PLACE IN RETURN BOX to remove this checkout from your record. TO AVOID FINES return on or before date due. MAY BE RECALLED with earlier due date if requested. DATE DUE DATE DUE DATE DUE 5’08 KzlProlecc8-PresICIRCIDaIeDue.indd WHY DO HIGH COURT JUDGES JOIN? JOINING BEHAVIOR AND AUSTRALIA’S SERIATIM TRADITION By Rebecca Danielle Wood A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University In partial fiJlfillment of the requirements For the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Political Science 2008 ABSTRACT WHY DO HIGH COURT JUDGES JOIN? JOINING BEHAVIOR AND AUSTRALIA’S SERIATIM TRADITION By Rebecca Danielle Wood The American majority opinion tradition is the fulcrum on which theories of joining behavior on the US. Supreme Court are balanced (e. g., Hammond et a1. 2005; Maltzman et a1. 2000; Segal and Spaeth 2002). Because majority opinions alone carry the weight of precedent in the American system, they provide a strong motivation for the Justices to assent to a common set of reasons. The High Court of Australia, however, operates under a seriatim opinion tradition, wherein each Justice writes a separate set of reasons for his or her decision. Even though the Australian system does no explicitly encourage joint opinions, the High Court produces a substantial—and increasing— number of j oint opinions each year. The goal of this dissertation is to explain why Justices on the High Court engage in what appears to be unnecessary joining behavior. Why do they accept the reasons of their colleagues when there is no institutional reward for doing so? This dissertation builds upon the existing literature by developing and testing a model of j oining behavior that is applicable in courts using a seriatim opinion tradition. Using data from the High Courts Judicial Database (Haynie et al. 2007), this dissertation uses a time series fractional cointegration analysis to provide support for the assumption that the seriatim tradition is functioning properly in the High Court of Australia. In other words, the analysis finds no evidence of an underlying consensual norm that discourages individual Justices from writing separate opinions. A series of logistic regression analyses reveal patterns in joining behavior on the High Court. Justices on the High Court engage in joining behavior because 1) the Chief Justice successfully facilitates such behavior, 2) the Justices are able to find coauthors with similar policy views to their own, 3) the case at hand is simple and/or not of great importance, and 4) because the Justices are accustomed to and comfortable with the process of collegial decision making. Copyright by Rebecca Danielle Wood 2008 To Marvin and Mary Wood ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Like most dissertations, this one would not have been possible without the support of faculty, friends and family. My advisor Reginald S. Sheehan maintained a consistent level of confidence in me that I did not always believe I deserved. He gave me the freedom to pursue the questions I found most interesting in the manner I found most compelling. He provided me with the opportunity to work on the High Courts Judicial Database (Haynie et al. 2007). Not only did this give me the experience of working on a large collaborative data project, but it also inspired the research in this dissertation. Reggie also made it possible for me to travel to Australia as part of Michigan State University’s study abroad program. He has been my sounding board and my advocate. Had it not been for C. Neal Tate, I would not have pursued my Ph.D. at all. His Proseminar in Public Law at the University of North Texas introduced me to the scientific study of judges and courts, and his encouragement convinced me that I might be able to contribute to this field. He taught me to think about judicial behavior in a scientific way, and his enthusiasm for the enterprise continues to be an inspiration. In the relatively short time that I have worked with Thomas H. Hammond, he has had an enormous impact on this project. His comments on the later versions of this work challenged me to be ever more precise, and this dissertation is much better for his efforts. I also greatly appreciate the contributions—and the patience—of Kenneth C. Williams and Christopher E. Smith. Some of the research for this dissertation took place during my time as a Visiting Scholar at the Australian National University Faculty of Law. My thanks to the ANU vi Faculty of Law for their support, and especially to Fiona Wheeler and Michael Coper who helped me to secure the position. I also want to thank the Australian scholars and practitioners who took the time to introduce me to the subtleties of judi cial behavior on the High Court. Among them are Chief Justice Sir Anthony Mason, Justice Michael Kirby, Andrew Lynch, John McMillan, Waanda McCarthy, and George Williams. Harold J. Spaeth spent a great deal of time coaching me during the early phases of this project. His comments on my early research gave me the confidence to submit and present my first solo conference paper, and I am very grateful for that. Patrick McLeod provided me with much-needed tools to make sense of my mountains of data, and Harold Clarke taught me how best to use those tools. Frank Feigert taught me what I deeded to know in order to be a positive force in the lives of my students, as did Donald Songer (if from a distance). Susan Johnson and RoHan Williams saw me through many of the rough spots, be they data-related or otherwise. Kris Dunn provided invaluable support, especially in the last-minute formatting debacle. I owe a debt to my fellow graduate students, particularly those involved with the more recent incarnations of the department softball team. My family provided unwavering support and understanding during this process. Amanda Vannieuwenhoven provided much late-night assistance sorting through files of coding sheets. Aaron Wood provided the logistical support for my world travels. My mother Mary Wood read countless drafts at a time when volunteers for the task were hard to come by. She, along with my father Marvin Wood, dropped everything to help me on innumerable occasions. They have been the enthusiastic team in my corner since the beginning, and I cannot thank them enough for it. vii TABLE OF CONTENTS List of Tables ..................................................................................................................... xi List of Figures ................................................................................................................... xii List of Figures ................................................................................................................... xii Introduction: Joining Behavior and the Australian High Court .......................................... 1 Chapter One: Practice and Procedure in the High Court .................................................... 2 The Institutional Context .............................................................................................. 2 Staffing the High Court ................................................................................................ 5 The Legal Profession ............................................................................................. 6 The Selection Process ............................................................................................ 9 The Resulting Judges ........................................................................................... 10 High Court Jurisdiction ............................................................................................... 14 Original Jurisdiction ............................................................................................ 14 Appellate Jurisdiction .......................................................................................... 18 High Court Jurisdiction and the Privy Council ........................................................... 19 Daily Operating Procedures ........................................................................................ 24 Setting the Agenda .............................................................................................. 24 The Panel System ................................................................................................ 27 Hearing Cases on the Merits ................................................................................ 30 The Decision and Reasons ................................................................................... 36 Practice and Procedure in Comparative Perspective .................................................. 42 Chapter Two: A Brief History of the High Court of Australia ......................................... 44 The Early History of the High Court .......................................................................... 44 Establishing an Identity (1903-1919) .................................................................. 45 Growing Pains (1919-1950) ................................................................................ 51 Time to Regroup (1950-1964) ............................................................................. 58 The Modern High Court ............................................................................................. 60 The Barwick Court (1964-1981) ......................................................................... 60 The Gibbs Court (1981-1987) ............................................................................. 67 The Mason Court (1987-1995) ............................................................................ 71 The Brennan Court (1995—1998) ......................................................................... 77 The Gleeson Court (1998-present) ...................................................................... 83 The High Court Centenary and Beyond ..................................................................... 85 Chapter Three: Existing Theories of Joining Behavior .................................................... 89 The American Literature ..................................................................................... 89 viii Judging Across the World ................................................................................... 95 Australian Jurimetrics and Beyond ..................................................................... 98 Conceptualizing Joining Behavior ............................................................................ 106 Decision Patterns ............................................................................................... 107 Joining Behavior in the US. Supreme Court .................................................... 108 Joining Behavior in the Context of the High Court ........................................... 120 Chapter Five: Consensual Norms on the High Court ..................................................... 122 Defining Types of Opinion-Writing Behavior ......................................................... 123 Terminology ...................................................................................................... 123 A lexicon for describing High Court opinion-writing ....................................... 125 Consensual Norms in the Literature ......................................................................... 127 Consensual Norms in the Australian Context ........................................................... 131 The Norm of Concurring Opinions ................................................................... 132 Dissent and the Consensual Norm ..................................................................... 138 An Underlying Norm of Consensus in Australia? ............................................. 144 Chapter Six: The Production of Joint Opinions ............................................................... 157 Joining Behavior and Case-Level Characteristics .................................................... 157 Characteristics of the Decision Making Environment ....................................... 158 Case Characteristics ........................................................................................... 168 The Disposition of the Case .............................................................................. 179 Joining Behavior and Judge-Level Characteristics ................................................... 182 Approach to the Working Environment ............................................................ 182 Social Background Characteristics .................................................................... 185 Chapter Seven: Data and Measures ................................................................................ 189 Joining Behavior on the High Court ......................................................................... 189 Operational Definitions of Joining Behavior .................................................... 193 Predicting the Single Opinion for the Court ...................................................... 195 Predicting Other Joint Opinions ........................................................................ 197 Operational Hypotheses ............................................................................................ 