- to contribute to our identities. The point of bringing up Blake’s understanding of group identity is not to point out the different uses of the term for his project and for mine. In fact, the differences are less notable than the connections his discussion makes between the various accounts of identity that have been outlined here thus far. One such connection is that in appealing to one’s group membership in her own social self-understanding, a person acquires a self- conception of the sort Korsgaard takes to be the root of reasons. Blake also notices what Lindemann did in constructing her account of counterstories: some of the elements of our identities are grounded in conscious resistance to oppression.64 Blake focuses on the accomplishment of reappropriation, the taking up of disparaging labels as a matter of pride; what Lindemann describes is a changing of the associations that the labels conjure up. What is important here is the common element of alterability: group-based elements of personal identity, whether characterized narratively or not, do not necessarily make inexorable demands of their bearers. Thus the practical impact of identities is not linked to a certain view of just what constitutes a personal identity. This, if you will recall, is entirely in the spirit of this chapter, which is importantly concerned with accommodating as well as conjoining various accounts of identity. In the next section, I will explicate Harry Frankfurt’s account of personal identity, which is centrally concerned with the practical efficacy of 6‘ Blake (2001), p. 133. 81 personal identity. I will be supporting Frankfurt’s view, as well as his notion of endorsement that will play a large role in characterizing the unity of identity. Desire endorsement views Addressing criticisms of the ideal of unity in the previous chapter gave much opportunity to outline Frankfurt’s conception of personal identity, but only in a negative context. Here it will be illuminating to review Frankfurt’s account in the interest of showing the connections between it and other conceptions of personal identity just discussed. Frankfurt takes personal identity to be comprised of desires. Now, as an early party to the philosophical discussion of personal identity, Frankfurt doesn’t use the phrase ‘personal identity’ as many more recent writers do. Rather, he speaks of the processes of identification by which one acquires and divests herself of the desires that comprise her as a person. But it is clear from later works that personal identity is just what he takes to be at issue."5 The object of the process of identification, Frankfurt ”6" and “the development of a distinctive and repeatedly claims, is “individual identity robust sense of personal identity.”67 Frankfurt takes persons most characteristically to be volitional beings; of any person he argues “the boundaries of his will define his shape as a person.”"8 The most stable of these boundaries, he argues, “comprise the necessary conditions of his identity.”69 I don’t intend to defend the all implications of these claims, but offer the passages only as illustrations of the core of such a view of personal identity. ‘55 And it is clear judging from the personal identity related claims of various of his critics, as discussed in Chapter 1, above. 6" Frankfurt (1999), p. 110. 67 Frankfurt (1999), p. 108. 68 Frankfurt ( 1999), p. 114. 69 Frankfurt (1999), p. 115. 82 According to Frankfurt a person identifies with desires through her endorsing them. Endorsement takes a number of forms, all grounded in a structural relationship between first-order desires — desires simpliciter, motivating desires — and second-order desires — those that take other desires as their object. Thus my desire to eat chocolate is a first—order desire, and my desire that my desire to eat chocolate cease is a desire of the second order. If I, alternately, desire that I desire to eat chocolate, I thereby endorse the desire to eat chocolate. If I, further, desire that my desire to eat chocolate is one that I want effectively to be motivated by (since I could desire to have but not act on a desire to eat chocolate), the desires are called volitions.70 Some desires, though they are endorsed, are fairly transient (my own desire to eat chocolate is of this sort). Others are desires that their possessor desires to continue — for example, were my desire to do philosophy wane, I would be concerned, and perhaps upset, since I desire that my desire to do philosophy continue. Desires of this sort play a role in caring. Those things that a person cares about are things that she wants her desires for to persist. Intuitively, things that a person cares about are most central to her identity, and we sometimes speak as if the person and the things she cares about are one and the same: if her project is thwarted, she is thwarted; if her lover is displeased, she is displeased.71 Benefits to the things cared about are benefits to she who cares about them, as well. Not every desire and characteristic that is properly attributable to a person is one that she actively and consciously cares about, or even is one that she actively desires to 7" The general practice in this context is to call all desires, whether volitions or not, ‘desires’ unless there is a specific point to be made with the distinction; the default is, understandably, to assume that an endorsed desire is one the person wants to be moved by. 7' These two examples might be taken to illustrate distinct phenomena: thwarting her project is tantamount to thwarting her, but there is a causal link between her displeasure and that of her lover. 83 have. Some undesired characteristics belong to a person if she simply accepts them - if she has a characteristic she prefers not to have but is not willing to expunge it; harmless vices that a person simply lives with are of this sort. Others a person wants to eradicate but is unable to, such as some unalterable behavioral trait, or an intractable chemical dependency. A point not often noted by critics is that Frankfurt does acknowledge (if only in passing) this feature of actual lives. Regarding the possession of desires just as in other aspects of life, he writes, “people often settle for less than what they think it would be possible for them to get.”72 A person’s identity, on Frankfurt’s model, is implied to be the whole set of first order desires with which she is satisfied, plus all the higher-order desires she has. Certainly a person identifies with more than just her first-order desires, her desires to do something or other. Frankfurt acknowledges that second-order desires can be subject to still hi gher-order desires; I might wish, contrary to fact, that I wasn’t satisfied with my desire to sleep through the morning’s lecture. A theoretically possible infinite regress into ever higher levels of endorsement is open to practitioners of extreme self-reflection, but for most of us, if we don’t find internal conflict rearing its head of its own accord, we don’t go looking for it. A critic of Frankfurt’s view might question what makes the a persons highest level desires (of whatever level the process terminates) hers.” The critic’s worry is that if her first-order desires are hers on the basis of her second—order desires, and those are hers on the basis of her third-order desires. . .then the merely theoretical possibility of infinite regress seems, to the critic, more than merely theoretical. 72 Frankfurt (1999), p. 103. 73 This is a version of Christman’s concern, discussed in Chapter 1, above, that an autonomous person’s higher-order desires themselves be autonomous. 84 One response to this worry is to reemphasize the point that endorsement is primarily a matter of satisfaction, or lack of conflict.” The worry, that is, takes its strongest form if ‘identification’ is taken to be an active connection between lower- and hi gher-order desires, since on this understanding in order to determine whether a lower- order desire belongs to a person there must be an appeal to some specific higher-order desire (the one that is to actively endorse the first), a specific hi gher—order desire about which it may be wondered whether it itself is hers. But since endorsement is ultimately a matter of a lack of conflict, there is no specific hi gher-order desire the status of which might be questioned. Now, this negative use of ‘endorsement’ — negative insofar as it denotes a state of lacking something, namely, conflict — might seem to stretch the notion of endorsement. The origin of the term is grounded in the practice of endorsing checks by writing one’s name on their back (‘dorsal’), certainly an active sense of the term. But consider this sort of use: In the fullness of time the ship was ready to receive her passengers. I was introduced to the young gentleman who was to be my roommate, and found him to be intelligent, cheerful of spirit, unselfish, full of generous impulses, patient, considerate, and wonderfully good-natured. Not any passenger that sailed in the Quaker City will withhold his endorsement of what I have just said.75 The claim is not that none of the passengers will fail actively to indicate their belief in the positive qualities of the roommate, but rather that no passenger would disagree. In this usage, ‘endorse’ is related to ‘approve’, a sometimes passive exercise, as when, say, ninety Senators approved (of) the bill — certainly not all 7“ Other responses to it can be found in Chapter 1, above, where Christman’s regress objection to Frankfurt’s notion of autonomy was addressed. 75 Twain (1869), ch. 2. 85 ninety sang the praises of the bill, but they were effectively satisfied with it, that is, did not ultimately dispute its passing. To return to the worry about infinite regress in identifying with higher-order desires: if it still remains, there is another response to the critic. The response is that a person’s hi ghost-order desires aren’t hers, strictly speaking — they are, rather, what make certain lower-order desires hers. If this is true, then it is inappropriate to expect that whatever makes the lower-order desires hers must also make the hi gher-order desires hers. An analogy to support this interpretation is found in the philosophical study of law. Consider the law prohibiting burglary - it is a law in virtue of its being a bit of written legislation.” More specifically, it is our law in virtue of its being written legislation. But whatever makes bits of written legislation law cannot itself be a bit of written legislation, of course, since if it were, the connection between written legislation and law would never get off the ground. Whatever makes legislation law cannot be something of ours in the same way that the law prohibiting burglary is ours. In the same way, we need not expect (contra the claim of the critic) that a person’s highest-order desires be hers in virtue of their being subject to some still-higher-order desire. But those hi ghost-order desires are indeed hers, in the same way as whatever makes legislation law is part of our legal system (on a suitably broad understanding of ‘legal system’). The critic might reply that the analogy is a false one, since in the case of personal identity, whatever makes my desires mine is different (in content, at least) from what makes your desires yours. Not so in law, since whatever it is that makes a piece of legislation law for us is the same thing that makes a different piece of legislation law for 7" Well, a number of bits, since I assume there to be pieces of legislation relevant to burglary on both state and federal levels. 86 them; whatever grounds the local authority of legislation is the same in the United States as it is in Canada. This reply, though, ignores the many differing grounds that have, historically and currently, underwritten the authority of written legislation: the authority of the monarch, religious authority, and general considerations of justice, to name just a few.77 Other analogous cases can be outlined, the most obvious of which, like the case of identity, involve a system comprising one level of components that are subject to the evaluation of components of another level.78 Many such examples support the claim that the grounds on which certain desires are a certain person’s desires can be a part of her identity without those grounds being (impossibly) subject to the self-same grounds. Thus, in a number of different ways, the infinite regress concern is answerable. A more applicable concern regards the constituent parts of identity generally. One might suppose that the elements of personal identity are by no means exhaustively categorized by reference solely to desires. Certainly, desires are explanatory, perhaps essentially so, of other identity constituents. A person who identifies as a socialist desires that political structures be arranged in a certain characteristic manner; someone who cares about the natural environment identifies with a range of desires such as (for example) the desire to use less fuel, and the desire that urban sprawl be reduced. But a person who admits that she is homeless, and that being homeless is thereby part of her identity, is not clearly standing in some internal relation to some set of desires. 77 This latter consideration has been invoked in trials of war criminals, who have been argued to be subject to laws that are nowhere written down, and required to ignore legislation that is contrary to certain basic principles of justice. 73 The rules of games, as a further set of examples, are the rules of certain games, though the determining criteria are not themselves the rules of any of the covered games. 87 Indeed, each of these accounts has some degree of incompleteness; narratives, group membership, and the things we care for are, as has become apparent in the foregoing, are all elements of the identities of persons, but none fully characterize the range of identity-constituents. Even a fairly modest understanding of general characterization will likely need to take up components of each of these accounts. This could take place coherently at a number of levels. Narratives are likely full of reference to Frankfurtian desires, for if the point of a narrative self-understanding is to make sense of one’s actions, often only by reference to desires can certain actions be understood. The self-descriptions of practical identities will at least sometimes be a narrative description, as for example understanding oneself as ‘Jennifer’s husband’ -— which, if it has any content beyond that common to any husband, this content will likely take the form of a historical narrative. Having examined a number of accounts of personal identity -— answers to the general characterization question - the specific characterization question still remains. This, recall, is the question of which specific element — which story, which desire — belongs to a given person. Although in the course of addressing the general characterization question, illustrations appealing to specific identities were made, a more focused look at the varied answers to the specific characterization question will show there to be far less agreement on this question than the previous. One point of agreement, though, will become clear: that endorsement plays an important role in each of the accounts’ answer to the specific characterization question. Since the notion of endorsement is especially difficult to ascribe to Schechtman’s account, the following 88 section will directly consider Schechtman’s version of the specific characterization question before I explain the role of endorsement in other accounts of personal identity. Schechtman and the specific characterization question Some approaches to what I am calling the specific characterization question serve immediately to narrow the range of answers. Consider Schechtman’s claim that “the most familiar examples of the characterization question are more specifically questions of which characteristics are truly those of some person (as opposed, say, to those which are his as result of hypnosis, brainwashing, or some other form of coercion).79 This claim presumes that a characteristic a person is coerced into having is not truly hers - a common thought, as was seen in the previous chapter. Discussing the way in which Frankfurt’s account of personal identity answers the specific characterization question — and how this answer figures into the broader landscape of identity we now have before us — is a fruitful way in which to examine Schechtman’s assumption. A structural view of identity agrees in many instances with Schechtman’s assumption that a coerced desire does not belong to the person so coerced. One can be given group membership against her will — be inveigled or even bullied into joining a labor union she does not want to be a part of, for instance. Desires can be instilled in her that she prefers not to have — if you take a bite of this chocolate, you might come to desire more, though prefer that you didn’t have such an unhealthy desire and so resist it. On the structural view, these characteristics are not ones that the person identifies with. Since to identify with a desire, say the desire to eat that chocolate, entails that the person 7" Schechtman (1996), p. 73. 89 endorses the desire - she wants to have the desire — the structural view holds that the unwanted desire to eat the chocolate is not hers. She doesn’t care about labor unions — in fact, just the opposite — and so her membership is not a constituent element of her true identity. The more problematic cases involve a coercive and typically wholesale manipulation of the second-order desires in virtue of which other characteristics are identified with. Such cases range from the rare to the ubiquitous: conversion experiences, hypnosis, brainwashing, socialization both oppressive and benign, and childhood education and indoctrination. On the structural view of identity, so long as the person endorses the desires on which she acts, they are her desires. The pretheoretic interpretation of paradigm cases tends, I think, to be clear enough. Consider a socially well-placed, emotionally and mentally competent adult who acquires a desire to make a charitable donation to an organization that she sought out of her own accord and put time into researching the goals and successes of the organization. The desire corresponds to her other desires and commitments, and is not out of character (she tends to be a cautious but regular charitable donor, and she is also giving of her time to certain causes). There is little dispute over this desire properly being attributed to her. At the other end of the spectrum, an impoverished, uneducated homeless adolescent who is forcibly taken into the compound of a suicide cult and brainwashed through threats and chemical manipulation into endorsing the aims of the organization is not typically thought to truly identify with those aims. The desires she possesses because of brainwashing are, we tend to think, not her desires. 9O Cases lying somewhere between these extremes, though, are more difficult to judge. Imagine a not so well-off woman who has never made a charitable donation. One day she is deeply moved by a mainstream news media story about the plight of Sudanese women, and makes a large financial contribution to a hi gh-profile charity organization. Or consider the various methods of indoctrinatin g children and adolescents that we typically take to be legitimate: enforced education, the system of punishment and reward that parents as well as the larger society employ to encourage positive behaviors, beliefs and attitudes. It can be very difficult to separate our intuitions about characteristics, desires and beliefs that are good for a person from our intuitions about those characteristics, desires and beliefs that are her own. Those elements of a person which come about as the result of required, usually public, education; those that benevolent parents instill through various conditioning methods; the attitudes that accompany a positive change of heart motivated by bare emotion can all benefit the person who possesses them. But when the content at issue is different, intuitions tend to change. An elementary school child who has been taught that the forms and functions of biological organisms are a function of evolution by natural selection is thought (ceteris paribus) to have a belief that is truly hers. But a similar child who attends school across the state line might be taught - within the context of a distinct world-view — that the forms and functions of biological organisms are a function of the creator’s intent and active construction. This belief, many would tend to think, is not her own. But, as I have argued, the self-benefit of a person’s identity elements is no more relevant to whether they are properly attributed to that person than is the benefit of a 91 person’s quotidian possessions — that bottle of whiskey might be bad for me, but it is nonetheless mine. The same argument applies to elements that in some way deviate from reality — that a belief is false (even dangerously so) has by itself no bearing on whether it is mine.80 The introduction of Lindemann’s account of identity has given the opportunity for another response, one that satisfies more intuitions than those grounded in property metaphors. Explaining much of the damage of oppression requires that we hold such harmful identity elements, even those acquired through non-self—directed means, to be properly attributed to the persons these elements damage. Recall the notion of infiltrated consciousness. Infiltrated consciousness is the internalization, by members of oppressed minority groups, of the hateful, dismissive or otherwise disparaging characterizations that dominant groups attribute to them.81 Much the same phenomenon has been argued to be at work in the internalization of self-detrimental desires.82 The primary explanatory virtue of the notion of infiltrated consciousness is its role in making sense of harm to oppressed persons in cases where there is no outside force directly and actively harming them. Such external forces are relatively visible: legislation that denies rights (e. g. regarding property or marriage) to members of minorities; violent hate crimes (sometimes more descriptively called ‘bias crimes’); the various mistreatments that stem from stereotypes (as when police refuse to take seriously the accusations of a Latina against her purported attacker, since she is just an overexcitable Hispanic). 8" A distinct sort of case is one in which the belief in question is one which is impossible to hold — for instance, a manifestly self-contradictory one. Philosophers are, of course, in the business of talking people out of such beliefs, but since many people seem to be in the business of believing just such beliefs, I take this sort of case to be unresolved. 8‘ Nelson (2001), p. 21. 82 Benson (1991). 92 Not so visible is the method of other of oppression’s damages, those that follow from other than externally visible mechanisms. The substantial damage caused by self- image disorders such as anorexia and body dismorphic disorder, for example, which are at least in part encouraged by unattainable social norms regarding physical appearance, cannot be explained as a function of external force.83 External forces operate against the desires of those they harm — gays who want their unions to be recognized by marriage rights are denied these rights against their desires, for example. But the anorexic wants to be dangerously thin, and identifies with this desire. The notion of infiltrated consciousness explains how it is that social norms damage the anorexic even though her situation accords with her desires. To deny that the anorexic is truly identified with her desire to be dangerously thin is to recast her situation as one of (merely) external forces. But as the example of anorexia vividly shows, this is to misunderstand the phenomenon entirely. Replacing the external forces, the norms prescribing thinness, with more reasonable ones is entirely unhelpful to anorexics: as noted earlier, anorexia is in part characterized by a stage of resistance to recommendations of different body image.“ Thus, the motive force is internal. As suggested above, the determination of whether a desire acquired through non- self-directed processes is to be attributed to a person cannot be made on the basis of a universally applicable criterion. To deny wholesale that at least some coercively acquired desires are truly the desires of the person in whom they reside and whose 8" ‘External force’, that is, in the sense that anorexics are not being withheld food. The original source of the desire to be thin might be external, but the point here is that it is (and works as it does only because it is) internalized. 8“ Levenkron (2000). 93 actions they motivate can entail ignoring the magnitude and even the very nature of the damage that oppression inflicts on them.85 The structural view of identity, as I have argued, usefully illuminates the way in which coercively-acquired desires are sometimes truly attributed to their possessors. On the matter of coercively-acquired desires, Schechtman’s narrative self- conception view has a troubling implication. Her recommended “constraints on an identity-constitutin g narrative” include the requirement that one’s self—conception “must cohere with what might be called the “objective” account of her life - roughly the story that those around her would tell.”8" As a criterion intended to deny manifestly false self- conceptions, such as my conceiving of myself as Napoleon Bonaparte, it seems warranted. But the constraint will also serve to undermine, for example, my self- perception as a morally worthy being if those around me deny its accuracy.87 Furthermore, this constraint is in tension with the essential core of Lindemann’s project — to defend the notion of counterstories with which a person can deny the truth of the stories that those around her tell. If a person’s self-narrative must be in at least general correspondence with the narrative others tell about her, it seems as if the degree to which a person can construct her own identity, and react against parts of it she rejects, is severely limited. In explaining precisely what is wrong with Schechtman’s constraint, it is useful to note that its aim is somewhat similar to that of counterstories. This, what she calls ‘the 85 The closely related question of whether actions that flow from such desires are properly considered autonomous actions will be taken up in Chapter 3, below. 86 Schechtman (1996), p. 95. 87 The film Gaslight (Cukor, 1944) illustrates the loss of self-perceived moral worth. Paula is convinced by her new, devious husband Gregory that she is insane; subsequently, she comes to believe herself unable to make basic decisions about her own actions. 94 reality constraint’, is a practical requirement on the content of identity so that identities might be socially useful tools. “Living the life of a person requires living in the same world as other persons”, and to live in the same world, Schechtman claims, is largely to agree on two fronts: facts and interpretations.88 There is indeed a certain modicum of factual agreement necessary for social interaction and for the recognition of others’ personhood that is the precondition of such interaction. But the reality constraint regarding interpretation is not so straightforward. Schechtman uses as an example a paranoiac who imagines that, contrary to fact, everyone around her is an agent of the CIA and is watching her. Schechtman says, “the narrative self-constitution view does not take the alleged persecution to be part of the person’s history, despite the role it plays in her narrative.”89 Schechtman seems here to be thinking that persecution couldn’t be a part of this person’s identity since the persecution doesn’t exist, just as it can’t be the case that Santa Claus brought the gifts, since Santa Claus doesn’t exist. But this is a matter of the reality constraint regarding facts: the fact of persecution. The fact of persecution cannot be a part of this person’s identity because there is no such fact. This claim should be relatively uncontroversial. But contrary to Schechtman’s assertion, there are important senses in which the interpretation is a part of her identity. This could be the case for a number of reasons. As Schechtman admits, “the line between observation and interpretation is notoriously difficult to draw”,”0 and so we might dispute whether the paranoiac’s imaginings have at least a grain of truth to them. Interpretations are also quite observer-dependent; a 8" Schechtman (1996). P. 119. 8” Schechtman (1996), p. 126. 9° Schechtman (1996), p. 127. 95 chronically sexually-harassed woman is more attuned than most people to noticing disrespectful behavior toward her and interpreting it as such. There is an even more straightforward way in which one’s interpretations feature in her identity, whether or not these interpretations are accurate in some sense. The existence of the content of the interpretation (i.e. that there are CIA agents watching) is not what is relevant to her identity, but the story that constitutes the interpretation itself is. That the interpretation is part of her identity is indicated in multiple ways: by its place in her (narrative) self-concept, its role in explaining her actions, and (a point Schechtman doesn’t address) the probable agreement by others that she is making just such an (incorrect) interpretation. And unlike the case of Santa Claus, there does actually exist such an interpretation to take its place in her identity: her own interpretation. Another constraint Schechtman defends is the articulation constraint, which “acknowledges that the elements of a person’s narrative he cannot articulate are his, but says that they are only partially his — attributable to him to a lesser degree than those aspects of the narrative he can articulate.”91 Thus someone whose fear of flying, for instance, prevents her even from entering an airport but does not feature into her self- narrative — she cannot explain how this fear relates to her other fears (it doesn’t), nor tell a historical narrative of its genesis (she might not know how she came to fear flying) — is part of her identity, but less a part than if she were able to tell how the fear features into the whole of her life’s narrative. It is often thought that such fears as phobias are somewhat alien to their possessors (or, revealingly, ‘victims’). 9' Scehchtman ( 1996), p. 117. Other cases are dissimilar. Imagine an extreme narcissist. She considers herself perfect in every way. She cannot articulate her narcissism (since she takes herself to be perfect, while narcissism is a fault), but it is central to her identity: virtually every one of her beliefs, desires and actions are best interpretable as a belief, desire or action of a narcissist. So unlike other examples in which an identity element is not in fact, but could in principle be, articulated - consider a person aptly identified as a creep who takes himself to be a perfect gentleman, or psychotics, who tend not to self-identify as psychotics -- at least some identity elements exclude even the possibility. In the light of these sorts of examples it seems that the articulability of the identity element is not relevant. The notion of endorsement, in the sense of lack of dissatisfaction with the element, is more explanatory. The phobic cannot narratively articulate her fear (she can admit that it moves her, but she cannot make sense of it in the story of her life), and is dissatisfied with it.92 The narcissist shares with the phobic the inability of articulation, but the narcissist is not dissatisfied with this element of her identity. The inarticulable narcissism is attributable to the narcissist, but not the phobia to the phobic — a distinction tracked not by articulability but endorsement. There are other shortcomings regarding the articulation constraint. Schechtman claims that the point is not merely that inarticulable elements are less one’s own, but that the relationship between these elements and a person’s life is importantly different than that shared with articulable elements. “Those features of one’s life which cannot be articulated do play a role, but they play a role different from that played by those which 92 According to the DSM IV (the most recent edition of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of the American Psychological Association), adult phobics recognize that their fear is unreasonable. 97 can be” she says; “their influence is rigid and automatic”.93 But simply because something is inarticulable, because it is unconscious, does not mean that it is rigid. A person’s unconscious hatred of her mother can manifest itself in quite varied and situation—sensitive ways. An unconscious feature is indeed automatic, in the sense that it operates without one’s conscious awareness (like the processes of digestion, or most sleeping dreams) but then Schechtman’s claim is the trivial one that unconscious desires operate unconsciously.” The heart of identity Throughout the examination of views of personal identity, the notion of endorsement has repeatedly come to the fore. Endorsement of an identity element, the satisfaction entailed either by approving of the element or admitting to possession of it, is sufficient for identification. The important role of endorsement is seen especially clearly in considering externally-attributed identity elements: infiltrated consciousness is a person’s endorsement of a harmful or oppressive conception that others have of her. The distinction between infiltrated consciousness and (mere) oppressive attributions rests on endorsement: a person who takes up as her own the oppressive attributions of others experiences no inner conflict; she is satisfied with the characterization of her identity; she endorses it. Whatever elements we take to constitute the identities of persons, we are now in a position to see that endorsement is the means by which specific elements come to be those with which a person is identified. Endorsement of desires by hi gher-order volitions 93 Schechtman (1996), p. 118. 9“ Which may in fact be the claim she intends to defend. In a footnote she affirms, “[me claim that unconscious material is rigid should [...] be taken to indicate [. . .] that it cannot be directly affected by what is part of consciousness.” (1996, p. 141) 98 just is the core of the structural account defended above, and the notion explains how other sorts of identity elements are identified with. Korsgaard’s notion of a practical identity, a conception under which a person values herself, involves endorsement in the ‘approval’ sense. Recall also Blake’s discussion of the reappropriation of disparaging labels. The group memberships that come about as a response to oppression, such as his example of taking up the ‘geek’ epithet as a matter of pride illustrates endorsement in something much more like the ‘acceptance’ sense; reappropriation involves creating the self-respecting interpretation on which a person can admit a not entirely benign attribution into her identity. The ‘geek’ label is attributed to persons, certain of whom likely do not endorse it, but those who do endorse that identity can do so through reappropriation — reinterpreting the label so that it does not cause identity conflict. The telling of counterstories involves endorsement insofar as the process makes the absence of endorsement manifest. Faced with dissatisfaction with some (narrative) identity element, a person dissociates herself from it through constructing an alternative and incompatible narrative. The dissociation that is a function of counterstories is practical in nature; counterstories are told in the interest of making some real change in the world. But inseparable from this practical alteration is an internal disaffiliation from the attributed identity element. The exact relation between the internal and external disidentification will vary from case to case — internal repudiation may provide the motivation and justification for the practical telling of the counterstory; internal dissociation might, alternately, be dependent on the recognition of others that can be 99 gained only after the counterstory is given uptake. Whatever the mechanism at play in specific instances, the counterstory is a practical mechanism of endorsement. Unification I will argue in the following chapters that unification of one’s identity is desirable. A reminder to the reader of the general content of the arguments of the following chapters is in order at this point. The unity of identity will be defended on three fronts. First, on the structural view of autonomy that I will defend, possessing a unified identity is a precondition of acting autonomously. Second, acting with integrity has often been considered (by philosophers, at any rate) conceptually equivalent to being internally unified; though I will deny this thesis, I will argue that the unity of identity figures into acting with integrity as a practical precondition as well as an explanatory feature of integrity. Third, romantic loving is underpinned by the unity of identity at two points: the valuing of one’s beloved and romantic commitment. The remainder of the present chapter will outline the notion of unity that will feature in the subsequent discussions. Though the aim here is to support the ideal of the unity of identity, since the approach to identity is practical rather than metaphysical, and since the arguments outlined above all appeal to certain activities, an important sort of unity will be the unity of action and motivation. Action need not be thought of as unified in the sense Alasdair MacIntyre advocates, in the sense of having a telos, either in the sense of “the good of a whole human life, the good of a human life conceived of as a unity”, or the more global sense of “the good life for man”.95 Having more than one goal does not entail disunity; analogously, many artifacts are unified, but have more than a single goal (or, without 95 MacIntyre (1981), p. 189. p. 172. 100 appearing to attribute intentionality to artifacts, ‘a single function’). An automobile, that unified mass of protective, motive and comforting elements, has more than one goal; an art museum is often expected both to house artworks and itself serve some aesthetic function. But what unification of action does entail is relative absence of conflict between various actions. If an art museum was itself beautiful but failed to protect the artworks within (perhaps because of a magnificent, sublime hole in the roof), it would fail to attain the goals expected, and be characterized by a functional disunity. In the analogical examples as well as in regards to personal identity, ‘absence’ of conflict is often a fuzzy concept, and as such not only demands judgment rather than algorithmic application, but also suggests that there will be some boundary cases about which there might be reasonable disagreement. For while it is clear that a museum of charcoal drawings with no roof would fail to be unified in its functions (since all the works within would be ruined by the first rainfall), it is not as clear (and perhaps indeterminate) whether an art museum whose windows let in daylight sufficient to view artworks under the best lighting conditions but also sufficient to degrade the pigments of the paintings over time is unified in its functions. Likewise, the internal conflict between my caring about the environment and my desire for an ambulance ride, rather than a walk, to the hospital may be too slight to be relevant. In order for actions to be unified, the motives that ground them are, exceptional cases aside, best unified. This sort of unification is straightforwardly characterizable much in the same fashion as unity of action — the absence of conflict. This is the level of unity most relevant to desire-endorsement views, as discussed above. If a person has both a desire to smoke and a desire not to smoke, her desires are as such not unified. If 101 she has a desire to write the paper this afternoon and a desire to sleep the whole afternoon, her desires are not unified. When these conflicting desires are ones the person identifies with, a disunified set of desires is tantamount to a disunified identity. In the next chapter I will address those sorts of cases in which the disunified desires are each a motive.96 Such a unity of motives is necessary for autonomous action, according to the hierarchical account of autonomy I will defend. The notion of ‘unified around’ -- as in ‘the painting is unified around the beatific Madonna’ — is relevant to the unity of identity. In a painting about which this sort of claim is made, that which is the unifying element of the painting - the Madonna, continue to suppose — is the most important element. This notion of ‘important’ can be cashed out in various ways, many illuminating of personal identity. Were the image of the Madonna erased from the canvas, the painting would be considered destroyed, though if other elements were erased, the work would be merely damaged. We might well understand the other elements of the painting by reference to the Madonna (e. g. the child in the painting is understood differently than is the child in a painting unified around plump dancing peasants, a la Bruegel). The presence of the Madonna puts constraints (aesthetic ones, in this analogy) on the inclusion of other elements; a Fuselian imp, for instance, is precluded. Less metaphorically, it can be noted that some of a person’s narratives are more central to her self-understanding than others, some of a person’s self-conceptions are more motivating. One or a small subset of a person’s self-understandings often serve to anchor the rest. These anchors — central and important concerns and self-understandings 9" As it was noted above, a desire can be other than a motive or volition. 102 — are a person’s principles. Such principles can be the identity elements in virtue of which a person stands in a relationship of endorsement to her volitions, desires, and other identity elements; so long as her first-order desire does not conflict with her principles, she is said to endorse that desire, and her identity is in this respect unified. Thus, another relevant mode of unification is grouping one’s motives, etc. under the auspices of one’s principles. I will address the connection of this sort of unity with the notion of integrity in Chapter 4. Since self-conception underlies motives, a number of relevant sorts of unity regard one’s self-conception. One’s own self-conception can be internally consistent, that is, relatively free from internal conflict between its various elements. This might be in virtue of the content of one’s practical identities: there seems no conflict in the sorts of reasons associated with the practical identities ‘mother’ and ‘gardener’ (thought there may of course be conflicts of other sorts, most obviously temporal conflicts: there is simply not enough time in a week to meet all the demands of each). All the possible and desirable aspects and forms of unification are not exhausted by the avoidance of conflict: simply the conceiving of oneself as a whole, that is, as unified, is itself a mode of unity. It is a desirable one, as well, as I will argue in Chapter 5. A sort of resolution of conflict can be attained by compartmentalizin g one’s various self-conceptions. A person who conceives of herself as a feminist in her personal life but cannot while she is in her corporate work environment is engaged in compartmentalization, creating insular identities that, because they are not allowed to interact, do not conflict. Calling this lack of conflict ‘unity’ might be misleading, though, since what is interpreted as reconciling conflict within a person is equally 103 interpretable as avoiding conflict by creating two persons. Since I don’t take the metaphysical outcome of such a debate to be important, I will argue instead, also in Chapter 5, that compartmentalization is quite undesirable in light of certain effects it has on our practices of loving. A unified identity, then, is one which is marked by endorsement - that is, a lack of conflict between and among elements. But considering the extensive literature criticizing the nature of the structure in structural accounts of autonomy, it is surprising that there is little written that attempts to characterize the possible structures a unified identity might take.97 Opponents of the ideal of unity generally take there to be a limited range of possibilities, often simply equating ‘unity’ with ‘homogeneity’ or ‘ossification’.98 Seeing no reason to defend one certain form of unity, but desiring to say something so to initiate the philosophical investigation into unity, we might simply lay out a few of the more obvious forms that such unity might take. To equate ’unification’ with ‘homogeneity’ is both practically and theoretically implausible. Practically, one would have a very narrow range of reasons for action (perhaps so narrow as to make much more than the basic necessities of life impossible to acquire). Theoretically, the notion of ‘homogeneity’ excludes the possibility of a number of distinct practical identities; a homogeneous entity is the same throughout, having no distinguishable elements. That a highly unified identity might have a certain degree of ossification is certainly possible, but the likelihood of such an identity being undesirably 97 Even Mullin (1995), explicitly claiming (p. 3) “we need to speak with more clarity when we refer to selves as unified”, fails to offer clarification. Her notions of ‘assimilation’, ‘compartmentalization’, and ‘negotiation’ are notions of how selves get unified; as to what unity is, her discussions, like those of many others, repeatedly assume it to be ‘homogeneity’. 9" The ‘ossification’ charge was defended against in the previous chapter; homogeneity is discussed immediately below. 104 rigid is low; change in one’s identity can be the function of many factors, only one of which is the relation between practical identities. Internal to the person but external to her identity are many potential causes for identity alteration: change can be motivated by the realization of error, either of the grounds of one’s endorsements99 or the understanding of just what one’s endorsement of a certain identity entails; change in identity can be the result of some sort of internal emotional disturbance such as depression. External to the person entirely are a multitude of forces — social, political, physical — that will affect the constitution of an identity that is even minimally responsive to the world. The possible structural variations of a unified identity fall into two broad categories: hierarchical and non-hierarchical unification. A hierarchically—unified identity might be organized as a pyramid: one primary identity that trumps all others by having authority over some few which in turn have authority over a larger set, and so on. One identity ‘having authority’ over another means that the authoritative identity is the one the reasons of which are typically authoritative in cases of identity conflict. Often one’s moral identity occupies the top of this sort of hierarchy in a Kantian fashion, and so a test of moral permissibility might resolve lower-level conflict.loo A similar but non-pyramidal structure is an autocratic one: reasons of one identity typically trump those of all others which themselves have relatively equal authority. Though an identity of this sort could be excessively rigid, it is usually a caricature; dramatic characters and the public personae of famous and infamous persons seem to overlay such an identity, but it is the nature of fictional and popular characters to portray 9” Here, as at other points where I neglect the cognitive in favor of discussing the connative, I owe the noting of this important point to James Lindemann Nelson. “’0 The most well-known critique of such a model is Wolf (1982). 105 just a segment of a full identity. Real persons possessing such an identity might be overwhelmingly pitiable: survivors of extreme violence, such as rape or genocide, often identify only with their being minimally physically alive, and have no other reason- giving self-description.’°' A parliamentary structure would be one in which more than one identity element share authoritative force. As a contingent matter, some identities tend not to conflict, at least in very problematic ways - avid novel-reader and environmentalist seem a fairly nonconflicting pair — but likely these have not enough content on which alone to base a meaningful life. Identities that in principle don’t conflict are more promising: the conflict, both philosophical and quotidian, between one’s relational identities and her ‘02 and the desirability of rendering these somehow moral identity is significant, conceptually unconflicting is indicated by philosophical attempts to do so.103 An aversion to talk of internal authority might lead one to consideration of non- hierarchical structures, on which one’s various practical identities are relatively equal.104 Many of our identity conflict-reducing tactics aim at such an egalitarian internal economy; in the conflict between sexual orientation and religious beliefs, for example, a sort of reconciliation is often attempted by altering one of the identities (e. g. change what it is to be a Catholic) so that the two neither conflict nor rule over one another.105 '0‘ See for example Brison (2002), chapter 3. '02 The philosophical conflict I have in mind here is the one begun by Williams (1981). '03 E. g. Velleman (1999), which characterizes love as a moral emotion; if love is a source of moral reasons, then though it might conflict with other sources of moral reasons (duty to impartial beneficence, say) it can’t conflict with morality itself. '04 Marilyn Friedman’s (1986) account of this sort is discussed, albeit briefly, in Chapter 3, below. '05 Dubowski and Korda’s (2001) film Trembling Before G—d, a documentary look at the lives of homosexual Hasidic and orthodox Jews, is a powerful illustration of the conflict that motivates such a reconciliation. Lindemann (2001) is an account of how such l"-personal identity change might take place. 106 Similarly for identities that conflict not in principle but contingently, we attempt to alter the world such that conflicts are minimized. Making it more practically possible to be both a mother and a careerperson is one way we have restructured not the identities themselves but the ways in which they are able to be acted upon. When this alteration is not so much of the world but of our organization of it, persons and their lives can get compartmentalized; the parent who reduces identity conflicts by (merely) temporally delimiting the authority of his identities (being a businessperson from 9 to 5, and a parent nights and weekends) can“ indeed reduce conflicts but not only risks not having a desirably coherent life but also must guard against the failure of the compartmentalization (for example, being a parent gives reasons to act even during the time a parent is a businessperson). Another undesirable sort of unification can be achieved by arbitrariness: conflicts between identity- granted reasons are resolved arbitrarily each time they arise. This is probably common enough, but is self-undermining: practical identities don’t so much give reasons for specifiable, distinct actions as they give reasons for sets of actions that constitute projects. If ‘environmentalist’ is one of a person’s practical identities she has reason not so much to ride her bike to work today but to ride her bike to work generally. The less often she acts on this reason, the more her ‘environmentalist’ identity is undermined. The present work is intentionally noncommittal as to the specific structure the unified identity might take. It is possible given any of these structures both to realize the (relatively) conflict-free coexistence of varying practical identities and to have a rich capacity for autonomy, integrity, and the ability romantically to love. A unified identity, 107 one marked by endorsement, is of central importance in supporting these capacities. This claim, and its defense, is what I will take up below. 108 _3_ Autonomy Saw the mirrors in two. I’m a divided man. The little I try to do Is less than I can. - Theodore Roethkel In the previous chapter, I argued that a person’s identity, by giving her practical reasons, underpins her actions. More accurately, each of her practical identities (which together constitute her overall identity) gives her such reasons. This connection between who one is (however characterized) and her actions is central to the notion of autonomy. It might be thought that a person is autonomous just in case she acts in virtue of reasons conferred by her practical identities. This thought is implied, anyway, by the foregoing discussion of practical identity. But even if this were the only contender for an account of autonomy, the matter cannot be so simple. Numerous practical identities give each of us numerous reasons for numerous actions. Such exponential multiplication of practical commands makes it unlikely that they will all congeal into a coherent directive. And, as the poet Theodore Roethke notes (in a fragment; we do not know the context of this observation of his), we don’t need to appeal to the mathematics of exponential growth to know that the connection between identity and action is not always clear and ' Roethke (1974). 109 direct. We look in the mirror, look at who we are, and see that we are divided. This division, in turn, limits the actions that one may properly count as her own — or so Roethke suggests, and so I will argue here. In philosophical discussions the foregoing observations about a person’s actions and her relation to them typically are made in terms of autonomy.2 Specifically, the question of whether internal division is centrally relevant to the judgment of a person’s autonomy is a question given an affirmative answer by those who subscribe to a structural view of autonomy, and a negative answer by those who hold either a content- specific or a procedural view. Such accounts share many features, but differ as to their central requirement on autonomous action. Content-neutral accounts hold autonomy to be judged only by the structural relation of elements of the agent’s volitional economy. Content-specific accounts take the correspondence of action to specified moral facts to be a defining criterion of autonomy. Procedural accounts hold that the content and structure of an autonomous agent’s internal economy must either have come about by, or be modifiable by, processes that do not themselves depend on the actual economy itself. In this chapter I will defend a structural account of autonomy against content-specific accounts and procedural accounts. I will support a structural account of autonomy though three routes: primarily, by presenting reasons in light of which procedural and content-specific accounts are untenable as they stand (and thus supporting a structural account by default); by answering criticisms of structural accounts; and also by showing that one desirable 2 Typically, that is, in the analytic philosophical tradition. 110 feature (the ideal self) of procedural and content-specific accounts can be satisfactorily accommodated by a structural account. Having defended a structural notion of autonomy, an explication of this sort of autonomy will suffice to show how unity of identity is necessary for autonomy. That is, the defense of a structural account of autonomy is tantamount to the defense of the ideal of unity. As will be explained more fully below, such an account takes the arrangement of the autonomous person’s internal economy to be a practically unified one; the elements of one’s personal identity, through their practical role in agency, are ideally unified on a structural account of autonomy.. The last brief section of this chapter will explain why autonomy is desirable, and also what its limits are in underpinning a good life. An outline of conceptions of autonomy The range of what has been argued to count as ‘autonomy’ is very wide, and so a brief taxonomy is in order.3 The most general distinction might be made between content-specific and content-neutral views. A contemporary content-specific view (one that will be discussed in more detail in what follows) is that of Susan Babbitt.4 Babbitt argues that a person is autonomous only if her actions aim at her own real interests in human flourishing. Since oppression can lead a person to possess an inadequate self-concept — convincing her, incorrectly, that she is subordinate, or merits no self-respect, to mention just two elements of such a self- concept — her real interests may not be those interests she perceives herself to have. Thus she will not necessarily be autonomous in virtue of acting from her perceived interests; 3 Addressing both political and personal autonomy, and the relations between them, would broaden the discussion even more. Here I address only personal autonomy. 4 Babbitt (1996). 111 she will be autonomous only if she acts so to further her real self interests. Some actions — those that fail to promote one’s own flourishing — are not autonomous regardless of who performs them. This sort of view is in contrast with a content-neutral view, on which whatever criteria there are for autonomy, the criteria will not be grounded in a certain content. Rather than the content of the actions or their motives, the structure of the agent’s internal economy — her desires, commitments, various identities, elements of her self — is the determinant of autonomy. The most prominent structural view, sometimes called the ‘Dworkin/Frankfurt model’ is, not surprisingly, an amalgam of the accounts of Gerald Dworkin and Harry Frankfurt.’ Frankfurt’s version of the account was distinguished from, and shown to be superior to, Dworkin’s in Chapter 1, above, and in what follows I will continue to focus on Frankfurt’s version. On this structural view, an autonomous action is one that is the product of a desire that the agent endorses via a higher order desire. The specific structure that characterizes autonomous actions, then, is a hierarchy. On a structural view, an action with any content whatsoever might count as autonomous, so long as it issues from a person with the requisite sort of internal constitution. On procedural accounts, whether an action is autonomous is judged on the procedure by which the agent acquires or maintains the desires that move her. Some accounts (such as those of Paul Benson and John Christman) focus on the legitimacy of the process by which the desire was acquired, while others (that of Diana Meyers) include a host of interrelated, ongoing processes. Complicating the construction of a helpful taxonomy, procedural views share features with both content-specific accounts 5 The moniker is used in e.g. Christman (1988). 112 and content-neutral accounts: Meyers’s account, as we will see in the next section, has an explicit moral requirement, and the following explanations of other procedural views will show that they implicitly deny the autonomy of actions with certain moral content" What all these accounts — content-neutral, content—specific, and procedural -— accept that the conceptual core of autonomous action is self-govemance. That is, all agree that only elements of a person herself can motivate an action if that action is to be considered an autonomous one. But which elements of a person are truly her own? Frankfurt ’s structural account Harry Frankfurt, as outlined in the previous chapter, takes personal identity to be essentially a matter of volition, and so his accounts of identity and autonomy are closely intermingled. This can be seen most clearly by looking at the most basic elements of his view: desires. The desires a person identifies with are those she endorses, that is, desires which are in no conflict with any of her hi gher-order desires. When both of the desires at issue are volitions — that is, when both are desires she wants to be effective in her own motivation - they are the grounds of autonomous action. Simply put, an action is autonomous when it is motivated by a self—endorsed volition. This might seem a bare, somewhat austere view of autonomous action.7 As the account has developed, both conceptually and historically, it shows a more human face in its notion of caring. The objects of some desires are the things a person cares about, such as moral principles, political ideals, other persons, and the like. If a person cares about, say, socialism, she identifies with her desire for socialism: she desires that political 6 Of course, structural views are subject to an apparently similar claim: there is an implicit moral aim underpinning the account. The ‘moral content’ that I refer to here regards the content of the (purportedly) autonomous acts themselves, not to the moral goals (in the pejorative sense of ‘agenda’) furthered by the promotion of the account. 7 And, of course, of personal identity as well; this criticism was allayed in the previous chapter. 113 structures take a socialist form, and she is satisfied that she has that desire. She also, insofar as she cares about socialism, desires that her desire persist. Simply desiring socialism would lead to no particular response if the desire ended, but if she cares about socialism she would be upset if her desire for it waned.8 To care, then, is not merely (as we sometimes imply) to desire strongly, as we might say in a teenager who we say cares about being popular. It is rather, in Frankfurt’s usage, to want the desire to continue, and relatedly to be disposed to experience a loss were the desire to disappear -- unlike most teenagers who I suspect are later relieved to find that adulthood has divested them of such desires.9 Because the conceptual core of caring resides in the notion of endorsement, that which a person cares about can motivate autonomous actions as well. Grounding autonomy in the things we care about is intuitively satisfying, at least more so than the bare ‘desire-endorsement’ model. Many of us sometimes (and some of us often) feel as if we are doing things against our will when the things we do are things we do not care about. The Frankfurtian model helps to explain and even to legitimate this feeling. It must be kept in mind that a person has many (autonomy-grounding) desires for things she does not care about, but when she realizes distinctly that she does not care about the object of her actions, this tends to be a matter of her acting on desires with which she does not identify. Career disillusionment, or falling out of love, or even broader existential crises (as they are sometimes called) can herald a failure to care about one’s employment, partner, or life (respectively); these things can then take the form of a goad — moving us non-autonomously. 8 That is, if only the desire for socialism, but not her hi gher-order desire that her desire persist, waned. It is common enough to cease to care about something (or someone) and experience no dissatisfaction thereby. In these sorts of cases, though, one’s hi gher-order desires have withered as well as those of the first-order. 9 As teenagers, we tend to think we care about a wide range of things that we come to realize (for better or for worse) we merely had powerful desires for. 114 The basic desire-endorsement structure of the model itself is sound, as well, and withstands a range of criticisms — or so I will continue to argue throughout the current chapter. Taking up a certain one of these criticisms, one lodged by Marilyn Friedman, will serve to support this claim of soundness as well as to explicate some further details of the view.IO Friedman’s criticism is aimed at the notion of what she calls the ‘split-level self’, which Frankfurt might be thought to advocate. On his understanding, the desires that motivate autonomous action have a distinctly hierarchical structure. Lower-order desires are endorsed (literally, ‘on the back of’) by higher-order ones. Not only are there two unequal sets of desires, but the self is split (at least conceptually) into two distinct elements. Friedman’s proposed ‘bottom-up’ structural approach, on which first-level desires play a role in evaluating higher level “principles”, as she calls them, could be taken as opposed to Frankfurt’s structural account; indeed, it is intended as such. Instead of a split-level self, the two elements could be seen to work in a sort of harmony. Not the least virtue of describing persons’ internal economy in this way is its accuracy — sometimes our (mere) desires do play an important role in the modification of principles (and commitments, allegiances, and the like). But Friedman criticizes the accounts of no less than seven philosophers together under the heading of ‘split level self’. The split self that she seems to be wary of is a conception she attributes in large part to Dworkin, who understands the reflective self to be the ‘true self’; thus within a person there can be two selves, the true self and the merely apparent self. Friedman derives some elements of the conception from the view ‘° Friedman (1986). 115 of S.I.Benn, on which the true self is linked to one’s values, ideals, and principles. The idea that there are two selves, only one of which is the true self, is distinct from Frankfurt’s view on which a person identifies with some desires and disidentifies from others; in order to cohere with Friedman’s conception, the disidentified desires would have to coalesce to form another resident self, an impossibility if being a person requires possessing hi gher-order desires from which reflection proceeds.” Another point on which Friedman’s bottom-up view fails to contravene Frankfurt’s specific formulation regards the characterization of desires vis-a—vis their structural role. Since on Frankfurt’s view hi gher-order desires are distinguished from lower-order desires simpliciter by their taking other desires as their object, it is incoherent to suggest that lower-order desires take higher order elements (whether characterized as desires or principles) as their objects.‘2 If, as an example of a common sort of occurrence, a person’s first-order desire to smoke plays some role in the reformulation of her hi gher-order desire that she not smoke (i.e. the desire not to have the desire to smoke), the desire to smoke must be accompanied by a distinct hi gher-order desire — the desire to desire to smoke.13 There is no reason to think this incompatible with Frankfurt’s view; the view lays no restrictions on the sources of novel second-order desires, and so they could well come about in response to certain first-order desires that are rewarding to satisfy, or quite difficult to divest oneself of. Otherwise, this is simply a case of urges overpowering principles, which is not at all what Friedman is proposing. “ The other self, the one that is not the true self, would according to Frankfurt’s view be a paradigm example of a wanton. ‘2 This point, as well as other responses to Friedman’s criticisms, is made in Christman (1987). ‘3 A possible reply could involve a desire that is by its nature, so to speak, both a first- and second -order desire, but I am unable to think of an example of such a desire. 116 Friedman’s proposal that all the things with which a person identifies, whether bare desires or deeply-held principles, play a role in evaluating each other, shares an important feature with Frankfurt’s structural account. That feature is the unification of identity. If an autonomous action is one that is motivated by an endorsed desire, the agent’s identity (constituted of the desires with which she identifies), vis-a-vis that action, is unified. For example, acting on a desire to smoke (to use the above example) can be autonomous or non-autonomous. Someone acting in the grip of her desire to smoke (as it is sometimes put) is not autonomous when she smokes if being ‘in the grip of’ implies a resistance, however futile, to the desire. Such a resistance entails an internal conflict; her desires are not unified. The example of a smoker is an apparently problematic but actually illuminating one with which to continue to explicate the structural view. If the desire to smoke is one the smoker identifies with, and as such has no conflicting desires, she acts autonomously. The desires (relevant to smoking) with which she identifies are unified, and so her action is a self-directed one. There are a number of points at which this sort of claim about an autonomous smoker meets resistance. Certainly she has some conflicting desires — the desire not to smell like smoke, or the desire to not spend money on cigarettes, or the like. This is one form disunity takes: conflict between first-order desires.l4 In autonomous action these dissenting desires might well exist (they often do), but are silenced; these are desires a person (if honest, and sufficiently self-aware) admits herself to have, but are not desires ‘4 Frankfurt (1988), pp. 164-165. 117 by which she wants to be moved. Conflict is absent since the desires that are not in accord with the volitions on which she acts are just that: desires, and not volitions.15 She possesses them, but since she does not want them to motivate her action, there is no conflict. It might be objected that smoking is a peculiar example to use to describe autonomy since people are hooked — smoking is (to limit the range of types of smokers we are considering) an addiction. There are at least two possible issues here, one relating to freedom of action, and the other to the status of the desire that motivates the action. Regarding freedom of action: to the extent that a person is addicted, she is not free to act otherwise — the phrase ‘freedom from addiction’ is almost a mantra in some circles. But freedom (i.e. freedom of action, not metaphysical freedom — the freedom of an unmoved mover) isn’t the issue — you need autonomy to be free, but not vice versa. Autonomy is a precondition of freedom of action since if your act is not autonomous, it is heteronomous, controlled by someone or something other than yourself. To be controlled by another is one way in which a person can be unfree. But the sort of freedom that a satisfied smoker lacks is not necessary for autonomy. When Martin Luther, asked to recant the claims contained in his writings, declared, “Hier stehe ich; ich kann nicht anders” (‘Here I stand; I can do no other’), he was not refusing to recant, but stating the impossibility (not metaphysical, but agential, impossibility, of course) of his recanting. He was unfree, but not thereby non- autonomous. '6 He was expressing his most deeply-held convictions - convictions which, '5 See, above, the distinction between desires and volitions. ‘6 Not unlike the smoker in the grips of her desires, Luther admitted to being “captive to the Word of God.” The distinction here is that Luther was assumedly completely satisfied with his lack of freedom to do otherwise. 118 because they are his, guide his autonomous actions, but convictions that were so deeply rooted that to act against them was impossible. Likewise, then, the fact (if it is one) that a smoker is not free not to smoke does not itself entail that she is non-autonomous. So long as the desires with which she identifies guide her actions, she acts autonomously. The second abovementioned issue regarding addiction, one that helps even further to explicate Frankfurt’s view, is that an addict has the desire whether she wants it or not. The foregoing discussion entails only that some (unspecified subset of) addicts act autonomously when they are moved by the desires characteristic of their addiction. Now, when addiction takes the form of an inner conflict, the conflicted person is not fully identified with either (or any, where there are more than two) of the desires that are in conflict.[7 This is why, consistent with widely-held intuition, this sort of addict - the one who does not identify with the urges that move her — is not autonomous. But when an addict is satisfied with her desire, she acts autonomously when she is moved by it, even though, like Luther, she can do no other. This sort of addict, like Luther, is not free to do otherwise, though she is not moved against her will; her own will moves her, and so she is autonomous. On Frankfurt’s view, then, whether an action is autonomous is judged strictly on the grounds of the structural relation between the first-order desires by which she is motivated and relevant second-order desires that may conflict with those of the first order. The necessary structural relation is one marked by a lack of conflict — that is, as outlined in Chapter 2 above, a unified one. '7 ‘Fully’ might seem to imply that ‘identification’ is a scalar notion. On Frankfurt’s view, ‘fully’ alludes to the degree to which conflict must be absent — namely, fully absent - regarding some desire in order for that desire to be one with which the person is identified. There are, on this view, degrees of conflict, but identification (and hence autonomy) requires that this precisely specified bar be reached (“Identification and Wholeheartedness”, Frankfurt, 1988, pp. 159-176). 119 C ontent-specific accounts To lead a bit obliquely into the discussion of content-specific accounts of autonomy, the locus classicus of what is sometimes called ‘infiltrated consciousness’ is an example from Thomas Hill.‘8 His example of the deferential wife is of a person who has fully accepted social norms of feminine subordination. Fully and wholeheartedly devoted to her husband, she actively subordinates herself to him, gaining her happiness and her self-identity from her servility, and all with her own full endorsement. She forms no independent desires of her own, desiring only to please her husband, and when she satisfies desires of his, she feels happy and fulfilled. Her consciousness is infiltrated (though Hill does not use these terms, he is certainly referring to the same phenomenon) in virtue of her not only being subject to the norms of servility, but having integrated them into her own stable, conflict-free internal economy. Hill’s example appeals to the intuition that even though the deferential wife considers herself happy and fulfilled, acts only on her own desires and is not forced against her will into subservience, something is amiss. The ex hypothesi claims that she is free, happy, and in control of her own life, it is argued, cannot be true. Not often noted by secondary authors, but relevant here, is the fact that Hill himself used the example to further argue that the deferential wife violates her duty of self-respect. Her fault is a moral one (though this is not to say that she is blameworthy), stemming from her having a certain morally wrong “attitude concerning one’s rightful place in a moral community.”'9 The deferential wife fails to fulfill her duty to maintain self-respect. ‘8 Hill (1973). '9 Hill (1973). p. 90. 120 Such a duty-based interpretation has apparently failed to appeal to a number of philosophers offering alternative readings. The first to be discussed here is Susan Babbitt, who argues that oppressed persons, like the deferential wife, who accept and endorse inaccurate claims of their subordinate status fail to possess an adequate self- conception.20 It is because of this adequate self-conception that persons in similar positions are not autonomous, in spite of certain understandings of autonomy on which they may be seen to be so. The argued lack of autonomy the deferential wife exhibits is not a matter of a failure of self-govemance. The “liberal view’”' of autonomy that Babbitt positions herself against has trouble making sense of the lack of autonomy in cases of infiltrated consciousness. Babbitt presents the liberal view of autonomy as a view of practical rationality, on which someone acts rationally (i.e. autonomously) “when she weighs her options in light of relevant information and does or chooses that which is most likely to advance more of her aims than other options.”22 Further, on the liberal view, an agent’s interests are determined by this same process — a person’s interests lie in satisfying her aims, fulfilling her desires, pursuing her goals. On the liberal view, Babbitt claims, an autonomous act is one that leads to the satisfaction of one’s aims, and so it is in a person’s interests to perform actions that best satisfy those aims. 2" Though similar to Hill’s interpretation of the issue as being one of self-regarding attitude, contemporary moral-psychological and moral-sociological interpretations of the deferential wife diverge sharply from the original deontological focus. 2' Babbitt (1996), p. 44. Babbitt notes that this view is not aptly so named in virtue of its being advanced by liberals, but rather because it takes the first—person perspective as the favored one. Though her target is ostensibly John Rawls, it is not clear that this is Rawls’s conception of autonomy as “acting from principles that we would consent to as free and equal rational beings” (Rawls (1971), p. 516). Rawls’ conception seems to imply an ideal self view not entirely unlike Babbitt’s, though I won’t pursue this criticism of Babbitt’s argument here. 22 Babbitt (1996), p. 38. 121 The important feature of such a view of autonomous action is its instrumentalism. In being instrumental, the process is evaluated by the results relative to the initial aims of the agent; whatever aims the agent perceives herself to have. The instrumental focus also implicitly sidesteps the procedure of determining just what a person’s interests are; interests seem simply self-evident. The process of autonomous action is one of information processing, of gathering relevant information and determining, largely empirically, what action is most likely to help satisfy one’s aims. Thus the view implies that the primary barrier to autonomy is a lack of information, a deficiency of factual knowledge. Babbitt points out that the deferential wife is, on the liberal view, autonomous on all counts. Her desires are indeed well satisfied by actions that are directed toward the satisfaction of her husband’s desires, and so the instrumental feature of autonomy is fulfilled. Nor would any factual information need be thought to change the actions or desires of the deferential wife. Hill puts this point well: “She readily responds to appeals from Women’s Liberation that she agrees that women are mentally and physically equal, if not superior, to men. She just believes that the proper role for a woman is to serve her family.”23 The intuition that something is wrong with the situation of the deferential wife is perhaps best brought out by Babbitt’s appeal to ‘interests’. The deferential wife is just a person who is supposed not to choose actions that lead to the fulfillment of any interests relevant to a good human life. Whether she knows it or not, Babbitt points out, the 23 Hill (1973). p. 89. 122 deferential wife has an interest in flourishing, in self-respect and dignity.M But pursuing these interests and satisfying the desires she actually has are not coterrninous Thus the main shortcoming of the liberal view of autonomy, as Babbitt sees it, is that a person’s interests are not always self-known, because she may have desires that even under conditions of full factual knowledge and capacity for instrumental reasoning might not lead her to actions that are in her real interests. A person’s real interests may not follow from her current desires by any path. Autonomous action is to be judged by what “would constitute autonomous action if conditions were such that it were possible for her to deliberate as a full human being.”25 These conditions, for the deferential wife, are a change in her social environment, and - following from this — a change in herself. Her oppressive social environment is the root cause of her inadequate self-understanding: she has been inculcated with norms of subordination and with the abilities (how to manage her appearance, how to walk, how to talk, how to think) that help her to obey these norms. But even more importantly for her to be autonomous, Babbitt argues, is a change in who she is, in who she takes herself to be. The deferential wife and those in similar situations need to conceive of themselves as someone whose proper role is to pursue their own flourishing, not that of others to whom they are submissive. Thus, on this account of autonomy, some actions are non-autonomous no matter who performs them. Servile actions, self-harmful actions, actions that undermine or are inconsistent with one’s own self-respect are, by definition, not autonomous actions. It is this implication that makes Babbitt’s a content-specific account. 2‘ Babbitt (1996), p. 14 and throughout. 25 Babbitt ( 1996), p. 6. Italics in original. 123 There are two main concerns that show Babbitt’s conception of autonomy and her defense of it to be untenable. One is that whatever the merits and accuracy of the appeal to cases of oppression in addressing issues of autonomy, to define autonomy in terms of resistance to oppressive forces, forces that prevent certain persons’ flourishing, has yielded an excessively narrow conception of autonomy. This can be seen through a number of familiar counterexamples that undermine Babbitt’s view and show it to fail to account for autonomous action generally, as I will go on to explain. The second concern is perhaps even more troubling. The claim that a person’s interests might well be better determined by someone other than herself is not necessarily itself problematic, but when this claim is taken to support the notion that a person could be more autonomous when acting from interests only others realize, the possibility of real personal damage is close at hand. I will address these issues in turn. Babbitt’s analysis of the damage caused by oppression to the capacity of persons to act in ways that promote their own overall flourishing is comprehensive. She establishes about those persons in situations similar to that of the deferential wife that “desiring the kind of self-determination we might think characteristic of a good life would depend on their undergoing a change to their actual selves — a change to their sense of themselves as well as a change to the actual interests and commitments they possess.”26 That is, many victims of oppression would live a good life only if they acquire different goals, if the (self-)direction of their lives were to change in fundamental ways. But the self-interest criterion for autonomy is too narrow. It may well be that one reason that some Oppressed persons are not able to act autonomously is that they are 2° Babbitt (1996). p. 45. 124 prevented from acting in ways that promote their own self-interest. But this is not to agree that autonomy generally is a matter of acting thus. Consider actions that are altruistic in the strong sense of the term. While we do call altruistic actions that benefit persons other than the agent, altruism in the strongest sense characterizes an action that benefits another person while inflicting costs on the agent. Such self-sacrifice would necessarily be non-autonomous on any account of autonomy that requires the promotion of self-interest (though actions that are altruistic in the weaker sense could be autonomous). Acts of straightforward self-sacrifice — parents who give up their own goals and instead promote those of their children, people who help strangers with no expectation of reciprocation, acting morally without regard to one’s own desires -— would be judged to be non-autonomous following Babbitt’s demand that autonomous action benefits oneself.27 Many of the paradigm examples of autonomy that Babbitt offers support the foregoing claims. She makes repeated references to the character Sethe in Toni Morrison’s novel Beloved as an exemplar of autonomous action; Sethe kills her children rather than allow them to be returned to slavery. What Babbitt finds important (important enough to quote twice, and refer to numerous times) is not that the children’s death was merciful, but that Sethe took it to be a self-interested act: “It was a kind of selfishness I never knew nothing about before. It felt good. Good and right.”28 Indeed, most of the proffered examples of autonomous action involve harm to others: Ridley Scott’s Thelma 27 Though there is no indication that this response is one Babbitt might offer, it can be noted that these examples are not, as they are in other contexts, subject to a egoist interpretation on which an apparently self-hannful action can in fact benefit the agent through her desire e. g. to save the stranger; there may be, on the strongest version of this view, no altruistic actions at all. But this response is inconsistent with Babbitt’s viewpoint since it embraces the so-called liberal view that Babbitt has positioned herself against; the egoist response, that is, appeals explicitly to desire-maximization in its interpretation of supposedly altruistic actions. 2” Babbitt (1996), p. 22 and again on p. 27 . 125 and Louise is taken to be about “the struggle for autonomy”29; the central scene in the film involves Louise’s shooting to death Thelma’s rapist (out of a sort of vicarious vengeance, not because Thelma needed to be defended). Marleen Gorris’s A Question of Silence is “the story of three women — a secretary, a waitress, and a housewife — who come together in a dress shop and (gruesomely) murder the dress-shop owner, a man they have never seen before.”30 Babbitt considers their action “reasonable’”' and takes this situation to be “significant as regards the individuals’ moral responsibilities to maintain their own sense of self-respect and dignity”, that is, the objects of autonomous action.32 My attribution of a self-interest view of autonomy to Babbitt is not simply a matter of interpreting her paradigm cases of autonomy thusly. Babbitt explicitly defines ‘autonomy’ in terms of self-interest. “Autonomy is a special kind of agency, the capacity to take control of one’s life and to realize one ’s best interests.”33 She writes of the preconditions required “to act autonomously, to be in control of their lives, where control is the realization of best interests.”34 But surely, contrary to both Babbitt’s strongly suggestive examples as well as her explicit demand that autonomy essentially promote one’s own interests, actions that benefit others while bringing harm to oneself can be autonomous. Indeed, a common and plausible assumption is that actions that proceed in spite of contrary self-benefiting desires, desires which are suspected of being the source of much heteronomous action, are likely candidates for the label of autonomy. 2" Babbitt (1996), p. 88. 3° Babbitt (1996), p. 112. 3' Babbitt (1996), p. 121. 32 Babbitt (1996), p. 112. 33 Babbitt (1996), p. 45. Italics added. 3" Babbitt (1996), p. 105. Italics added. 126 There are two responses that could be offered in defense of Babbitt’s arguments regarding the nature of autonomy. One is that Babbitt is not attempting to defend a conception of autonomy generally, but rather is arguing that there is a need in cases where person ’s moral self-conceptions are damaged by oppression for just these persons to attend to their self-interest in order to regain autonomy. To be sure, all of the examples that Babbitt offers of autonomous action are examples of distinctively oppressed persons in oppressive circumstances. But at least in claims such as “control [of one’s life] is the realization of best interests”, and others quoted above, she offers her arguments as applying to questions of autonomy generally. Further, Babbitt offers no reason to think that a person who because of oppression fails to realize her own interests differs from a person who for some other reason — moral saintliness, everyday codependency, habitual self-deprecation, or some other non- systematic cause — fails to aim her actions at her own self-interests. Indeed, in Hill’s original essay, the Deferential Wife was not different in this way from a person he termed the Self-Deprecator; each sort of person, Hill presumed, were in the same situation, morally and agentially speaking. Babbitt offers no reason to think otherwise. The second possible response is that it might be that what Babbitt has in mind is not simply an action’s outcome as determining whether it is an autonomous one, but rather the distinctly moral quality of the action — whether this moral quality is judged by the effect of the action or by its grounds. Though such an argument need not take a Kantian line, this is arguably what Kant had in mind regarding autonomy - that only 127 morally worthy acts are autonomous.35 Unfortunately, Babbitt here offers no explicit argument as to why we ought to think that autonomy includes a moral element. Diana Meyers (whose account will be examined more fully in the following section) does offer such an argument in her account of procedural autonomy. Appealing to the objective point of view that, it is often argued, we take toward ourselves in quiet moments of self-evaluation as well as in defending our choices, commitments and actions publicly, she writes, People’s intense concern with their personal decisions, the complexity of the processes whereby they ponder their options, and the ways in which they sometimes criticize the choices they have made would be inexplicable if personal autonomy were reducible to uncoerced choice.36 If what Babbitt calls ‘the liberal view’ were correct, then, our prospective deliberation regarding, as well as our retrospective evaluation of, our choices would be impossible to comprehend. What Meyers seems to ignore is the multitude of evaluative criteria that do ”37, that is, on objectively not, as she claims, depend on “genuinely good things valuable considerations. We criticize our own choices, for example, when they were guided by desires that were less strong or less subjectively important than others that could have guided our choice. The complexity of decision processes can be quite pronounced in clearly non-objective contexts - choosing a new pet that is to be compatible with one’s own personality and tastes, or deciding on a gift that will be appreciated by its recipient are both based essentially on nothing “genuinely good” but rather on what can be just as elusive: the determination of ’5 This line of thought regarding autonomy is not pursued here, as I take it that the Kantian model has been sufficiently undermined to preclude its viability. 