198 Characteristics of the Decision Making Environment ....................................... 198 Case Characteristics ........................................................................................... 205 Outcome of the Case ......................................................................................... 211 Judge Characteristics ......................................................................................... 213 Approach to the Working Environment ............................................................ 213 Social Background Characteristics .................................................................... 215 Controlling for Panel and Coalition Size ........................................................... 216 Chapter Eight: Analyzing Joining Behavior on the High Court ..................................... 222 Methodology ............................................................................................................. 222 Models of Single-Opinion Dispositions ............................................................ 225 Case-Level Models of Joining Behavior ........................................................... 227 Judge-Level Models of Joining Behavior .......................................................... 234 Joining Behavior on the Gleeson Court ............................................................. 241 ix Chapter Nine: Conclusion and Future Research ............................................................. 256 Evaluating the Findings ............................................................................................ 257 Appendix A: Judges of the High Court of Australia by Seat .......................................... 261 Appendix B: Coding Classifications ............................................................................... 262 Bibliography .................................................................................................................... 266 LIST OF TABLES Table 1 - Justice Attributes on the Barwick Court .......................................................... 64 Table 2 - Justice Attributes on the Gibbs Court .............................................................. 69 Table 3 - Justice Attributes on the Mason Court ............................................................ 74 Table 4 - Justice Attributes on the Brennan Court .......................................................... 81 Table 5 - Justice Attributes on the Gleeson Court .......................................................... 84 Table 6 - Unit Root Tests on Log-Transformed Separate Opinions per OWO ................................................................................................................. 150 Table 7 - Unit Root Tests of Log-Transformed Separate Opinions per 100 Opinions ............................................................................................................ 151 Table 8 -— Unit Root Tests and Robinson's Gaussian Semiparametric Estimates of d (OWO Data) .............................................................................. 154 Table 9 - Cointegrating Regression of Dissents on Concurrences ............................... 155 Table 10 — Descriptive Statistics for Model VariablesT ................................................ 201 Table 11 - Correlation Coefficients between Control and Independent Variables ........................................................................................................... 218 Table 12 - Collinearity Diagnosticsl ............................................................................. 220 Table 13 - Case-Level Logistic Regression Predicting Single-Opinion Dispositions ....................................................................................................... 224 Table 14 — Case-Level Logistic Regression Predicting Joining Behavior ................... 228 Table 15 — Judge-Level Logistic Regression Predicting Joining Behavior .................. 233 Table 16 — Judge-Level Logistic Regression Predicting Joining Behavior on the Gleeson Court ........................................................................................ 242 Table 17 - Individual Models of Joining Behavior on the Gleeson Court .................... 245 Table 18 - Reduced Individual Justice Models of Joining Behavior on the Gleeson Court ................................................................................................... 246 Table 19 - Performance of Hypotheses in Seven Models of Joining Behavior ............................................................................................................ 252 xi LIST OF FIGURES Figure 1 - Original Jurisdiction Cases as a Percent of Reported Cases: 1965-2002 ........................................................................................................... 17 Figure 2 - Number of Privy Council Cases in Commonwealth Law Reports by Year .................................................................................................. 23 Figure 3 - Average Panel Size by Year ........................................................................... 31 Figure 4 - Total Number of Cases by Year ..................................................................... 32 Figure 5 - Percentage of Cases with at least One Joint Opinion ..................................... 40 Figure 6 - Concurring and Joint Opinions in Majority per 100 Reported, 1965-2002 ......................................................................................................... 135 Figure 7 - Percentage of Cases with Concurrences and Joint Opinions in Majority, 1965-2002 ......................................................................................... 136 Figure 8 - Concurring and Dissenting Opinions per Opinion-Writing Opportunity ....................................................................................................... 149 Figure 9 - Opinion to Vote Ratio on the High Court over Time ................................... 190 Figure 10 - Percentage of Unanimous Cases with Single-Opinion Dispositions ....................................................................................................... 1 97 Figure 11- Percentage of Cases with Any Joint Opinion and Smaller Coalitions Only ................................................................................................. 198 Figure 12 - Liberalism Scores by Party of Appointing Prime Minister ........................ 205 Figure 13 - Predicted Probabilities of a Single-Opinion Disposition by Panel Size .......................................................................................................... 226 Figure 14 - Predicted Probabilities of Joint Opinions by Panel Size ............................ 229 Figure 15 - Predicted Probabilities of a Joint Opinion by Panel Liberalism ................ 230 Figure 16 - Predicted Probabilities of a Joint Opinion by Panel Diversity ................... 231 Figure 17 - Predicted Probabilities of a Joint Opinion in Criminal Cases by Panel Liberalism ............................................................................................... 232 Figure 18 - Predicted Probabilities of a Decision to Join by Panel Size ....................... 235 xii Figure 19 - Predicted Probabilities of a Decision to Join by Ideological Distance ...................... ' ....................................................................................... 237 Figure 20 - Predicted Probabilities of Joining Behavior by Nonparty Participation Rate .............................................................................................. 238 Figure 21 - Predicted Probabilities of Decision to Join across Approach to Working Environment ...................................................................................... 239 Figure 22 - Predicted Probabilities of Decision to Join on Gleeson Court by Coalition Size ............................................................................................... 243 Figure 23 - Scree Plot for Gleeson Court Conditional Distance Matrix ....................... 248 Figure 24 - Derived Configuration of Joining Behavior Conditional on Votes ................................................................................................................. 249 Figure 25 - Liberalism Scores of Gleeson Court Justices by Party of Appointing Prime Minister ............................................................................... 251 Figure 26 - Average Number of Decisions to Join over Previous Five Cases, by Justice ............................................................................................... 254 xiii INTRODUCTION: JOINING BEHAVIOR AND THE AUSTRALIAN HIGH COURT It is because of this basic need for mutually confirmatory studies that quantitative analysis must finally operate at an international level. — Anthony Blackshield (1972, 64) The research presented in this dissertation adapts existing judicial behavior theories to courts with varied institutional arrangements. Specifically, theories of joining behavior that have been developed almost exclusively to explain majority opinion coalitions on the US. Supreme Court will be generalized to explain joining behavior on the High Court of Australia—a court without a majority opinion tradition. The High Court is producing an increasing number of joint opinions each year. The goal of this research is to explain why Justices on the High Court engage in what seems to be unnecessary joining behavior. Why do they accept the reasons of their colleagues when there is no institutional reward for doing so? To address this question, this dissertation is organized into the following chapters. Chapter One provides an introduction to practice and procedure on the High Court. Chapter Two presents a brief history of the High Court, with a special focus on the issues and personalities that have shaped the modern Court. Chapter Three focuses on the foundations for a theory of joining behavior. Chapter Four presents an econometric analysis of consensual norms on the High Court. Chapter Five presents eleven conceptual hypotheses derived from the existing theories, but adapted for the unique characteristics of the High Court. Chapter Six provides operational hypotheses and describes the data and measures used to test them. Chapter Seven conducts a series of tests of these operational hypotheses and presents the results. Finally, Chapter Eight offers some concluding remarks about joining behavior on the High Court. CHAPTER ONE: PRACTICE AND PROCEDURE IN THE HIGH COURT As in the case of the United States, we believe that the decisions of this court will breathe a living spirit into the dry bones of a parchment constitution, and that your names will live in history with those of the illustrious exponents of American constitutional law. — Govemor-General Tennyson to the Court in 1903 (Bennett 1980, 23) The Govemor-General’s remarks at the commissioning of the first three Justices of the High Court illustrate the overt comparisons already being made between that institution and the one on which it was modeled: the US. Supreme Court. While the High Court of Australia was fashioned largely in the image of the US. Supreme Court, there are many differences in practice and procedure between the two courts (Hunt 1930). Because most theories of judicial decision-making behavior have been designed to study Justices on the US. Supreme Court (Atkins 1991), institutional differences make it inappropriate to transplant these theories wholesale to judges in other courts (Tate 1983). After a brief review of the structure of the Australian government, some important institutional characteristics of the High Court are outlined. These include the broad jurisdiction of the High Court, the way Justices are selected, the structure of the legal profession from which they arise, and the daily operating procedures that govern the handling of the Court’s business. The Institutional Context The structure of the Australian government has been described as a “Washminster” system—part Westminster parliamentary government and part Washington-inspired separation of powers (Thompson 1980). This arrangement is detailed in the Commonwealth Constitution, which was enacted by an act of the British Parliament1 and 1 Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act 1900 (Imp). took effect on January 1, 1901. Australian independence came as a peaceful agreement between Britain and the Colonies, and the new government maintained its ties to the British crown. As such, Australia is a constitutional monarchy with the Queen of England as its nominal sovereign. So friendly was this relationship that the new Australian government invited King George V to open its inaugural parliamentary session on May 9, 1901 (Hirst 1998). Australia adopted a federal structure similar to the American government. The national legislature is a bicameral parliament made up of a lower house (the House of Representatives), an upper house (the Senate), and the Queen, who is typically represented by a Governor-General chosen on the advice of the Australian Prime Minister. Members of the House of Representatives are elected in single-member districts based on population and using preferential voting. In keeping with the Westminster tradition, the leader of the party or coalition with a majority in the House becomes the Prime Minister. The Prime Minister forms his government by assembling a Cabinet and other ministers from among the members of his own party in Parliament. This combination of parliamentary government with a maj oritarian electoral design encourages a strong two-party system, where party discipline is maintained through the unitary nature ofthe legislature and the executive (Galligan 1987). Because the House is the origin of all supply (or appropriation) bills, the party in control of the House essentially controls the government. The Senate was modeled not on the British House of Lords but on the US. Senate (Meek 1999). Each of the six states is allotted 12 senators, and the mainland territories each have two.2 Senators serve six-year terms. The intent was for the Senate to represent the interests of the states (Hirst 1998). Unlike the US. Senate, Australian senators are chosen through a proportional voting system using statewide multi-member districts. This arrangement promotes the proliferation of political parties, such that the party composition of the Senate is much more diverse than the largely two-party House (Lijphart 1999). This diversity contributes to the Senate’s role as a house of review, as it often results in divided government—something otherwise rare in parliamentary systems (Sawer 1999). The government cannot pass legislation—including supply bills—without the assent of the Senate. When the Senate refuses to pass supply bills, the government may be forced to dissolve Parliament in order to keep from a government shutdown. In this way, the structure of the Senate adds a separation of government power that is not found in the British Westminster system. Some argue that the most important feature of the Australian government is its federal arrangement (Galligan 1995). Each of the six Australian states has its own parliamentary government.3 The head of government in each state is the Premier. The state Premier is the leader of the party or coalition with majority control in the lower house of that state’s parliament. Each state also has a Governor who is appointed by the Queen on the advice of the state’s Premier. The distribution of power between the national and state governments has been one of the major sources of political 2 The six states are New South Wales, Queensland, South Australia, Tasmania, Victoria and Western Australia. The mainland territories are the Australian Capital Territory and the Northern Territory. The Constitution does not guarantee representation for these territories, so their representation in the Commonwealth Parliament is by statutory arrangement. 3 Three of the territories are also self-governing: the Northern Territory, the Australian Capital Territory, and Norfolk Island. The unicameral legislatures in the territories are called “legislative assemblies,” and are parliamentary in design. The remaining territories are governed by the national government. disagreement since Australia’s federation (Blackshield 1972). The authors of the Australian Constitution rejected the more centralized wording found in the Canadian Constitution4 in favor of an American-style arrangement, where the states retain all powers not delegated to the national government (Hodgins et al. 1978). Just as in the United States, though, the boundaries of national power are incompletely delineated in the Constitution. The High Court has played an important role in refereeing the distribution of power between the two levels of government (Selway and Williams 2005).5 It has been a distinctly political branch of government from the start, even if the Court itself has been slow to acknowledge this fact (Galligan 1987). While Westminster-style governments are characterized by parliamentary sovereignty, Australia has been characterized by constitutional sovereignty since its founding document took effect (Gleeson 2003b). The architects of the Australian Constitution recognized this, and some acknowledged the crucial role the High Court would play in maintaining constitutional sovereignty (Mason 2003a) Staffing the High Court In countries with a civil law tradition, judges and lawyers begin their careers on separate paths. Would-be judges and lawyers attend separate training institutions, and there is little lateral movement between the two professions (Guamieri 2004). In The relevant provrsron rs Section 91 of the Canadian Constitution, which specrfies that the federal government retains reserved powers. Section 52 of the Australian Constitution enumerates the powers of the Commonwealth Government, leaving residual powers to the states. 5 Most decisions of the Australian judiciary were originally appealable to the Privy Council in Britain. The Constitution has always stipulated that the High Court is the final arbiter of inter se questions—~questions dealing with the distribution of power between the federal and state governments. This arrangement is addressed in detail later in this chapter. common law countries like Australia and the United States, judges are often chosen from the ranks of the legal profession. As such, the process is far less self-selecting than in civil law countries. As a preliminary step to understanding how judges function on the bench, it is necessary first to examine the way in which people become judges. In Australia, as in the American federal judiciary, judges are given their jobs by politicians. This is the main opportunity for the government of the day to exert dejure influence over the judiciary. Understanding how and why judges are selected for the job, then, is a very important step for understanding what they do once they arrive (Ostberg and Wetstein 2004) The Legal Profession The legal profession in Australia dates back to well before Australian Federation.6 As in colonial America, the British system was imported as the basis for the legal profession in Australia. Each colony developed its own Bar admission and regulation structures, and these structures are still largely in place today. This is a similar system to the United States, where the Bar is organized on a state level. The current state systems are all derived from a shared legal tradition, but the state legal societies do differ to a degree. There is no nationalized legal profession currently, although the Law Council of Australia (LCA) and others have been working to unite the various state—based systems (LCA 2003). The legal profession in Australia is a multi-billion dollar industry, generating more than AUD$1O billion in 2002 (LCA 2003). In the states of Victoria, Queensland, and 6 The term “Australian Federation” refers to the culmination of the process by which the six self-governing British colonies in Australia united in a federation. This is akin to the use of the term “American Founding.” New South Wales, unlike the unified American systems, the legal profession is divided. As in the British tradition, these three states divide practitioners into two types of lawyers: solicitors and banisters (Meek 1999). A solicitor handles all non-trial matters. This includes the drawing up of wills and real estate transactions. Additionally, the solicitor conducts the initial legal research in preparation for a case, and then turns the matter over to a barrister. The solicitor has no direct parallel in America, although the role performed by a solicitor combines certain aspects the duties of a paralegal and a research attorney. The solicitor is the main point of contact between a litigant and his or her legal representative, and may join law firms and distribute work among colleagues (LCA 2001). In most cases, a client must hire a solicitor, who will then provide initial legal advice and procure a barrister on the client’s behalf. Barristers are expert advocates, and plead cases at both the trial and appellate levels. They are solo practitioners, and are not permitted to join forces to form law firms (LCA 2001). Barristers appointed to argue cases in front of the High Court receive the title of Queen’s Council (QC). This is also commonly called “taking silk.” It is a professional ranking, as is becoming a member of the US. Supreme Court Bar, but is bestowed on barristers by the Crown.7 This honor is generally attained by only the most exceptional barristers after ten to fifteen years as a practicing junior counsel (Meek 1999). Like members of the US. Supreme Court Bar (McGuire 1994), QCs also tend to be elite members of both their profession and their society. In Victoria, Queensland, and New South Wales, barristers and solicitors are regulated under different bodies. In these states, the Bar is the professional organization 7 In the Australian context, “the Crown” refers to the head of the British monarchy, who is also the Australian head of state. for barristers. In other states, both types of practitioners are regulated by the state Bar. It is from the ranks of the Bar that most judges are selected (Gleeson 2003a). Some of the distinctions between the barrister and the solicitor, however, are common among all of the states and territories. In 1993, the state of New South Wales passed legislation allowing practitioners to be listed as both barristers and solicitors. Prior to this, however, the banister was not allowed to perform the duties of the solicitor, and vice versa. In the states with an undivided profession, lawyers can be admitted as practitioners, enabling them to perform the duties of a solicitor, a barrister, or both. With the introduction of a mutual recognition scheme in 1992, it has become relatively simple for a lawyer in one state to gain permission to practice law in another state. In addition, standards for admission to the profession are similar across states. An applicant must have a degree in law. This is roughly an equivalent to an American bachelor’s degree. The Australian law degree typically takes five years to complete, and law students also earn a degree in an additional subject. Admission to the profession also requires practical training, which involves serving an apprenticeship or articles of clerkship. The membership of the profession, however, remains relatively homogeneous. As of 1999, there were more than 30,000 members of the Australian legal profession (LCA 2001). The majority of these worked in private solicitor practices. Despite the fact that there are now nearly equal numbers of male and female law graduates, the profession remains dominated by men. Nearly 90% of barristers, for example, are men. Legal aid offices and community legal centers are staffed largely by women, while men tend to dominate the other, more lucrative sectors of the profession (LCA 2001). The Selection Process Unlike the American Constitution, the Australian Constitution provides explicit instructions for the selection of all Commonwealth. judges. The process is governed by section 72, which provides: The Justices of the High Court and of the other courts created by the Parliament — (i) Shall be appointed by the Governor-General in Council; (ii) Shall not be removed except by the Governor-General in Council, on an address from both Houses of the Parliament in the same session, praying for such removal on the ground of proved misbehaviour or incapacity; (iii) shall receive such remuneration as the Parliament may fix; but the remuneration shall not be diminished during their continuance in office. (Commonwealth Constitution, § 72) In 1977, this section was amended following a national referendum to prescribe a mandatory retirement age of 70 years for all judges. Appointments to the High Court are formally made by the Governor-General, who is the British Crown’s representative in Australia. The Governor-General’s choice is almost always based on the recommendation of the Prime Minister’s Cabinet through the Attorney-General (Evans 2002). The High Court of Australia Act 1979 (Cth)8 added the additional requirement that the Attorney-General consult the states before the recommendation is made. The role of the states in the process, however, is minimal at best (Moens 1997). There is no formal judicial confirmation process. Procedures for the selection of judges are based on tradition as opposed to hard and fast legal requirements. The Commonwealth Attomey-General typically advises the state Attorneys-General of vacancies and solicits nominations.9 Nominees for the High Court are selected by the 8 The abbreviation in parentheses represents the jurisdiction in which the act was passed. Following the Australian Guide to Legal Citation (Kirwin and Masters 2002), “Cth” is the abbreviation for “Commonwealth,” in this case the Commonwealth Parliament. 