3" Meyers (1989), p. 18. ’7 Meyers (1989), p. 18. 128 what is subjectively good. Lastly, people’s concern for their own decisions may be due in part to their striving for moral rectitude, but such concern is surely at least sometimes explicable in other terms: narcissism or even pedantry explain such concern even if they do not justify it. Indeed, there seems little reason to suspect that moral rigorism is at all common in daily life.38 There is much more to decision and action than bare (instrumental) autonomy, certainly, but this does not require that autonomy have a moral element. Without a more satisfying argument for the inclusion of moral elements in the notion of autonomy, the instrumental use of ‘autonomy’ (the concept) in attempting to promote best interests remains the most plausible interpretation of Babbitt’s arguments. This focus on the effects of one’s actions (the effect being promoting one’s best interests) plays a role in the second, more troubling, reason to think Babbitt’s account untenable. Valuable in identifying the details of this criticism is a passage from Babbitt, partially cited above. “But to the extent that some people are in fact deprived of dignity and self- respect in their actual lives, desiring the kind of self-determination we might think characteristic of a good life would depend on their undergoing a change to their actual selves — a change to their sense of themselves as well as a change to the actual interests and commitments they possess.”9 Babbitt’s point here is that no amount of factual information will be of help to certain oppressively socialized persons, since one thing that is restricting their autonomy is “their actual selves”. It is hard to doubt that the lives of many persons — all of us, likely — would not be improved with certain changes to our actual selves. Many of us would be happier and ’8 And even less reason to think it desirable. 3° Babbitt (1996). p. 45. 129 morally improved, ultimately, were we coerced into certain changes in our preferences and the associated actions. Some of these improvements may be so important as to justify paternalistic intervention. To be sure, Babbitt devotes an entire chapter to the denial of Will Kymlicka’s implausible claim that “no life goes better by being led from the outside according to values the person doesn’t endorse”.4O But on Babbitt’s view it is crucial here to recall that autonomy is essentially a matter of a person’s pursuing her own best interests, and that one of the primary checks on autonomous action by oppressed persons is an inadequate self-conception, one that fails to represent their real value as persons. This conception of autonomy along with the plausible claim that a person is not always (and some people are never) in a privileged position to identify their own best interests as well as their personal value sums to the peculiar claim that certain persons might be more autonomous were their lives led by values they themselves don’t endorse. Babbitt’s response is to argue that without active and possibly coercive intervention into societal structures, it is impossible for certain persons even to make real choices about their interests. Furthermore, such intervention is already ubiquitous: the social structures already in place force certain understandings on persons, often oppressively. This response, though, does not go far enough to defend against the possibility of (further) illegitimate intervention in other’s lives. On the liberal picture that Babbitt is positioned against, the benefits of paternalistic intervention in the life of a person is at least countervailed against by the value of autonomy, of her living her own life in spite of 4° Babbitt (1996). p. 84. 130 the well-being she might garner by external intervention. On a view that holds personal well-being to be conceptually equivalent to autonomy, there is no such guard against intrusive intervention. Thus Babbitt’s account of autonomy leaves open the possibility of political abuse to an even greater degree than does the so-called liberal view. This is a real worry since just what ‘human flourishing’ entails is an open question. Historically, widely accepted conceptions of flourishing in the Western world have included adherence to a certain elitist set of virtues, obedience to the church, commitment to scientific reasoning, and membership in a master/slave hierarchy supposedly for the benefit of members of both groups. It is historically still the case (within mainstream American political and social culture) that the dominant conception of human flourishing is tied up with assumptions of rugged individualism, heteronorrnativity and an economic model of human value that would be even more undesirable were it enforced in the name of autonomy. (Nor even need we restrict conceptions of flourishing to those of the mainstream to find such examples — consider Michigan Congressperson Barbara-Rose Collins’s early 1990S support of the Unremunerated Work Act, legislation that would have required the financial value of the unpaid work done primarily by women to be figured into the US Gross Domestic Product — yet another economic model of human value.) Without a substantive conception of ‘flourishing’, which Babbitt does not offer (instead taking “the ”41 concept “human flourishing” to require empirical investigation ), the recommendation that flourishing be imposed on persons is a dangerous one. 4' Babbitt (1996), p. 9. 131. Meyers ’s procedural account On procedural accounts, specifiable processes and the abilities required for one to undertake these process are essential to autonomy. Such accounts vary according to the nature of the defining process — the most general distinction within procedural accounts is between views that focus on the procedure by which a person comes to acquire the desires in which her autonomous actions are grounded, and those that take autonomy itself to be a procedure. Diana Meyers argues most explicitly for the latter, that autonomy itself is best understood through an analysis of the various procedures that constitute its practice, and as such she defends a procedural account.“2 She takes autonomy to be a tripartite phenomenon, including self-discovery, self-definition, and self-direction. Thus an autonomous person knows who she is, is able to effect changes in who she is, and is able to direct her life in accordance with who she is. Meyers understands each of these three elements of autonomy essentially as processes underpinned by “autonomy competency”, which refers to “the repertory of coordinated skills that make self-discovery, self- definition, and self-direction possible.”43 The skills of autonomy competency are numerous and varied. Autonomous persons are able to be resistant to external pressures, and, relatedly, have resolve — the determination to act on their own judgments.44 Autonomy involves the evaluation of one’s own desires, including the ranking of desires, the envisaging of alternative desires, ‘2 Though Meyers does in fact characterize autonomy as being inseparable from the processes she outlines, and she does label her account as a procedural one, I will go on to show that there are central elements of her account that overshadow the procedural criteria. ‘3 Meyers (1989), p. 76. ‘4 Meyers (1989), p. 83. 132 and the ability to imagine the outcomes of acting on various desires.“5 The autonomous person is engaged in ongoing adjustments to her self-image as her actions dictate, and as she fashions and adjusts her life plan."6 This last characterization, of a person involved in a dynamic relationship with a self-constructed life plan — which Meyers explains to be “a largely schematic, partially articulated vision of a worthwhile life that is suitable for a particular individual”,47 and, somewhat differently, “a comprehensive projection of intent”48 — is also clearly one of process. Working out such a plan, determining how to best act in accordance with it and modifying it in the fact of change in desire, ability and external conditions are ongoing tasks. The notion of a life plan is a central element of Meyers’s account. For people with life plans, the plans are also, Meyers argues, a “mirror [of] their authentic selves”, since they are partially systematic and partially explicit articulations of one’s desires.49 Thus to act in accordance with one’s life plan is just to act in accordance with one’s authentic self (alternately, “true self ’).5° As to the centrality of the authentic self in understanding autonomy, Meyers claims, “personal autonomy requires a touchstone. That touchstone is the unique authentic self.”SI There are a fair number of demands Meyers makes on the autonomous person that one can take issue with. One is the seemingly ad hoc demand that the authentic self be unique. In a fairly trivial sense, every entity is unique — numerically unique — but Meyers ‘5 Meyers (1989), p. 81. 4" Meyers (1989), p. 84. ‘7 Meyers (1989), p. 51. ‘8 Meyers (1989), p. 49. ‘9 Meyers (1989), p. 50. 5° Meyers (1989), p. 75 and elsewhere. 5' Meyers (1989), p. 19. has something more substantial in mind. “The leading phenomenon of personal autonomy,” she writes, “is human diversity. Unless one is impressed by the uniqueness of individuals, and unless one delights in this variegation, one will not suppose that these unique personalities should somehow be manifest in people’s lives, and one will never wonder how personal autonomy is possible?”2 This is likely a reaction to two concerns. One cause of this reactive demand is the dominant Kantian understanding of autonomy as rational action grounded in universal principles. In taking issue with such an understanding Meyers claims, “as rational beings, people are all alike.”53 Dissatisfaction with such an absurd characterization of autonomous persons motivates the uniqueness criterion. Another cause for the demand is likely the existence of the sort of socialization that aims to instill certain desires uniformly; oppressive socialization might be thought to be of this sort”4 But it is too strong a demand to put on autonomous persons that they be unique. The degree to which I share your desires, whether accidentally or even causally (some cases of empathy, for example, involve shared desires), is not clearly related to the degree to which I am autonomous. As noted above, the demand that one’s authentic self be unique is not apparently an integral part of the conception of autonomy Meyers defends. The traits and abilities that characterize autonomy competency, though, are the constitutive elements of the 52 Meyers (1989), p. 82. 5’ Meyers (1989), p. 13. 5“ A fact easily overlooked is that the uniformity of desires is not itself importantly relevant to oppression, but certain patterns of instilled desires certainly are. The fact that persons are oppressed in virtue of their group membership entails that oppressive socialization will tend to aim at unifomrity of desires within groups (so that, for example, all women will desire to be domestically skilled), but the oppression is a function of the possession of the desire by women and not men. 134 account — and many of these traits and abilities are either not characteristic of people generally, or not part of the authentic selves of many actual persons. Those with autonomy competency are said to engage in candid communication about their own concerns, have lively recall, vivid imagining, openmindedness, and alertness to the reactions of others. ”These are skills with which everyone is acquainted and with respect to which each of us knows roughly how proficient she is.”55 That autonomous persons must possess these qualities is an unrealistic demand, for two reasons. The first is that the claim that people generally are aware of the degree to which they themselves possess these qualities is simply false. Even without empirical data it is not difficult to determine that most people overestimate some of their own abilities at least occasionally. But data are not lacking. Numerous studies have shown that such overestimation of one’s own abilities is ubiquitous.56 The second reason that such characteristics are not legitimate criteria for judging autonomy — especially on an account that holds autonomous action to be that action grounded in the authentic self - is that such characteristics simply are not part of everyone’s authentic self. Meyers claims that chronic obliviousness to self-referential responses, awkwardness or rigidity in envisaging and appraising options, uncommunicativeness about one’s needs, desires, values, and so forth, imperviousness to others’ feedback, timidity about acting on the basis of one’s own deliberations, and obstinate inflexibility in executing a chosen plan [. . .] signal the individual’s inability to fathom his or her authentic self”.57 5" Meyers (1989), pp. 87-88. 5" Though the most thorough attempt to determine the extent of personal overestimation is in medical contexts (Ward, et al., 2002), social psychologists are indeed interested in the phenomenon in the general population (DeAngelis, 2003). 57 Meyers (1989), p. 88. 135 Thus to take oneself to be uncommunicative, impervious, or timid in these ways is to misunderstand one’s own true self. But this demand entails that there is no one who in fact unimaginative, uncommunicative and unobservant, a claim that excludes many persons. This may seem to be a misguided interpretation of Meyers’s claims. It would seem unlikely that that she is denying anyone an authentic self. The plainness with which this claim is stated, though, makes other interpretations difficult: “An authentic self is a self that has autonomy competency and that emerges through the exercise of this competency.”58 If an authentic self has autonomy competency, then any self without autonomy is not an authentic self. Since it is agreed by all parties to the debate over autonomy that there are some persons who lack it, on Meyers’s account there are some persons who lack an authentic self. That suggests that there is no person who they truly are. What Meyers is more plausibly interpreted as seeking in the notion of the authentic self is better termed the ‘ideal self’. A bit of textual exegesis is required to substantiate this claim, and so I will end the discussion of Meyers’s account by doing just that. As noted above, the concern surrounding the authentic self is grounded in the worry that a person can fail to know who she really is, and thus fail to act as she really wants to. Meyers makes this claim in many different ways, and in varied contexts and arguments. At one point, she puts it this way: Autonomous people must be disposed to consult their selves, and they must be equipped to do so. More specifically, they must be able to 5" Meyers (1989), p. 53. 136 pose and answer the question “What do I really want, need, care about, value, etcetera?”; they must be able to act on the answer; and they must be able to correct themselves when they get the answer wrong.” This is a familiar sounding passage, but focusing on the last portion of it will likely reveal something novel. What is it to get the answer — to the question ‘what do I really want, need, care about, value’ — wrong? It could be that a wrong answer is one that is personally mistaken — as when I have a feeling that makes me think I need sleep, when in fact I need to drink some water, or (somewhat differently) when a person buys a new car thinking she wants more creature comfort in her life, when in fact she wants envious attention from others. In these sorts of cases the error regards determining one’s actual internal state (thirst, vanity). The mistake in these sorts of cases is epistemic. Another way in which a person might be wrong about what she really wants, values, and so on, is that she could in fact want and value the wrong things. This is the sense at hand in the judgment of the amateur psychologist who claims that what you really need is love, and thus your need for money (though descriptively true of you) is wrong, morally. This is the sense in which valuing the sorts of things that Klan members characteristically value is morally wrong. This bipartite interpretation of Meyers’s view is supported by claims that imply both an element of self-govemance and a moral element to autonomy. “Any ostensible case of autonomy could be debated. Was the crucial choice the right one to make, or not? Was the agent really in control of his or her life, or not?”60 As we saw in the previous section, Meyers offers an argument in support of the claim that there are moral criteria involved in the judgment of whether an act was 5” Meyers (1989), p. 52. 6° Meyers (1989), p. 9. 137 autonomous. If autonomy is grounded in the authentic self — the “touchstone” of autonomy — then it would seem there is a self that a person ought to have, namely, the self from which autonomous actions flow. Meyers does argue, in a line of thought quite similar to one pursued by Lindemann (discussed in chapter 2, above), that persons possess identity elements that they would rather not — disparaging, oppressive, and simply undesired third-personal attributions. She describes the ways in which persons can and do go about reconfiguring their own identities — by attempting to make one’s actions cohere with her aspirations, reconciling her specific goals with her group memberships, and so on - so as to engage in the process of self-configuration of authentic selves. But here, too, not only is the authenticity necessary for autonomy a matter of discovering (or ‘defining’; Meyers uses both terms) one’s self by acting on the desires and values that one has, it is also a matter of determining which “desires, personal traits, values, interests and aims shouldl seek to enact”."l That is to say, Meyers’s notion of autonomy involves not acting on the desires I have so much as acting on the desires I ought to have. In this way, the desires with which a person in fact identifies might well be less germane to her own autonomy than desires with which she (morally) ought to identify. The authentic self is thus better understood as an ideal self — ideal, that is, not merely in some normative sense or other, but rather ideal regarding the possibility of acting autonomously. Though Meyers has named her own account ‘procedural’, it should be apparent from the foregoing explication that the most prominent features of the account have less 6' Meyers (2000), p. 166; emphasis added. 138 to do with its procedural features than with the notion of the authentic self that plays so central a role in autonomy. Although the next part of the discussion affixes the ‘procedural’ label to accounts that were not so named by their original authors, the accounts of autonomy from Paul Benson and John Christman illustrate more centrally important procedural requirements on autonomous action. Procedural responses to the structural model Both of the accounts of autonomy, from Paul Benson and John Christman, to be discussed in what follows are largely responses to the structural model of autonomy, as defended by Harry Frankfurt. (in what follows, ‘the structural model’)."2 On this model, a person is autonomous just in case she identifies with her motivating desire. What it is to identify with a desire is less simple, as discussed above, in Chapter 2, but recall the basic outline of ‘identification’: to identify with a desire is just to endorse it, where to endorse a desire entails the possession of no second-order desire that conflicts with it. So someone who acts on a desire she wants to have (more specifically but less straightforwardly, since the criterion is a negative one, ‘a desire about which it is false that she wants not to have it’) has thereby acted autonomously. Both Benson and Christman are unsatisfied with the structural model for similar reasons as those which motivated criticisms from Babbitt and Meyers. Each argues that Frankfurt’s hierarchical account of identity is unacceptable since it does not account for the importance of the manner in which one comes to possess her hi gher-order desires. On the structural account, a person who comes to possess desires through coercive or 62 In this section, like in the discussion of the structural model in Chapter 1, I will appeal most often to Frankfurt’s claims, rather than those of Gerald Dworkin, primarily because of Frankfurt’s more extensive writings on the subject. Since Benson criticizes only Frankfurt’s version of the model, and Christman takes the two versions to be “essentially the same” (1991, p. 5), this focus on Frankfurt is legitimate. 139 manipulative processes and endorses them on the basis of similarly-acquired second- order desires is autonomous when she is motivated by these desires. This is so since autonomy is judged simply on whether the endorsement relationship holds, not on the basis of the way in which this relationship came about. Christman recommends adding to the hierarchical model the requirement that a person must have the self-reflective ability to approve of the process by which she acquired her desire. This ability must be self-transparent, non-self—deceptive and minimally rational. Benson argues that hi gher—order endorsement — the core of the structural model — is alone neither necessary nor sufficient for autonomy. He proposes adding to the model a condition of critical competence regarding action — that a person need to be able to discern the reasons that there are for her to act. I will discuss each of these proposals in turn. C hristman ’3 historical criteria A clear formulation of Christman’s principal claim is “that the central focus of autonomy must make particular reference to the processes of preference formation, in particular what makes them ‘manipulative’ in a way crucially different from ‘normal’ processes of self-development.”63 Thus, Christman realizes that which was discussed at some length above: simply because a desire is manipulatively or coercively instilled in a person is not sufficient to ground a charge of illegitimacy; such inculcations are ubiquitous and permissible in early education, for instance. The illegitimate sorts of manipulations of desires might come about as the result of brainwashing, or oppressive socialization of the sort involved in Hill’s example of the deferential wife. 6" Christman (1991), p. 10. 140 Consistent with Frankfurt’s account is the possibility “that a thoroughly manipulated individual could be considered autonomous.” Christman asks us to “[i]magine someone who has been secretly hypnotized to want strawberries. . .But such a person is surely not autonomous relative to this desire for strawberries”64 This last claim, employing the vague phrase ‘relative 10’, could mean either or both of two things. It could mean that her acting on the desire for strawberries (by, e. g. eating one) is not an autonomous action. It could also mean that there is something non-autonomous about her very having of the desire. The former interpretation is just the sort of claim at issue in the present chapter, and as such it calls for no direct response here. The latter reading, involving desires that are themselves autonomous, is a claim that was discussed above, in Chapter 1. There I argued that only actions, and not desires, are said to be autonomous. Given this further explication through an example of the phenomenon at issue, we might more clearly understand Christman’s point. Rather than (as ‘autonomous’ suggests) understanding desires ideally to be self-governed, or self-motivated, we might see the point about hypnotically-acquired desires to be that they are inaccessible to self-alteration. Once a person submits to (or is otherwise subjected to) hypnosis, she can neither eliminate nor alter the desires she comes thus to possess. I assume (having no experience with hypnosis) that the post-hypnotic subject feels no internal conflict regarding the implanted desires. But, as Christman acknowledges, this inalterability is true of many of our desires, including some of those that are most central to our self-conceptions. Such desires are 6" Christman (1991), pp. 8-9. 141 often “too much entrenched”"5 into one’s self-conception to be subject to alteration by any but the most radical (and, notably, non-self-directed) upheavals. In agreement with many of the this work’s readers, Christman admits that “I would not say that my desire to study philosophical questions, which for me has this character, is not autonomous.”66 Thus, the mere ability to alter one’s desires is not at the heart of Christman’s concern regarding autonomy. Christman’s view aims to “eliminate the need for the condition of identification (as such) altogether.” 67 Irrelevant to determining autonomy is agent’s evaluation of her desire at a particular time, Christman claims. What matters is what the agent thinks about the process of coming to have the desire. Thus, a person is autonomous just in case she acts on a desire that she acquired through some process of which she approves. Specifically, the criteria Christman proposes are these: (i) A person P is autonomous relative to some desire D if it is the case that P did not resist the development of D when attending to this process of development, or P would not have resisted that development had P attended to the process; (ii) The lack of resistance to the development of D did not take place (or would not have) under the influence of factors that inhibit self-reflection; and (iii) The self-reflection involved in condition (i) is (minimally) rational and involves no self-deception?" Among the problems with such a view is its silence on cases in which a person acts (intuitively, autonomously) on some desire she possesses in virtue of some unapproved-of process. Consider a philosopher who realizes that argument from ‘55 Christman (1991), p. 6. 6" Christman (1991), p. 6. ‘7 Christman (1991), p. 10. ‘8 Christman (1991), p.11. 142 authority is insufficient grounds on which to endorse a desire. Nonetheless, at one time she acquired a desire to drink Diet Pepsi because her then—idol, Ray Charles, promoted the beverage in advertisements. Does she now act autonomously when she drinks Pepsi- Cola to satisfy her desire for a sweet-tasting, caffeinated, carbonated beverage? I think she does. Christman’s view might allow for the intuitive interpretation of this case if we stipulate that the desire she now has to drink Diet Pepsi is a different desire than the (non- autonomy-grounding) desire she had to drink Diet Pepsi when she was watching cola advertisements. Other than for the support it would lend to Christman’s View, though, there seems no reason to think the two desires are distinct. It might be replied that the imagined case violates none of the criteria. It does not violate the most obvious, (iii) the notion of ‘minimal rationality’, since Christman takes this merely to be reasoning that “does not contain manifest contradictions?"9 It does violate (i) if it is allowed that the person as she is now is the one who does not retrospectively resist the development of the desire; the now-philosopher now knows that celebrity endorsements are poor grounds for desires. This reading of (i), though, cannot be the reading at issue, since then it fails to accommodate the sort of cases Christman has in mind, e. g. brainwashing. The now brainwashed person does not retrospectively resist the process of her brainwashing, just as Paul does not resist the process of his conversion (though Saul might have)?" If (i) refers only to the person that she was at the time of the desire-acquisition, then this precludes many cases of retrospective disapproval — once a 6” Christman (1991), p. 13. 7° Acts 22. “I could not see for the glory of that light” (22:11) Paul recounts at least partially metaphorically, and he admits that “even while I prayed in the temple, 1 was in a trance” (22: 17). Paul became blind and unaware, and thus is in a situation similar to that of the hypnotized or oppressively socialized person. 143 person has approved of the process, she identifies with the desires that it gives her ad infinitum. To disallow future reevaluations of one’s identity is certainly incorrect. There are further problems involving the endorsement of a desire’s formative process. Whether the self-evaluation of the process is made by the person as she is before she has acquired the desire in question or after, the evaluation itself is inextricably dependent on more than rationality, reflective ability and freedom from self-deception. Self-evaluation is essentially dependent on the content of one’s desires (and also her beliefs, and fears, and so on). The example of the deferential wife shows that rationality, reflection and freedom from self-deception are not sufficient to ground the sort of self-evaluation that would enable her to repudiate her putatively illegitimate desires." She is minimally rational, in Christman’s sense of being free from manifest contradiction. There is no reason to doubt that she is self-reflective; “No one is trampling on her rights, she says,” Hill imagines, “for she is quite glad, and proud, to serve her husband as she does?72 That is, the deferential wife responds to the claims of others that her rights are being violated; she looks inward to see whether she feels this way, and finds she does not - in fact she finds a feeling of pride. (Indeed, the force of the example depends on her reflecting and, having done so, finding nothing at all amiss.) She is, though not as obviously, free from self- deception as well. She is clearly deceived, but not by herself. She herself is indeed in error (regarding her moral beliefs, or her empirical beliefs, or the source of her personal 7' Two points bear mention regarding this claim. The deprecating tone of ‘putatively illegitimate’ here refers not to the undesirability of the deferential wife’s desires (with which I completely agree), but rather to the sense of ‘illegitimate’ at issue here - namely, ‘not truly her own.’ Also, the claim consciously brackets consideration of those clearly external forces (e. g. the threat of physical harm) that prevent persons from repudiating certain of their desires; that is to say, rationality, reflection and freedom from self- deception are never, strictly speaking, sufficient (without certain external facts obtaining) to self— evaluation. 72 Hill (1973), p. 89. 144 value, depending on the commentator), but deception essentially involves a connection with an accepted truth from which other beliefs or actions deviate.73 Thus the deferential wife meets the proposed criteria for autonomy. The example of the deferential wife cannot be generalized to all cases in which we aim to determine autonomy, of course. For example, many cases of less- comprehensive oppressive socialization clearly involve a degree of self-deception; a victim of intimate abuse might deceive herself into believing that she deserves the abuse, in order to construct some explanation, however implausible, of her experience. But Christman’s account entails other implausible judgments. On his view there could be a person who acts autonomously when she is motivated by some desire she acquired through a process of which she approves but which in virtue of its content she disdains and repudiates. What Christman is appealing to is not the general sort of process by which a person comes to have a desire (e. g. my parent’s benevolent paternalism) but rather specific instances of processes (e. g. the instance of benevolent parental paternalism in virtue of which I acquired my desire to study science in the interest of landing a good- paying job upon graduation). I may, indeed, come to think that this instance of my parents’ guidance undesirable; I may think that studying with future pecuniary reward in mind is tantamount to squandering an education. But in this case, then, the content of the desire is doing all the work of determining which processes yield desires with which I will identify. Thus, the subjective judging of desires on the grounds of their genesis is 73 This is why ‘lying’ is not in principle inconsistent with ‘truth-telling’ - a person who is in error regarding the truth value of some proposition, and who also lies in regards to it, ultimately conveys the truth. Knowing that you are being lied to — but being unaware of the state of the liar’s knowledge — alone tells you nothing about the truth value of the deceptively-intended claims; thus deception is an intentional concept, not an epistemic one. 145 either patently false (‘1 got this benighted desire from my benevolent parents, so it must be mine’) or superfluous, since it depends essentially on the content of the desire. What Christman seems to be aiming for is a view on which desires are subject to more evaluation than mere endorsement in order for them to ground autonomous actions. Of course, ‘endorsement’ does not (contrary to Christman’s implication) exclude ‘evaluation.’ In either approving of or accepting the various elements of one’s identity there is (in some circumstances more than others) a critical consideration of the value of the element, the degree to which it coheres to other elements with which one identifies, and so on.74 But any such evaluation is limited, Christman realizes, to judgment on the basis of the desires, beliefs, and the like, that one already endorses. Thus while attempting to elucidate a manner of self-evaluation that is not essentially dependent on that which is being evaluated is an understandable sort of project, Christman’s suggestion does not helpfully further that project, for the reasons laid out above. Benson ’5 critical competence condition Paul Benson has much the same goal as does Christman, and a proposal that shares elements with both Christman’s and Susan Babbitt’s View.” He aims to account for cases of oppressive socialization like that of the deferential wife. Women who are socially coerced into shaping their appearances so as to be visually pleasing to men often come to internalize the judgments that failing to maintain their appearances for men’s pleasure is a personal failing. This judgment, of course, is untrue, and so he claims such 7" Even in situations of what we might call ‘endorsement by silence’ (endorsement by refusing or failing critically to evaluate), the decision to refuse to evaluate is itself a critical evaluation of a higher order (since in order to make such a decision one must have considered whether further evaluation would be worthwhile). Cases in which one simply fails to evaluate — in which a person accepts a desire of hers out of disinterest in or ignorance of her possession of it — involves her not considering the desire worthy of her attention, which is itself an evaluative stance. 7’ In Benson (1991). 146 socialization “systematically lead[s] women to internalize false construals of their personal value and, in consequence, to misconstrue many of the reasons there are for them to act?“ Like Christman, Benson takes autonomous action to be grounded in desires and other motives that are subject to more than hi gher-order endorsement. Like Babbitt, he argues for the inclusion of a content-specific epistemic element in the notion of autonomy. Babbitt’s requirement, recall, is that autonomous actions aim at the actor’s best interests, essentially involving the autonomous person’s adequate self-conception that leads her to knowledge of what her best interests are.77 Benson describes oppressively socialized women as lacking correct beliefs about what constitutes their own personal worth. This epistemic error leads, as noted in the cited passage above, to failure to act on appropriate reasons. Most basically, Benson’s dissatisfaction with structural accounts lies in their restricted characterization of ‘autonomy’. “These views assume that critical reflection facilitates autonomy mainly in virtue of its efficacy in the motivation of an agent’s action, regardless of whether or not the agent is a sufficiently competent criticizer to be able to recognize and appreciate for herself the reasons there are for her to act in various ways.”78 Thus structural views, the claim runs, allow all self-directed actions to count as autonomous, whether or not they are the actions of a sufficiently competent criticizer. It is worth noting that simple epistemic error does not itself entail a loss of autonomy. If it did, then no one, or radically fewer people than we tend to think, has 7" Benson (1991), p. 389. 77 This is a central element of Babbitt’s notion of “personal transformations” by which one can acquire “beliefs that make possible an alterative interpretation of his society.” (p. 3) 7'3 Benson (1991), p. 396. 147 been autonomous: we just didn't know (and probably still don't know) just what our own individual or more broadly human flourishing entails. Suppose we come to realize, not entirely implausibly, that human flourishing requires maintaining a strong connection to the natural world, through working to preserve a pre-human environment and seeking to understand ourselves primarily as part of the natural (as opposed to, say, the more broadly moral) world, and the like. It would be quite odd to think that this fact would entail that all of us who had failed to live in this natural fashion — though they might have been failing to flourish, or may have even been living morally badly in some broader sense — were not autonomous. Benson’s claim is, fortunately, not so categorical. “Persons do not suffer reduced autonomy merely because they have false beliefs about what they should do, or because they act contrary to what there are the best reasons for them to do?” Autonomy is preserved, Benson argues, in at least two sorts of situations: (1) in which the person “autonomously decides to curtail rational consideration of certain of his motives or available lines of action”, and (2) in which the person, though having exercised critical competence, simply makes a mistaken judgment.80 By way of agreement, I will pass over (1) and focus on (2), especially on the notion of ‘critical competence’. This notion, I’ll go on to show, is problematic in at least two ways: The critical competence necessary for autonomy is an ability to reflect not merely on one’s higher-order preferences, though Benson’s view requires this ability as well; at least at many points in the discussion, he poses his recommendations as additions to Frankfurt’s view. The critical reflection that is the function of hi gher-order endorsement 7'9 Benson (1991), p. 397. 8° Benson (1991), p.397. 148 of first-order volitions must be sensitive to “the reasons there are”.8| There are at least two readings of the quoted phrase, each of which indicates problems with the object of the critical reflection criterion, namely practical reasons (I’ll discuss the process of critical reflection itself in a moment). On the weak reading, on which the reasons at issue are (merely) “the reasons that their hi gher-order motives afford”82, no addition has been made to a standard structural account. This is because Frankfurt-style endorsement already provides the agent with reasons grounded in her hi gher-order desires. The apostle Paul, for example, has at least one more reason to serve God than does Saul — that reason is that Paul endorses (whether actively or by mere lack of internal conflict) his serving God.83 On the other hand, a strong reading, on which ‘the reasons there are’ refers to reasons external to any desires (lower- or hi gher-order) of the agent, might seem to cast autonomy’s net problematically wide, in ways discussed in earlier sections of the present chapter. Benson is apparently aware of the problematic nature of content requirements on autonomous action, for, as noted above, he allows for the possibility of autonomous actions grounded in mistaken judgments, so long as critical competence features in deliberation. There are two points to be discussed regarding this reasons requirement. The first is grounded in the nature of practical reasons, and the second in Benson’s fallibilist characterization of the critical competence that ideally leads to the reasons there are. 8' Benson (1991), p. 396. 82 Benson (1991), p. 399. 33 There may, of course, be disagreement as to whether Saul has a reason to serve God or not; the point is that however many such reasons Saul has, Paul has (at least) one more. 149 The nature of practical reasons is a concern here in light of a contemporary dispute over whether a certain reason for a certain person must, to be considered a reason for her, appeal to some desire, aim, or motive that the person already has. Benson realizes that an account of autonomy that includes a responsiveness-to-reasons requirement might seem to separate the grounds of action from the agent herself, since it appeals to something conceptually outside the agent’s will, too far from the “self- regulation, or self-determination, that seems to stand at the conceptual center of the notion of autonomy.”84. This is a worry primarily in light of a conception of reasons as things that “serve to justify actions; their status as reasons does not depend on their actually belonging to explanations of the agent’s actions.”85 This external conception of reasons, as it has come to be called, denies that a reason need be in some way connected to some desire, aim or motive of the agent to whom it is a reason. Benson denies the accuracy of such a conception, at least in the context of autonomy. “Now, when I act autonomously,” he claims, “. . .these reasons must be capable of being the grounds on which I form my decision and subsequently undertake to act?“ The distinctly autonomous agent is one for whom “the motivational capacity of ”87 than for the nonautonomous person who, as exemplified by reasons is more robust oppressively socialized women, is blind to certain of the reasons there are. So the autonomous agent, at least, is a person to whom the relevant reasons are internal - that is, the reasons do have connections with her motives. 8“ Benson (1991), p. 398. 85 Benson (1991), p. 401. 8" Benson (1991), p. 402. 87 Benson (1991), p. 408, fn 23. 150 If Benson is making a claim about the nature of reasons, then, it might seem a limited one. Reasons, on his account, are by nature justificatory claims, but in the special case of autonomous actions they serve a motivational purpose in virtue of the autonomous agent’s appreciation of them. Thus the connection between a person and her actions is preserved, since whatever role “the reasons there are” play in her actions, it is only because she sees them as reasons that they are connected to her actions. The criterion of autonomy is now shifted from some feature of the relation between an agent and her actions to the agent herself - more specifically, to that part of her self-identity concerned with her conception of her own value. Broadly speaking, the critical competence condition puts restraints not so much on what reasons a specific autonomous agent can act on as it puts restraints on what she is to identify with at all.88 This entails that certain persons fail to act autonomously not because they fail to govern themselves, but because they have an identity that could not, given any connection with the person’s actions, be involved in self— governance. The oddity of such a view — on which a person with certain identity elements cannot be autonomous with respect to them regardless of the actions they motivate — has been repeatedly noted in the foregoing discussions. Specifically, Benson’s view denies autonomy to anyone who is in error, to some substantial degree, regarding her own personal value. This seems at first to be a specific subtype of the now-familiar ideal self. Benson’s ideal self is one who self-identifies as a person with the degree and sort of personal value that an objectively accurate identification of her would reveal. But in fact, Benson’s version of this view involves a 8” It also assumes that successful critical reflection will lead to ethical convergence on ‘the reasons there are’, an assumption incompatible with Williams’s brand of intemalism. 151 troubling dilemma.89 If the oppressively socialized person acts in accordance with her misvaluation, she fails to respond to the reasons there are, and is thus not autonomous. If she acts contrary to this valuation - that is, acts as a person who knows her real value, in accordance with the reasons there are — she would fail to act autonomously, not being self—regulating.90 Given that “feminine socialization has insinuated its lessons into their ”91 most stable views of what they are and ought to be as persons , the only possibility for autonomy for such persons will often be radical change in who they are —- perhaps, practically, to become someone else. The second concern mentioned above, regarding Benson’s characterization of critical competence, shows that the critical competence condition is little help here, at least insofar as one might support an addendum to the structural view. The critical competence condition appears not to be a part of the structural view in cases in which a person endorses her desires in the negative, or passive, sense of ‘endorsement’ — that is, where she experiences no internal conflict regarding a first-order desire. If she fails to experience such conflict because she has simply been blinded (through oppressive socialization) to the possibility of negatively evaluating (and thus experiencing internal conflict regarding) her desire, critical competence is supposed to give such her a tool with which to come to this negative evaluation. 8” This dilemma is likely present certain other views under discussion here. It is especially clear in Benson’s account, though, since this account weights equally heavily the notion of self-regulation (which, for example, Susan Babbitt’s account was relatively unconcerned with) and acting with regard to objective reasons. 9° A great deal depends here on the details of exemplary cases. If she is coerced into acting in a self- valuing way -- say she is fined unless she acts in such a way -- she is not autonomous vis-a-vis her understanding of her own value, though it might be debated whether she acts autonomously in relation to the financial motive. 9' Benson (1991), p. 388. 152 It is not clear, though, what this process would amount to that is over and above endorsement. It certainly cannot be a process on which every one of a person’s first- order desires are actively evaluated before (or even after, in retrospect) they can ground autonomous action — the range of autonomous actions is much greater than the range of actions performed on the basis of motives that have been subjected to explicit critical evaluation, unless we think there are vanishingly few autonomous actions performed. More plausibly, autonomous actions are grounded in motives that could be the subject of such evaluation just in case the agent saw some reason to evaluate them. Think here, for example, of the process by which most people are able critically to evaluate the safety of our immediate surroundings — we (again, most of us) do not always check that no one is lurking behind the door, that the iron is off, that the carbon monoxide detector isn’t going off, and so on. Rather, if we notice something a bit amiss, we have the ability to look behind the door, check the iron, and so on. Now this ability is one the autonomous agent, on the structural view, does indeed have. If she senses something (internally) amiss, she can either probe for the root of the conflict, or remain in conflict without knowing why; in either case, the desire in question is not one she is autonomous in regards to, just as Benson demands. If, rather, we interpret the critical competence condition in the light of the stronger reading of “the reasons there are” - that is, the reasons there are regardless of the person’s subjective motives — the situation is little better. Not that Benson explicitly recommends such a reading of the critical competence condition. Indeed, critical competence as a fallible ability — one, that is, that ideally leads to the reasons there are, but is a necessary component of autonomous action even when it goes awry — might 153 appear to offer a reply to the abovementioned dilemma of a person’s being autonomous only if she becomes someone else. Given that critical competence in evaluating one’s motives is a fallible tool, the problem that faces oppressively socialized and hence nonautonomous persons is not centrally their failure to apprehend reasons, but is rather that they lack the ability to do so (whether or not that ability leads to success). If this is the case — that the radical alteration of one’s values, aims, social commitments is not so necessary for autonomy as is simply the ability to apprehend reasons - then the worry that a person might have to in effect become someone else is misplaced. But although Benson explicitly claims that critical competence is a fallible ability, and that “one can exercise the requisite critical competence and still arrive at a mistaken assessment of what there is reason for one to do””, he describes it solely in terms of its success. He gives an example of a woman who “had sufficient competence at critical reflection to be able to appreciate the unreasonableness of some features of her gender training.”93 Benson flatly states that “autonomy requires having sufficient competence at critical reflection to be able to detect and appreciate the reasons there are to act in various ways?” In both the example and the statement, sufficiency of competence is characterized in terms of what goal a person is able to reach. A bit later, Benson tells of a situation in which “inasmuch as I can apprehend that my desire is not irrational and that I have no good reason at the moment to do anything else, I can possess all the critical 9 ’95 ability that autonomy demands And since Benson is explicitly discussing the autonomy of specifiable actions, not “that sort of autonomy which attaches only to 92 Benson (1991), p.397. 9" Benson (1991), p.397. 9" Benson (1991), p. 397. 95 Benson (1991), p. 400. 154 ”9" it is not the case that ‘ability’ means something like extended periods of agents’ lives ‘tendency’. The emphasis, it is clear, remains still on connection with the reasons there are, and thus ultimately on the values, desires, goals, and commitments with which the autonomous person identifies?7 The reasons of the ideal self The foregoing proposed accounts of autonomy each suffer flaws that make them inadequate replacements for the structural account. The reasons for this inadequacy, as we saw, vary: Babbitt’s narrow range of concerns leads to a narrow understanding of autonomy; Meyers’s account is grounded in an implausible notion of the authentic self, and contains an inadequately-supported moral element; Christman’s criteria for preference formation ultimately do not support judgments in the intended cases. Beneath these distinctions, these accounts share a conception of the central problem of autonomy. I agree with the claim implied by all the philosophers under discussion that if there is something about a person’s volitional economy that is outside her control, there will be a degree of autonomy lacking in actions that issue from that portion of her volitional economy. This just follows from the ‘self-control’ element of autonomy — since, for example, my motive to hand over my wallet to the mugger is not in my control (it is, rather, in the control of the mugger), I am thereby not autonomous when I hand over the wallet.” This should be uncontentious. 9" Benson (1991), p. 390. 97 There may, of course, be a way to characterize the ability without reference to its success. Meyers’s similar notion of ‘autonomy competency’ was characterized by the various abilities that constitute it, but as I argued there, many of these abilities are ones that apparently autonomous persons lack. 9‘"That the example depends specifically on coercion might make it contentious regarding autonomy, but the point it illustrates should be clear. 155 But the absence of such gun-to-the-head coercion is not sufficient for the sort of control at issue in the non-structural accounts. What these accounts require for autonomy is that the motivational elements with which a person identifies are under the auspices of some further elements with which she identifies but that are not themselves part of the set of motives they govern. An internal economy that supports autonomous action must have some portion insulated from the rest, at least when ‘the rest’ fails to meet the criteria peculiar to the different accounts. For example, the closed-minded, socially unaware person is autonomous on Meyer’s account only if she acts openmindedly and with alertness to the reactions of others. The shared intuition, then, is that there is some sort of ideal self that the person could autonomously act from within, if only she could become (or act as) that self: Babbitt claims that any person, whatever her perceived interests, is really interested in flourishing; Christman implies that the self I become is really only me if I have control over that self-becoming process; Benson argues that only by identifying with specific sorts of morally desirable reasons can a person be autonomous; Meyers explicitly argues that central to autonomy is the acting not on apparent desires but rather on the real desires of what she calls the authentic self, which I argued to be an ideal self. Ideal-self views are by no means assuredly benign. Consider the marginalizing effects of denying the autonomy of persons who are not able to critically evaluate the makeup of their internal states. On the strongest (by no means an implausibly strong) interpretation of ‘critical evaluation’, this includes all persons, given the ‘view from nowhere’ requirement of such self-evaluation. In a certain sense, every person is like the paranoid who denies attributions of paranoia to her on the grounds that they are certainly 156 lies constructed by those who are persecuting her. This observation should at least give us pause: There can be no well-ordered inquiry into the question of how one has reason to live, because the prior question of how to identify and to evaluate the reasons that are pertinent in deciding how one should live cannot be settled until it has first been settled how one should live.99 There is, alternately, a more localized interpretation of the self-reflection demand, on which a person evaluates not her entire internal economy but rather portions of it. The thought here might be (as, for example, John Christman has suggested) that certain legitimate elements of one’s identity are to support reflection on those whose legitimacy is questioned. But as we saw, the criteria Christman recommended were insufficient to the task (as they failed to explain exemplary cases), and other more substantial elements would likely fall to an infinite regress as the above quoted passage suggests. Aside from these problems, the relative rarity with which persons tend to engage in even this localized sort of self-reflection would entail that there are very few autonomous actions performed. When I look at my own life, at least, the ratio of autonomous actions to self-reflective actions is abundantly weighted toward the former. Finally, as I’ve noted earlier, the danger of misguided paternalism can be increased by holding an ideal-self requirement on autonomy as well. On some ideal-self views (for example, that of Susan Babbitt) a person’s action may in certain fairly common cases be said, paradoxically, to be autonomous (over and above merely beneficial) only when it is guided by the wishes of someone other than herself. None of the foregoing should be taken to mean that in all situations one’s ideal self is irrelevant to autonomy. Some actions are coincident with a desire that one wants, ’9 Frankfurt (2004), p. 26. 157 but does not (yet) possess. A parent who disdains organized education, but who sees the happiness school brings to her child, might want to act as if she valued education. When she acts as if she had a positive opinion of education, she acts autonomously, for this is the manner in which she desires to act. As a practical matter these situations lead often enough to the eventual realization of one’s ideal self. This is relevant not only to the case of the parent - who in acting out of love for her child and as if she valued education, comes to value education — but also to situations in which a person intentionally acquires a wanted desire by acting as if she already has it. A person who wants to desire to watch art films would perhaps best go about gaining this desire by watching some art films, and hopefully coming to appreciate them and thus to desire to watch them.‘00 Persons who want to act on desires the objects of which we sometimes call ‘acquired tastes’ fall under this description. Examples of these sorts suggest that there is room for an ideal-self element in an account of autonomy that is neither implausible nor conducive to political exploitation. In what follows, I will outline such a notion. Korsgaard, as we saw, argues that reasons follow simply from one’s existing identity: ‘An X doesn’t Y.’ I have supported this view as accurate; I have argued, though, that it is too narrow. A person gains reasons not only from her identification with the self she is but also from the one she desires to be. Since a person is not typically entirely 1"" On the structural desire-endorsement model, the explanation of such a situation is interestingly complex. Ex hypothesi, the person has a second-order desire to want to watch art films, but does not yet have the first-order desire that is the object of the second-order desire. This might seem to entail that the second- order desire is actually a desire of the first order, since some desire of hers must be motivating her to watch the films, and it was stipulated that she does not have the requisite first-order desire. What she does possess (if she is practically rational) is a first-order instrumental desire to do whatever she determines necessary and sufficient for her to acquire the desire to watch art films. The italicized passage, of course, happens also to refer to ‘the desire to watch art films’, a desire which she does not, by stipulation, possess. Since this in an intensional context, though, there is no incoherence in claiming her to desire ‘to do whatever she determines. . . ’ and not desire ‘to watch art films’. 158 identified with each of her practical identities, but rather is such to a degree, and typically either waxing or waning in relation to the identity, she also gets reasons from her stance toward the identity-element. If she endorses, say, being an environmentalist (which no one is perfectly all the time), and so she desires to be more closely identified with ‘environmentalist’, she gets a reason not since an environmentalist simply does buy a fuel-economical car (they all don’t), but rather she gets a reason to buy a fuel-economical car in virtue of her wanting to be (more of) an environmentalist. Her becoming more closely identified, so to speak, with a certain practical identity can take a number of (concurrently realizable) forms. She might gain a relatively wider range of reasons from the identity element; the reasons that stem from this identity might tend to trump those of other of her identities; the identity might take a hi gher-order role, being the basis on which other of her practical identities are judged. The structural account of autonomy that is at the core of this understanding explicitly contains an ideal-self element, in fact. Frankfurt gives an example: Someone who loves justice, for instance, necessarily wants to be a person who serves the interests of justice. He necessarily regards serving its interests not only as contributing to the realization of a desirable social condition, but also as integral to the realization of his ideal for himself. His love defines for him, at least in part, the motives and preferences of his ideal self.101 Described in this way, acting in accord with one’s practical identities -— where these practical identities are affiliated with the things the person cares about — is to promote one’s ideal self. '0‘ Frankfurt (1999), p. 139. 159 It is consistent with the notion of the ideal self that appears in the quoted passage above that a person who loves justice not only be a person who wants to serve the interests of justice but also does serve the interests of justice. One’s ideal self need not be entirely distinct from one’s actual self; many of the desires, beliefs, values, and the like that a person wants (ideally) to identify with are ones with which she already does identify. This is consistent as well with the notion of the ideal self as it featured into views discussed above. Babbitt’s account maintains only that oppressed persons fail actually to realize the interests that they have in flourishing, and so nonoppressed persons might well realize their own best interests and as such act from their ideal selves. When Meyers asks which “desires, personal traits, values, interests and aims shouldl seek to enact”, the implication is that there is a correct answer to this question, an answer that some persons get right. "’2 Christman certainly would not deny that some persons have the ability to self-reflectively evaluate their desires, nor would Benson claim that no one succeeds in appreciating the reasons there are. Thus, the ideal self of the structural view is consistent in this aspect — that sometimes the ideal and the actual coincide — with the implicit ideal self demand of the previously discussed accounts. This is, though, still a weaker notion of the ideal self than those earlier discussed. The ideal self must be within the possible present imaginative or conative state of the person. This was not necessarily the case regarding other views. Babbitt, for example, explicitly argued that some oppressed persons who fail to have a self-conception adequate to their own flourishing lack the capacity even to imagine a world in which such a self-conception might figure into their identity. ‘02 Meyers (2000), p. 166; emphasis added. 160 The ideal self that is constituted by desires, goals, values, et al, with which a person wishes to but does not yet identify is, I have suggested and continue to maintain, more plausibly the source of autonomous action than some objectively ideal self. The ideal of this ideal self refers to the person whose actions are under scrutiny, thus maintaining the self— governance that is the core of the notion of autonomy, as is claimed by all parties to the debate. To summarize the argument of this chapter: I have argued that identity disunity undermines autonomy because the most acceptable account of autonomy is a hierarchical account. The reasons that alternative accounts are less acceptable are as follows. Susan Babbitt’s ‘human flourishing’ account of autonomy is not only too narrowly focused on oppression’s effects on the possibility of autonomy to be taken as an account of autonomy proper, but it is also even more open to political abuse as the mainstream liberal view that motivates Babbitt’s own account. Diana Meyers’ procedural view of autonomy is unacceptable insofar as the characteristics that the autonomous authentic self is said to have are characteristics that the authentic selves of many real persons simply do not have. John Christman’s requirement that an autonomous person approve of the process of her desire-acquisition is implausible since such approval is either irrelevant (in cases where a person gets a desire she actually wants, though through avenues she disapproves of) or, since it is grounded in desires the person already has, superfluous to the Frankfurtian account. Paul Benson’s critical competence condition, which requires not only that autonomous persons be self-regulating but also that they be motivated by objective reasons, implies that those who are non-autonomous due to oppressive socialization cannot be self-regulating. I61 The hierarchical account of autonomy holds that a person acts autonomously just in case she acts on a desire that she endorses, that is, a desire with regards to which she has no internal conflict. These desires just are the ones with which she identifies, and so disunity (conflict) of identity will negatively impact autonomy. And as I have argued in the previous chapter, the notion of endorsement is applicable not just to desires but also to a wide range of possible identity elements, elements which (like desires) motivate and give reasons for action. Whatever characterization we give of the identities from which we act, they are from the point of view of autonomy ideally unified. The value of autonomy and the unity of identity A few more general comments are in order at this point, not the least reason for which is to indicate the direction of the subsequent discussion. An observation not yet noted is that some amount of the resistance to the thought that a unified identity is necessary for autonomy is grounded in a certain belief about the value of autonomy. Since some persons have distinctly disunified identities (and most persons do, to a degree), and since the ability to act autonomously is of the highest value, to rest autonomy on unity entails denying the value of the lives of many persons. Maria Lugones alerts us to the multiplicitous subject’s “invisibility and worthlessness in the eyes of those who attempt to control multiplicity” by (inter alia) supporting unity requirements on autonomy. ’03 But a lack of autonomy makes a person metaphorically invisible only if boundless autonomy is a sine qua non of human life, and makes a person worthless only if ‘03 Lugones (2003), p. 130. 162 autonomy is the only, or perhaps primary, source of human value. Both these assumptions, while perhaps commonly implied, need not be accepted. No person is autonomous in every action; neither is anyone (victims of terrible psychiatric or social pathologies notwithstanding) fully bereft of autonomy; the truth of these claims should be obvious. Less obvious is the idea that autonomy is not a trait of the highest value. Autonomy can be valuable in itself (many of us often act as if it is, at least, and so it is at least valuable to many of us), though some will value it more than will others. But as I’ve continuously stressed, the fact that an action is autonomous does not entail that the action is a good one, morally or otherwise. Further tempering any thoughts of the overarching value of autonomy, the pursuit of many other valuable things — many personal relations such as romantic love and parenting, as well as the undertaking of certain sorts of long-range projects’o“ -- often requires restricting one’s (episodic) autonomy. If there is some sort of hierarchy of values, autonomy may not (always) occupy the top position. This is not to say that autonomy is not a good to be pursued. Some valuable things are reduced in value partially or completely if not attained autonomously; things that are valuable mainly in virtue of their having been acquired (or created, or pursued) by the person to whom they are valuable are of this sort. Food is valuable whether she who consumes it acquired it autonomously or not, but the Grand Prize-winning pumpkin is (most) valuable to she who grew it; there is much value in satisfying one’s own desire to run a marathon, but virtually none at all in a 26.2-mile forced march. It often matters that one’s actions are her own. '0‘ Those projects, at least, that are not embraced wholeheartedly. Training for competition in endurance events sometimes involves Ulysses tactics, for example running a route on which at the point one is likely to want to turn back, completing the course is actually no greater a distance. 163 Even to give up or minimize the self-guided nature of one’s actions — as certain sorts of Buddhists aim at, and is suggested by those ethical views that are grounded in altruism rather than personal duty — is, on these views, to be done by a person, not to her. As Odysseus’s famous choice shows, there may be good reason to give up one’s autonomy. There is less reason, though, to have it taken away. Beyond the value of one’s actions being her own, it does of course matter that "’5 This is the intuition (possibly connected with the one’s actions are morally good ones. inflated valuation of autonomy) behind much criticism of structural accounts of autonomy, as has been discussed above. While I maintain that autonomous actions can be immoral or imprudent, there is a notion closely allied to autonomy about which this claim does not hold. This is the notion of integrity. The conceptual and practical relations between autonomy and integrity take a multitude of diverse forms in the philosophical literature. Susan Babbitt, for example, seems to take integrity to be conceptually identical to autonomy.'°" On some views, integrity is at odds with the demands of morality - a commitment to morality can be and often is incompatible with acting with integrity.‘07 Sorting out some of these connections is the task of the next chapter, which takes up the discussion of integrity and its relation to autonomy, principles and commitments, morality, and the unity of identity. "’5 It doesn’t merely matter morally that one’s actions are morally good; this claim is not tautologous. It matters to many of us personally (to those persons, that is, who take morality up as a personal project), and the morally worthy life might be seen to have an additional aesthetic value, as well. ‘06 Babbitt (1996). “’7 Williams (1973), pp. 108 ff., and (1981). 164 _4_ Integrity The discussion of the present chapter will focus on the connection between integrity and the unity of identity. The notion of integrity has been the subject of a fair amount of philosophical attention since Bernard Williams’s revival of interest in the topic over three decades ago', and since then a number of strongly disputed accounts have been presented to support the claim, often implicit, that integrity just is a form of personal integration or unity maintained in the face of disunifying forces. Beyond this shared feature, there has been little in the way of conceptual convergence among these accounts. The present contribution to the philosophical discussion of integrity has four aims. First, to shift the discussion from the character trait or personal virtue of integrity to integrity as a characteristic of a specific act. My second aim is to present a view of integrity, which I will call the taxonomic view, which identifies distinct sorts of integrity and thus will help to make sense of much of the stalemate in the current literature. Third, this view of integrity addresses and attempts to accommodate an intuition that surfaced repeatedly in the last chapter’s discussion of autonomy — the intuition that the moral content of an action is relevant in determining whether that action is one’s own. The fourth and main goal here is to show that the unity of identity is a crucial element of, but not simply equivalent to, the ability to act with integrity. Certain character traits are commonly exemplified by public figures or literary characters: Othello ’s Iago is an exemplar of treachery, Mother Teresa a paradigm of ‘ Williams (1973). 165 altruism, Oscar Wilde of wit. Integrity has a number of supposed representatives: Martin Luther King, J r., Mohandas Gandhi, and Abraham Lincoln are representatives of the character trait of integrity to the extent that their names can be taken as synonymous with the term. “My father never backed down,” I might say. “Why, he was a virtual Gandhi for his whole life.” At least in a standard context, the intent of such a statement is easy to grasp: I am claiming that my father was a man of integrity. (It should not be thought that all of the work in characterizing my father is done by the phrase ‘never backed down’. I could use that phrase to describe him followed by a reference to Attila the Hun and the character trait I am attributing to him would be understood very differently.) But (of course) the reality of such commonly lauded public figures is more complex. If we point out that Gandhi tested his commitment to brahmacharya, total control of one’s own desires, by enlisting various (often young) women to lie naked beside him, the attribution of integrity might seem less apt.2 Or consider King: as the man who fought so long and so bravely for the rights of black Americans, he is clearly a person of integrity. But as a man who plagiarized portions of his PhD dissertation’, or as a womanizer, we might not know whether to award him the honorific label of ‘integrity’. One important philosophical concern regarding integrity seems to be the construction of an account of integrity that will help us reliably to make such judgments, as seems especially difficult when judging the integrity of a person who seems for some reasons to deserve the attribution but for other reasons not to deserve it. I don’t assume that integrity is the only character trait that is complicated in this way. I have chosen to investigate integrity since (among other reasons) we do tend to 2 As reported by Mehta (1993), p. 43. 3 A habit that began with the presenting as original his first sermon, which was actually one “lifted” from Rev. Harry Emerson Fosdick (Frady (2002), p. 19). 166 weight it very heavily in certain important situations — we often aim to choose our friends, our lovers, our business associates and our political leaders on the grounds of their integrity. Integrity is also often taken to be a laudable quality of one’s own self. “Whatever happens,” a person may tell herself, “at least I have my integrity.” (I myself happen to have kept a message contained in a fortune cookie, which in a fit of whimsy I affixed to the cover of my checkbook: “You value your principles higher than any money or wealth?) The currently available philosophical conceptions of integrity do not help us to perform this important task of judging integrity. This is because each of the main accounts are subject to quite simple counterexamples, cases of persons who we take not to have integrity but who are characterized by the account as possessing integrity, as I will now show. Contemporary accounts of integrity As mentioned above, Bernard Williams is often credited with sparking the current philosophical interest in integrity. Williams has argued that acting from moral concerns (he restricts his discussion to strictly utilitarian sorts of moral concerns) can be at odds with acting with integrity. This is because, as Williams claims, “each of us is specially responsible for what he does, rather than for what other people do”, an idea “closely connected to the value of integrity?" The demands of utilitarianism, though, make no distinction between what I do and what other people do, and so utilitarianism cannot make sense of the special connection I have with my own actions. " Williams (1973), p. 99. 167 One way in which Williams is understood is as giving a clean hands view of integrity; this is how Cheshire Calhoun, for one, has characterized his view.5 On a clean hands view, a person acts with integrity when she refuses to be the agent of some specific moral harm, a refusal that may itself entail some greater moral harm coming about. Williams asks us to imagine George, a biochemist in need of a job. He is offered one, but it is ajob that involves research aimed at developing chemical and biological weapons. George objects to chemical and biological weapons. Although George and his family need the money, and his taking the job will prevent some more zealous researcher from taking the job, and George’s family have no qualms about his taking the position, he turns it down. George knows it to be likely that his turning down the job will not prevent any such weapons from being created, and that he could have even slowed the manufacture of some of these weapons by accepting the job and then being a bit of a slacker, he shows integrity, on the clean-hands picture, by refusing to participate in what he takes to be evil. It is not that he prevents evil, but he keeps his hands clean of it. The attribution of integrity to George seems apt. After all, even though George could have had a good-paying job, and his family would have thought none the worse of him, he respected his commitments to himself, to his beliefs that if there are going to be chemical and biological weapons in the world, at least he himself will not be the maker of any of them It should be borne in mind that though this view of integrity is commonly attributed to Williams, he does not offer much in the way of a defense of the view. His argument, rather, is that utilitarianism carries with it a notion of negative responsibility 5 Calhoun (1995). 168 that sometimes (as in George’s case) demands that one dirty her hands to prevent great evil; such a moral requirement can (again, in certain cases) undermine the possibility of integrity. Thus, Williams’s explicit position is that the possibility of integrity depends on (as Calhoun characterizes the matter) being able to keep one’s hands clean, but he does not claim that integrity just is doing so. Calhoun points out that the clean hands view is at least incomplete, for sometimes dirtying one’s hands shows integrity. A soldier in a just war might be thought to have integrity in virtue of her dirtying her hands for a greater moral good. A person who dirties her hands by intervening in the marriage of a friend who is having an affair might similarly be judged to have integrity. Suppose she knows that her interference will offend her friend with its moralism, perhaps even losing her this friend, and further suppose she stands nothing to gain from the cuckolded husband, whom she has never thought much of to begin with. She simply thinks (however distasteful the means to thwarting it) that such a wrong ought not to be occurring 6 So, the clean-hands picture of integrity is incomplete. It accurately accounts for some, but by no means all, cases of integrity. Perhaps one complicating factor is the inclusion of the moral element. Considering the cases of both George and the friend of the unfaithful wife shows that the attribution of integrity does not follow on the relation of their action to the greatest moral 6 Depending on the back—story, these two examples can do different work than the example of George. George’s situation is one in which there is only one moral harm at issue: the production of weapons. The case of the soldier might be of this sort, if we suppose that the just war is one in which some persons will be killed, but with the goal of preventing the killing of a greater number of persons which will occur if the war is not fought. But a just war may be fought in which one moral harm — the killing of a number of persons — is perpetrated in the interest of preventing a distinct (and greater) moral harm — genocide, for example. The case of the friend has similar interpretive options. The one moral harm at issue might be that of failing to be trustworthy; two distinct harms - marital infidelity and invasion of privacy, perhaps — might both be relevant. 169 harm; George has integrity in the case where a greater harm is allowed, whereas the friend has it in the case where she refuses to allow (what she takes to be) the greater harm. What the attribution of integrity seems to depend on, rather, is what the action shows about the agent. George’s refusal to take the weapons manufacturing job shows that he is not the sort of person who makes such weapons. George is not committed to a moral ideal, at least not a primarily consequentialist one — that is, that there be fewer chemical and biological weapons in the world — since if this were the case he would have taken the job and done slovenly work, undermining the efficient production of such weapons. George is, rather, committed to a certain conception of himself, a conception as a person who does not make such weapons. Likewise, in trying to stop her friend’s infidelity, the woman shows something about herself — her conception of herself as primarily a moral agent, and only secondarily a friend to be trusted come hell or high water.7 These considerations recommend that the proper account of integrity be one on which attributions of integrity respond to the connection between a person’s actions and her self-conception. We might call this an identity view of integrity.8 On this view, a person acts with integrity when she acts from those beliefs, commitments and principles that are central to her own self-understanding. Calhoun attributes this sort of view to Williams as well, an attribution that has at least some suggestive textual support. About the demand that we might make on George to take the weapons research job so to prevent a more zealous person from doing so, Williams claims that this would be “to alienate him 7 Of course, a trustworthy friend is not a defacto outcast from moral community. But on a certain ethical view made plausible by considerations in Williams (1981) and Wolf (1982), the demands of personal relationships and the demands of morality can and do conflict. If they do, there is a choice to be made as to which will be more authoritative, that is, a choice as to how to conceive oneself. 8 Again, following Calhoun (1995). 170 in a real sense from his actions and the source of his actions in his own convictions [. . .] in the most literal sense, an attack on his integrity.”9 If to alienate a person from her own convictions is an attack on her integrity, preserving the correspondence between one’s own convictions and actions would seem to support her integrity. A commonsense sort of view of integrity — emphasizing the etymological connection with ‘integration’ and ‘integral’ —that holds that integrity just is a certain sort of wholeness is consistent with this view as well. The identity view does have a number of strengths. It accounts for the case of George and of the adulterer’s friend, as just noted. The identity view also explains the damage of oppressive social forces to persons who are prevented from acting with integrity.10 The members of oppressed social groups - for example, women — are often forced into certain patterns of actions, and thus can be prevented from acting in accordance with their own principles.ll Their ability to act with integrity is in this way impeded. (Is it any wonder why the paradigm representatives of integrity - King, Gandhi and Abraham Lincoln already mentioned, and we might add Winston Churchill and John F. Kennedy — are all men?”) On the identity view, the mechanism by which the oppressed are prevented from acting with integrity is clear. Integrity just is acting in accord with your self-conception, an ability often denied the oppressed. 9 Williams (1973), pp. 116-117. '0 As argued by, e.g. Babbitt (1996) and Lugones (2003). “ And are sometimes prevented even from coming to have their own principles at all. '2 Mother Teresa and Rosa Parks come to mind as women of integrity. Mother Teresa’s integrity, though, is in virtue of her extreme subordination of any self-directed desires, a peculiar (though still appropriate) example of acting from principle. Parks tends to be publicly misunderstood as a woman who had an isolated if bold idea (not to yield her bus seat), but few take that action to be grounded in long—standing principle and association with the NAACP (in a notice of her death (October 24, 2005), ABC News wrote of her “public conception as a quiet, domestic woman who was just too tired from a hard day’s work to get up from her seat”). 171 Alas, there are intuitive examples of integrity that the identity view fails to capture. Recall Othello’s Iago, who out of wanton jealousy caused multiple murders and a suicide. Shakespeare does not offer much as to Iago’s own self-conception, but it certainly was not a positive one; in one of his rare moments of self-reflection Iago admits “I am nothing if not critical.”13 He also importantly takes himself to be dishonest: when Othello mentions personal discord, Iago sarcastically replies with a reference to musical discord in saying, 0, you are well tun’d now! But I’ll set down the pegs that make this music, As honest as I am." Further, Iago is acting in accord with his self-conception, as he implies that he is not at all at the mercy of some force outside himself: ’Tis in ourselves that we are thus or thus. Our bodies are gardens to which our wills are gardeners; so that if we will plant nettles or sow lettuce. . .either to have it sterile with idleness or manured with industry; why, the power and corrigible authority of this lies in our wills. If the balance of our lives had not one scale of reason to poise another of sensuality, the blood and baseness of our natures would conduct us to the most preposterous conclusions... '5 And so Iago connives to effect the murders of Desdemona, Emilia and Roderick, and Othello’s suicide. Now, the morally demanded action would have been (as Iago seemingly should have realized, at least judging from his understanding of reason’s trumping of the baseness of his nature) for him to take arms against his own unjustified hatred and jealousy of Othello, to resist the powerful internal forces moving him to murderous deception. (Indeed, oftentimes the most powerful force to resist in acting with integrity is a force emanating from within oneself.) '3 Othello, Act 11, scene 1. '4 Othello, Act 11, scene 1. '5 Othello, Act 1, scene 3. 172 A far different play than Shakespeare’s Othello might have Iago resisting the “green-eyed monster” of jealousy that drives him. This Iago could have realized that jealousy was driving him; this Iago would have taken up his own counsel of Othello to beware jealousy; this Iago would have taken up noble reason, rather than base passion, as the core of the will he speaks so highly of; this Iago would take up cool (presumably moral) reason as his principle. This Iago would have acted with integrity in standing up to desires that moved him against (what we are now hypothetically supposing to be) his reasonable will. That is, this Iago would act with integrity if he would act from moral considerations. Morally speaking, Iago ought to put aside his self-conception of a person who is critical and dishonest, and refuse - by resisting his powerful feelings of jealousy — to manipulate those of whom he is jealous. The inclusion of a moral element in judgments of the character trait of integrity has intuitive appeal. If we deny the attribution of integrity to Martin Luther King, the denial likely rests on a judgment that no matter what brave and selfless things he did to motivate racial desegregation, he is not a man of integrity because of the innumerable liaisons he engaged in to the moral harm of his family, his political cause, and in many cases the women he misled. Here, our judgment depends on the thought that integrity is attributed to a person in view of their whole life, or at least a substantial portion of it, and that this life must have been a moral one (overall, or on balance, or at least not marked by egregiously immoral content). The hypothetical (and admittedly contentious) ‘Nazi of integrity’ might be interpreted in the same way. For example, it is entirely consistent with the tenets of the 173 National Socialist Movement that a member of the party largely dedicates her life to the preservation of the natural environment. But if we are less comfortable attributing integrity to her than we are to John Muir or Rachel Carson, it is likely because of the conflict between her other beliefs and actions with the attribution of integrity. The immorality of one aspect of the Nazi’s life (it might be thought) taints the totality of her life, at least as regards integrity. So on a moral View, integrity might be said to characterize a person only if she leads her life at least largely in correspondence with morally permissible principles. But recall our judgment of George. There was no hesitation in the evaluation of George’s integrity in spite of our ignorance of whether he is a member of the Nazi party, or encourages young girls to sleep next to him, or plagiarized his dissertation. That is, we were content to judge the integrity of George’s action (or, perhaps, the integrity of George qua agent of a specified action), rather than George himself. Judging the integrity of a person’s actions rather than judging the person herself can change the polarity of our judgment. Even if Martin Luther King is not a person of integrity (because, for example, of his sexual habits), some of his actions show great integrity. His refusal to leave jail after his arrest in Albany, Georgia, until negotiations between the city and black leaders had been settled was an act of integrity. It was an act done out of selfless commitment to a lofty moral principle, an act that he feared the personal consequences of (believing, understandably, that the police might kill him). Implicit in this judgment is a view of integrity on which an action is one of integrity only if it is motivated by a moral principle. 174 Considering actions rather than character can cause our judgments to alter in the other direction as well. It is the belief of many people that Abraham Lincoln was a person of integrity, though some of his most important actions — such as defending the emancipation of slaves as a political tactic aimed at the preservation of the union rather than aimed at the freeing of the slaves per se — arguably lacked integrity.