9 The Attorney-General in a parliamentary system is a Member of Parliament by definition. This is in contrast to the American Attorney General, who is appointed by the President from outside Congress. Any government from the legal profession. They usually come from lower levels of the judiciary or the Sydney or Melbourne Bar. The Commonwealth Attomey-General presents this list, along with his or her additions and recommendations, to the Cabinet. The Cabinet then makes a decision, and the Governor-General carries out the formal appointment. The Resulting Judges In the current system, the list of names presented to the Cabinet is not on the public record, and this fact concerns many observers. There have been a number of calls for reform of the current selection system, most calling for a more formalized merit selection process. Some politicians have made clear their desire to shape the Bench to reflect their own political leanings. In one example, former Deputy Prime Minister Tim Fischer made it known that the Howard government intended to appoint only “capital ‘c’ conservatives” to the Bench (Jackson 2003, 3). The Australian Democrats, a minor party, proposed a merit-based selection plan intended to minimize the impact of political consideration on the resulting appointments. This plan was dismissed as unnecessary by the Law Council of Australia and the Liberal Coalition government, among others (LCA 1997). Many important people, including Justice Michael Kirby, have called for greater transparency in the process, with an eye to keeping political forces out of the process (Childs 2001). Justice Mary Gaudron has called attention to the potential danger of invoking the “merit” justification for appointments made in the current selection system (Gaudron 2002). Because the pool of potential nominees is small and lacking in diversity, the nominee from the ranks of Congress would have to resign his position, as per Article 1, section 6 of the US. Constitution. 10 Australian judiciary tends to be a highly homogenous group (Gleeson 2003a). This is especially true in the High Court. Justice Gaudron, appointed in 1987, was the first female to sit on the High Court bench. Justice Gaudron had high hopes that her 2003 retirement would lead to the appointment of a female replacement, but, in her words, “we muffed it” (Mazzocchi 2003, 1). The return to an all-male Court sparked renewed debate about the appropriateness of affirmative action-type policies for High Court nominees. With Gaudron’s retirement and subsequent replacement by Justice Dyson Heydon, there were no female Justices on the Bench until the appointments of Susan Crennan in 2005 and Susan Kiefel in 2007. Former Chief Justice Sir Harry Gibbs has expressed concern that, at least in Queensland, merit has been surpassed by gender as the deciding factor in nominations for judicial appointment Richards 2000). National Bar Association President Tom Glynn points to the importance of strictly merit-based selection procedures, ruling out a “female seat” on the bench (Mazzocchi 2003). The Attorney-General has said that John Howard’s Liberal Coalition government used exactly such a merit-based program for selecting new judges. In response to questions about Justice Gaudron’s male replacement, he responded as follows: Gender was not a basis for identifying whether people were suitable for the appointment or not. What we seek to do is appoint the best person for the job. (Attomey-General Daryl Williams, as quoted in Rubenstein 2002, 3) It is clear, however, that there is a lack of consensus on this issue. Many observers are highly critical of the notion that there is a single “best person” for a position on the nation’s highest court (Rubenstein 2002). Alexandra Richards, former president of Australian Women Lawyers, explains this position: 11 There are, at any given time, a number of lawyers who have the requisite ability, character, temperament and experience to be suitable for a particular judicial appointment. There is no serious argument that appointments should be made otherwise fi'om those so qualified as are willing to accept an appointment. However, to suggest that the “best” appointment from within that group can be identified on the basis 0 “merit” is to give a false objectivity to something which can only be a matter of opinion and judgment. (Richards 2000, 1) This is what Justice Gaudron has called “the merit fiction,” and she cites it as one reason why women are still highly underrepresented at the Bar and in Australia’s senior judiciary (Gaudron 2002). She admits that this problem “wouldn’t matter a fig,” except that having women in the judiciary is crucial to administration of justice (Gaudron 2002, 5). This sentiment is echoed by other women in the legal profession, who often note that a diverse bench is one that can better administer justice in Australia’s diverse society (Rubenstein 2002). Similar arguments are advanced on the need for more diversity in other areas. One complaint is based on the lack of geographic representation on the High Court. Of the first 44 appointees to the High Court, more than half have come from the state of New South Wales (Dominello and Neumann 2002). Over 80% have come fi'om either New South Wales or Victoria. Another complaint is the lack of racial diversity on the Bench. All of the Justices—current and former—are white. Some judges are cautiously optimistic. Chief Justice Murray Gleeson notes that the professional base from which judges are selected has been expanded, so that now “there is a wider pool of legal talent than used to be drawn upon” (Gleeson 2001a, 3). Gleeson argues that the judiciary will inevitably reflect the population of the legal profession— admittedly with some delay (Gleeson 2003 a). Because of the increased diversity in the younger generation of lawyers, the ranks of the judiciary are bound to follow suit. Justice Ian Callinan has also noted the increased number of female members of the highest ranks 12 of Australia’s legal profession. Addressing the newest Queen’s Counsel appointees in 2000, he made mention of the number of females in the group: There are among you only five women. Tonight is not the occasion to debate whether that number should be regarded as a reasonably sufficient number in all of the circumstances. But on any view, that you are at last here and that your numbers are increasing show that we have moved a distance from some of the discriminatory practices of the past. (Callinan 2000, 3) In general, though, many of the Court’s onlookers do not share in this confidence. Justice Gaudron spoke at the inaugural meeting of the Women Lawyers’ Association of New South Wales, noting that little progress has been made since the first female Australian lawyers emerged—nearly a century ago (Branson 1997). Federal Court Judge Catherine Branson spoke to the group a few weeks later. She argued that the obstacles facing women in the profession start not with the judicial appointment process, but much earlier in the legal career (Branson 1997). The subtle bias experienced by female practitioners from law school to judicial vetting often hinders them in their quest to achieve the top positions in the profession (Branson 1995). Kim Rubenstein argues that the problem is not just with the homogenous pool of potential judges, but also with the group of people doing the deciding: At the moment it is a predominantly male conservative cabinet deciding who the "best" person is for the job. Indeed, our century-old experience of judicial selection has shown that when male politicians gaze at the available gene pool of potential High Court appointees, they only see reflections of themselves, and what they understand as depictions of merit. (Rubenstein 2002, 1) The replacement of Justice Mary Gaudron with Dyson Heydon increased the prevalence of this kind of criticism. Many female practitioners saw this as an affront to the cause of promoting diversity, noting that there were plenty of well-qualified females from which to choose (McDonald 2002). 13 High Court Jurisdiction Jurisdiction is the power and authority of a court to hear and rule on controversies, and forms the crux of the institution’s role and function. The American Constitution was undoubtedly the model for a great deal of the Australian Constitution, especially where the judicial power is concerned (Cowen and Zines 2002). The Australian Constitution, however, was drafted more than a century after its American counterpart. The lessons of the American experience informed the Australian framers. The differences between the two documents reflect those lessons, as well as the fundamental differences between presidential and parliamentary governmental structures. Original Jurisdiction Like the American Constitution, the Australian Constitution lays out particular situations in which the highest national court hears cases at first instance. The original jurisdiction of the High Court is laid out in section 75, which reads: In all matters (i) arising under any treaty; (ii) affecting counsuls or other representatives of other countries; (iii) in which the Commonwealth, or a person suing or being sued on behalf of the Commonwealth, is a party; (iv) between States, or between residents of different States, or between a State and a resident of another State; (v) in which a writ of Mandamus or prohibition or an injunction is sought against an officer of the Commonwealth; the High Court shall have original jurisdiction. (Commonwealth Constitution, § 75) This section confers an original jurisdiction that is similar—but not identical—to the original jurisdiction that Article 111 Section 2 of the United States Constitution confers on its Supreme Court. Many of the specific subject matters conferred by the Australian Constitution were probably adopted without much thought as to their suitability for the Australian situation (Cowen and Zines 2002). One similarity is the use of the term ‘matters’ in describing the Court’s jurisdiction. This has been interpreted to mean that the High Court, like the American Supreme Court, lacks jurisdiction to provide advisory 14 opinions (Cowen and Zines 2002). Additional restrictions were implemented in the Boilermakers’ Case,10 when the Court held that non-judicial functions could not be delegated to judicial bodies. The Australian Constitution contains a specific provision allowing the Commonwealth Parliament to confer additional matters to the original jurisdiction of the High Court. This is a significant departure from the American system. The provision in section 75(v) of the Australian Constitution is similar to the provision in the American Judiciary Act held invalid in Marbury v. Madison. 11 Under the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth), the High Court’s original jurisdiction was exclusive in matters involving suits between states, between the Commonwealth and a state, or matters in which a writ is sought against an officer of the Commonwealth. Original jurisdiction in matters of constitutional interpretation, admiralty, and federal law are not constitutionally entrenched, but are instead left for Parliament to confer. The Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth) provided this jurisdiction. Additionally, Parliament has conferred original jurisdiction in a number of other matters through such legislation as the Commonwealth Electoral Act 1918 (Cth), the Income Tax Assessment Act 1936 (Cth), the Patents Act 1952 (Cth) and the Admiralty Act 1988 (Cth). As a result of Parliarnent’s tendency to add to—but never subtract from—the Court’s original jurisdiction, it grew to proportions much larger than that of the US. Supreme Court (Cowen and Zines 2002). By the 19605 this extensive nondiscretionary original jurisdiction, coupled with the burdensome nondiscretionary appellate jurisdiction l 0 R v Kirby; Ex Parte Boilermakers ' Society of Australia (1956) 94 CLR 254 H (1803) 1 Cranch 137 15 discussed in the next section, resulted in nearly insurmountable workload pressures (Bennett 1980). As the scope of Australian statutory law increased, the High Court was unable to continue its role as federal trial court while still maintaining its more important role as interpreter of the constitution (Beaumont 2002). Section 77(iii) of the Australian Constitution provides Parliament the option to parse the federal jurisdiction among the various state courts. In the 19705, the High Court increasingly remitted cases to appropriate state supreme courts for determination (Cowen and Zines 2002). Matters arising under laws made by the Commonwealth Parliament were routinely handled by state courts under this provision, but this still left a great deal of work to be handled by the High Court alone (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). The High Court was still the preferred venue for adjudicating on first instance in many matters because it provided a level of uniformity and consistency that the numerous state courts could not match (Mason 2000). This left the High Court with an incredibly high caseload. As Attorney-General, Garfield Barwick was instrumental in presenting a solution to this problem. He first advocated the creation of an intermediate federal court in the early 1960s, but the Federal Court of Australia did not begin to exercise jurisdiction until February of 197 7 (Beaumont 2002). This new statutory court was created through amendments to the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth). It was to be a small court, with jurisdiction conferred in special areas only (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). The Federal Court began by handling mostly bankruptcy, administrative law, industrial law, and trade practices law. 16 Figure l - Original Jurisdiction Cases as a Percent of Reported Cases: 1965-2002 50 40* 30‘ 20~ 10‘ Percentage of Cases *7 i w a f fi‘v f v 1%4 '85 '88 '70 '72 '74 '76 '78 '80 '82 '84 '% '88 '3] '92 '94 '% '98 '0] 2CD? Soon, the Federal Court began to assume jurisdiction concurrent with much of the High Court’s original and appellate jurisdictions. Some of this transfer arose from the increasing tendency of Parliament to confer original jurisdiction through legislation (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). In Phillip Morris,12 the High Court also expanded the Federal Court’s original jurisdiction by refining its doctrine of accrued jurisdiction to include the Federal Court (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). Some scholars have speculated that the establishment of the Federal Court alleviated much of the workload stress due to original jurisdiction cases (Gageler 2002a). Figure 1 shows the original jurisdiction cases as a percentage of all reported cases. Among the reported cases from 1970 through 2002 there seems to be little lasting shift in the overall percentage of original jurisdiction cases. At the most, original jurisdiction cases have constituted a maximum of 13 cases of the Court’s business in a year. 12 Philip Morris v. Commissioner of Business Franchises (Vic) (1989) 167 CLR 399 17 Appellate Jurisdiction The majority of the High Court’s caseload comes from its appellate jurisdiction. One of the main differences between the Australian High Court and the American Supreme Court is the breadth of appellate jurisdiction conferred by the respective constitutions. While the American Supreme Court is limited to adjudicating federal issues, the High Court may hear appeals from state courts even in the absence of a federal question. The American founders were deeply suspicious of the new centralized government, and were loathe to allow it interfere in the affairs of the states. By contrast, the Australian experience provided no impetus for such a complete separation (Quick and Garran 1901). Section 73 of the Australian Constitution therefore confers a general appellate jurisdiction to the High Court, subject to such restrictions as Parliament cares to legislate. This section also prevents Parliament from restricting the jurisdiction to hear appeals from the state supreme courts. The availability of appeals from judgment is not derived from the common law tradition, but instead is largely a product of statute. Because of this, the nature and extent of the availability of appeal varies depending on the statute conferring the right (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). The appeals process serves to correct trial court errors, and also to provide consistency and clarity in the law and its proper application. The role of the High Court in this process is largely the latter, especially in recent times. Before 1984, many of the appeals to the High Court came as of right. This right to appeal was conferred by the various statutes under which the litigation was commenced, and was usually related to the amount of money at issue in civil litigation. In addition, interlocutory judgments could be appealed by leave to appeal, granted by either the state supreme courts or the High Court. Such leave would be granted if the 18 judgment in the lower court was arguably incorrect (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). The Court had a largely nondiscretionary appellate jurisdiction for that reason, and many of the cases before it tended to be similar and straightforward (Gleeson 2000b). Amendments to the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth) in 1976 altered this situation slightly. The new default mechanism for taking an appeal to the High Court was to obtain special leave to appeal. Appeals as of right remained, however, in constitutional issues or issues involving property in excess of AUD$20,000. This nondiscretionary appellate jurisdiction was removed in 1984 through further amendments to the Judiciary Act. These amendments provide that appeals will not be heard by the High Court unless the High Court itself grants special leave to have an appeal heard on the merits. Criminal appeals have always required special leave, but most civil litigation enjoyed a right to appeal until the 1984 amendments. The result of these amendments was to abolish the Court’s nondiscretionary appellate jurisdiction, in service of the Court’s role as interpreter of laws. ’3 High Court Jurisdiction and the Privy Council The Judicial Council of the Privy Council in England sat above the High Court at the pinnacle of the Australian legal system for most of Australia’s history. The Privy Council is a division of the British House of Lords, and is also called “Her Majesty in Counsel.” The Privy Council is partially staffed by English Law Lords. There is no limit to the number of Privy Counsellors, and there are currently around 550 members. It is 1 3 Additionally, the Court has changed its interpretation of what constitutes an appeal. Section 73 of the Constitution provides High Court jurisdiction “to hear and determine appeals from all judgments, decrees, orders and sentences” of a number of different types of courts. Recently, the Court has held that determinations can be made on questions posed to the court during the course of trial proceedings without the trial court judge’s assent (O’Toole v. Charles David (1991) 171 CLR 232). 19 not an appellate court for England proper, but instead is a body of judges charged with maintaining a degree of unity in the English common law around the world (Matson 1993). In addition to the British jurists, judges from many of the Commonwealth countries are regularly appointed as Privy Counsellors (V oigt et al. 2006), including a number of former High Court Justices.l4 Traditionally, the Privy Council was made up of special advisors, and their decisions were phrased as advice to the British monarch. For this reason, there is a long tradition of unanimous judgments on the Privy Council—a tradition that Barwick helped to eliminate during his service (Blackshield et al. 2002). The constitutional provision allowing appeals to the Privy Council was a major point of contention at federation. The Privy Council was one mechanism through which the precedents of the British judiciary were “continually injected into the caselaw of the Australian states” (Castles 1971, 139). As early as 1906, the Privy Council experienced a hostile Australian reaction to its intervention in Australian litigation (Blackshield et al. 2002). The relations between these institutions were unpredictable, due in part to the ever-changing membership of the Privy Council. At times, the Privy Council might promise not to interfere in certain situations, only to have a differently constituted Privy Council forget or ignore such arrangements (Blackshield et al. 2002). The Constitution remains silent on appeals from the state supreme courts to the Privy Council, tacitly leaving no limitations on such appeals. There are, however, two constitutional limitations on Privy Council appeals from the High Court. First, the High Court has always retained the right to determine all questions regarding the distribution 1 This lrst mcludes Barwrck, Gavan Duffy, Gibbs, Griffith, Krtto, Knox, Latham, McTrernan, Menzres, Owen, Rich, Stephen, Taylor, Walsh, and Windeyer (Blackshield et al. 2002). 20 of federal and/or state powers, often called inter se questions. The relevant portion of the Constitution reads: No appeal shall be permitted to the Queen in Council from a decision of the High Court upon any question, howsoever arising, as to the limits inter se of the Constitutional powers of the Commonwealth and those of any State or States, or as to the limits inter se of the Constitutional powers of any two or more States, unless the High Court shall certify that the question is one which ought to be determined by Her Majesty in Council. (Commonwealth Constitution, §74) Over the years, the exact definition of an inter se question has been the subject of much debate and litigation. In the end, potentially important federal issues were excluded from this category, including interstate trade, separation of powers between branches of the Commonwealth government, and many questions of inconsistency between state and Commonwealth legislation (Blackshield et al. 2002). While the High Court only issued a single prerogative writ to appeal under section 74,15 the Privy Council was still able to hand down numerous important constitutional decisions. This is especially true in the interpretation of section 92, which provides for free trade among the states (Blackshield et al. 2002). It is through the second limitation on Privy Council appeals that the High Court eventually obtained final jurisdiction over all matters. This second limitation is found in the last provision in section 74, which reads: Except as provided in this section, this constitution shall not impair any right which the Queen may be pleased to exercise by virtue of Her Royal prerogative to grant special leave of appeal from the High Court to Her Majesty in Council. The Parliament may make laws limiting the matters in which such leave may be asked, but proposed laws containing any such limitation shall be reserved by the Governor-General for Her Majesty’s pleasure. (Commonwealth Constitution, §74) 15 . . . . . The High Court issued a section 74 certificate in Colonial Sugar Refining Co v. Attorney General (C th) (1912) 15 CLR 182. Justice O’Connor’s absence resulted in an evenly split vote among the remaining four Justices. 21 The first exercise of this provision was undertaken by the Commonwealth Government when it passed the Print Council (Limitation of Appeals) Act 1968 (Cth). This legislation limited potential Privy Council appeals from the High Court to those that did not potentially deal with an issue of federal law. In Kitano v. Commonwealth,16 the Privy Council agreed that this was a valid exercise of parliamentary power under section 74. Several years later, the Commonwealth Parliament passed the Privy Council (Appeals From the High Court) Act 1975 (Cth). This legislation abolished all remaining appeals from the High Court to the Privy Council without prior permission of the High Court. This provision was challenged in the High Court in Attomey-General (Cth) v. T &G Mutual Life. ’7 The High Court rejected the challenge and declared that it would no longer certify cases for appeal to the Privy Council. As per the 1968 legislation, no appeal to the Privy Council remained (Blackshield et al. 2002). Although appeals from the High Court and other federal courts were abolished, cases could still be appealed to the Privy Council from the decisions of the state courts. This resulted in a unique situation where litigants who were unsuccessful at the state court level could effectively choose their appellate venue (Blackshield et al. 2002). This provided wealthy appellants the ability to “shop around” for their preferred remedy, giving them a distinct advantage over respondents (Gleeson 2002a). Litigants continued to appeal to the Privy Council from the state courts long after the High Court refiised to certify firrther appeals. Although the total number of Australian cases in front of the 6 1 (1976) AC 99,135 CLR 1. 17 (1978) 144 CLR161 22 Privy Council subsequently declined, the Commonwealth Law Reports continued to report cases appealed to the Privy Council into the 19805 (see Figure 2). Figure 2 - Number of Privy Council Cases in Commonwealth Law Reports by Year '0 9. 8 7 6i 5 U, i 8 to 4i O ‘5 3i 8 or 2« ‘3? e 1- a) 0. 