“ In considering the person, we find integrity; in considering the action, we do not. On which ought judgments of integrity to focus? One response involves the observation than even persons of integrity need not to be perfect in their performing of actions of integrity. Thus, we can continue the quotidian practice of attributing integrity to persons, not to their actions. But this response is not entirely satisfactory, since there can be imagined a person who performs all acts of integrity save one, and this one so egregious that we are moved to refuse the attribution of integrity to her. The Nazi of integrity is again a possible example here. More plausible is a view on which integrity is first considered as a characteristic of actions, a characteristic that becomes attributable to a person who engages in some certain number of acts of integrity, or ratio of integrity-featuring actions to other actions, or something of the sort (though I won’t be offering any helpful formula here, since I do not expect that there is such a formula). This is a more plausible view since attributions of integrity must ground in the integrity of actions in some fashion; it is absurd to speak of some person of integrity who has never performed an act of integrity, or to attribute '6 Of course, most actions lack integrity in the sense that judgments of integrity are simply not relevant - most quotidian acts are of this sort. But an action can also lack integrity in the sense that judgments of integrity do apply, and the action is found lacking. This is the sense in which one might take Lincoln to have lacked integrity in using slaves as mere means, means to the preservation of the Union. 175 integrity to a person and claim their actions are not at all relevant to the judgment.’7 An attribution of the character trait of integrity presupposes a decision as to which of the person’s actions motivate the attribution. This is why a dispute over whether, e.g., Martin Luther King was a person of integrity will (I suspect) devolve into a discussion of which of his actions were central to his character, or most relevant in some other way to the attribution. Once that is decided, the judgment of integrity is a straightforward matter. These relevant actions must be actions with the quality of integrity, either in themselves (and thus they lend the quality to the person who performs them) or in the sense that they are actions such that to engage in them either makes the agent, or shows her to be, a person of integrity.18 This conclusion — that integrity is most basically a characteristic of acts rather than of persons — is certainly contrary to traditional views. Philosophers have tended to take integrity to be a trait of character, or a disposition, or a characteristic of a whole human life. But to characterize integrity as essentially a characteristic of persons is mistaken. As I’ve argued above, each of such views fails to reflect our judgments of integrity in certain cases. As it seems from the foregoing discussion, taking integrity to be a characteristic of persons leaves the question of whether a certain person is a person of integrity open. Consider whether George is a person of integrity. Williams claims he is, ‘7 The former might not quite be absurd; I suppose that a dispositional account of integrity might be defended on which certain persons (the oppressed, perhaps, or, for quite different reasons, persons in persistent vegetative states) who are disposed to act with integrity but are effectively prevented from doing so still warrant the attribution of integrity. It is not clear how well such an account would hold up, but it seems at least coherent. But at any rate (and this is my point), we would first need an account of what makes the acts to which the person is disposed acts of integrity. '8 That is, actions can be either the perceptual apparatus through which we see that a person has the character trait of integrity (‘1 see from her actions that she has integrity’), or the actions can be the constituent parts of that trait (‘Doing that will give her integrity’). 176 since George refused to accept the weapons-research job. But just as one swallow does not a summer make, one act of integrity does not (I assume) a person of integrity make. Certainly other of George’s acts suggest (If George is at all like you and me) that he is not a person of integrity (after all, he’s forcing his wife financially to support their family because of his ultimately ineffective pacifist hang-up). Even if integrity is acting in accord with one’s personal commitments in refusing to be an agent of harm, or being disposed to do so in relevant circumstances, or habitually doing so for the right reason at the right time, reasonable disagreement will arise regarding many cases of supposed integrity. There is a further reason to take integrity to be primarily a characteristic of acts. In judging whether an act is one of integrity, we are of course judging the act of a person (so there is no fear that attributing integrity to acts involves conceiving of agentless acts). But in judging the integrity of an act we do not need to appeal to whether the agent is a person of integrity. For example, in evaluating the integrity of Martin Luther King’s unfaithful sexual behavior, the fact (if it is one) that King was a man of integrity has no bearing. Thus the judgment of an act ’s integrity can be made independent of knowledge of the agent’s (supposed character trait of) integrity. Not so regarding judgments of the character trait. For example, in judging whether King was a person of integrity, there will be ineliminable reference required to his acts not simply qua acts, but qua acts of integrity. In order, that is, to judge whether King was a person of integrity, the question of whether (and which of) his acts had the quality of integrity has to have already been addressed. 177 In short, the primary philosophical motivation for here investigating act-integrity rather than character—integrity is epistemic. Investigating the character trait of integrity has so far yielded only a handful of inconclusive and conflicting accounts, as outlined above. Further, as I have just argued, even though it makes perfect sense to attribute integrity to persons, this attribution is made in the light of certain actions, actions which are actions of integrity, and for which we need an account. I do not suppose that there is any deeper relevance of acts to the nature of integrity. Whatever the precise connection between acts of integrity and persons of integrity, then, we can say two things: a person of integrity must perform at least some acts of integrity at least sometimes; and following from this, if we search for a account of persons of integrity, we need first an account of acts of integrity. Even though we may have made headway by reducing the problem of integrity to that of acts of integrity, it is no more clear what the desired account might look like. The views described above, the clean hands view, the identity view, and a moral view each have problems corresponding to the range of our everyday judgments. Most notably, seemingly contrary judgments seem equally plausible. George’s refusal to take the weapons research job is an act of integrity, but if George were instead to take the moral high ground — which is, I take it, to reduce the production of weapons whatever the personal cost — and take the job in spite of his distaste, this would be plausibly interpreted as an act of integrity. Lincoln’s dedication to the preservation of the Union was a central element of his self-identity, and so pursuing that goal to the point of civil war was an act of integrity on an identity view, but I take it that it would have showed integrity had 178 Lincoln allowed the Confederacy to secede rather than feigning concern for the slaves in pursuing ulterior political motives.19 The solution I will suggest to remedy these odd conclusions may itself sound odd. The suggestion is that our judgments are correct: George shows integrity in refusing the job, and he shows integrity in taking the job. Lincoln showed integrity in pursuing the cohesion of the Union, and he would have showed integrity by refusing to pursue that goal in light of his having to dissemble to do so. What alleviates the oddness of this suggestion is the provision of a taxonomy of integrity, as follows. What George shows in refusing the weapons research job is personal integrity. This, recall, was the crux of Williams’s point in this example — that personal integrity is often in direct conflict with utilitarian sorts of moral demands (such as, in this case, the utilitarian demand to minimize harm). What has gone unexamined in the philosophical discussions of integrity is the distinction between integrity of this sort and moral integrity. Moral integrity and personal integrity are distinct potential evaluations of an action. As the case of George shows, an action that shows personal integrity need not be an action of moral integrity.20 ‘9 This judgment depends in part on the facts that slavery in the American South (at that time, the Confederate States of America) would have ended of its own internal decay in a relatively short time, and that Lincoln privately professed to have absolutely no interest in whether slaves were held or not “My paramount object in this struggle is to save the Union, and is not either to save or to destroy slavery. If I could save the Union without freeing any slave I would do it, and if I could save it by freeing all the slaves I would do it; and if I could save it by freeing some and leaving others alone I would also do that. What I do about slavery, and the colored race, I do because I believe it helps to save the Union; and what I forbear, I forbear because I do not believe it would help to save the Union.” (Lincoln, letter to Horace Greely, August 22, 1862.) 2" George’s situation needs to be explained a bit differently for an attribution of integrity upon his accepting the job to be appropriate. Suppose that George is very opposed to weapons research and the thought of taking such ajob turns his stomach — he does not think he could respect himself if he were to take the job. George might even wow that his family will come to think less of him were he to take any part in such an industry. But he realizes that he can perhaps save just one life, or perhaps even many lives, by taking the job and being less efficient at it than some other more zealous researcher; he overcomes his distaste out of 179 There are other sorts of integrity that, while virtually unexamined by philosophers, are straightforwardly uncovered. Consider whether Abraham showed integrity in his intention to sacrifice Isaac.2| To answer affirmatively, to agree that Abraham’s is indeed a “story of integrity”22 is to appeal to religious integrity. Consider Stanley Mil gram’s (in)famous experiments on obedience to authority; if Mil gram showed integrity in engaging in this research, it is intellectual integrity. William Styron’s character Sophie exhibited interpersonal integrity in choosing to die with Nathan rather than live with Stingo.23 We might call a view that recognizes these distinct types of integrity (types that are severally but not yet jointly described) and the relation between them ‘the taxonomic view of integrity’. This is the view I am defending here, and is a view that takes up many elements of established accounts, for example the observation that personal integrity (as acting from one’s principles or commitments) and moral integrity (as doing what morality demands whatever the personal cost) can and often do conflict. What sets the taxonomic view apart from others is the observation that personal integrity and moral integrity (and many other sorts) are all parts of a useful account of integrity. To claim that, say, only personal integrity is integrity (as Williams has strongly implied) is incorrect on the taxonomic view. The suggested labels of these sorts of integrity that feature into the taxonomic view may not be familiar. For example, though we do sometimes speak of intellectual integrity, ‘interpersonal integrity’ is (to me, at least) an unfamiliar term. Nonetheless, the the realization that he has a moral obligation to minimize harm in the world (or to respect the ends of others, or to act bravely), and to conquer his own irrational and ultimately self-centered emotions. 2‘ Genesis 22. ’2 Mooney (1986), p. 23. 23 Styron (1979). 180 judgments that they track should be recognizable. We do evaluate these sorts of acts as acts of integrity. But we also get confused, as I’ve argued, when we fail to distinguish the distinct types of integrity. A further feature of the taxonomic view (which I’ll use an extended example to illustrate below) is that it takes all sorts of integrity except moral integrity to be qualified sorts of integrity. Moral integrity is integrity unqualified. In claiming, for example, that Stanley Mil gram acted with intellectual integrity we limit our claim. To claim, simply, ‘Mil gram acted with integrity’ would invite explanation (and puzzled looks). This is because he did not act with moral integrity, but rather with a subtype of integrity, as I will explain.24 Consider the following “general principle” described in the American Psychological Association’s Code of Ethics: Principle C: Integrity Psychologists seek to promote accuracy, honesty, and truthfulness in the science, teaching, and practice of psychology. In these activities psychologists do not steal, cheat, or engage in fraud, subterfuge, or intentional misrepresentation of fact. Psychologists strive to keep their promises and to avoid unwise or unclear commitments. In situations in which deception may be ethically justifiable to maximize benefits and minimize harm, psychologists have a serious obligation to consider the need for, the possible consequences of, and their responsibility to correct 7" For those readers unfamiliar with Mil gram’s series of experiments: Mil gram enlisted subjects on the pretence of testing the effects of punishment on learning. The actual aim was to determine whether subjects would cause (what they thought to be) substantial harm, by electric shock, to other persons when this harm was demanded by a person in authority. Many test subjects (that is, those who were administering the shocks) experienced extreme emotional distress during the experiment. In the first run of the experiment, 26 out of 40 subjects completed the experiment - that is, they continued to administer shocks gradually increasing in intensity to the maximum 450 volts in spite of the extreme (though feigned) pain to the recipient. The famous ‘Mil gram’s 37’ comes from a later iteration of the experiment, in which the subject did not directly administer the supposed shocks, but directed a peer to do so; 37 out of 40 subjects in this situation completed the experiment. (This synopsis and other details I mention below are drawn from Milgram 1963, 1964 and 1977 and Baumrind 1964.) 181 any resulting mistrust or other harmful effects that arise from the use of such techniques.25 Mil gram seems to have failed to maintain this principle on nearly all counts. He deceived his test subjects, by misrepresenting both the object of the study (as punishment rather than obedience ), the role of the participants (who thought themselves helpers rather than test subjects), and the effects of their actions (subjects thought themselves to be administering real electrical shocks). It is not clear that he minimized harm to the subjects, some of whom were “reduced to a twitching, stuttering wreck [. . .] rapidly ””26 approaching a point of nervous collapse , and though three subjects experienced “full- blown, uncontrollable seizures”27 “ only one instance of the experiment was terminated because of this. Mil gram was accused of neglecting to correct for harm to subjects, exhibiting a “posture of indifference” toward the emotional state of his subjects.28 The APA integrity principle is clearly a morally characterized one, speaking as it does of responsibility and obligation to honesty, fairness, and minimization of harm. Mil gram thus, in violating on many points the commonsense understanding of integrity that it codifies, acted without moral integrity. But consider some of his responses to such criticisms of his actions. Though Mil gram did reply to a number of the moral concerns, much of his defense appealed to the intellectual and scientific value of the experiment. “['T]he problem of destructive obedience,” he writes, “ ...because it is the most perplexing, merits intensive study.”29 Nor did he take this stance to be his alone, for he claims that “many [of the subjects] felt gratified to have taken part in scientific research 25 American Psychological Association (2002), p. 3. 2" Mil gram (1963), p. 377, attributed to an unnamed observer. 27 Milgram (1963), p. 375. 2" Baumrind (1964), p. 422. 29 Milgram (1964), p. 848; italics added. 182 they considered to be of significance”30 , and a subsequent survey of the test subjects revealed that 4 out of 5 of them “felt that more experiments of this sort should be carried out”.31 Even a very disapproving editorial writer for the St. Louis Post-Dispatch noted that “the rationale offered as justification is that it was in the interests of science.”32 Indeed, the polemical, somewhat despairing tone of even Milgram’s articles published in psychology journals indicates that he took the knowledge gained through the experiments to be of utmost importance. The entire first page of his original article describing the experiment (in the Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology) speaks of the horrors of obedience to the Third Reich. (Mil gram’s experiments took place shortly after, and were almost certainly given impetus by, the trial of Adolf Eichmann; surely the cotemporaneous escalation of the (so-called) Vietnam Conflict played a similar role.) The intellectual question to which Mil gram desperately wanted an answer was this: “if X tells Y to hurt Z, under what conditions will Y carry out the command of X, and under what conditions will he refuse?”’3 This extended discussion of Stanley Mil gram is intended to support the claim, and the underlying theoretic account, that a person might act without moral integrity but with e.g. intellectual integrity.’4 Note that while different types of integrity are distinguishable, many will not be categorically distinct. Recalling William Clifford’s argument that belief has a central ethical element suggests that Mil gram’s pursuit of knowledge was inextricably moral; similarly, Abraham certainly took ethics and religion 3" Milgram (1964), p. 850. 3' Milgram (1964), p. 849. 32 St Louis Post-Dispatch, editorial, November 2, 1963. ’3 Milgram (1964), p. 848. 3" There might, I suppose, be thought to be distinct categories of moral integrity (Kantian and Utilitarian, say) which could conflict. 183 to be complementary if not identical. Nonetheless, distinctions can be made — Mil gram took his inquiry to be fundamentally an intellectual one, into a “most perplexing” question, and if we don’t take there to be a distinction between moral and religious demands, then it is unclear why Abraham’s willingness to sacrifice Isaac is so noteworthy.35 Mil gram was a scientist, not an insurrectionist (especially if these are success-terms; Mil gram largely succeeded in answering the psychosocial question, but we can say without unreasonable cynicism that the answer has had no noticeable practical effect on human behavior). Returning now to the heart of the taxonomic view, it has been implied by Bernard Williams that personal integrity, not moral integrity, is integrity proper. Utilitarianism’s problem with understanding integrity, he claims, is grounded in a failure to “coherently describe the relations between a man’s projects and his actions?” Harry Frankfurt suggests this sort of ranking as well. He imagines someone who “has no personal boundaries whose inviolability he might set himself to protect,” and so “there is no such thing for [him] as genuine integrity.”37 But if personal integrity is true, unqualified integrity, then attributing integrity to Mil gram’s actions wouldn’t raise eyebrows and call for an explanation (which it does). There are certainly cases that might seem to suggest that personal integrity is integrity proper. Ridley Scott’s film Thelma and Louise tells the story of two women 35 Perhaps there are other interpretations of the situation — supposing both that religion and morality are one and the same and that Abraham did (or at least should have) willed Isaac’s sacrifice only in the face of a great inner struggle suggests that Abraham acted out of moral integrity rather than the conflicting interpersonal integrity. 1 do not expect that the provision of a taxonomy of integrity will make attributions of integrity a matter of applying an algorithm; there are a number of ways to interpret a situation, but the point is that the taxonomic account is relevant to all of them. 3" Williams (1973), p. 100. 37 Frankfurt (1999), p. 115. It is worth noting that Frankfurt does not offer quite an account of integrity; but makes suggestive remarks that, like those of Williams, are aimed only at describing certain conditions under which acting with integrity is impossible. 184 who act immorally but at the same time act with integrity. To take a specific scene as an example, Louise prevents Thelma’s rapist from continuing the act, but even after the immediate threat is past, Louise (motivated by her own remembered rape), shoots the man to death. This could be taken as an act of integrity; clearly Louise acts for reasons that form, for her, a principle — a set of beliefs, self-conceptions and motives that are central to who she is. Now, the attribution of integrity to Louise’s act is disputable in a way that, say, Martin Luther King’s refusal to leave the Albany jail is not. That is, one might argue that no act of murder could be also an act of integrity; holding a ‘clean-hands’ view of integrity such as the one Calhoun attributes to Williams would clearly entail such a stance (Louise importantly dirtied her hands). But if there is something to the thought that Louise did show integrity in committing an illegal, arguably immoral, and ultimately self- destructive act, the taxonomic view makes sense of that thought — Louise showed personal, though not moral, integrity. And it is because Louise’s act is debatable in a way King’s act (of moral integrity), is not — that is, because a demand for qualification of the attribution of integrity to Louise’s act is perfectly understandable — that I claim moral integrity to be integrity unqualified. Personal integrity is, further, a precondition of moral integrity — an act of moral integrity is the act of someone whose personal principles are moral ones.38 This is why, for example, Huckleberry Finn’s self-perceived wanton act of helping the slave Jim was a morally positive act, but did not involve integrity on Huck’s part; it was morally good 3” McFall (1987), p. 16. A point not made by McFall, but worth noting here regards cases in which a person acts with moral integrity but out of character. Here, the degree to which we attribute integrity to such an act is the degree to which the person is, through the act itself, taking the moral principle as her own. 185 that Huck sheltered Jim, but whatever moral principle is relevant here, it wasn’t Huck’s moral principle.39 Personal integrity is thus distinct in its relation to moral integrity, since neither intellectual, nor religious, nor the other subtypes of integrity are preconditions of moral integrity.’0 There are further elements of integrity that are not unique to the taxonomic account. For one, as has been implied throughout the foregoing discussion, acts of integrity are resistant — to general social forces, to features of specific situations, or to powerful contrary inclinations. A person can show integrity by resisting the norms of male privilege, resisting her father’s specific demands for male privilege, or (for a man) resisting one’s own desire to’exploit the powers of male privilege. So, for example, a man might show integrity by turning down an offer for a desired job, an offer made to him at the expense of a more deserving woman who was passed over for the offer. Absent the forces he resisted (which in this case are two: male privilege, and his own desire for the job), integrity would not be an issue here. This element of integrity is implicit in many views. In Williams’s original discussion, for example, acts of integrity are importantly resistant to (utilitarian) moral demands. Similarly for Frankfurt, integrity is posed against demands to violate the limits of a person’s own volitions, “limits that might serve at once to anchor his judgment and to specify the requirements of his integrity?"I Lynn McFall, elements of whose view will be discussed below, maintains that “integrity requires “sticking to one’s principles”, ’9 Denying integrity to Huckleberry Finn does not preclude the possibility of other honorific evaluations pertaining to him and his conduct; he may, for example, be virtuous (Arpaly, 2002). 4" Interestingly distinct is academic integrity, which seems just to be a certain sort of moral integrity, characterized by the practical context in which it is displayed. Thus it cannot be said of a person that she showed academic but not moral integrity. 4' Frankfurt (1988), p. 179. 186 moral or otherwise, in the face of temptation”."2 There seems no reason to doubt the correspondence of this shared element of philosophical views to our everyday attributions of integrity. Certainly acts of integrity come neither effortlessly nor without some degree of risk."3 A resistance feature has been taken to be the very defining feature of integrity in Cheshire Calhoun’s account of integrity as ‘standing for something’."4 “Integrity,” she argues, “calls us simultaneously to stand behind our convictions and to take seriously others’ doubts about them.”45 The person of integrity adopts “the co—deliberative perspective?“ taking her own deliberative conclusions to be important, both to herself and to others, while also respecting the claims and criticisms of others. Failure to stand behind one’s judgments in front of others explains judgments of failures of integrity — one can lack integrity through making a considered judgment but then abandoning it cognitively or practically; neither (according to Calhoun) are fanatics, those who push forward in denial of the advice and criticism of others, as such candidates for integrity. Standing for something in the sense Calhoun defends, though, is neither integrity proper nor integrity qualified, but rather is one aspect of integrity considered generally. Standing for something is neither sufficient nor even necessary for integrity, and cannot stand on its own as an account of integrity. At the very least, it suffers from the same shortcomings as do other contemporary accounts: it is susceptible to straightforward counterexamples. Many of these illustrate that respecting the claims of others is not ‘2 McFall (1987), p. 7. ‘3 How much resistance has to be overcome in order for an act to be one of integrity is not a static matter, of course; for Iago to act honestly toward a person of whom he is jealous is a contender for the title of act of integrity, though for me it would likely not be, since I don’t have Iago’s powerful inclinations to subdue in myself. 4“ Calhoun (1995). ‘5 Calhoun (1995), p. 260. ‘6 Calhoun (1995), p. 258. 187 necessary for integrity. Socrates, in submitting to execution, refused to accept the considered judgments of those other members of his deliberative community. To be sure, he did engage his peers in (characteristically one-sided) discussion on the matter, but there seems to be no reason to doubt that he would remain unconvinced by their arguments and entreaties. Martin Luther, at the Diet of Worms, certainly acted with integrity in refusing to recant (“Here I stand; I can do no other”), though he made it clear that there was nothing anyone but God could say to change his mind (“my conscience is captive to the word of God”) — a clear instance of a person’s placing himself outside of the deliberative community. Fanatics can thus sometimes exhibit integrity in the very acts that suggest their fanaticism, and examples can be provided at length: Socrates and Luther just mentioned, as well as both Albert Einstein’s and, earlier and more powerfully, Galileo Galilei’s, intellectual integrity/fanaticism in supporting an (at the time) absurd view of the physical world; at least one prominent writer has argued that Mother Teresa is a fanatic at least in part in light of acts the taxonomic account would call religious integrity."7 Thus it is not at all clear that Cal houn’s denial of integrity to so-called fanatics is tenable. It is not even clear that there needs to be a deliberative community, in the sense of a group of relative equals who listen to, consider and respect the reasoned opinions of each other. Imagine (as some people do) a black woman named Rosa Parks who had a bold, singular and completely novel idea, perhaps born of frustration with the very lack of a deliberative community, to refuse to give up her seat on the bus. This Rosa Parks (like ‘7 Hitchens (2003). 188 the actual Rosa Parks) acts with integrity, though Calhoun’s account cannot explain this fact. Other situations suggest that there may be tension within Calhoun’s view itself, between the central characteristic of integrity (standing for one’s deliberative conclusions) and the requirement that a person must stand for something only as a member of a deliberative community. When, imagine, standing for one’s deliberative conclusion that nonwhite persons have and deserve exactly the same moral considerations as do white persons against members of the National Socialist Movement, it is odd to think that respecting the deliberative capacity of the Neo-Nazis, taking seriously their doubts about the basic rights of non-Christians, homosexuals, and blacks, could possibly contribute to one’s integrity. In the well-worn example of the Nazis at the door of the house in which the Jews are being sheltered, certainly the provider of shelter acts with integrity. It is quite implausible to think that having a reasonable conversation (actual or even hypothetical) with the Nazis, carefully considering their reasons for their project of extermination and their underlying racial hatred, would make the attribution of integrity any more strong or appropriate.“ In such a case, refusing to give any uptake whatsoever to arguments supporting racially-grounded political violence might be just what integrity demands.49 Calhoun’s view also fails to account for cases where a person such as George can stand for either of two things: his personal commitments or a moral principle; the distinction in George’s options is invisible to Calhoun’s account. This observation is ‘8 It may, of course, be prudent to feign such interest in the Nazi’s opinions. ‘9 It is likely that this intuition rests (with a bit of circularity, admittedly) on the assumption that moral demands ground true integrity, and further that the relevant moral consideration here is respecting the personhood and moral self-esteem of nonwhite people by excluding Neo-Nazis from discourse entirely. 189 especially relevant here since distinctions between the sorts of integrity outlined in the taxonomic view hinge on distinctions in the source of resistance: acts of personal integrity are grounded in one’s personal principles; religious integrity stems from religious commitments; acts of interpersonal integrity find their strength in personal relationships; and so on. A final point to note about the resistance requirement is that it is the most apparent characteristic that distinguishes moral integrity from the closely related notion of moral rigorism (the trait of always actively doing what one thinks is morally best), since one can be a moral rigorist even if she never experiences any resistance to her views or actions.50 Lynne McFall has offered a view of integrity that shares some characteristics with the taxonomic view, but I disagree with some of the details of her account, as well as with her ultimate conclusion. For McFaIl, integrity is ultimately a matter of acting from one’s identity-conferring commitments, “a set of principles or commitments that makes us who we are.”5| Defeasible commitments, on the other hand, do not ground integrity - being defeasible, one can leave them behind with no remorse or loss to one’s sense of self-value — but neither do just any identity-conferring commitments. The grounds of personal integrity must be important. The grounds of moral integrity must, unsurprisingly, be moral. That the grounds of integrity must be important (in some sense than more than merely subjectively important) should be apparent; trivial contexts are not the places we look for integrity (this is another feature of integrity that is shared at least implicitly by all 5" Another distinguishing feature is the diachronic nature of rigorism; a specific act can be one of integrity, but no one act is an act of moral rigorism. 5' McFall (1987), p. 13. 190 contemporary philosophical views). But that acts of integrity must be moral is only clear, I am arguing, on the taxonomic view, and McFall’s argument for the moral grounds of integrity is unconvincing. Her defense involves a distinction between personal morality and social morality. Personal morality is “that set of moral principles and commitments that I adhere to that I do not expect everyone to adhere to and that need not be characterized by impartiality.”52 Social morality is, conversely, both universal and impartial. This distinction is necessary to sidestep the Williamsian observation that integrity can be and often is at odds with (impartial) morality; McFall’s move, then, is to conceive of the partial commitments that are opposed to what Williams considers moral demands as themselves moral — personally moral. McFall maintains that personal integrity is a precondition of moral integrity insofar as for a person to act with moral integrity, the moral principles that ground her action must be her own; about this there should be no dispute. McFall’s ultimate point is that “moral integrity is as much a threat to social morality as [is] personal integrity.”53 By this she means that personal moral integrity (the sort of integrity grounded in non- universal and non-impartial principles) is a threat to morality of the universal and impartial sort just as much as (per Williams) integrity qua acting from one’s own possibly amoral principles is such a threat. There are two problems with McFall’s conclusion. One is that the distinction on which it depends, that between personal and social morality, isn’t anywhere near a compete categorization. There are moral stances one can take that are universal and partial (‘honor thy father and mother’; ‘everyone ought to look out for number one’); 52 McFall (1987), p. 17. 5* McFall (1987), p. 20. 191 there are moral stances that are non-universal and impartial (‘my parents raised me to consider everyone’s interests equally, but you might justifiably disagree’), and her view gives no account of cases in which these figure. Second, it is not clear that in the end her distance from Williams’s view is anything but nominal. Calling certain non—universal and non-impartial stances ‘moral’ may be legitimate and even illuminating in a number of ways, but does not undermine Williams’s point that if universal and impartial considerations are the filter through which other values must pass, there is a real loss to leading the sort of lives in which partial and subjective commitments feature as prominently as they often do. To summarize a bit, the taxonomic view of integrity has a number of strengths. Most importantly, it explains a wide range of our judgments, a feature I’ve appealed to in defending the plausibility of the view. It also accounts for cases in which a person can show integrity through performing either of two conflicting options — George’s taking the job on moral grounds, or refusing it on personal principle — so long as the action performed is grounded in principle against resistance. Noting another substantial strength of the View of integrity proper as moral integrity returns us to an issue left unresolved in the previous chapter’s discussion of autonomy. Recall that a number of accounts of autonomy emphasized the relevance of the moral characteristics of action in evaluations of actors; though I attempted to show this implausible, the thought that an autonomous action must be in some sense a moral action might well have an intuitive attraction. The view of integrity on offer here can be seen as at least a partial vindication and explanation of that intuition. 192 Recall that on the taxonomy into which moral integrity fits, personal integrity — the acting on one’s own principles in the face of pressure to do otherwise — is a necessary but not sufficient condition for integrity proper. This condition along with the condition that these principles are moral ones are conjointly sufficient for integrity. That is, true integrity is possible only for the person whose practically effective principles are moral ones. The structure of this account resembles, then, the structure of content-specific accounts of autonomy but, as I’ve argued, offers a more plausible locus of morality in the life of the agent. Integrity and unity It may yet be unclear how the moral view of integrity supports the ideal of unity thesis. That integrity rests essentially on an action’s being grounded in a moral principle (rather than in endorsement, say) implies that even a radically disunified person could act with integrity, so long as the right principle is in play. Consider just what we might mean when talking of principles. We speak sometimes of basic principles, the core concepts of some area of investigation or practice. As examples, consider that Freud held the basic principles governing human behavior to be eros and thanatos (the life and death instincts, respectively); the four principles of visual art are proportion, scale, balance, and unity within variety; equality is a basic democratic principle. The focus here is on the overarching nature of the specific principle — so, for example, equality is to ground or at least feature into all (or most of, or the most important of) the specifics of democratic practice. ‘Principle’ in the moral context can refer to an unwaveringly held rule: ‘Honesty is her highest principle.’ In this sense, the degree of strength, importance, or scope seems 193 to be emphasized by calling something a principle rather than simply a rule or guideline; the occasional mendacity of someone for whom honesty is (merely) a guideline should not be surprising. ‘Moral principle’ is distinct not only from ‘guideline’ but also from ‘moral belief’, in at least the following way. A thief might hold the moral belief that it is wrong to steal (i.e. that stealing is a wrong-making consideration); she asserts the belief to her confidants, holds an epistemic pro-attitude toward the belief, can explain what makes stealing wrong, and so on — but she nonetheless has to steal to feed herself and her family. We wouldn’t say, though, that she has a moral principle regarding the wrongness of theft.54 Indeed, it is one of the harms of certain sets of social conditions that some persons are prevented from possessing such principles, though they might possess such a belief. To attribute a moral principle to someone is thus often to suggest a stronger and more reliable connection with action than is suggested by an attribution of moral belief.55 To call someone, more broadly, a principled person implies something further about the content of her principles, for while ‘profit regardless of the human cost’ might be someone’s highest principle, we wouldn’t call this person ‘principled.’ A principled person tends to be so considered if she is one for whom the positively evaluated principles of honesty, respect, charity, and so on are overarching concerns, and so guide her actions. 5" It may be (I think it is) that the wrong-makingness of theft is the case, and that this is necessarily, conceptually true; if there is nothing wrong with my appropriating that object that you are in possession of, then it has to be the case that the object wasn’t in fact your property (since if it was, there is at least the slight wrong of violating your right to property). If I am correct about the nature of theft, then the example above is more broad: everyone (on pain of conceptual incoherence) believes that theft is wrong, though fewer hold this as a principle. 55 It should be clear that this analysis of ‘principle’ and ‘belief’ and so on is an analysis of quotidian usage of and distinctions between the terms. The powerful philosophical arguments regarding the motivational power of practical beliefs are, given this context, not to the point here. 194 Not all philosophical theories, though, hold morality and principles to be associated in this way. Moral particularism is one such theory, and an explanation of just what particularism takes a principle to be will help us to understand how principles figure into the lives of persons who act with integrity.56 The philosophical debate between moral particularists and moral generalists employs the notion of a principle quite heavily.57 ‘Moral principle’ - which, by the way, is something that generalists claim we need in order to engage in moral practice, and particularists deny that we so need — has been understood in two distinct ways that feature into the particularist debate. One understanding carries the sense of an absolute guideline, as in Kant’s argument in favor of the principle of honesty. Jonathan Dancy calls this conception, which he takes to be “largely discredited”’8, the subsumptive option. A principle in this sense is a rule that admits of no exceptions or mitigating conditions, and is decisive when it applies. For instance, to take honesty to be a moral principle in this sense is to hold that when the situation is such that one can be honest or dishonest, one must be honest, full stop. This conception agrees fairly well with some common usage; someone who claims to subscribe to the principle of benevolence but then neglects to help an injured person might expected to explain her action in a certain way: why the action wouldn’t have been one of benevolence. Some claim that this absolutist conception, the subsumptive option, doesn’t exhaustively characterize the ways in which principles can be understood, and argue that 5" Another moral view that relies heavily on the notion of a principle, as we saw earlier in the discussion of Bernard Williams’s concerns about integrity, is Utilitarianism. The main reason I choose to illustrate the matter by appeal to Particularism is that I take the Particularist position to pose a problem for my account of integrity, which I take up in the following section. 57 I mention this debate not only as a means to introduce some useful conceptualizations, but also since, as I will point out, there is a conflict between the notion of integrity I support and the desirability of leading a distinctly particularist sort of life. 5" Dancy (2004), p. 3. 195 there are (many) defeasible moral principles. Benevolence, taken as a defeasible rather than absolute principle, might be understandably foregone when the cost is too high. The existence of conflict between the reasons given by various principles also recommends understanding them as defeasible. Honesty might (more plausibly) be such a defeasible principle, and charitableness another; these two principles each give reasons for acting in a certain manner, reasons which may in some easily imaginable cases conflict. A moral principle, on this reading, points to non-trumping considerations for action, and at best plays into an all-things-considered judgment of what one ought to do. It is important to keep in mind that these last two conceptions of principles are more metaphysical than practical conceptions, as they are concerned with “theories about reasons rather than with life”;59 they are certainly more metaphysical than moral- psychological. But there are illuminating and relevant points of contact between moral principles (of the sort ‘lying is wrong’) and what is at issue in the notion of integrity that is supported here: that is, moral principles taken up as personal principles — as in a person who takes up as her own principle ‘lying is wrong’. Even Jonathan Dancy, who denies that moral practice best be grounded in principles, admits that as a matter of fact “people order their lives (and the lives of others) according to their principles”."0 What is it for a person to order her life according to her principles? The answer to this question uncovers the connection between integrity and the ideal of the unity of identity. We might understand a person’s principles by analogy to principles themselves. For example, much as equality is a democratic principle insofar as it is supposed to 59 Dancy (2004), p. 2. 6° Dancy (2004), p. 2. 