0 T fl f j fl i fi fi f 1%4 '88 '88 '70 '72 '74 '78 '78 '80 '82 '84 '88 '88 '90 '92 '94 '98 '98 '00 2002 This also resulted in a good deal of confusion at the lower court levels. Various High Court Justices advised lower court judges to abide by High Court precedent, but these judges effectively had two different — at times conflicting —- masters. This dilemma was finally solved in 1986 with the passage of The Australia Act 1986 (Cth). This was one of a pair of statutes, the other of which was passed by the United Kingdom Parliament. The effect of these statutes was to give the Australian states independence from Britain. They served to end all remaining appeals from the Australian judiciary to the Privy Council, among other things (Blackshield 2002b). This placed the High Court at the apex of the Australian legal system and made its judgments the highest source of precedent (Twomey 2002). These formal developments, according to some scholars, also helped cultivate a new mindset amongthe High Court Justices (Blackshield et al. 2002). Before the 23 abolition of these appeals, the Privy Council had a direct and tangible effect on the decisions of the High Court, as well as on the development of law in Australia (Gleeson 2000b). As the formal structures of this influence were removed, the Justices were no longer bound by English authority. The Justices used this opportunity to exert control over issues previously controlled by English precedent, including the rapid development of a new approach to section 92 (Gleeson 2002a). Daily Operating Procedures In many significant ways, the daily operation of the High Court of Australia is similar to that of the US. Supreme Court. Given the shared common law tradition, many of the same concepts are applicable to both institutions. There are, however, a number of procedural differences. While seemingly negligible, they can produce many significant differences in terms of agenda, decision making, and the reporting of decisions. The theories of judicial decision making that are most well known in American circles assume a particular set of operating procedures. Even procedural rules that seem very similar can produce very different effects (Glendon et al. 1999). Only by examining the rules and traditions that shape the daily operation of the High Court can the appropriate adjustments be made to our existing theories. Setting the Agenda The current agenda-setting process in the High Court is roughly comparable to the American Supreme Court’s certiorari process, but with several important differences. In the American Supreme Court, a writ of certiorari18 is granted when at least four of the 18 To complicate the situation further, the term writ of certiorari means something substantively different in the Australian legal context. A writ of certiorari in Australia serves to quash a lower court decision. It is granted as a remedy on the grounds that 1) there was error on the face of the lower court record, 2) the lower court acted outside its jurisdiction, or 3) the applicant was denied procedural fairness at the lower 24 Justices agree that an appeal should be heard on the merits. The decision is made in a conference that all Justices attend, and is made based on examination of the written submissions alone. The Supreme Court clerks have a large role in this procedure, as they are responsible for drawing up memoranda for each of the applications (Perry 1994). In the High Court, the agenda is set through the special leave process. When there is no leave as of right, all parties wishing to appeal must apply for special leave to appeal. These special leave petitions are heard by a subset of the Bench. The panel is chosen by the Chief Justice, and is now typically made up of two to three Justices (Jackson 2002b). The panel size is a matter of practice, and is not dictated by law (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). The practice in the past was to have a three judge panel in civil cases, five judges in criminal cases, and seven Justices in cases deemed important by the Chief Justice (Gibbs 1986). This has been abandoned in favor of the smaller panel sizes, largely due to workload concerns (Australian Law Reform Commission 2000). The applicant traditionally has a right to appear in person for an oral argument on the application, which is limited to twenty minutes of argument and five minutes of reply for the applicant and the respondent (Clark 2003 ). These oral arguments are increasingly being heard via video link between Canberra and the other capitol cities. While oral arguments take up valuable time, the Court has been reluctant to eliminate this tradition altogether (Clark 2003). These oral arguments serve to supplement the written briefs submitted by counsel, which have been required for special leave applications since 1994 (Jackson 1996). Recently, however, Chief Justice Gleeson has advocated eliminating the right to appear in person as a way to save the Court valuable time (Clark 2003). Changes court level. In the American context, a writ of certiorari serves to grant the applicant a hearing on the merits before the Supreme Court. 25 to the High Court Rules in 2004 now allow the Court to determine special leave applications on the papers only, if it is deemed appropriate by two Justices (Doogan 2004) Until recently, the special leave process was not the primary way by which cases came to be heard by the High Court. In its earlier years, the Court had a substantial non- discretionary jurisdiction. The Court, for example, was obligated to hear appeals from state supreme courts in civil matters involving £300 (Jackson 2002b). Appeal as of right was also guaranteed in cases in which the outcome may affect a person’s status in terms of citizenship, marriage, divorce, bankruptcy, and insolvency. In addition to the abolition of these appeals as of rights, the creation of the Federal Courts allowed the High Court to share its original jurisdiction with lower courts. These two developments, taken together, have virtually eliminated the High Court’s non-discretionary jurisdiction. The High Court has interpreted these acts of Parliament as a grant of complete discretion as to the cases it hears (Solomon 1999). Thus, the High Court’s agenda became almost wholly dependent on the special leave process. Although the practice was challenged in the Smith Kline & French 19 case, the Court upheld the practice unanimously. In the High Court, like the American Supreme Court, the refusal of a special leave application is not equivalent to a denial of the appeal. A special leave application heard by a panel of five or more Justices is often disposed of during the special leave process. The High Court often grants special leave with specific terms. On some occasions, the Court will require one litigant to pay the other litigant’s costs of appeal. Additionally, special leave is subject to rescission at or before the hearing on the merits (Jackson l 9 Smith Kline & French Laboratories v. Commonwealth (1991) 173 CLR 194. 26 2002b). In 1999—2000, the High Court decided 387 special leave applications, of which 66 succeeded. Due to the ever-increasing number of special leave applications being heard, many hearings are now being conducted via a closed-circuit video link system. Both Courts follow similar guidelines when deciding whether a case will be heard. The American Supreme Court has written its own guidelines in Rule 10. These guidelines reflect the role of a secondary appellate tribunal, which is to clarify important points of law, and generally not to simply correct trial court errors. The criteria for the High Court are set out not by the Court itself, but by Parliament. The provision in Australia that corresponds to the Supreme Court’s Rule 10 is Section 35A of the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth). This section requires the Court to consider the need to promote uniformity throughout the legal system, the public importance of the question, and the individual-level interests of justice and fairness. The Panel System In the United States, it is rare to see a Supreme Court case on which fewer than nine Justices sit. In Australia, however, this is a very common occurrence. Instead of sitting en banc, the High Court sits in panels. Neither the Australian Constitution nor the Judiciary Act gives much help in determining how these panels are assigned (Schubert 1969a). This panel tradition comes largely from two factors. First, the Court has always operated on a circuit system. In the early years, the Justices seldom lived in the same city, and travel was long, harsh and difficult. Because of this, it was much more efficient to allow for a subset of Justices to comprise “The Court and exercise 1t5jurrsdrctron. 0 20 While the US. Supreme Court abandoned the circuit-riding practice after 120 years, the High Court of Australia still travels to the various state capitals to hear cases each year. Because of the role circuit riding plays in keeping the Justices abreast of the legal and societal differences across a large and diverse nation, some American scholars argue that the Supreme Court should readopt the practice (Stras 2007). 27 Additionally, a High Court Justice was usually serving on the Privy Council at any given time. This required one Justice to travel to England, often for months at a time. Instead of putting the work of the Court on hold, the panel system allowed for the continued completion of day-to-day business (McMillan 2003). The size of the panels is dependent on a number of different factors. The Judiciary Act and the High Court Rules require that a Full Court consist of no fewer than two Justices. In appeals from the Full Court (or Court of Appeal) of a state supreme court, a Full Court must consist of no fewer than three. Aside from these rules, the jurisdiction of the Court may be exercised by any number of Justices (Brennan 2002a). A single Justice in chambers may exercise the Court’s jurisdiction in cases dealing with practice and procedure. The single Justice, when necessary, may refer a question to the Full Court. Traditionally, appeals brought from decisions of single state supreme court judges were heard by a panel of three Justices. Since the 1984 changes to the judicial system, however, appeals from single state supreme court judges are extremely rare (Brennan 2002a). Most of the appeals from state supreme courts have now been heard by a Full Court or Court of Appeals division of the state supreme courts, and are heard in the High Court by a panel of five or more Justices. Special leave petitions may be heard by panels of three Justices, but criminal case petitions are often heard by five Justices and disposed of during the special leave process. The assignment of panels is arranged by the Chief Justice. The Chief also assigns Justices to a schedule of sitting in chambers or in original jurisdiction cases (Mason 2002d). While the Chief may organize the panel assignments, any Justice is entitled to sit on any case if he or she so desires, although this privilege is seldom invoked (McMillan 28 2003). The Chief Justice typically selects panels of five Justices unless the case is deemed especially important (McMillan 2003). Typically, these especially important cases involve interpretation of the Constitution. In such cases, all available Justices are assigned to the panel (Brennan 2002a). There is little information available about how a Chief Justice might capitalize on this power, as Schubert observes: The apparently available explanation is not very satisfactory: reference is made to ‘settled practices’ and to ‘common sense’ — which remain equally undefined — as the basis for the exercise of discretion which takes into account such self-evidently weighty measures as the ‘relative importance of a case’ and the number of j ustices ‘available’ for assignment. (Schubert 1969a, 10) It seems clear that many contemporary Australian legal scholars do not see evidence that the Chief Justices use the power to assign panels to affect the outcome of a case (McMillan 2003). As the current Chief Justice has noted, I’ve never heard any complaints by people about the system by which we select the five to sit. I’m the one who proposes who sits, and it’s usually done on the basis of evening out the workload. (Gleeson, as quoted in Clark 2003, 10) Schubert (1969a), however, finds evidence that at least one Chief Justice——Dixon—did not choose panels randomly. As the jurisdiction of the High Court has changed, the number of Justices on the average panel has also changed. With the elimination of non-discretionary jurisdiction, the Court now hears more of these “especially important” cases, and far fewer cases that are heard by three-judge panels (see Figure 3). According to Chief Justice Brennan, The Court tries to ensure that the opinions of all available Justices are secured to finally settle any questions of these kinds. It is unsatisfactory to have finely balanced questions resolved by fewer Justices than a majority of the whole Court. (Brennan 2002a, 61) 29 This mle of thumb, however, is not always followed perfectly. In Woods v. Multi- Sport Holdings,21 only five Justices sat on the panel. Justice Kirby was not one of them. In a subsequent case involving a similar question,22 Justice Kirby expressed his disappointment about the majority decision in Woods, and implicitly about his absence from the panel. In Ex Parte Aala, 23 Kirby noted that the seven-member panel might have been overkill: In this matter, this Court has been involved, not in the elucidation of some important question of constitutional, statutory or other legal significance. The applicable principles are clear. This Court has been engaged in nothing more than the elucidation of the facts and the application to them of settled rules of law. Although the size of the panel is related to the type of case involved, it is not clear that the membership of any given panel is related to the Chier assessment of any individual Justice’s ideology, predilections, or likely vote on a case (McMillan 2003). Issues like illness, vacation, preparation for retirement, service on the Privy Council, and geographical location may affect the panels, but Australian scholars anticipate that, as far as they can tell, concern for efficiency dominates this process (McMillan 2003). Because the most important cases tend to involve all of the Justices, the Chief Justice’s ability to assign panel membership would not likely benefit him much on major policy decisions. Hearing Cases on the Merits Like the US. Supreme Court, the High Court rules on the merits of only a fraction of the cases brought to it. The abolition of appeals as of right has allowed the Court the discretion to choose cases to be heard on the merits. This has allowed the Court to hear 2’ (2002) 208 CLR 460. 22 Graham Barclay Oysters v. Ryan (2002) 208 CLR 460. a -3 Re: Refitgee Review Tribunal; Ex Parte Aala (2000) 176 ALR 219. 30 fewer and fewer cases on the merits over time (see Figure 4). While the procedure for hearing and deciding cases on the merits is similar between the US. Supreme Court and the Australian High Court, there are some important differences. Figure 3 - Average Panel Size by Year 100 90 r 80 l 70 < 80 4 50 . 40 30 < 20 - 10* 0 1%4 '88 '88 '70 '72 '74 '78 '78 '80 '82 '84 '88 '88 '93 '92 '94 '98 '98 '00 Number of Cases Submission of written briefs Written briefs are a relatively new addition to the High Court’s decision-making procedure. It was not until the 19505 that the Court provided a non-compulsory procedure for the submission of written cases or detailed briefs. Before this, the Court relied almost exclusively on oral arguments. Chief Justice Latharn applauded the measure, indicating that it would increase clarity and efficiency (Bennett 2002). In 1982, the Court began to require barristers to present rough outlines of their arguments to the Justices at the beginning of arguments (Brennan 2002b). The submission of cases fully briefed “on'the papers” prior to argument was finally mandated by the High Court in 1997. This was largely an attempt to increase the Justices’ understanding of the cases prior to oral argument. In recent years, the Court has 31 increasingly adopted the stance that oral argument must follow from the information provided in the written briefs (Young and McLeish 2004). Especially when hearing appeals on the merits, though, the Justices do not see the cases on the papers as a replacement for oral argument (Leigh 2000). Figure 4 - Total Number of Cases by Year too 90- so« 70- sol 501 any 0') (D 8 30« o ‘5 20« a g 10' z 0 1964 a as '70 '7'2 '7'4 is “is ab '62 '54 as '88 '50 '52 E {as as do As in the United States Supreme Court, litigants are not always the only parties to submit briefs. Interveners and amici curiae are less common in the High Court than in the US. Supreme Court. As in the United States, amici curiae do not become actual parties to the proceedings. Instead, they appear before the court or submit briefs in an attempt to assist the Court when the actual litigants are unwilling or unable to provide certain information. In the High Court, interveners become full parties to the proceedings, although sometimes limited to specific issue areas. Until recently, there was no statutory right to intervene. Instead, leave to intervene was granted at the discretion of the Court. In 1976, amendments to the Judiciary Act gave attomeys-general of the Commonwealth and the states the right to intervene in cases 32 where constitutional interpretation is involved (Burrnester 2002). Now, government interveners are nearly always granted leave to intervene or appear as amicus curiae. The Court, however, retains its discretion as to whether or not to allow other parties to intervene. Traditionally, the Court has been reluctant to allow interest groups or other non-govemment parties to intervene (Williams 2000). As a result, most of the intervening appearances and written brief submissions occur in constitutional cases, usually about the distribution of power between the Commonwealth and the states (Parish 2000) In the United States, the Justices on the Supreme Court have four clerks apiece, and these clerks have a crucial role in processing and summarizing incoming briefs (Perry 1991). Because of the huge workload, much of the Supreme Court’s work is delegated to law clerks. In Australia, however, this is not the case. Although a High Court associate’s job description is similar to that of a Supreme Court clerk, Australian Justices tend to rely on them less (Leigh 2000). One reason for this might be the smaller workload. The associates may create summaries of written briefs, but this is not the norm. This means that the associates have less influence at this stage of the process than their American counterparts (Leigh 2000). Oral arguments After the submission of the written briefs, litigants present oral arguments to the Court. The High Court spends an average of about one day hearing oral arguments for a single case. This is quite extensive, especially when compared to the two hours spent per case by the United States Supreme Court. Chief Justice Gleeson thinks that this comparison is not very helpful, though, because the US. Supreme Court does not “have our tradition of oral advocacy” (Clark 2003, 10). While most of the work of the highest 33 courts of Canada and the United States are done “on the papers,” the Australian judiciary has adopted the British focus on oral arguments over written briefs (Leigh 2000). As Chief Justice Brennan notes, The practice of the Court has been to rely heavily on oral argument. The dialectic of advocacy and exchanges between Bench and Bar illuminate the issues for decision and usually identify the material on which the decision is based. (Brennan 2002b,197) For this reason, the High Court has declined to adopt formal time limits for oral arguments, except in the case of special leave applications (Bennett 2002). Despite the lack of formal limits, the length of oral arguments has declined over time. Before written briefs were commonplace, the Court relied almost exclusively on oral argument. The evolving process of getting access to briefs prior to oral argument has helped to shave significant time off of the actual hearings (Brennan 2002b). This focus on oral argument makes it far more relevant to the decision-making process than is typically ascribed to oral argument in the United States (Glendon et a1. 1999). Although some research has shown oral arguments to be marginally important in the US. Supreme Court (Johnson 1997), the brevity of these arguments necessarily limits the amount of information the Justices can expect to extract from the parties. Chief Justice Gleeson observes of the US. Supreme Court system that “most of their work is done on the papers” (Clark 2003, 10). Nonparty litigants are rarely allowed to participate in oral arguments in the US. Supreme Court (Segal and Spaeth 2002). The lack of time limits on High Court oral argument leaves significantly more time for the Justices to engage counsel. It is perhaps for this reason that the High Court does allow for oral presentations from interveners, and less often for amici curiae (Burrnester 2002). 34 The courtroom environment during oral argument has changed over time, largely influenced by the composition of the Bench and the leadership of the various Chiefs (Bennett 2002). At times, the Bench has been known for intense interrogation of counsel, rarely allowing them to finish a sentence without interruption. Justice Dixon resolved to curtail such judicial Socratic methods, but it was revived under Chief Justice Barwi ck (Gageler 2002c). Because the Justices use oral arguments as an important part of the decision-making process, counsel will often be faced with difficult questions about the quality of their arguments (Hayne 2004). For this reason, barristers are encouraged by the Bar to “turn judicial questioning, including in particular hostile questioning, to his or her advantage” (Young and McLeish 2004, 16). Some J ustices—both past and present—have been exceptional in their displays of wit and humor on the Bench (Davis and Simpson 2002). Others, however, find such banter distasteful and distracting (Ackland 2003). Gleeson has argued that the display of humor on the bench can have unintended consequences, largely because “judges and legal practitioners may underestimate the seriousness which litigants attach to legal proceedings, and they can become insensitive to the misunderstandings which might arise if the judges appears to be taking the occasion lightly” (Gleeson 1998). Additionally, the Justices expect counsel to refrain from attempting to appeal to the emotional or otherwise extra-legal sensibilities. As Justice Hayne warns, “the Court is not a jury let alone a talk- back radio announcer's audience” (Hayne 2004). The spontaneous nature of the oral argument process, however, often produces comedy despite attempts at restraint. Some argue that this judicial humor is an inextricable part of the judicial decision-making process (Heerey 2004). Common 35 examples are wry comments to counsel about the poor quality of their arguments (Davis and Simpson 2002) or playful jabs at their fellow Justices (Ackland 2003). In a recent case,24 for example, counsel for the appellant produced a pistol as an exhibit. Justice Gleeson commented to counsel: “If you are going to point it at us, would you mind pointing it in the direction of Justice Callinan?” While humor might be taken to an extreme in the judicial context, it can be used to relieve the stress and frustration of the courtroom environment when used judiciously (Davis and Simpson 2002). The Decision and Reasons The decision-making process in Australia is much different from that of the US. Supreme Court. Because of the influence of the British system, the Justices follow a seriatim tradition of individual opinion writing. This has important consequences for the process of negotiation and opinion creating. In addition, the traditions and norms on the Court make the opinion-writing effort look foreign to American onlookers. The differences, in turn, necessarily change the motivations driving the decision—making behavior of each individual Justice. The seriatim opinion-writing tradition Like the early US. Supreme Court, the High Court of Australia follows a seriatim opinion-writing tradition. Latin for “one after the other,” the seriatim tradition calls for individual opinions or reasons to be produced by each judge. This method of individual opinions was inherited from the English tradition. Under its first Chief Justice, John Jay, the US. Supreme Court adopted this procedure. Under Chief Justice John Marshall, - however, the tradition was abandoned in favor of a single per curium opinion (Ginsburg 24 Gillard v. The Queen (2003) 219 CLR 1. 36 1994). Only one opinion of the Court was typically handed down, and any dissenters remained silent (Gleeson 2003b). This change was largely an effort on the part of Marshall to reduce the appearance of discord and to protect the Court’s legitimacy (Seddig 1991). This practice was not universally applauded. As Thomas Jefferson wrote in a letter to a sitting Supreme Court Justice, The practice is certainly convenient for the lazy, the modest and the incompetent. It saves them the trouble of developing their opinion methodically and even of making up an opinion at all. (Jefferson 1822, 1) Indeed, the practice of publishing a single majority opinion was later abandoned in the Supreme Court in favor of a hybrid system. While the Supreme Court retains the majority opinion, other Justices are free to express concurring or dissenting views in separate opinions. The majority opinion still maintains importance, though, because precedential weight is only attached to opinions joined by a majority of the Justices. The High Court, however, never strayed from the British seriatim opinion-writing process. Although there have been intermittent attempts to consolidate the majority into a single opinion, these attempts have always been short-lived (Coper 2002c). Instead, the rugged individualism of the Court and its members has encouraged them to produce individual opinions (Mason 2003c). While Justices do occasionally join opinions, the solitude and independence of a barrister’s work likely works to feed the seriatim opinion process (Wheeler 2003). This process, however, is not without its own difficulties. In terms of clarity of law, the tradition of producing multiple “majority” opinions makes discerning the ratio decidendi far more difficult. As Chief Justice Mason observes, 37 The Court is a collective institution; it is the Court, rather than the individual Justices, that decides the case and declares the law. There is now an expectation that the Court will declare the law in clear terms in order to provide guidance for trial judges, the legal profession and the community. (Mason 2002d, 91) This tradition does provide individual accountability, but provides little help for those wishing to discern the common thread among majority opinions. Though there may be a majority agreement on the result, the reasoning used to get to the decision can vary widely (Willheim 2002). While legal academics like the intellectual challenge of discerning the ratio decidendi, practitioners often lament this tradition (McMillan 2003). Judicial conferences The US. Supreme Court has long followed a tradition of formal judicial conferencing. In some of these conferences, the Justices meet to discuss cases heard on the merits. After a discussion of the case at hand, apparently proceeding in descending order of seniority, the Justices cast a vote (Segal and Spaeth 2002). The most senior Justice in the majority assigns the authorship of the majority opinion, and discussion moves to the next case. The most junior Justice opens the door for the refreshments, answers the telephone, and keeps records of the conference proceedings (Ginsburg 1994). In Australia, however, the process is far more obscure. It has varied wildly over time, largely dependent on the personalities of the Justices and the leadership of the Chief Justice (Simpson 2002). The closest thing to opinion assignment probably happened under Chief Justice Latham after the appointments of F ullagar and Kitto. The Privy Council looked unfavorably on this practice, and it soon faded. The practice of holding conferences waxed and waned over the years. It seems as though incoming Chiefs were likely to attempt to begin such a tradition, but most abandoned it altogether in short stead (Mason 2002d). 