196 ground or at least feature into all the specifics of democratic practice, a person’s principles ground or at least figure into the specifics of her life. Someone whose principle is honesty is largely honest; in the life of a person among whose principles is fairness, her actions will be marked by fairness, whatever their content."1 Whether a specific one of a person’s principles is absolute or defeasible depends on the possibility of acting on the principle, conceptual features of the principle itself, and a person’s relationship to the principle, facets which I will discuss briefly in turn. First. many of us take honesty not to be a good choice for an absolute principle — there are simply too many situations in which variously, the amount of harm to be avoided by lying is too great to recommend honesty, other moral demands preclude honesty, or personal (or some other sort) of integrity demands dissemblance. Such a principle, because of real-world practical demands, is best not taken to be an absolute principle. Second, the degree of defeasibility of such principles might also be determined primarily with reference to the principles themselves — the concepts rather than the practice. It might plausibly be argued, say, that the principle of freedom of speech ought to be subordinate to the principle of harm. Such an argument might appeal primarily (or initially) to just what counts as ‘speech’ and what counts as ‘harm’ — that is, we will determine just what the principles themselves are.” But most importantly to the present discussion, when considering principles as characteristics of persons — ‘benevolence is her principle’ — the matter is different. For 6’ I am not claiming that every person who holds onto some so-called principle, e.g. the principle of freedom of speech, holds it as her principle; freedom of speech figures into specific human lives in different ways than it figures into the behavior of the state. That is, a person can subscribe to something that in some other context takes the form of a principle without it taking the same role in her own behavior. 62 This is not to deny that adjudicating between the relative values of principles does not sometimes or even best involve consideration of the practical effects of holding up one or the other of these principles as more important. 197 while a person may well consider her principle of honesty to override her principle of kindness, this ranking need not be so in virtue of some objective facts about the value of honesty and the value of kindness (perhaps she doesn’t know these facts). This ranking can be grounded in the relative degrees to which she identifies with these principles. Recall the various modes of identification that were discussed and defended above. Identification can be described in narrative terms — as the construction and attribution of stories on the basis of which we can comprehend our own and others’ actions. Identification might be thought of as a self-description on the basis of which a person values herself. Identities are in part structures of desires, or are composed of group affiliations. At the root of these conceptions, I argued, is the notion of endorsement — the positive evaluation or acceptance that is marked by a lack of internal conflict regarding the identity element. It is not true, of course, that a person with principles cannot experience conflict regarding them. Sometimes quite the opposite is the case. The example of the conflict between honesty and benevolence is a famous one, of course.63 A person whose principle is healthy living might experience an overwhelming urge to eat an entire plate of cookies, or to smoke a cigarette. The unification that characterizes the identity of a person who has principles is, in fact, often enough initiated by internal conflict. To attempt to structure one’s life in such a way as to be able consistently to endorse a specific principle - in order, that is, for the principle to be one’s own — involves unifying one’s identity. This unification can be described with the terms of any of the accounts of personal identity that have been outlined above. A woman whose narrative 6" As evidenced by the common resistance to Kant’s “On a Supposed Right to Lie Because of Philanthropic Concerns.” 198 identity elements include ‘good Catholic’ and ‘radical feminist’ will (very) likely experience internal conflict regarding them. It is not implausible to think that such conflict might be so damaging as to motivate conciliation. Suppose she takes up feminism as her principle, or comes to realize about herself that she does, unbeknownst to herself, hold feminism as a principle."4 Feminist demands then take precedence in her life — precedence over, among other things, religious claims. She adopts feminist principles, endorses feminism, and unifies her identity around it. She thereby reduces (internal) conflict with religious aspects of her identity; when faced with a decision whether to support Planned Parenthood, conflict is lessened by the fact that though she may still be a Catholic, her principles are feminist ones. Identities grounded in group membership are similar. Consider the identity ‘African-American’, doubly interesting here because this supposedly unitary identity is actually composed of a historical/racial element as well as a national element, a pair which can easily be imagined to ground conflict."5 One with such conflict might take up racial (that is, rather than national) fidelity as a principle. Desires can be at the core of principles as well."6 One who desires that political society have a socialist sort of organization might desire that her desire persist; that is, she cares about socialism. When she takes up socialism as her principle, she organizes her life around the principle, by voting for certain political candidates, joining appropriate 6" Remember that since endorsement is characterized by an absence of active internal conflict, a person can be said to endorse something she is not aware she identifies with. Thus, one or more of a person’s principles can be unknown to her, and that a person holds X as a principle is often enough not a decision of hers but rather a discovery about herself. 65 I write “supposedly unitary”, because, for example, of the common sorts of race/gender/disability information forms that conflate racial and national identity with the unitary category ‘African-American’ in the same way such forms conflate sexual and gender identity by allowing only two choices (ignoring, say, biological males who gender identify as other than male). 6" Neither this nor any of the foregoing claims entail that principles do not ineliminably contain other elements such as beliefs, for example. 199 political organizations, and disavowing certain of her other desires, such as the desire to own a business. Though conflict has a role in the adoption of principles (and thus in identity unification), it is less clear that a person can be ambivalent regarding her principles. If she is unsure which principle to adopt, neither of the principles are yet hers (having not yet been adopted). A person’s principles, when they themselves conflict, are not her principles at all. A person cannot concurrently hold as her principles both feminism and fidelity to the sexual status quo. Both of these principles cannot, it should be apparent, be core organizing features of her practical life. She may espouse feminist beliefs, even sincerely so, but be internally compelled to remain relatively subservient; in this case neither one is her principle. She may be (sincerely) faithful to the status quo, but desire that she be otherwise, that she be a feminist; in this case she has a principle, though it is one that is on it’s way out, so to speak. Conflicting principles are thus either not principles, or are at best potential (though not potentially coexisting) principles. In summary, then, to act with integrity is to act on a principle in the face of resistance. When that principle is a moral one, the act is one of moral integrity — what is often considered integrity proper. Because, as I’ve argued, principles are composed of just those elements that constitute personal identities, and because principles guide action in a structured, coherent, holistic way, acting with integrity is at odds with identity conflict. Integrity and particularism Mentioning, as I did above, the debate over moral particularism uncovers a possibly unacceptable entailment of the view of integrity as moral integrity. In this 200 section I will address this potential problem for the account of integrity I’ve defended, first outlining briefly Jonathan Dancy’s moral particularism and how he figures integrity into it, then showing at least two ways in which integrity as I characterize it appears to be in conflict with particularism. I will proceed to explain how particularism does not undermine the moralized view of integrity defended here, and then note why Dancy’s and my sort of principles are not as different (as some readers may already have noticed) as they seem. Particularism’s two main claims are these: the practice of morality does not require the application of general moral principles to specific cases, and doing so will often enough fail to give morally correct results. Both these claims depend on the theory of contributory reasons: what is a reason for thing in one case may in another case be a reason not to (1), or even be no reason at all. For example, ‘because that man possesses it’ is sometimes a reason against Robin’s taking it, though if the man is a rich man and Robin is Robin Hood, then the reason is a reason in favor of Robin’s taking it. If Robin Hood acts on the principle ‘taking someone else’s possessions is wrong’ he will in many cases fail to act correctly. Now, Dancy takes integrity to have the status of a contributory reason.“ That means that ‘because the act is one of integrity’ can be a reason for doing it, or be a reason against doing it, or be no reason at all. On a certain conception of integrity, this is initially plausible. If we take integrity to be commitment to one’s deepest personal ideals (a‘ la Bernard Williams), that an act is one of integrity is a reason for the biochemist ‘7 Dancy (2004), p. 121. 201 George to do it, though it is a reason for a mobster beginning a process of self-reform not to do it. There are a number of problems with taking integrity itself to be a contributory reason, though. For one, the assumption that the integrity of an act yields some further reason, over and above that act’s being, as on the Williamsian view for example, an expression of one’s deepest personal ideals, is questionable. Recall George’s decision to refrain from accepting the weapons research job. George’s reason (one of them, anyway) for acting as he did is that investigation into new and better weapons technology is morally wrong, at least as George sees the moral situation. If George acted as he did because weapons research is wrong, the fact that the wrongness of weapons research figures as one of George’s personal ideals cannot give George yet another reason to act as he did, since this is not another further fact about the situation. To make the point with a Wittgensteinian flavor: there is nothing left after we subtract from George’s acting on his personal ideal that weapons research is wrong George’s acting on the wrongness of weapons research?" Nor is it clear that the motivational aspect of such a reason would be coherent. A person of integrity does not, for example, give her last dollar to a local food bank because it is an act of integrity — she does so because it will provide food for the hungry, something she thinks she ought to help remedy. Insofar as an act is done because it is an act of integrity, it isn’t. This is true both on William’s view (which the present discussion has so far been implying) as well as on the taxonomic view. If integrity is just personal 6" To be sure, George’s personal ideal — that is, his principle — regarding the wrongness of weapons research implies other further reasons: because his principle is that weapons research is wrong it is likely that he also is against the employing of such weapons, a moral stance which provides him an additional reason. The point, though, is that even where the propositional content of a reason is also (part of) the propositional content of a principle, this does not itself constitute a further reason. 202 integrity, that is, acting from one’s personal ideals, a person might well take ‘acting with integrity’ as a personal ideal. But this itself has no content — there is no action that is just acting with integrity, although refusing to promote weapons research might be an act of integrity, as might be drinking the hemlock or nonviolently resisting the colonial authorities. Thus, ‘because it is an act of integrity’ is a poor candidate for a reason, contributory or otherwise. From the first-personal standpoint, the reason undermines itself. But integrity isn’t just acting from one’s deepest personal ideals — integrity is acting against resistance and on personal principles that are moral ones. Thus ‘act with integrity’ would itself have to be a moral principle in order for it to ground an act of integrity. Below, I will argue that ‘act with integrity’ is not itself a moral principle, and thus can’t itself ground moral integrity. Remembering that integrity is acting on distinctly moral principles leads to the other way, alluded to in at the beginning of the current section, in which integrity seems to be at odds with particularism, a relatively more practical than theoretical conflict. Recall that acting on moral principles is just what the particularist says we ought not to do, since doing so will cause us to get things wrong, practically speaking. Acting with integrity is precisely the wrong way to go about being a moral person on the particularist view. This is indeed a conflict between particularism and the taxonomic view of integrity. In addressing the conflict, I will first concede that it is not always advisable, prudent, or all-things-considered- good to act from moral principle. Consider the moral principle ‘always give a person what she deserves’ (possibly the strongest contender for 203 the status of universally applicable principle), and a situation in which an armed maniac threateningly waves her gun around a crowded room and demands moral praise from you. It would certainly be ill-advised — and wrong — to act with moral integrity in giving the gunman what she deserves (which is, I take it, moral reprobation). Such cases suggest that to act with integrity is not always to get things right, morally speaking. This seems accurate; even denying the claims of particularism, there are many ways in which an act grounded in moral principle can go wrong, from bad moral luck to social prohibition against certain persons acting from moral principle. As an example of the latter, recall the earlier discussion (in Chapter 2, above) of Ridley Scott’s film Thelma and Louise, and the act of self-respect — the killing of Thelma’s rapist — central to the film. Arguably, that act of integrity went badly wrong: with one exception (the actions of Slocum, the detective who only halfheartedly attempts to capture Thelma and Louise), their act of resistance is misunderstood as pointless violence; much physical and psychological harm and property damage follows from the act; Thelma and Louise take their own lives two days later. There are strong reasons to think that Thelma and Louise had no morally agreeable options open to them; there seem no such reasons, though, to deny that they acted with integrity. Once the score is taken, so to speak, to act out of moral principle can turn out to have been the wrong choice. But insofar as it is desirable and praiseworthy to act with integrity, the distance particularism makes between correct acting and principled acting is problematic. Because particularism incorrectly takes integrity to be a contributory reason, it misunderstands the value of acting from principle in situations where to do so is to act with integrity. So rather than particularism posing a problem for the taxonomic view of 204 integrity, the taxonomic view in fact, to some degree, undermines the plausibility of particularism. In closing, I am aware that some readers may have noticed an apparent category mistake in the foregoing discussion. When Dancy speaks of a principles, what he is referring to is a moral-metaphysical entity that many people think stands in favor of (or opposed to, as the case may be) a certain action in all cases where it applies. What I am calling a principle is a certain set of identity elements as they figure into some certain person’s identity — a moral-psychological entity. Thus, it might be thought that Dancy and I have nothing to say to each other regarding integrity, since we are not using ‘principle’ in at all the same way. But this thought is incorrect. What links the two conceptions of ‘principle’ is this: a moral principle — ‘charity is always right’, say — qua moral-metaphysical entity is something that applies to all relevant acts of all persons. Notably here, it applies to all the relevant acts of each specific person; looking at the way in which principles of the sort Dancy denies shows that a person’s adopting of this sort of principle has the effect of unifying a person’s identity in the way I have described. Dancy himself notes this in mentioning persons who “act ‘consistently’, where this means making their decisions in such a way that they can all be fitted in under the same set of principles?"9 The relation between metaphysical principles and moral-psychological principles can be described in the opposite direction as well: a person whose personal principle is charity believes it to be true that charity is always right.70 Moral-metaphysical principles and moral- "9 Dancy (2004), p. 2. 7" Always right for her, at least; a person who adopts a principle, even a moral one, need not think that the principle applies to other persons. 205 psychological principles are not only closely linked, but they might be thought to be different ways of talking about the same normative regularities. In summary Integrity, that feature of actions by which they are performed in the face of resistance and on the grounds of one’s personal moral principles, is grounded in the unity of identity insofar as principles serve to guide and focus large sets of one’s actions and large segments of her identity. The taxonomic view of integrity defended in support of this claim was, as we saw, also one that explains and supports the intuition regarding the content relevance of autonomy, which I argued to apply rather to integrity. Because true integrity is a characteristic of actions grounded in one’s personal moral principle, acting with integrity is not merely a matter of acting out of a unified identity, but instead requires an identity unified around a moral principle or principles. 206 _5_ Love: value and commitment Our minds are porous and forgetfulness seeps in; I myself am distorting and losing, under the wearing away of the years, the face of Beatriz. - Jorge Luis Borges, “The Aleph” In Jorge Luis Borges’s ostensibly metaphysical story ”The Aleph”, he writes of a place in space and time that contains in itself all other places in space and time; all events, all people and all moments are contained in this Aleph. The reader comes to realize, though, the Aleph is a fiction, for Borges weaves into this story one of a poet, Carlos Argentino Daneri, who attempts an epic poem that aims to lay out in verse the entirety of history; the parallel Borges implies between Daneri and the Aleph suggests that anything all-encompassing is futile, ridiculous, or impossible. Borges’s story is, in the final analysis, about love: the tale’s ultimate parallel is between the impossible Aleph, the ridiculous Daneri, and the futility of the narrator’s fully characterizing (or even completely remembering) his love, Beatriz. Indeed, just below the story’s surface is the won'y not only that the memory of his beloved Beatriz, but also love itself, is fading; I share this worry, and it is the motivating thought of this chapter. 207 I also agree with Borges’s implication that love is, like the whole of the universe or even the whole of human history, not fully characterizable. Thus 1 will not here give an account of love; though my claims are to be held to standards of consistency, they are not intended to be comprehensive. There is little to be gained (rather more accurately, there is something to be lost) by spelling out necessary and sufficient conditions for the concept and practice of love. Instead, I will focus on two elements that are relevant and perhaps central to a plausible conception of love: the valuing of, and commitment to, one’s beloved. I will explain why I take each of these to be important. To determine the nature of the value in loving is theoretically important since loving involves — or according to some just isI — a certain sort of valuing. As I will argue, the nature of the value that is relevant to the practice of loving is practically important as well: the sorts of characteristics of persons that we are socially prescribed to value are not the same characteristics that we ought (on other criteria) to value. This discrepancy is grounded at least in part in a misconception of just where the value of one’s beloved derives from. Related to this last point is one about commitment. To commit oneself to another in a loving relationship can be as fulfilling as fairy tales, film and other narratives often portray.2 Romantic commitment is supposed to facilitate an increased ability to further one’s own projects and desires, for at least a wide range of projects and desires — the emotional support of a committed partner aids the other’s career pursuits and parenting goals, to mention just two obvious examples. And at least one recent sociological study has found that women in marriages marked by commitment on the part of both partners ' E.g. Velleman (1999). 2 Pace Trollope, who wrote in Barchester Towers, “There is no happiness in love, except at the end of an English novel.” 208 report being happier than do other married women (even happier than women in less committed but more egalitarian marriages).3 But this sort of commitment is seemingly rare in contemporary western society, and we are, I think, the less fortunate for this rarity. Commitment, of course, is not always desirable; to pledge oneself to another person (which is what commitment is commonly taken in no small part to involve) can lead to psychological, social and even legal entrapment in a life that is unpleasant and even harmful. In this chapter, I will argue the following. The mode of valuing in which we engage in romantic relationships involves bestowed rather than appraised value. This process is distinctively undermined by identity disunity since romantic love both takes a singular object and extensively permeates a lover’s identity. Though the focus here will for largely idiosyncratic reasons be on romantic love, some of the considerations can be applied mutatis mutandis to paternal, filial and agapic love.4 In the chapter’s final section, I will defend a conception of ‘commitment as giving oneself’ as a more plausible alternative to a common conception of ‘commitment as a promise.’ I will then show how commitment to a romantic partner — like other sorts of commitments that circumscribe the boundaries of a person’s identity — is tantamount to unifying large areas of the landscape of one’s identity. 3 Wilcox and Nock (2006). " Most clearly, the ways in which commitment to the object of our love serves as an identity-unifying force are relevant to love whatever its object. Other features, such as the singularity of the object of love, are not relevant to other sorts of love, while a bestowal view of value is central to agapic love. 209 Valuing A claim to objectivity is a claim to speak for all those whose voices count; it is a license not to listen. - Naomi Scheman, Engenderings It may not be immediately clear how objectivity is relevant to a discussion of value and loving. It should be more clear that value is an important element of the notion of love. While love may be a matter of more than valuing, I take it as indisputable that if Jane loves Jill, Jane values Jill. What is eminently disputable is the nature of this valuing. To say that Jane values Jill might be to say that there are certain qualities that Jill possesses that are inherently — and so objectively — valuable, and Jane’s love for Jill is (partially) constituted by an apprehension of those qualities. This is what has been called an appraisal view of love. Altemately, Jane’s loving of Jill might involve Jane’s bestowal of value onto Jill. On such a bestowal view, the value of Jill as a beloved is entirely a matter of Jane’s placing of value on her. Some bestowal views allow that in the initial stages of falling in love, the nature of the value of the beloved is of the appraised sort, since otherwise it is difficult to understand what would motivate the lover to choose to bestow value on one possible beloved among many who are equally devoid of the relevant sort of inherent value. Other views of value are certainly possible, but it is not apparent that there will be views not subsumable under the ‘appraisal/bestowal’ distinction. For example, it might be thought that the value of a beloved person (read ‘value qua beloved person’ here and 210 in what follows) is only apparent to her lover — an appraisal view. Further, none of my claims here should be taken to imply that Jane and Jill’s relationship cannot have both appraised and bestowed sorts of value; Jane and Jill’s relationship is (supposing it is a realistic relationship) not solely a romantic one. They are likely involved simultaneously in a relation of friendship, and perhaps numerous more instrumental relationships, such as that between rock-climbing partners. If differing modes of valuing feature in different sorts of relationships (as I think they might), then differing modes of valuing will feature in the set of Jane and Jill’s relationship. The discussion here artificially separates out their romantic relationship. This might all be thought to interest only the academic. Whether my beloved is inherently valuable or is valuable only in virtue of my bestowal certainly cannot matter to her or to me. While the philosophers go on disputing, she and I will go on loving, none the worse for the theoretical uncertainty. But this is not entirely true. The nature of love’s value is of more than theoretical importance. Whether we love in virtue of value that is thought to be inherent in our beloved, or in virtue of value that is bestowed by the lover, makes a great deal of practical difference. Hence, I will argue in support of one of the contending accounts. The appraisal view A number of prominent writers take love to be a matter of appraisal of the value of the beloved object, idea, or person. I don’t take one or another of such accounts to be authoritative; indeed, not all the important philosophical claims about love are made in the interest specifically of defending some certain account over another. Nor to I take one or another writer’s claims particularly susceptible to criticisms. I will appeal to a few 211 such accounts — that of David Velleman, Iris Murdoch, and Plato — in order to sketch the outline and a few illustrative details of the sorts of claims that make an appraisal view distinct. On appraisal views, love is, to take David Velleman’s characterization as one example, “an arresting awareness” of “the value inherin g in its object”.5 Within Iris Murdoch’s suggestive discussion of morality as “attention to reality inspired by, consisting of, love?" she argues that “the ability to direct attention is love,” a precondition of the “intellectual ability” of “accurate vision.”7 Claims of love essentially involving an awareness of some valuable quality or other — usually accompanied by visual metaphors — go back at least to Plato’s Symposium. There, after considering a number of views of love as a process of making up for some deficiency in the lover, Socrates recounts the arguments of Diotima, who said, The man who has been thus educated in matters of Love, who has beheld beautiful things in the right order and correctly, is coming now to the goal of Loving: all of a sudden he will catch sight of something wonderfully beautiful in its nature.8 Not only is love thus a matter of ‘beholding’ or ‘catching sight of’ some quality — namely, beauty -- of the beloved. This quality is in the beloved’s nature — an objectively apprehendable quality, as Diotima had explained: It is not beautiful ...in relation to one thing and ugly in relation to another; nor is it beautiful here but ugly there, as it would be if it were beautiful for some people and ugly for others.9 5 Velleman (1999), p. 360. 6 Murdoch (1970), p. 67. 7 Murdoch (1970), p. 66. 9 Cited in Solomon and Higgins (1991), p 26. 9 Cited in Solomon and Higgins (1991), p 26. 212 Though a number of views can be thus interpreted as appraisal views, only the source of the value of the beloved is agreed upon; the supposedly valuable qualities themselves vary. Diotima took beauty to be the only relevant valuable characteristic of love’s object. Velleman’s account, distinctly, takes the valuable characteristic of the beloved to be her “capacity to care about things in that reflective way which is distinctive of self-conscious creatures like us”, that is, her moral personhood grounded in her rational will.” Murdoch implies more simply that love seeks to attend to “the idea of perfection” which moves us “because it inspires love?” It might seem that Murdoch’s is not a view about the love of persons (imperfect as we are); if this is true, it is not true because of the nature of love, but rather because of the way in which we in fact tend to love: “human love,” she writes, ‘is normally too profoundly possessive and also too ‘mechanical’ to be a place of vision.”12 A more homely appraisal view might take the valuable characteristics inhering in a person to be such things as her sensitivity, her love of nature, even (following Yeats) her yellow hair.l3 Whatever the specific object of the lover’s awareness, it is just that: an awareness, a perception, an apprehending of some value that exists in the beloved and independently of the lover.” There are a number of difficulties with appraisal views taken generally. One is what we might call the problem of substitutability. The problem is this: if loving involves ” Velleman (1999), p. 365. “ Murdoch (1970), p. 62. '2 Murdoch (1970), p. 75. ’3 "Never shall a young man,/ Thrown into despair/ By those great honey-coloured/ Ramparts at your ear,/ Love you for yourself alone/ And not your yellow hair. " '4 ‘Independently’ in a metaphysical, but not necessarily causal, sense. Her love for nature might exist only because it was nourished by her history with her lover, but the point is that the value of this attitude of hers is not dependent on her lover or their history. 213 an appraisal of objective value, the object of love ought to be substitutable for an object with the same or, possibly, different but equally valuable qualities.” It is apparent (perhaps analytically so) that equally valuable things ought to be valued equally, at least by a person who is not axiologically disabled in some way. We do not tend to think, though, that a lover presented with a person who is value-identical to her beloved ought romantically to value this new person. While in other contexts it is legitimate to expect all to value certain characteristics of persons relatively equally — we justifiably expect all academic analytic philosophers to value any person’s clarity of thought, for instance — it is not legitimate to expect a person who values the tenderness of her beloved to value that same quality in some other person.” There are various replies to this criticism. One defense against this oddity of an appraisal view is that objects of love are not substitutable because the reason for loving a person is given by the relationship the lover has to the beloved.17 On such a view whatever valued qualities of a beloved might be duplicated in another person, but these two persons are not substitutable as beloveds since the lover shares a unique history and trajectory of love with only one of them. This might be taken as no more than an amendment to the list of valuable qualities of the beloved, though; one of my beloved’s valuable qualities might be that she shared some experience with me, or shares some plan or project with me.18 '5 Only possibly, since distinct sorts of value are not (always) commensurable. '6 This, of course, assumes a set of practices of loving that does not include such things as forced marriages. Since I aim to explicate facts about our current practices this assumption is justified. '7 Kolodny (2003). By ‘relationship’ Kolodny is referring to “my present concern” together with “our history of shared concern and activity and [...] my friend or lover’s present concern for me.” (p. 162). '8 On a slightly different note, the claim that one’s relationship to the beloved gives special (positive) value to her is not always the case: if a person whom I love has an affair, I might well disvalue her less for this action if she is someone with whom I have little history or concern; the longer our history, and more prominent our shared concern, the more 1 might despise her. 214 Velleman’s Kantian account, on which what is valued in loving is the beloved’s rational will, is able to reply to the problem of substitutability with a distinction between ‘dignity’ and ‘price’. Since the value of quotidian objects is commensurable - the value of one pair of shoes can be compared to that of another pair of shoes, or to that of a coffee maker — objects have a price. But if something “is exalted above all price and so admits of no equivalent, then it has a dignity?” Perhaps this avoids the substitutability worry, but at a cost: the cost of being unable to judge between the value of you and the value of her, exalting both above all price, and being compelled to love you both. Call this, then, the problem of specialness. The problem of specialness, which Velleman details quite extensively, is the worry of a beloved that if everyone is distinctly lovable for some invaluable quality, there is nothing special about oneself, romantically speaking. Velleman takes the worry to be very deeply rooted, at least from a developmental point of View: “We are told by adults who love us, and want us to feel loved, that we are special and irreplaceable [...] and we wonder: If everyone is so special, what’s so special about anyone?”20 Nor is the thought that one is unique (qualitatively or numerically) a help, since “it is easily defeated by the very same standard. How valuable can our uniqueness make us if everyone is unique?”21 Given Velleman’s concern for the problem, his solution to it is unsatisfying. He introduces a distinction between judging value and appreciating value. We properly judge the value of objects, and in this way rate, rank and compare their value relative to each other; we properly (to recall Velleman’s abovementioned distinction) consider objects to have a price. But because persons have dignity rather than price, the proper '9 Kant, Groundwork, 4:434, quoted in Velleman (1999), p. 364. 2° Velleman (1999), p. 363. 2‘ Velleman (1999). P. 363 215 way to apprehend the value of persons is not to judge it but to appreciate it. Because we appreciate but not judge the value of our beloved, there is “a ban on subjecting him to 9922 comparisons , such as the demanded comparison implicit in the question ‘what makes me more special than her?’. The question ought not to be asked, even, for being special “entails being seen to have a value that forbids comparisons.”23 But if everyone has this sort of incomparable value, then an explanation of why we love only certain persons is necessary. Velleman supposes that this is a question of why we love a person “for his observable features” such as physical traits, mannerisms, and (presumably, though unmentioned) character traits such as courage and honesty. At least regarding mannerisms such as ‘the way he walks’, Velleman claims that we love people for them because such love is “a response to his gait as an expression or reminder of his value as a person?” This much seems true, and a valuable observation - that our tendency to say (and believe) that we value, for instance, our beloved’s tenderness is better described as a valuing of our beloved for (in virtue of) her tenderness. But such a description returns us to where we began: if any relevant mannerism or trait of body or character is an expression or reminder of one’s value as a person, then the question ‘why love me, rather than him?’ stands unanswered. The problem of the best beloved is this: even on an appraisal view that does not include the notion of value as ‘a dignity’, it would seem to follow that the accurate appraiser of value would be compelled to love certain persons.” Indeed, if there were a ’2 Velleman (1999), p. 367. ” Velleman (1999), p. 370. 2" Velleman (1999), p. 371. ” The problem, of course, is worse on an account that does include the notion of a dignity: I am normatively compelled to love every person. Velleman notes that such love is “constitutionally impossible”, and our choosing one of all the obligatory beloveds is assisted by the fact that “the human 216 most valuable person, everyone who was an accurate perceiver of value should love her, thus making the current relatively egalitarian distribution of beloveds somewhat odd.” The bestowal view (and a hybrid account) On a bestowal view, the value of the beloved does not exist in her inherently. Her value is solely a function of her lover’s valuing her — ‘valuing’ here being an active verb.” The lover does not perceive the value of her beloved, she rather gives her beloved value, by valuing her. “When we love,” writes Irving Singer, “we create value”.” In order to illustrate what I take to be the central distinction between bestowal and appraisal views, it will be valuable to consider the ways in which such views agree. On both views, a specific feature of one’s beloved -- that set of behaviors of hers that we might consider as constituting her sharp wit, for instance — does exist in her. That is, she really does have a tendency spontaneously to interject intelligent remarks characterized by subtle punning or inventive metaphor, all with a quick if slightly dark humor. IfI value my beloved in part for this particular set of behaviors, I perceive that she in fact exhibits these behaviors. What distinguishes a bestowal view of value from an appraisal view is the supposed source or locus of whatever value this set of behaviors has. On an appraisal body and human behavior are imperfect expressions of personhood [. . .] hence the value that makes someone eligible to be loved does not necessarily make him lovable in our eyes.” (p. 372) Not only is the shift from moral personhood as a normatively and rationally necessary object of respect to personhood as making one eligible for loving respect illegitimate and unexplained, but this explanation of Velleman’s is just that — an explanation, specifically of why we love selectively. But given Velleman’s project of reconciling loving with Kantian - that is, impartial and inexorable — moral demands, a justification of selective love seems required. 2" And, it might be noted, making for an odd interpretation of the old saw ‘There is someone for everyone.’ That is, instead of Vx3y(ny), 3ny(ny). ” ‘Value of the beloved’ should be taken throughout to mean ‘value of the beloved to the lover, and this only in her role as beloved.’ That is, ‘value’ does not here include human value, self-value, value to others, value to God, and all the other sorts of value (inherent or bestowed) properly attributed to her. ” Singer (1987), p. 392. 217 view, since valuing is perceiving the value of one’s beloved, I perceive the valuable characteristic of ‘wit’ in her. This claim is both phenomenological and metaphysical; not only does it seem like I perceive value that she in fact has, but also the phenomenology could well be accurate — if the value of her behaviors is anywhere, it is (so to speak) in her. A bestowal view is — if indeed I perceive the value in my beloved — an error theory, for although the features in virtue of which value is bestowed do exist objectively, the value is not perceived, but is rather conferred by the lover.29 Thus (as further illustration), the reason why a lover might value the wit of his beloved, a person who others might rather take to be cynical, flippant or facetious, a bestowal view explains as follows. Since cynicism, flippancy and facetiousness are each both descriptive and evaluative terms, who I call witty and you consider flippant are being described the same by you and by me — where we differ is in our bestowal of value on the (physical) behaviors we both perceive.” Because the value of a beloved is not inherent in the beloved but rather bestowed by the lover, the bestowal view neatly sidesteps the problems of substitutability and specialness that make appraisal views untenable. The problem of substitutability — that someone with my same value (or degree of value) should be an adequate romantic replacement for me — is not an issue on a bestowal view since there is no other person 29 That the bestowal view is an error theory will not need to be accepted universally. The phenomenology of the overall experience of love differs widely between persons, as do certain elements of it such as the valuing of one’s beloved, and so for some lovers the bestowal view is phenomenologically accurate. 30 This point might be clearer to the reader with analogical examples. A somewhat complex one: suppose I take a certain man to be a ‘thieving nigger’, while you take him to be a ‘poverty-stricken African American man’. The point here is that you and I can agree on all the (non-normative) facts - e. g., that he stole another person’s property, he is homeless, he is unemployed and uneducated, he lives in a society which systematically denies to him opportunities it allows to white people, and so on - but at the same time disagree on our evaluative judgments, as evidenced by the difference in terms we use to characterize him. A very simple illustration: you and I taste the same beer, a heavily-hopped India Pale Ale. You blurt out ‘Eww...bitter!’ and 1 say ‘Yum...bitter!’ 218 who has the same (degree of) value as me." Similarly for the problem of specialness: where on the appraisal view the lover judges (or as Velleman points out, appreciates) the beloved’s uniqueness, a quality everyone has, the bestowal view holds that the lover takes only her beloved to be unique or special. Thus, the bestowal view is subject to neither of these problems. A bestowal view, like an appraisal view, can be seen to entail a number of odd notions that demand a bit of discussion. One is the description of valuing that is inconsistent with (some people’s) phenomenal experience. There are at least two ways in which one’s experience might fail to accord with the account defended here. One is in the difference between love’s feeling like a passive happening — ‘falling in love’; ‘overtaken by love’ - as against the apparent active valuing that is supposed to be undertaken by the lover. One response is that the account of valuing defended here is not argued to be a comprehensive account of the whole of love (as I explained at the beginning of the chapter); the feeling of falling is explainable by some other feature of love.32 Another response is to point out that the phenomenological experience of loving takes widely varying forms between persons, and so perhaps an appeal to subjective experience can be illuminating but nowhere near conclusive. The other phenomenological discrepancy regards the source of the value of one’s beloved: a person might well feel that his beloved’s wit really is in her, and that he 3‘ Except, that is, from the lover’s point of view. But the bestowal view’s recognition of the not uncommon phenomenon of coming to love someone else — through bestowing value on some other, new, beloved - further lends credence to such an account. 32 Possible explanations range from ‘falling in love is no more loving itself than falling in the shower is showering itself’ (that is, just a small part of the total practice, as well as an accident there are good reasons to try to avoid) to the observation that the way in which we conceive of a practice such as loving can radically affect our subjective experience of that practice (and so our experience reflects and is caused by an incorrect understanding of what we are in fact doing), an observation that carries some substantial argumentative weight in the present chapter. 219 himself sees that valuable quality of hers. This, I suspect, is the experience that motivates the construction of appraisal views (as well as the ubiquitous visual metaphors), and understandably so. But to motivate the construction of an account is not the same as supporting it; this, in the face of the deep conceptual problems with the appraisal view, is something that the phenomenal experience of some set of persons is not sufficient to do. Another, non-phenomenological, issue might be raised against the implication of the bestowal view that any personal characteristics or any person (however horrible) might romantically be valued. The thought that love might be given to anyone, regardless of their worth, is admittedly consistent with observation, for even more baffling than the extraordinary nastiness that characterizes certain people is the fact that, often, they are loved by someone (consider Henry VIII’s six wives, at least some of whom loved him in some substantial sense, or the high value Bonnie placed on Clyde). In this regard, then, the bestowal view shows a distinct phenomenological strength. Nor is there any real weakness entailed by this implication, for a person who values her beloved for, say, his domineering, violent treatment of her can (or better, should) still be strongly criticized. She (we can legitimately think or say) should not value that in him since if she did not she would be happier, she would have more personal freedom, others would respect her more, she would have the sort of self-respect required of a Kantian moral agent, and so on. Further, these considerations might be expected to have some traction on her. If she indeed wants happiness (or freedom, et al) and the connection between these of her desires and a change in her valuing is well-drawn she will ceteris paribus be drawn toward revising her objects of value.33 Some people will, of course, ’3 Ceteris paribus, that is, since she must be minimally practically rational, and there are not stronger (to her) considerations moving her to maintain her current valuing practices, and so on. 220 continue to value such things. But (to make the specific point at hand) what the bestowal view denies is that what is wrong with her valuing what she does is that what she values simply isn’t valuable. Such an appraisal view is, as I continue to argue, implausible and unnecessary to make sense of (and improve) our practices of valuing. To return to addressing possible criticisms, it might also appear that a bestowal view has the lover bestowing value gratuitously. If a lover’s evaluations are not a response to some real value, then they are not a response to anything. Perhaps one’s beloved ought not to feel so special after all, if she was chosen as an object of love arbitrarily, and even at that is given more value than she deserves. Singer attempts to respond to these sorts of entailments of a bestowal view; I will outline his responses below, and then follow with what I will argue to be more plausible answers to these concerns. Singer claims to defend a hybrid account on which love is marked by a “complex network of bestowals and appraisals”.”4 Though he admits that bestowal is necessary for love, he distinguishes two sorts of appraisals that occur as well. What he calls objective appraisals are made using the value scale of one’s community. Singer offers as illustration the evaluations of judges at a beauty contest. Individual appraisals are those made with special reference to one’s own interests and preferences. It seems that the straits between the Scylla of appraisal and the Charybdis of bestowal are perhaps too narrow to navigate successfully, and Singer scrapes the rocks at many points. In an elaboration of bestowal he claims, “the lover accepts the beloved, responds affinnatively to her attributes even though he knows that from an appraisive 3" Singer (1987), p. 390. 221 point of view they could be evaluated in a less positive way”.35 But to respond, and to evaluate in the sense of ‘judging’ used here, is just what happens in appraisal. If this claim of Singer’s is true, then value is appraised. But at another point he claims, “all appraisals must ultimately depend on bestowal since they presuppose that human beings give importance to the satisfying of their needs and desires. Without such bestowal nothing could take on value of any sort”.” If this is true, all value is bestowed. In any case, it is flatly contradictory with his claim that “bestowal would not occur in human beings without appraisal”.37 Finally, in an argument aimed at showing the incoherence of the notion of ‘infinite worth’, he writes, “in themselves [...] people have neither “infinite worth” nor infinite worthlessness. They acquire value and the lack of it only as they are valued or value themselves in their relations with one another”.38 Such acquiring is the defining feature of a bestowal view. To summarize a bit: I have argued that there are substantial problems with appraisal views, especially with but not limited to Velleman’s Kantian account; I have also shown how at least one attempted hybrid view39 -— Singer’s — contradictorily conflates two distinct sorts of valuing. Thus the abovementioned apprehensions toward accepting a bestowal view still remain. One, recall, is that there is a certain arbitrary flavor to bestowal; in addressing this concern here I will make it more explicit by casting it in two closely related ways. One way to characterize the concern is that bestowal seems to allow a limitless, willy- ” Singer (1987), p. 392. 3" Singer (1987), p. 393. 97 Singer (1994), p. 141. In Singer’s defense, this claim might be a purely psychological one, and the former (that bestowal is the foundation of all value) an axiological one. I am not aware, though, that Singer explains how the practice and theory of valuing could be so fundamentally opposed. 3" Singer (1987), p. 403. 39 The only one of which I am aware; the literature on valuing in love is not large. I do not deny that a hybrid view of some sort is not possible. 222 nilly casting about of value. Velleman raises this sort of issue in motivating his own appraisal view against views which allow that “we needn’t see or be moved to see [one’s beloved] as he really is?” He claims that lacking accurate perception of the real value of one’s beloved often entails “overvaluation.”"l Singer, more richly, claims that bestowal without appraisal entails love [to be] a flight of fancy, or an emotional explosion that destroys the humdrum facts of ordinary life, or a blind allegiance, or an affirmation (however sublime) that ascribes objective perfection despite what everyone knows about the limits in mere humanity.“2 In these claims, Velleman and Singer confuse the nature of value with its excess. Simply because something is bestowed gratis rather than in response to some prior state of affairs does not entail that such bestowal will be unjustifiably gratuitous. Consider here gift- giving versus bill-paying, and the fact that while gifts are bestowed, only rarely are they bestowed excessively. The second way to characterize the concern about arbitrariness comes from a more first-personal point of view. If value is bestowed, rather than judged, I may wonder whether I warrant her love —- another version of the problem of specialness. After all, it is not in virtue of some objectively valuable quality of mine that she loves me. There seems no reason for her to love me rather than him. While it is indeed not by the light of some inherent value that a lover sees her beloved as she does, all is not darkness. This woman who I call bold, you call brazen. I bestow value on her, while you do not."3 In my loving her, I provide the light by which 4° Velleman (1999), p. 351. 4‘ Velleman (1999), p. 351. 42 Singer (1987), p. 394. 43 “Some say thy fault is youth, some wantonness;/ Some say thy grace is youth and gentle sport;/ Both grace and faults are lov’d of more and less:/ Thou mak’st faults graces that to thee resort./ As on the finger 223 she may be seen, and thus the reason for loving her exists (satisfying those who expect that love is to be responsive to reasons). Indeed, in bestowing value on her, I may provide the light by which she can see herself as valuable and thus see the reason she is loved legitimately and non-arbitrarily. This thought — that only through being loved can a person see herself as a proper object of love — is not mere romanticism. Certainly the value that others bestow on us contributes to our self-conceptions as valuable persons -— this is a not trivial feature of awards and honors, for instance. But what is more, valuing oneself may be practially possible only insofar as one is valued by others. Recall the deferential wife, who believably was supposed to lack a sense of self-value because of her husband’s failure to value her. Reconsider also Lindemann’s notion of master narratives, those often third- personally constructed character-narratives. A master narrative such as ‘single mother’ only now (not, say, as the character-type was understood in the 1950’s) carries with it a bestowal of value; now (much more than 50 years ago) is a single mother as such able to value herself. Through being valued, a person can come to see herself as valuable; through being loved, a person can come to see herself warranting that love. Even if the beloved is not valued in virtue of his inherently valuable qualities, there is something in virtue of which he is valued; there is something, though inherently valueless, to which the attributions of boldness and brazenness refer. Admittedly, though, bestowal refers in large part back to the lover herself. She is the creator of value, the artist to the canvas that is her beloved. Value is bestowed on the beloved in virtue of facets of the lover as well as what might be thought to be mere contingencies — the of a throned queen/ The basest jewel will be well esteem’d;/ So are those errors that in thee are seen/ To truth translated, and for true things deem’d. . .” Shakespeare, Sonnet XCVI. 224 11 rant i.l|!l¢l|ll.ir 1 ‘1 it «will incident luck of a chance meeting, the unlikely state of interpersonal compatibility, that obscure thing called ‘chemistry’. Love is fortuitous, a fact the bestowal view does not attempt to hide. The bestowal view is thus the more plausible alternative since it answers the two most troubling problems to which appraisal views are subject: the problems of substitutability and specialness. But a bestowal view, as mentioned earlier, is taken by some to be an error theory, failing to correspond to some people’s experience of loving. There seem to be three ways to respond to an error theory. One is to defend an alternative theory, though I’ve argued above that the two alternatives defended in the literature — appraisal and a hybrid account — are unsatisfactory. Another is to accept the theory, and accept that our phenomenal experience is simply nonveridical. The third option, as I ’11 recommend in what follows, is to reconceive our own understanding of our practices, thus bringing phenomenology in line. The reason we ought to reconcieve our practices of valuing is because, as I now explain, such reconception will help to remedy a set of oppressive effects of loving. Many of the instances of romantic love that are damaging are distinctively damaging to women, and this in light of socially-prescribed patterns of valuing that direct women to value certain characteristics in their romantic partners. Value and oppression The oppressive effects of loving find their roots in whom we love, or more accurately, with whom we ought to love. The question of who we ought to love is based in no small part on the question of what personal characteristics ought to be valued in a beloved. Men ought to seek out women who are physically beautiful, domestically 225 talented, confident yet appropriately submissive. These are the valuable qualities of a wife, unless my cultural radar is substantially out of tune. Who ought she to love? A man, first and foremost. Beyond this, a man who allows her her career, and compliments her on her good hair days. She should value a man who takes control of the family’s affairs (except for the monotonous elements of childcare, of course) and allows her some bare minimum of moral personhood. The point of these nearly accurate caricatures is this: men are socially guided to value qualities of women that are beneficial to men (sexual attractiveness, concern for male comfort, and so on). Women are socially guided to value qualities of men that are beneficial to men (thinly restrained dominance, freedom from emotional burden)."" That is, the socially recommended values of desirable beloveds are values that are overwhelmingly beneficial not to women but to men. This set of conditions, whereby the system of norms is structured such that they ensure the benefit of the members of one group over the members of other groups, is a commonly accepted defining example of oppression. Thus, insofar as love is partially characterized by a certain sort of valuing, and insofar as the sort of valuing that occurs in our own practices of loving is a sort that tends to benefit men as it harms women, love is oppressive. There are of course many ways in which to pursue the amelioration of this state of affairs. Most commonly, the content of the purportedly valuable characteristics is recommended for change. For example, the idea that the male partner might be the primary domestic caretaker is gaining adherents, as is the virtually mainstream idea that 4“ The debt here to Marilyn Frye should be apparent. See Frye (1983). 226 romantic partnerships can be non-heterosexual. Because, as I’ve argued, the social influences of identity are neither monolithic nor homogeneous, much social reevaluation of this sort can have favorable and substantial effects. This is not to say that none of these sorts of efforts at changing the content of norms are misguided; for example, assertiveness training programs for women, involving both interpersonal communication as well as assault prevention, can be seen as unfairly shifting responsibility for change. 45 In these specific cases, the most practically feasible option has the unfortunate effect of perpetuating the unequal burden of responsibility. But it is not only the specific content of these norms that makes for this damaging oppression. The supposed nature of the value plays an important role in the systematicity of the oppressive norms, as I’ll argue next. The bestowal view reconsidered On a bestowal view of value, the beloved’s value comes from her lover. On such a view, the idea that there are values inhering in the beloved, that the lover is to judge, is incorrect, if not incoherent. To accept a bestowal view is thus to deny the force of socially mediated prescriptions of objective value. In other words, if the value of one’s beloved is bestowed, no one can be expected to judge value in some certain way, since such value isn’t judged at all. Thus a woman who is exhorted to perceive a controlling if tolerant man as appropriately valued can come to see that whether she bestows value on him is rather a matter of the sort of value she herself is to bring into existence. She can understand her valuing him to be an act of creation that need be responsive neither to external expectations nor even to internal needs. ‘5 The error here is that the content of the norm prescribing feminine reserve is assumed to need alteration, rather than the one prescribing masculine dominance. 227 The bestowal view thus portrays value as relative to the lover. The value of the beloved is more relative to the lover in a less instrumental sense than Singer’s ‘individual appraisal’. Recall that individual appraisal has the lover judging the value of her beloved on criteria applicable to how well the beloved and his characteristics fulfill some needs or desires of hers. Thus value is relative to the lover in the sense that it is not relative to some prior community.” There is, though, something a bit distasteful about a conception on which the value of the beloved is to be understood as satisfying some need of the lover — as a lonely person might value a dog, or a hungry person food.’7 Visceral reactions to instrumental conceptions of love aside, predominant understandings of the needs of men and women are skewed in such a way that also contribute to making the individual appraisal understanding undesirable. The slogan of resistance ‘A woman needs a man like a fish needs a bicycle’ has yet to be fully accepted; women are assumed to need men for personal protection (the most visible element of assault-prevention organizations on college campuses tends to be male walking escorts), and women are still, I think, taken to need men for partnership (consider the negative connotation of ‘spinster’, an unequal analogue to the much desired state of ‘bachelorhood’)."8 Men may be thought to need women, too, but for much more limited 4" Nothing in this distinction need be taken to deny that the desires and needs of specific persons are a function of society through socialization. Whatever one thinks about the degree to which a person’s own standards can diverge from society’s standards, it is at least phenomenologically apt to distinguish between a person’s valuing something that society has deemed valuable and valuing something in spite of societal expectations to the contrary. ‘7 These metaphors are distinct insofar as the former at least implies that there might be some return of utility to the beloved (since the dog hopefully gains from playing this role, as well), but the latter implies that the value is expended in satisfying the desire in virtue of which it is valued. If I appraise you positively in virtue of your ability to satisfy my desire for political power (a quality you have but I lack), when I have acquired what I seek, do I thus cease to value you? One can see how an appraisal view can be construed as an overly cynical view of love. ‘8 Thus even though non-heterosexual relations are socially accepted to a degree unknown in recent history, it is my impression that they are still taken by many to be a lesser sort of partnership. 228 purposes; for example, I take the still-popular sentiment ‘why buy the cow when you can get the milk for free’ to apply primarily to men (I have yet to hear a popular adaptation involving a bull). So a ‘need-satisfaction’ understanding of value — that is, Singer’s ‘individual appraisal’ model — plays a role in much of the same social damage to women as does his ‘objective appraisal’ understanding. On a bestowal view the value of the beloved is ‘relative to’ the lover in a different way. The value of the beloved is not taken to be a solution to the problem of how to satisfy desires. On a bestowal view, valuing is not a solution at all, but is, rather, an expression. The expression is an expression of who she, the lover, is. Her medium is her beloved. Through making him valuable, she expresses herself. The artistic creation metaphor suggested here is not mere rhetoric, for bestowal, like many sorts of expression, can be experimental in a way that appraisal cannot. ‘Experimental’, that is, in the sense that convention can be ignored (or at least bracketed) for the sake of exploring new ways of living.49 Because of this, a person who sees herself as bestowing value can feel free to ignore social expectations in the way an artist can but an art critic cannot (on some normative reading of these roles — a good art critic). What the critic asserts must be accurate, or at least useful; what an artist creates need have no such epistemic or utilitarian goal, and perhaps no preconceived goal at all.” ‘9 More precisely, certain specific conventions can be ignored or bracketed. There is no way to step outside the whole of what I here call ‘convention’ - socially-mediated factual and evaluative understandings. There are, though, ways to pick and chose which aspects of conventional thought one will accept or dispute, and this choice is made more free by conceiving of ourselves as lovers as notjudging by the criteria of socially- mediated standards. 5° 1 am thinking here of the artist as someone like the later Jackson Pollack (originator of what is sometimes called ‘drip art’), or at least a certain vulgar understanding of him as someone who created with neither content nor aesthetic assertion in mind. 229 Valuing and the ideal of unity Having defended a subjectivist account of value in romantic relationships has not yet made the connection with the unity of identity any more transparent. In the following explanation of this connection I will argue that the valuing in love is ideally supported by a unified identity, in two distinct ways: first, while appraising value is a process that has relatively little connection to the unity of identity, bestowing value is in fact undermined by identity disunity. Thus, I will show how the subjective valuing that characterizes romantic relationships is specially related to the unity of identity. Secondly, valuing one’s romantically beloved — as contrasted with, say, valuing a friend, or a work of art, or a favored piece of clothing — is distinct insofar as we tend to believe (as I think we ought to) that each of us can have only one romantic partner. This is a fact about romantic loving that is undermined by a certain sort of fragmentation that characterizes at least some disunified identities. That is, I will argue that the distinct object of romantic valuation makes the unity of identity specially important. I will discuss each of these two issues in turn. The ability to value is undermined by disunity much more on the sort of bestowal view of value that is defended here than on an appraisal view. To make this point, I will make use of the distinction between telic states (or processes, or relations), and thetic states (or processes, or relations)?l Empirical belief, for example, is a thetic state - that is, the aim of belief, or what it is for belief to go well, is that a person’s belief about a thing actually track the truth that is out there in the world. When this process goes wrong, the error is with the person’s mental state (specifically, her belief). On thetic 5' The telic/thetic terminology was first presented in Humberstone (1992). 230 processes, the mind is supposed to track the world To correct such an error, we attempt to influence a change in the person’s mind by, among other things, presenting her with more or better information, or giving her tools of reasoning. Consider, now, the contrasting telic process. A desire — my desire to eat chocolate, say — is an element in a telic relation, in which when things go wrong, the problem is that the world has not altered to satisfy my desire; in a telic process, the world is supposed to alter to fit the mental state. To correct this sort of error, we attempt to effect a change in the world by, in this example, finding me some chocolate. Now, appraisal of value is a thetic process. If something has value that is inherent in it, the aim of valuing is for the valuer’s belief to fit the truth about the valuable thing. Money is like this — a five dollar bill has inherent value (five dollars’ worth, to be exact). If a person values a five dollar bill at one dollar, she has erred, and the error is in her belief.” Her belief could be corrected: she could get better eyeglasses so she can read the numbers on the bill, or she could be corrected in a (very peculiar) mathematical misunderstanding that 1:5. There are likely other possibilities, all involving information or improved tools for acquiring it. Notably, none of the corrections involve her personal identity in any important sense. The five dollar bill is worth five dollars, no matter what the content or structure of one’s identity.53 But bestowing value, on the other hand, does importantly involve the elements of one’s identity. Explanations of why a person attributes value to X rather than Y that 52 There are, of course, cases in which, for example, three quarters are worth more to a person than a dollar bill (as when she needs exact fare for a bus). These cases involve distinct kinds of value, though, and so it would be fallacious (involving equivocation) to conclude that a dollar is worth less than three quarters. 53 Neither is there is a good analogue to a practical identity in the realm of theoretical reasons (we don’t, for better or worse, value ourselves as persons who act in accordance with the law of noncontradiction), to disarm a possible counterargument on this matter. 231 appeal to her identity often go unrequested, since they are obvious. Why I value Socrates more than Babe Ruth (in the realm of famous figures), coffeehouse conversation over poetry slams (for a pastime), or Jorge Luis Borges over Elizabeth Barrett Browning (for recreational reading) is clear: I am a philosopher.54 What makes a person who identifies as a Christian value humility is likewise apparent; similarly for a flower-child and world peace. Thus group identities importantly figure into a person’s value bestowals."5 Elements in a person’s complex of desires play a role in bestowing value, as well — unsurprisingly, since desires and, by extension, the things we care about are constituent elements of personal identity. The role of desires in valuing is a more direct role than that of group identities, though, for while group identity can explain a person’s valuing certain things, her desires just are her valuations. If a person desires something, then she values it. This is not to say that a person cannot desire something revolting, say — some things (a substantial number of very desirable films, for instance”) are desirable in large part because of the revulsion they cause. Nor does a person desire something she takes to be valueless, since at the very least she values what she desires instrumentally (being, as it is, the satisfier of her desire)” But taking an instrumental stance toward what one values is not necessary, nor as I argued above is it always appropriate. This stance is most clearly inappropriate in the context of interpersonal and more narrowly romantic 5‘ It cannot be countered that what makes me a philosopher is just (in part) that I have these preferences, since that assumes that I had the highly unlikely concatenation of evaluations (Socrates, conversation, Borges, and all the rest) prior to my being a philosopher. 55 None of this is intended to imply that group identities are sufficient for value bestowals. Identity elements in toto may be sufficient, but without an understanding of the range of identity-constituents (an understanding that we have yet to gain, as I argued in Chapter 2 above), such an argument would be difficult to construct. 5" Kubrick’s A Clockwork Orange, Noe’s Irreversible, and Coppola’s Apocalypse Now would be far less desirable were they not revolting. ” This instrumental connection between desire and value is not unique, as it holds for appraisative value as well. 232 relationships — as when, for example, I value my friend’s recovery from illness because it frees up my afternoons from visits to the hospital. Such an instrumental understanding, further, is not even necessary. I may desire that my beloved succeeds at her project, in spite of the fact that her success precludes the success of my project, simply because I value her success. Conceiving of personal identity as a set of practical identities — self-descriptions under which one values herself, her actions and her life, on Korsgaard’s description - suggests many examples supporting the tight conceptual connection between one’s personal identity and the patterns of her bestowals of value. Earlier (in Chapter 2), Socrates’ response to Crito’s offer of flight was taken as exemplary of the high degree of value placed on certain things in virtue of one’s identity. Recall the words of Socrates’ conscience: ...if you go to one of the nearby cities - Thebes or Megara, both are well governed — you will arrive as an enemy to the government. [. . .] Or will you avoid cities that are well governed and men who are civilized? If you do this, will your life be worth living? Will you have social intercourse with them and not be ashamed to talk to them? And what will you say? The same as you did here, that virtue and justice are man’s most precious possessions, along with lawful behavior and the laws?58 Socrates, in his defense of his peculiar (from the point of view of Crito, his friends, and “the majority”) set of values, explicitly appeals to relevant elements of his identity in saying that “not only now but at all times I am the kind of man who listens only to the argument that on reflection seems best to me.”59 That is, because he is a philosopher, he values — above his own life — social intercourse with civilized men, virtue, justice and lawfulness. 5” Plato, Crito, 53c. 59 Plato, Crito, 46b; italics added. 233 Similarly, Hill’s example of the Deferential Wife is illuminating here. She, because of her self-identifying most centrally as my husband ’3 wife came to bestow value exclusively on her husband’s projects. Given a different self-understanding — ‘Kantian moral agent’, as Hill recommended, or ‘feminist’ as others have implied — she would have bestowed value differently. Bestowing value, then, is a telic process. Given that I am a philosopher, I value Borges over Browning, or law over life; given that I care about your happiness, I value the success of your project. In each sort of case, if there is a discrepancy - if, say, I care about your happiness but fail to value the success of your project — the fault lies with the world: specifically, with the value that has not been bestowed on it. Now, thetic processes — like those involved in belief — are subject to a simple cure for personal disunity. A person who believes both, say, that it is raining here right now and it is not raining here right now can remedy the conflicting beliefs by a basic fix to her rationality (namely, an understanding of the principle of noncontradiction) and some empirical information (seeing whether she gets wet when standing outside). But consider an analogical situation involving value bestowal. A person who is a political philosopher (of a certain sort) may value her beloved’s sense of justice, fairness and concern for the less privileged. This selfsame philosopher is also, imagine, a modern Western capitalist, and so values the competitive spirit, the almost effortless ability to extract money from seemingly unprofitable transactions, and the drive to create vast economic empires. While not strictly contradictory, these are certainly conflicting value bestowals (indeed, if the reader sees oddness in the example of a committed capitalist with a sense of justice, the point about conflict has been made). The conflict here is 234 remedied by a change to her personal identity: by resolving the conflict that lies there. Because value bestowal is not a thetic process, the other sorts of solutions — corrections to rationality, improved information — are not relevant here (at least not centrally relevant; a person might bestow value in conflicting ways simply because she is in error about some relevant fact). She cannot value both (that is the conflict), and she values both in virtue of conflicting elements of her identity. To reduce or eliminate the conflict between the relevant identity elements would be to reduce or eliminate the conflicting value bestowals. Thus, because value bestowal is a telic process, it is undermined by the disunification of personal identity in a way that thetic processes are not. This is then, one way in which the valuing that is a part of romantic relationships is undermined by disunity. People do often have a practical solution to the value discrepancies that are the product of a disunified identity: we compartmentalize ourselves and our lives. Some compartmentalization is temporal; since being a parent and being a career-seeker often conflict, a practical sort of resolution is attempted by delimiting certain times during which each identity is to be in force. “It is Friday,” a person might say to her child, “a work day. I can’t go to the park with you today; but tomorrow I have off from being CEO.” Other compartmentalization is social; 1 might value justice in one person, competitiveness in another. Likely a large set of distinct sorts of compartmentalization could be characterized: cultural, similar to that Lugones has described (discussed above in Chapter 2), and as Kipling famously suggests in noting that “East is East, and West is West, and never the twain shall meet”; or gendered, in which value bestowals are made differentially according to the gender or sex of the recipient. 235 I have argued above that such compartmentalization is undesirable. Such compartmentalization is an especially unsatisfactory solution to the value conflicts that can arise relevant to the value bestowal of romantic love. As a mother, I might value your gentleness and concern (since I might suppose these qualities to feature in your interactions with my children), while as an ExxonMobil executive, I might value your estimation of money above all else, and your squashing anything and anybody that gets in the way of profit. Likely, my valuing in these discrepant ways will need to be focused on more than one person: as a mother, I will value one person, and as an ExxonMobil executive, I will value another person. This is how we sometimes manage friendships — one (set of) friend(s) is valued in virtue of certain aspects of our identities, another (set) by another aspect. I might have my rock-climbing friends and also my philosophy friends. Such a conflict-alleviating tactic is not available to the romantic lover, since the typical structure of romantic relationships is quite different from that of friendships. Herein lies the second abovementioned way in which romantic valuation is specially related to identity, insofar as the object of valuation — a romantic partner — is very unlike other objects of valuation. Importantly, romantic relationships are typically both monogamous and encompassing. In being monogamous, the option to value more than one person as a romantic lover is checked. Conflicting valuations cannot be remedied by valuing different things in different beloveds. The encompassing nature of romantic relationships does not directly preclude compartmentalized valuing. This aspect of love is a scalar consideration, for while a person’s relationship to her beloved either is monogamous or it isn’t, the range of aspects 236 with regard to which a person bestows value on her beloved is variable. He might value her for her wit and creativity but not for her sloth."0 There is a limit, though, to how many aspects of one’s beloved go unvalued —- under this (subjectively determined) limit, the individual respect that is part of love diminishes, or disappears. Thus, the more (and more important) aspects of a lover’s identity in virtue of which she cannot value her beloved, and the degree to which she cannot value them, the closer she approaches to not loving at all. A lover, then, is to value her singular beloved across diverse circumstances (circumstances sometimes akin to Lugones’ “worlds”). Were our ideal romantic relationship less than exclusive (most romantic relationships aim at monogamy in the bed, the heart, the home, the nursery, and the checkbook), identity disunity might not be problematic; I value you in the home setting and someone else in the bed — one’s sexual and domestic identities could be unproblematically disunified. But given that our partners are central in many of these as well as other realms, such discrepant valuing is not practically desirable. It is because of this exclusivity characteristic of romantic love — which I have no reason to argue against — that makes identity disunification especially relevant to romantic objects of valuing. An objector might attempt to turn the overall line of argument I’ve presented here on its head: since unified valuing of the sort I’ve defended is enormously practically demanding (and at the limit, perhaps impossible), this implies that we ought to question the desirability of monogamy. Certainly other arguments both in and outside of the philosophical literature have been raised against it. For example, in an article arguing 6" Though as I’ve mentioned, he may value her for her sloth. 237 that monogamous sexual relationships are damaging to individual women’s identities, Christine Overall relates this reasoning: Women, I suggest, are generally expected to incorporate the sexual partner into their own identity [. . .]. A woman who freely takes on a second sexual relationship in addition to the one she already has is likely to feel [an] expansion of her identity, or even a claiming or reclaiming of self."1 Further, women are argued to be differentially affected by the possessive aspect of monogamy — the term literally means ‘one wife’, and polygamy ‘many wives’; the thought that multiple sexual partners are more permissible for men than for women is certainly common. But monogamy need not be thought of as a sexual arrangement, just as — unsurprisingly - marriage need not be thought of as sexual possession. Overall usefully notes the example of Simon de Beauvoir and Jean-Paul Sartre, committed life-partners who were somewhat famously non-monogamous in the sexual sense. Their arrangement “suggests that it is possible and useful to distinguish between sexual exclusivity and possession, on the one hand, and on the other, the creation of a long-term, even life-long project with another person?"2 Beauvoir and Sartre were romantically, though not sexually, monogamous. Not only, then, is romantic monogamy clearly the subject of the bulk of criticisms aimed at monogamy, romantic nonmonogamy is not a live possibility, practically speaking. Monogamy (in the sense of a long-term project, less so in the relatively unimportant sexual sense) is insinuated to an extraordinary degree into religious”, 6’ Overall (1998), p. 9. 62 Overall (1998), p. 6. ‘3 Virtually all contemporary Judeo—Christian sects condemn polygamy (in the sense of multiple contemporaneous marriage), though the Bible clearly does not. 238 I”; psychological” and historical” moral”, social”, political and legal”, biologica understandings of who we are both as specific persons as well as humans generally. I do not think that one or more of these understandings could not be (or will not be, or has not been, or should not be) overturned. I do think, though, that sufficient of these understandings to ensure the continuance of monogamy as the only viable option for workable romantic relationships will continue into the foreseeable future; the magnitude of social revolution that would be necessary to effect the viability of nonmonogamy is enormous. Since, then, the appeal to monogamy in the above argument turns on the practical implications of it on identity and valuing, the claims regarding the fact and practice of romantic monogamy here are axiomatic. In a different world (better in some ways, perhaps, but very different), my arguments, as all arguments, will have less traction than they do here. "4 For example, Bernard Williams’ famous and powerful argument against impartial moral demands appeals to the practical reason given a person by the thought that love “is something which has enough power and even authority to conflict badly with morality” (Williams, 1981, p. 17). Williams’ argument takes as its most forceful example monogamous love and the sometimes morally conclusive fact, simply, “that it is his wife” (p. 18). ‘55 Consider even the multitude of ways in which the physical aspects of the social world are arranged, e. g the fact that automobiles have two front seats (me’nages a trois would be counterproductively uncomfortable even on the drive to dinner). 66 Perhaps the easiest to unravel of all the threads of monogamy, somewhat oddly. 67 Imagine, for example, the vast gulf (more vast than any so far) that would emerge between humans and other animals were we to come to think of ourselves as not importantly pair-forming creatures. 6" For example, while psychological understandings of parent-child relationships are fairly easy modified to accommodate gay or lesbian couples as parents, it is another matter entirely to adapt them to, say, a ‘three fathers and two mothers’ models. Even the literature on relationships between children and their remarried parents is not clearly applicable, nor do 1 see abundant reason to think these sorts of family relationships especially normatively good models. 69 Two thousand years of narrative on love would be outmoded, for instance; imagine the themes of Romeo and Juliet as laughable as the inhabitants of Huxley’s Brave New World found them. 239 Commitment It leaves you baby, if you don’t care for it... - U2, “One” Loving relationships fail for many reasons, and sometimes it is indeed better that the relationship fail. Legal changes that make it more possible to end problematic marriages have undeniably led to many improvements in people’s material lives and in their capacities for self-respect and self-direction. The other side of the story, though, is less uplifting; examples of the damage to persons -— both women and men, and both partners and their families —- by the ending of romantic partnerships can be cited at length. For example, shorter education, unemployment, and more risky health behavior are more common among people, especially among women, with a background of parental divorce”; widowhood is strongly correlated with increased risk of suicide, at least among heterosexual men"; suicide rates are twice as high among divorced or separated than among married persons”. I will offer a conception of commitment that is both consistent with the continuation of love that the partners to the relationship feel no pressing reason to end, and is also instructive as to how to perpetuate a loving relationship that one would on balance desire that it continue. What is it to commit oneself to a partner in a romantic relationship? Such a commitment, which I take to be a variety of the sorts of commitment persons have to aims, projects, and principles, is sometimes taken to share a conceptual core with a 7" Huurre at al (2006). 7’ Luoma and Pearson (2002). 7" Kposowa (2000). 240 promise. On such an interpretation a commitment is a type of self-initiated act of putting oneself under a temporally persisting obligation. A commitment of this sort might be seen as valuable in romantic partnerships, those ongoing associations that are inevitably marked to some degree by doubt, changes of heart and even changes of identity. That is, sometimes the person we love is a different person, although the same incarnate being, than the one we initially fell in love with. Our commitment to that being, or perhaps our commitment to the relationship itself, can help to perpetuate the partnership though such changes, just as a promise serves to perpetuate an obligation through similar changes.73 Understanding commitment between changeable persons as essentially a promise is not without its problems, though. As Derek Parfit writes, I might say, ‘I, and all of my later selves, shall help you.’ But it could be objected that I can bind or commit only my present self. This objection has some force, since it resembles the plausible claim that I can bind or commit only myself. In contrast, no one denies that I can promise you that I shall help other people, such as your children. It is therefore clear that I can promise you that I shall help your later selves.74 Thus it is difficult to understand how commitment, as promising or self-binding, could fulfill its role of helping to perpetuate a relationship through changes within each of the partners. It may even be more difficult to understand than Parfit lets on; in a specifically romantic commitment, the idea that one might promise to love some future person, presently unknown, is implausible.75 This problem may be even more common, too, than Parfit’s view of it might seem to imply. For even if we take such radical changes — Saul-to—Paul conversions —- to be 73 On the role of the valuing of the relationship itself, see Kolodny (2003). 7“ Parfit (1984/1987). p. 327. 75 This suggests that many instances of long-term promises may be in some sense incoherent. I think this is true, but this because many instances of long-term promises involve commitment of the sort explained below. 241 rare, substantive changes occur in within the same person over time. Few promises are categorical — my promise to go to a ball game with you next summer holds unless you cease to enjoy ball games, or the team dissolves, or the like - and so even relatively minor changes in persons can affect the content and perhaps even bindingness of commitments conceived of as promises. It may be that we (as lovers) don’t need commitment to play this role: sometimes one or both partners change so much that it would be best if the partnership dissolved. Furthermore, if the changes of self are not so radical as to recommend the dissolution of the old partnership, there is no obvious reason why one cannot love this new person — the partner who has changed — anew. Although lovers may not, strictly speaking, need commitment“, I take it that within our common practices it is often commitment that perpetuates many romantic partnerships through changes in the partners." Whether holding commitment to be necessary for romantic partnerships or not, philosophical accounts of love often take commitment to be a promise. In arguing that “commitment is precisely what love is not” Robert Solomon claims that “a commitment is an obligation sustained whether or not one has the emotion that originally motivated it.” 78 This is indeed central to the practice of promising: the creation of an obligation and motivation that persists in spite of the failure of the original motivation. Thus I promise to help you move next Saturday so that you can rely on my help even if I wake up that morning with no desire whatsoever to help you move. The promise also helps me by 7" Commitment as promising, that is. As we shall see, the sort of commitment that is a part of love shares structural and functional aspects with the sort of encompassing valuations that I have argued to mark romantic love. 77 The implied claim should not be read too strongly. I do not deny that many relationships persist not because of commitment but rather because of lack of exit freedom due to scarcity of alternative partners, financial pressures, social expectation, and the like. I do not wish to imply that commitment is more prevalent than it actually is. 78 Solomon, p. 27 . 242 giving me a motive that I might otherwise be able to produce in myself only through the psychically difficult process of voluntaristic desire formation. The obligation created by my promise will motivate me whatever my conative stance toward lifting boxes of books is come moving day. Solomon notes that this sort of obligation is a poor basis for motivating the persistence of a romantic partnership.79 Motioning toward the Kantian notion of ‘moral worth’ as being dependent on a good will, Solomon suggests “we might say that the emotional worth of an action is determined precisely by the degree to which we want to do it, regardless of our obligations. And that means that an act of love —- and ultimately love itself — is the very opposite of a commitment of any kind.”80 For the present purposes, I will pass on questioning whether every act associated with love must have emotional worth. We might also ignore the implication that love itself is reducible to acts of love.81 What does stand in need of investigation, though, is whether the thought that love ought to go on only because it is desired is inconsistent with a commitment of any kind. Is there a kind of commitment that is distinct enough from promising that might play an important role in romantic relationships? Richard White, in an investigation of friendship, notes that a person can commit herself implicitly. [W]hen I promise that I will repay the money that you lent me, I create an expectation that is equivalent to a commitment, given the institution of promise-making and all that it entails. Likewise, when I spend time with someone, accept their help, and make myself available to that person, by sharing the more intimate aspects of myself, I am also creating an 7’ Perhaps a stronger indictment of the thought that love might persist as a function of an (externally imposed) obligation is that since loving is not voluntaristic, obligation is not pertinent to it. so Solomon, p. 224. 8‘ And, of course, the categorical cleft between desires and obligations is highly contentious. 243 expectation that is equivalent to a commitment, given the institution of friendship and all that it commonly entails.82 Now, a promise to repay money is explicit. If I borrow money from you without explicitly promising to repay, but under circumstances in which it is reasonably understood that the transaction was a loan and not a gift, I have allowed an expectation to come about in you to the effect that I will repay the money. This is an expectation that I am obligated to fulfill. But it is not a promise — if I fail to repay the money, you may legitimately demand repayment, but only in virtue of my having borrowed it, not in virtue of some promise that is over and above the mere fact of borrowing. The foregoing distinction between promising and commitment — that promising is explicit while commitment need not be — is insufficient to relieve Solomon’s worries about obligatory loving. For even an implicit commitment can create such an obligation. A perhaps more vivid distinction between a promise and a commitment is that while a promise is explicit and thus self—evident, my being committed is something that I can come to find out about myself. Retrospective explanations of my behavior may accurately appeal to commitments of which I was unaware. When one day I wonder why I keep finding myself defending a friend against all those who criticize her, I may come to realize that I have been committed to her. A person can discover herself committed to a cause or principle in a similar manner.83 That commitments can be unintentional is most vividly seen when one intends not to be committed, but finds himself committed nonetheless. A person might join a strongly feminist philosophy department, intending to remain open-minded but skeptical 82 White (1999), p. 82. 83 A person can forget that she promised, of course. The distinction from commitment is that she does not (in non-pathological cases, anyway) later discover that she promised, although she may remember - or fail to remember — that she did. 244 about such an intellectual and political position. After time with his new colleagues, during which he is exposed to many ideas about which he tries to be considerate but resistant, he may come to realize that he has become committed to feminist principles. Another distinction between commitment and promising is that I can un-commit myself, but not un-promise myself. To act contrary to a promise one has made is just to break the promise, to fail to fulfill the obligation the promise entails. The promise has not been unmade, but rather unfulfilled. But a person can undo a commitment without breaking it, by acting contrary to it. This last claim is perhaps less a fact about commitment than it is a point of clarification regarding the details of the notion of commitment being defended here, as I will explain. There do seem to be cases of commitment in which the person who has committed has an obligation to act in accordance with the content of the commitment. Suppose you are halfway up a shaky ladder and 1, walking past, stop unbidden and hold the ladder. Once you continue climbing the now-secure ladder, it might seem clear that I have given you good reason to believe that I have committed (but not promised, of course, since whatever binds me to continue to hold the ladder is an implicit arrangement) to continue to assist you by holding the ladder. To offer a second sort of example, imagine a person who has worked tirelessly for years for some cause — Greenpeace, say — being actively engaged in the ongoing projects of this cause, and even starting many new constituent projects which she and the other members of the organization pursue. A last sort of case: implied romantic interest can be taken to indicate commitment — in a different day and age, a commitment to marry, though now more likely a commitment to focused romantic attention. 245 There are differing responses that show each of the cases not to be cases of commitment in which the person so committed is culpably bound to fulfill the supposed obligation. In the case of the helpful ladder-holder, it is hard to deny that were he to cease to hold the ladder while the need for such assistance remains, he would not be culpable for harm or even for the psychological security he led the ladder-climber to expect. But to suppose that this is a case of commitment implies that analogous cases are too. The expectation that I will not wantonly injure you with my automobile; the obligation a grocer has not to sell food she knows to be spoiled; the resentment you would feel on my holding the door for you only to let it close when you are halfway over the threshold - all these are real and legitimate (the expectation, the obligation, the resentment), but none of these are cases of commitment. To think they are is unrecognizably to alter the term. The second sort of commitment, commitment to a cause, is indeed an example of the sort of commitment outlined here. Further, a member of a cause such as Greenpeace could be expected to answer for her discontinuing her involvement in the project of, for instance, protecting the Minke whales. But this is because the project is a morally laudable one, not simply because she has committed to it. To criticize her abandonment of the whales then reduces to an appeal the sort of moral omission described in the first sort of case, above. The third sort of case — of one who is perceived to have committed to marry or at least romantically to attend to some person — is often enough not a case in which there exists culpability for failure to carry through the so-called commitment. A person who allows an expectation of marriage or continued romantic affection in another has ‘led her 246 on’, to use a common phrase, and is certainly liable to cause resentment for that; he is culpable for whatever harm follows from allowing an illegitimate expectation; he is guilty of deception (intended or not) insofar as he has encouraged or permitted her incorrect interpretation of his behavior and intentions. But all these are cases of something other than failure to carry through on one’s commitment, by a sometimes blameworthy action or set of actions contrary to the commitment. I will return to address this issue shortly, after a bit more necessary discussion of the notion of commitment. To act contrary to a commitment is either to find out that one has become uncommitted or, more actively, to engage in the very process of uncommitting oneself. Suppose I were committed to you and found myself acting contrary to that commitment. If my so acting were somewhat unthinking, that is, if it indeed was a discovery I made about myself that I acted in this way, my acting contrary to my commitment is a sign that I am not committed, either not at all or not in the way I took myself to be. To consciously act contrary to a commitment can be a way of ending the commitment. If I come to desire not to be committed to you any longer, I might end my commitment by acting so to end the conditions that supported the commitment.84 If my commitment to you involved my accompanying you to Botswana for five years while you do your PhD research, I can go about ending my commitment by declining to accompany you to Botswana. To come to desire not to be committed, though, suggests that the commitment has already begun to end, since commitment entails a desire that the commitment continue.85 Thus while a person might actively go about ending the 8“ If I simply come not to desire to be committed (that is, I lose the desire without gaining the opposed desire not to be committed), the commitment may persist of its own inertia for a long time. 85 I will return to further discuss this important feature of commitment. Interestingly, this self-perpetuating nature is common to a number of phenomena of both psyche and character as diverse as persistence and 247 commitment by wrapping up the loose ends, so to speak, the important part of the phenomenon is the discovery — the discovery that one is no longer committed. A person can discover that she herself is committed, and she can also discover that she is not committed. So a commitment need not be conceived of as a sort of promise. Another, more narrow, conception of commitment that understandably makes its way into philosophical meditations on love is that of commitment as exclusivity. Robert Nozick writes of commitment as a special sort of promise, a promise of exclusivity, especially sexual exclusivity. Probing the limits of an economic metaphor for love, he suggests that the energy expended in building a romantic partnership calls for a “guarantee that the other party will continue to trade with you”.86 Indeed, his account of love is aimed at answering the question “why would we want actually to give such a commitment to a particular person, shunning all other partners?“ While commitment may and often does entail exclusivity, this is largely accidental; the entailment is not a conceptual one.88 Consider commitment to ideals. A person can be committed to more than one ideal, as when someone is committed to both vegetarianism and environmental preservation. It is important to notice, though, that she cannot be committed to both environmental preservation and leisure travel of the world by private jet. So while some co-commitments are impossible, being committed to more than one ideal is not automatically ruled out. apathy. Both essentially include intended or expected continuance, since e. g. a person who is feeling globally unmotivated now but self-consciously and currently possesses a motive to act in some way in the future is not apathetic, but rather merely resting. 8" Nozick (1989), p. 78. 87 Nozick ( 1989), p. 77. 88 As mentioned in the previous section, the entailment is practical though very deeply rooted. 248 Regarding romantic commitment to another person the matter is different, given the pervasiveness of monogamous romantic partnerships. Romantic commitment is to one person (and even in what is probably the most common variation on monogamy, what occurs is not simultaneous commitments but rather a violation of the rules of commitment altogether: cheating). Sometimes (often?) one’s commitment to a person is even brought to an end by means of committing to another person. But this is not a basic fact about commitment per se. It is a fact about how romantic relationships tend to figure into our lives. A look at basic locutions might indicate that we have been on the wrong track all along. A person ‘commits herself’ and even ‘commits her life to’ some ideal or some person. These phrases suggest that what is being committed is inseparable from she who is doing the committing. ‘Co-mitto’ is, literally, ‘together, I am handing over’. That which is given is not distinct from the giver — in other words, I give myself. A person committed to an ideal has given herself, not merely her actions, to the ideal. She formulates her life around the ideal, and comes to think of herself as being someone committed to the ideal. Likewise, a person who commits herself to another person in a romantic partnership identifies with the object of her commitment. This is why I do not merely act in husbandly ways - rather, I am a husband. One who commits gives herself by means of a change in her identity. This conception of commitment as giving oneself has to meet the criteria discussed above. It has to explain its own role in perpetuating romantic relationships in spite of the forces of personal change. It must be immune from Solomon’s worry about obligation’s trumping of desire. It must be consistent with the observation that while a 249 person can actively undertake a commitment, it is sometimes a matter of self-discovery that one is committed. It might also illuminate the way in which we do tend to commit only to one person, while we commit to many ideals and projects. The conception of commitment as giving oneself can meet these criteria. There seems initially to be a bit of tension between the notion of giving oneself and the aim of explaining some fact about essentially changing persons. If the selfI am giving in my commitment is different enough from that self that is supposed to be engaged in a persisting relationship, it doesn’t seem that this notion of commitment is going to get us very far. In (nearly) everyday language, the concern is this: your commitment to continue to love me isn’t very helpful if you will soon be someone other than the person who so committed. Put more technically, the commitment C by person X to person Y at time T is not the same as C’ by X' at T2, and so can’t explain the role it is supposed to play in perpetuating relationships. Interestingly, the problem is distinct from the one that undermines commitments as promises in the earlier passage from Derek Parfit. To promise on behalf of my future self, recall, is illegitimate because promises I make bind only myself. Thus, if I change enough (enough to have a different self, that is), no prior promise will be binding on me, since the self that I obligated no longer exists.89 But commitment as giving oneself has a worse possible problem: the self that I gave no longer exists. If this appears to be a problem for the notion of commitment as giving oneself, it is only because of a snapshot view of the self that is being assumed. Such a view 8” There is a different conclusion that could be drawn here: because promises are binding on me, change though I might, I will not become a different person. That is, persisting obligations serve to bind together the parts of my temporal life, effecting a diachronic unification. Whatever the situation regarding promises, I claim that such temporal cohesion is one of the results of commitment. 250 assumes that not only does a person exist as given in a snapshot - that is, at a moment — but also that there might be two portions of a person’s extended life, metaphorically represented by two snapshots, which are in important ways independent of one another. The snapshot of me at birth bears no resemblance whatsoever with that of me receiving my college degree. This is a misleading view of persons. The life of a person is connected, moment to moment, day to day and year to year. These connections are effected by, inter alia, the commitments she makes and discovers.90 Thus, what is being given in commitment is a temporally persisting self, at least that portion of it that remains to unfold (it is not clear how a person might commit herself as she used to be, except by becoming that person again). So not only is commitment a giving of a temporal self, but commitment itself supports diachronic continuity. A person who is committed shapes her desires and plans around the object of her commitment. These desires and plans are themselves temporally extended: plans are just sets of intentions that look into the somewhat distant future (while a person can intend to turn the page of this essay, that is not the proper object of a plan, since it is too near and too simple a goal). Since plans extend forward in time, and commitment is an arrangement of these plans, a person’s commitments extend her forward in time.91 Commitment also has a retrospective element. It is when a person comes to realize that she has unconsciously been forming her own goals around those of another person that she discovers her commitment. We can know our own goals and desires 9° This continuity is also effected by memories, the less-momentous elements of commitments such as goals, desires and projects, and those elements of identity such as group membership and character traits that are attributed both lSt and 3'‘1 personally. To think of diachronic continuity as dependent only on some subset of these items would be a misleading view as well. 9‘ This observation was forcefully made in Williams (198]), Chapter 1. 251 without knowing their structure, the way in which they as a group correspond to some external point of reference. Such ignorance of the collective focus of our desires might in fact be the norm. It is when that focal point comes to light that the fact of one’s own commitment — the fact that one has given herself, in the form of her desires and plans, to a certain object or aim — is discovered. That commitment is a condition of one’s desires, rather than fundamentally opposed to desire, as Solomon assumed, explains two features of commitment: its self- perpetuating nature, and its inherent motivational force that is independent of external obligation. A committed person needs neither stick nor carrot to motivate her to perform actions commensurate with the commitment. This is, simply, because she is committed. Many of her desires collectively aim at the object of her commitment, and so she has the natural motivation of desire satisfaction to motivate her. Not every one of her desires is captured in this arrangement, but insofar as commitment entails the structuring of a substantial subset of one’s desires toward some object, the motivational weight of this subset will tend to win out over isolated recalcitrant urges to the contrary. This view of commitment might seem to allow for a commitment to be unwilling. Someone willingly committed to a certain person can come to knowledge of some fact (often a fact about the object of her commitment) that makes her present commitment unwilling. She might, alternately, discover herself to be committed to someone who she would never have consciously consented to commit to.92 If this is possible, then the motivational picture is not as clear. Someone unwillingly committed would have an 92 I suspect this phenomenon is fairly common, since while love may or may not be blind, falling in love almost certainly is. 252 arrangement of desires with a certain object, but she herself would not approve of this arrangement. Her commitment becomes a stick, moving her against her will. This does not correspond well to common use of the term ‘commitment’, and so recommends an addendum to the account. We simply tend to call something a commitment only if it is willing. This is the case especially in romantic commitments; familiar is the thought of Agathon in Plato’s Symposium: “And the effects [love] has on ’93 Even others are not forced, for every service we give to love we give willingly.’ commitments that come to self-awareness only after their formation would be, I suspect, retroactively reinterpreted as something other than a commitment if its possessor failed to endorse it. Hill’s deferential wife was, ex hypothesi, committed to her husband, though were she to be the subject of either feminist consciousness-raising or a morally positive conversion experience she may (for a time, at least) behave in the same way as before, but she would no longer properly be called ‘committed’. Finding oneself with unwanted (and unshakeable) large-scale arrangements of desires may be one element of ‘identity crises’, but not of commitment. The claim that a person might herself be up against her commitment is plausible only in an inverse proportion to the scope of the commitment. This is because commitments are significant constituents of persons, and so the degree to which a certain commitment constitutes a person is the degree to which she cannot be positioned against it. It is apparent that certain commitments are more self—constitutive than others.94 That is, we give our selves more fully to some objects of commitment. ‘More fully’ is 9" Cited in Solomon and Higgins (1991), p. 21. 9“ Although it is often less obvious which of a person’s commitments are more self-constitutive. 253 apt here, since the commitments that are more important to a person tend to be the ones which are formed from a weightier subset of her identity elements, whether these elements are desires, self-conceptions, group identifications, or narratives. Romantic commitment can be (and is ideally, I would argue) structurally similar to what S.I Benn calls a "core commitment", which is a principle "such that not to act on it would be to disregard, downgrade, or repudiate some central part of the web of one's moral beliefs, which supplies a unity and coherence, perhaps, to all the rest.”95 It should be clear by this point that romantic commitment is not usefully characterized as having the form or function of a promise. If the alternative account of romantic commitment I have presented here is plausible, then it should further be clear that the unity of identity plays an important role in such commitment. A person often identifies with the object of his commitment; I do not act like a husband, but rather become and identify as a husband, and so commitment is not so much an act a person performs as it is a characterization of an important, central part of his identity. I noted that when discovering oneself committed to some person, what is discovered is a particular clustering of desires, narratives, self-conceptions, goals, or other identity elements. Thus, to be committed is in large part just to be unified around, in the case of romantic commitment, another person and that person’s desires and goals. The motivational considerations that serve to distinguish committing from promising also serve to illustrate the internal unification that commitment entails. A person who is committed does not require the sort of external pressure to act that a person who has (merely) promised might, since the committed person’s desires aim at the object 95 Benn (1984), p. 43; emphasis added. 254 of her commitment. Even when an isolated desire is absent, the collective desires that constitute a commitment can motivate. For example, though I may not desire to go to the opera with you per se, I may still be motivated to go if I am committed to you — that is, I desire that you experience the pleasure you get (and I do not get) from attending the opera with me, I desire more generally that your projects not be thwarted, and so on. Important to notice here is that the motivating force of commitment is the motivation of an interconnected cluster of desires; the less cohesive this cluster, the more conflict present in the set of desires, the less apt is the attribution of commitment. Thus commitment, understood properly -— that is, not as a promise but rather as a clustering of identity elements - is itself a form of unity of identity. The issue of conflict in commitment is not limited to conflict within a single commitment. The conception of commitment defended here makes good sense of the conflict between commitments, as in cases of romantic partners with different religious commitments, for example. Because each partner is committed to her religion and to her partner (who is in turn committed to a different and possibly incompatible religion), practical and ideological conflict sometimes arises. An even more direct connection to the precise notion of unity under discussion in the present work is illuminated by the fact that a committed person endorses the identity elements that make up her commitment. I had suggested above that a person who undertakes to end her commitment isn’t doing just that, since the motivation to end a commitment to something occurs only in the relative absence of a commitment to that thing. This is not the case regarding promises, of course — one can consider breaking her promise while still fully in the grips of the obligation the promise entails. But 255 considering a few examples will illuminate both the nature of commitment’s terminus (and the connection with endorsement that this point is made in support of) as well as lending just a bit more support to the unity—based conception of commitment I am defending here. Imagine Karl, who is committed to socialism. He votes socialist, pumps Citgo gasoline into his car”, and shops at co-operatively owned markets and grocers. Karl self- identifies as a member of the Socialist party, and gains a great deal of personal self-worth from this identification; he sometimes thinks that were he a capitalist he could not look himself in the face. Karl desires that society be organized under socialist principles. When these desires falter or are opposed, as might happen after being psychologically manipulated by commercial advertisements, or when affected by people who he respects but who do not share his political views, he distances himself from these desires (‘I feel as if I want that new shiny Proctor and Gamble product, but I really don’t want such a thing’, he tells himself). That is, Karl endorses his desires that society as well as he himself be socialist. Because Karl is committed, he has a great many internal resources with which to perpetuate his commitment. He has many desires that correspond with socialism that trump isolated contrary desires; he has a great many self-conceptions (socialist, co-op member, nationalist oil supporter, and the like) in which to find self-value, and so can afford to forego other possible (and popular) self-conceptions (successful investor, self- made millionaire). 9" Citgo is a subsidiary of Petroleos de Venezuela, the Venezuelan national petroleum company. 256 It is because of the presence of this body of interconnected identity elements that it would be incomprehensible were Karl to end his commitment to socialism while all these elements remain in place.97 Certainly Karl might be motivated to end or alter his commitment by acquiring a powerful desire to control a vast financial empire, for instance. But if we suppose that Karl has this desire (and thus accepts it as his own, rather than distancing himself from it) then we are supposing that Karl’s commitment is already in the process of ending — disintegrating from the rift struck by this incompatible desire. As an illustration of romantic commitment’s similar structure, imagine Jenny, who is committed to Karl. She desires that Karl is happy, and that his projects, by and large, are successful. (Certainly she need not be committed to all the projects, ideals, and desires to which Karl is committed, and likely she is not; if she is committed to none of them, though, it is obscure in what way she is committed to Karl himself.) She conceives of herself as a person who backs Karl and his projects in this way. She gains self-value both from supporting Karl and from the success of his projects, and is thus committed to these projects as well. There are, of course, many ways in which Jenny’s commitment to Karl could be undermined. These ways are diverse and virtually innumerable: Jenny might come to identify with projects aligned with capitalist economic relations, and thus be unable to identify with socialist aims; were Karl’s sexual infidelity to move Jenny to end her commitment to Karl she might continue to endorse socialism but cease to desire that socialism qua Karl’s project be realized; Karl may become afflicted with some sort of 97 lncomprehensible, at any rate, in the normal course of events. Saul-to-Paul sorts of conversions involve a wholesale shifting of desires of both the first and second order, and so are explicable in terms of a change into a different person. 257 dementia or psychosis that destroys his ability even to have such projects to which Jenny could be committed.98 But for Jenny to continue to endorse socialism and Karl’s projects as originally described and at the same time to seek to end her commitment to Karl is inexplicable. The story of Jenny and Karl serves well as a point of return to the unanswered question regarding the culpability of one who has ended her commitment. Surely in some of the hypothetical paths of Jenny and Karl, certain ways in which Jenny’s commitment comes to an end are occasions for resentment from Karl. Were Jenny to end her commitment in virtue of her identifying rather with capitalist goals, or with the projects of some other person, or come to realize that she cannot identify with any male romantic partner’s projects when she discovers that she is a lesbian, Karl’s resentment seems warranted (even when Jenny abandons an Alzheimer’s stricken Karl who cannot experience resentment, it would seem warranted). Depending on the back-story, Jenny is certainly the proper subject of disapprobation if, for instance, she deserts the socialist project when she realizes that as a capitalist she could have a servant, a BMW and an increased power to direct other people’s lives at will. Such disapprobation need not be essentially moral; she might be legitimately charged with a failure of personal integrity for giving up her personal principles under pressure. Other cases will be more plainly moral: completely to abandon one’s romantic partner to dementia exhibits a profound lack of respect, a merely instrumental use of other persons that we tend to think morally heinous. 9" The account of commitment defended here denies that a person can, strictly speaking, be committed to someone who is dead, comatose, or severely demented, though he may be committed to that someone’s memory, her imagined or remembered projects (as Benigno was committed to Alicia in Almodovar’s (2002) Talk to Her), or to her care. 258 Commitment is thus one mode by which we organize our identities, and thus our lives. It is the content of our commitments -- the goals to which and the persons to whom we commit - that has moral standing. But although there is no culpability to ending a commitment simpliciter (again, commitments not being promises), there is at least one thought motivating their continuance. This thought is the barrenness of a life without commitment -— to projects, to causes personal and political, to principles and especially to other persons. 259 —6— Concluding thoughts In oneself lies the whole world... -- J iddu Krishnamurti The wide range of concerns in the foregoing chapters have taken us time and 1' again outside the typical ambit of philosophical discussions of personal identity; if there is truth in Krishnamurti’s observation, then the breadth of any substantial discussion of the person is expected, even necessary. A very brief reflection on where the arguments of this work were aimed will, I hope, make my central conclusions individually and jointly perspicuous. The one guiding thought throughout has been this: there are reasons thus far unmentioned in the philosophical literature on personal identity both to believe beneficial and to strive for a unified personal identity — and so the unification of one’s identity is an ideal toward which, for the reasons I offer, one might well strive. The sense of ‘unified personal identity’ I have defended is the relative absence of subjectively perceived internal conflict among the elements of one ’s personal identity, elements which include but are not limited to desires, narratives, principles, group identifications and self- conceptions. More specifically, I have argued that the most prevalent criticisms of unified identity views can be answered. Specifically, worries about the coherence of hierarchical 260 accounts of personal identity, the inadequacy of such identity to ground a person’s real interests, the alleged rigidity of a unified identity, and the damaging political consequences of promoting such a view were all mollified, and some I suggested are quite possibly groundless. I defended the ideal of identity unity for the role it plays in supporting personal autonomy primarily by showing how a structural account of autonomy — on which a person acts autonomously when she acts on desires she endorses — is a more plausible account than are either procedural or content-specific views. I explained how a better philosophical understanding of the notion of integrity (an understanding that I take to have value not merely within the context of the current project) enables us to see that when a person acts with integrity, she acts on principles — ‘principles’ being a sort of shorthand term for those clusters of things with which a person identifies that are unified into coherent, conflict-free clusters. Thus when a person acts with integrity she acts as a person whose identity is, at least locally, unified. Finally, I argued that the romantic lover has two pressing reasons to avoid a disunified identity. Since the mode of valuing of one’s beloved that is most theoretically plausible and socially beneficial is the telic process of value bestowal, identity disunity undermines such valuing in a way that does not affect the practice of appraising value. Lastly, I argued that commitment between lovers — that is, that state of organizing large measures of one’s life around her beloved — is itself tantamount to the unity of identity. Thus to value one’s beloved, a person best have a unified identity; insofar as she is committed, she does have such an identity. 261 I have defended the views here against what I take to be the strongest criticisms the philosophical literature offers. I do not suspect that my arguments here have been universally convincing, nor do I suppose that I have not missed substantive criticisms both extant and yet to come. It may come to be demonstrated that there is a feature of good lives, something more important than acting with autonomy, integrity, and love, that is possible only in the presence of substantial conflict between the various elements with which a person identifies. But insofar as that has yet to be demonstrated, and as autonomy, integrity and love do feature prominently into satisfying, good lives, we ought best to hold up the unity of personal identity as an idea]. 262 Bibliography American Psychological Association (2002). Ethical Principles of Psychologists and Code of Conduct. Arpaly, Nomy (2002). Unprincipled Virtue: an Inquiry into Human Agency. Oxford UP. Babbitt, Susan E. (1996). Impossible Dreams: Rationality, Integrity, and Moral Imagination: Westview Press. Barthes, Roland and Lionel Duisit (1975). “An Introduction to the Structural Analysis of Narrative”, New Literary History, Vol. 6, No. 2. Baumrind, Diana (1964). ”Some Thoughts on Ethics of Research: After Reading Milgram’s “Behavioral Study of Obedience”.” American Psychologist, 19, pp. 421-423. Benn, SJ. (1984) “Persons and Values: Reasons in Conflict and Moral Disagreement”, Ethics, Vol. 95, no. 1, pp. 20-37. Benson, Paul (1991). “Autonomy and Oppressive Socialization”, Social Theory and Practice, Vol. 17, No. 3, 385-408. Birenbaum, Arnold (1984). “Toward a Theory of Role Acquisition”, Sociological Theory, Vol. 2, pp. 315-328. Blake, Micheal (2001). “Geeks and Monsters: Bias Crimes and Social Identity”, Law and Philosophy, Vol. 20, no. 2, pp. 121-139. Borges, Jorge Luis (1970). “The Aleph”, The Aleph and Other Stories. E.P. Dutton and Co. Brison, Susan J. (2002). Aftermath: Violence and the Remaking of a Self. Princeton UP. Calhoun, Cheshire (1995). “Standing for Something”, Journal of Philosophy, May 1995: 235-260. Christman, John (1987). “Autonomy: A Defense of the Split-Level Self”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, Vol 25, pp. 281-294. Christman, John (1988). “Constructing the Inner Citadel: Recent Work on the Concept of Autonomy”, Ethics, Vol. 99, No. 1, 109-124. Christman, John (1991). “Autonomy and Personal History”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 21, no. 1, pp. 1-24. 263 Christman (2004). “Relational Autonomy, Liberal Individualism, and the Social Constitution of Selves”, Philosophical Studies, Vol. 117, No. 1-2, 143-164. Cukor, George (1944). Gaslight (film), Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer. Dancy, Jonathan (2004). Ethics Without Principles, Oxford, Clarendon Press. DeAngelis, Tori (2003). “Why We Overestimate Our Competence”, Monitor on Psychology, Vol. 34, No. 2. Dennett, Daniel (1989). “The Origins of Selves”, Cogito, 3, pp. 163-173. Dennett, Daniel (1992). “The Self as a Center of Narrative Gravity”, in F. Kessel, P. Cole and D. Johnson, eds, Self and Consciousness: Multiple Perspectives, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Dubowski, Sandi Sirncha and Susan Korda, dirs. (2001). Trembling Before G—d. New Yorker Films. Dworkin, Gerald (1970). “Acting Freely”, Nous, Vol. 4, No. 4, pp. 367-383. Dworkin, Gerald (1988). The Theory and Practice of A utonomy, Cambridge UP. Einstein, Albert (1961). Relativity: the Special and the General Theory, Crown Publishers. Ensler, Eve (1998). The Vagina Monologues. Random House. Frady, Marshall (2002). Martin Luther King Jr. Penguin. Frankfurt, Harry (1988). The Importance of What We Care About. Cambridge UP, 1988. Frankfurt, Harry (1999). Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge UP. Frankfurt, Harry (2004). The Reasons of Love. Princeton University Press. Friedman, Marilyn ( 1986). “Autonomy and the Split-level Self”, Southern Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 24, pp. 19-35. Frye, Marilyn (1983). The Politics of Reality. The Crossing Press. Hill, Thomas (1973). “Servility and Self-Respect”, The Monist, 57, 87-104. Hitchens, Christopher (2003). “Mommie Dearest: The Pope Beatifies Mother Teresa, a Fanatic, a Fundamentalist, and a Fraud.” Slate, October 20, 2003. Humberstone, LL. (1992). “Direction of Fit”, Mind, vol. 101, no. 401, pp. 59-83. 264 Hume, David (1739/1978). A Treatise of Human Nature. L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H.Niddich, eds. Oxford UP. Huurre, T., H. Junkkari and H. Aro (2006). “Long-term Psychosocial effects of parental divorce: A follow-up study from adolescence to adulthood”, European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience, 256, 4, pp. 256-263. Kolodny, Niko (2003). “Love as Valuing a Relationship”, Philosophical Review, 112, 2, pp. 135-190. Korsgaard, Christine (1996), The Sources of Normativity, Cambridge UP. Kposowa, Augustine J. (2000). “Marital status and suicide in the National Longitudinal Mortality Study”, Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 54, pp. 254- 261. Levenkron, Steven (2000). Anatomy of Anorexia, Norton. Locke, John (1690/1964). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, A.D. Woozley, ed. Meridian Publishing. Lugones, Maria (2003). Pilgrimages/Peregrinajes: Theorizing Coalitions Against Multiple Oppressions. Rowman and Littlefield. Luoma. Jason B. and Jane L. Pearson (2002). “Suicide and Marital Status in the United States, 1991-1996: Is Widowhood a Risk Factor?” American Journal of Public Health, 92, 9, pp. 1518-1522. MacIntyre, Alasdair (1981). After Virtue, University of Notre Dame Press. Martel, Yann (2001). Life of Pi. Harcourt. Mason, Gail (2002). The Spectacle of Violence: Homophobia, gender, and knowledge. Routledge. McF all, Lynne (1987). “Integrity”, Ethics, 98; 5-20. Mehta, Ved (1993). Mahatma Gandhi and His Apostles. Yale UP. Meyers, Diana Tietjens (1989). Self, Society and Personal Choice, Columbia University Press. Meyers, Diana Tietjens (2000). “Intersectional Identity and the Authentic Self” in Relational Autonomy, Mackenzie and Stoljar, eds. Oxford UP: 151-180. Milgram, Stanley (1963). “Behavioral Study of Obedience.” Journal of Abnormal Social Psychology, vol. 67, no. 4, pp. 371-378. 265 Milgram, Stanley (1964). “Issues in the Study of Obedience: Reply to Baumrind.” American Psychologist, 19, pp. 848-852. Milgram, Stanley (1977). “Subject Reaction: The Neglected Factor in the Ethics of Experimentation.” The Hastings Center Report, vol. 7, no. 5, pp. 19-23. Mills, Charles (2004). “Ideal Theory as Ideology” in Moral Psychology: Feminist Ethics and Social Theory, Peggy DesAutels and Margaret Urban Walker, eds. Rowman and Littlefield. Mooney, Edward F. (1986). “Abraham and dilemma: Kierkegaard’s teleological suspension revisited”, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 19, pp. 23-41. Mullin, Amy (1995). “Selves, diverse and divided: Can feminists have diversity without multiplicity?” Hypatia, Vol. 10, No. 4, pp. 1-31. Murdoch, Iris (1970) The Sovereignty of Good. Routledge. Nelson, Hilde Lindemann (2001). Damaged Identities, Narrative Repair, Cornell UP. Nelson, Hilde Lindemann (2002). “What Child is This?” The Hastings Center Report, vol. 32, no. 6, pp. 29-40. Nolan, Christopher, dir. (2000) Memento [motion picture]. Columbia Tri Star. Nozick, Robert (1989). The Examined Life: Philosophical Meditations. Simon and Schuster. Overall, Christine (1998). “Monogamy, Nonmonogamy, and Identity”, Hypatia, vol. 13, no. 4, pp. 1-17. Parfit, Derek (1984/1987). Reasons and Persons (1987 reprint with corrections), Oxford University Press. Puccetti, Roland (1973). “Brain Bisection and Personal Identity”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 24, No. 4, pp. 339-355. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice, Harvard UP. Roethke, Theodore (1974). Straw for the Fire. Selected and arranged by David Wagoner, Anchor Books. Schechtman, Marya (1996). The Constitution of Selves, Cornell UP.. Scheman, Naomi (1993). Engenderings: Constructions of Knowledge, Authority, and Privilege. Routledge; Ch 16: “The Body Politic/T he Impolitic Body/Body Politics”, 185-192. 266 Scheman, Naomi (1997). “Queering the Center by Centering the Queer: Reflections on T Transsexuals and Secular Jews” in Feminists Rethink the Self Diana Tietjens Meyers, ed. Westview Press. Singer, Irving (1987). The Nature of Love: Volume 3, The Modern World, University of Chicago Press. Singer, Irving (1994). The Pursuit of Love, Johns Hopkins UP. Solomon, Robert C. and Kathleen Higgins, eds (1991). The Philosophy of (Erotic) Love. UP of Kansas. Strawson, Galen (2004). “Against Narrativity”, Ratio, Vol. 17, no. 4. pp. 428-452. Styron, William (1979). Sophie ’s Choice, Random House. Twain, Mark (1869). The Innocents Abroad. Velleman, J. David (1999). “Love as a Moral Emotion”, Ethics, 109: 338-3 74. Walker, Margaret Urban (1998). Review of Susan Babbitt’s Impossible Dreams, in Hypatia, Vol. 13, No. 3, pp. 168-173. Ward, Mylene, Larry Gruppen and Glenn Regehr (2002). “Measuring Self- Assessment: Current State of the Art”, Advances in Health Science Education, 7, pp. 63-80. White, Richard (1999). “Friendship and Commitment”, Journal of Value Inquiry, 33,1, pp. 79-88. Wilcox, W. Bradford and Steven L. Nock (2006). “What’s Love Got to Do With It? Equality, Equity, Commitment and Women’s Marital Quality”, Social Forces, Vol.84, no. 3, pp. 1321-1345. Williams, Bernard (1973) “A Critique of Utilitarianism”, Utilitarianism for and Against, J .J .C. Smart and Bernard Williams: Cambridge UP. Williams, Bernard (1981). Moral Luck, Cambridge UP. Wolf, Susan (1982). “Moral Saints”, The Journal of Philosophy, 79, 8: 419-439. 267 EEEEEEEEEEEE llljlllllfllflllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllllll 2956 6