38 Some former High Court associates indicate that there is no formal conference process. Following the extensive oral arguments, oftentimes the Justices seem to understand where their colleagues will stand. Recent alumni indicate that there is now a monthly “judgment meeting.” Indeed, Chief Justice Gleeson has acknowledged this monthly meeting, as well as informal meetings over tea (Clark 2003). While the process remains secretive, the result of the monthly conferences is called the “judgment list.” This is a list of the matters before the Court along with the status of all active business. The list indicates who has written or joined opinions. After the business is done, these lists are destroyed. One thing that is certainly missing from this list — if it does exist — is a majority opinion assignment. The writing and circulation of drafts In the US. Supreme Court, the process of writing and circulating drafts is very important. Because of the weight a majority opinion holds, there is a high level of motivation for its author to recruit other Justices to join. Many of the Justices permit their clerks to write the first draft (Tarr 2003). The Justice will then edit the first draft, distribute it to his peers and respond to any concurring or dissenting opinion drafts that have been circulated. During the course of this process, Justices may change their votes or decide to write concurring opinions. The process in the High Court is somewhat different, due largely to the different opinion writing tradition. When it comes to opinion writing, High Court Justices work « more like a set of independent law firms than a collegial court. It is very rare that a Justice would allow an associate to create the first draft of the opinion (Craske and Haigh 2002). The Justices edit this draft to their liking, and then circulate it to the other 39 members of the panel. Oftentimes the original drafts will later be edited based on discussions with colleagues, or in response to other circulated opinions. Figure 5 - Percentage of Cases with at least One Joint Opinion 100 80- 60- 8 U') 40- or O '5 8) m 20h E‘ a) 8 61’ U f 1954 as as 7'0 '7'2 '71: "is 'is 'so at '84 'as as so '52 '54 '55 as '60 2002 This is not to say that the opinion circulation process is not important in the High Court. Clearly, the ability to have the first opinion in circulation allows a Justice to frame the case according to his perspective. This gives the first opinion author the benefit of influencing the way his peers interpret the case (Kirby 2003). The other panel members may decide to ad0pt some—or the entirety—of the first author’s reasoning. The pressure to negotiate and bargain for agreement, however, is almost non- existent in the High Court. Because the majority opinion will have no less precedential value if it is divided among various individual opinions, the Justices may express their particular thought process without worry of losing support for the majority outcome. Although there is no tradition of a single majority opinion, the Justices do join with their colleagues. Sometimes this involves actually signing multiple names to a single opinion. 40 In this situation, it is impossible to discern which Justice is the main author.25 Other times, a Justice may submit a very short opinion expressing concurrence with the reasons and result of another’s opinion. When considered together, these two types of j oint opinions occur considerably often on the Court (see Figure 5). On average, 30.2% of all Opinions handed down are joint opinions. Between 1965 and 2002, an average of 77% of cases had at least one joint opinion. As Figure 5 illustrates, however, joint opinions are becoming increasingly common. Proliferating the decisions As in the US. Supreme Court, one of the most important duties of the High Court is its proliferation of precedent through written opinions. The High Court’s authorized reporter is the Commonwealth Law Reports (CLR). Volumes of the CLR have been published privately since its inception in 1903. The CLR has contained select decisions of the High Court, as well as Australian cases decided by the Privy Council in London. Additionally, cases can be found in several other places, including the Australian Law Reports, the Australian Law Journal Reports and more recently the Australasian Legal Information Institute website26 and the High Court’s official website.27 Editors of the various reports have always reported only a selection of the High Court’s business (Meek 1999). Only cases deemed “important” are typically included. The presence of constitutional interpretation is a flag for the editors, and these cases are always included (Jones 2002). The editors, however, have not always been able to 25 The lack of an authorship designation, however, has not stopped legal scholars from attempting to discern which of the Justices penned particular joint judgments. 26 .. http://www.austlrr.edu.au 27 http://wwwhcourt. gov.au 41 appreciate the future importance of a case. In an attempt to fill in the blanks, the CLR issued a special volume in 1994. This volume included cases from up to thirty years earlier that had gained importance in High Court jurisprudence over time. As the Court’s discretionary jurisdiction has increased dramatically over the years, a higher percentage of the cases handed down have been reported. The practice of handing down ex tempore or “spur of the moment” judgments has declined, as the agenda has become more heavily weighted to difficult legal and constitutional issues (Kirby 1992). Currently, nearly all judgments of the High Court are reserved judgments, or judgment accompanied by written opinions handed down some time after oral arguments. These reserved judgments provide more detailed reasons, and are thus more suitable for inclusion in the reporters. As the proportion 0 “important” decisions has increased, so has access to the entirety of the High Court’s business. In 1980, legal scholar David Solomon began publishing The Legal Reporter, in which he included all of the High Court’s judgments (Jones 2002). Additionally, since 1997, the High Court itself has made available the full text versions of all opinions on its official website. The media coverage of the Court has increased over time, and the major Australian newspapers each have journalists who spend a significant portion of their time covering the High Court’s business (Williams 1999) Practice and Procedure in Comparative Perspective The High Court and the US. Supreme Court are alike in many respects. Each court sits at the apex of a British common law-inspired system, and each is charged with interpreting and clarifying the law for its respective judiciary. Each exercises discretionary jurisdiction, and they are both understood to be important political as well 42 as legal institutions. In some important ways, though, these two institutions differ. These differences are critical for conceptualizing the ways in which the behaviors exhibited by members of the High Court bench might be different from what we know about US. Supreme Court Justices. Differences in judicial selection, jurisdiction, agenda setting and opinion production must be considered before an attempt is made to use existing judicial behavior literature to explain the production of j oint opinions on the High Court. 43 CHAPTER TWO: A BRIEF HISTORY OF THE HIGH COURT OF AUSTRALIA Judicial biographies in Australia are as rare as hen ’s teeth. — Justice Michael D. Kirby (1998a, 1) The High Court of Australia shares much in common with the American Supreme Court. From a number of distinct state systems of courts, the enactment of a constitution created a new federal jurisdiction. The High Court, like the US. Supreme Court, has seen periods of calm, times of turbulence, and a number of very interesting characters. In order to understand the functioning of the contemporary High Court, it is important to conduct at least a cursory review of the High Court’s history. This history can help to put various current issues into context. Additionally, the understanding of the behavior of recent members of the bench can be illuminated by examining the tradition of decision making and interpersonal relations among Justices throughout the Court’s hundred-year history. The Early History of the High Court The High Court of Australia first sat on October 6, 1903. This first sitting took place in Courtroom Number One of the Melbourne Supreme Court, and it was met by relatively little popular excitement. It was reportedly a slightly awkward affair, and one Melbourne newspaper quipped that “the most experienced man in the court was the crier” (Bennett 1980, 23). That there was little public attention, however, did not mean that the opening of the Court was not the subject of intense debate among lawyers and politicians (Galligan 1987).28 28 The Court’s first case, Hannah v. Dalgamo (1903) l CLR I, asked the Justices to decide when the Court actually came into existence. The decision on the merits hinged on whether the Court was in existence as of the ratification of the Constitution on January 1, 1901, or not until the passage of the Judiciary Act in August of 1903. The Court ducked this question, instead rescinding the grant of special 44 The eventuality of a supreme court of appeal was taken without much comment during the process of drafting the Commonwealth Constitution (Bennett 1980). In the late 18905, the most pressing disagreements had to do with the maintenance of appeals to the Privy Council. By 1903, however, additional serious complaints were lodged during the Parliamentary debate over the Judiciary Bill, which would create the High Court (McHugh 2002). Among these concerns were gloomy prophecies that the Court would be a waste of resources and would have little or no work to keep it occupied (Bennett 1980). Many observers also assumed that the long-established state supreme courts, coupled with the Privy Council, would eclipse the High Court in prestige and importance. In this way, the High Court would be rendered largely impotent (Bennett 1980). In the years that followed, however, the Court would prove its critics to be profoundly mistaken. In a series of measured steps and giant leaps, the High Court ultimately cemented itself as a competent and powerful tribunal. Establishing an Identity (1903-1919) The personalities on the first High Court bench—along with impassioned pleas from the ambitious Attorney-General Alfred Deakin—helped to assuage much of this criticism (McHugh 2002). Indeed, the three men selected by the Protectionist Party government were quite distinguished. All had worked together in various capacities to draft the Commonwealth Constitution, and were all largely in agreement as to the political and economic role of the newly constituted government (Bennett 1980). leave on the grounds that the negligence question at hand “was not a question of sufficient public importance” (Coper 2004). 45 The Chief Justice, Samuel Griffith, was the Premier of Queensland prior to Federation. Griffith was widely seen as the main architect of the constitution.29 While some of his contemporaries thought him too self-serving and ambitious for the position (McHugh 2002; Clark 2003), his appointment was generally heralded by the press as a positive step (Gibbs 2002). He had proven himself a great legal mind in his role as the Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of Queensland. The puisne Justices30 were also among the most upstanding of Australian citizens. In fact, many legal scholars — past and present — argue that either one would have been a superior choice for the position of Chief Justice (McHugh 2002). Richard O’Connor had been solicitor-general for the state of New South Wales and was the first Leader of the Government in the Commonwealth Senate. Edmond Barton resigned his position as the first Prime Minister of the newly constituted Commonwealth of Australia in order to serve on the High Court. Both O’Connor and Barton were chosen for the position by Attorney-General Alfred Deakin. Deakin was criticized for his choice of Barton, as onlookers correctly anticipated that Deakin wished to succeed Barton as Prime Minister (Bennett 1980). During the first few years of its existence, the High Court made a significant mark on the Australian legal world. This was due largely to the leadership of its first Chief Justice (McHugh 2002). The members of the Bench enjoyed a friendly personal rapport, and these agreeable relationships translated into a high degree of ideological unanimity in 2 . . . . . . 9 According to Botsman (2000), It was not until John Reynolds’ 1958 publication of Andrew Inglis Clark’s draft constitution that Griffith’s role has been diminished, although only minimally so. 0 The term puisne (pronounced ‘puny’) is used to refer to the ‘junior’ judges, or any High Court Justice other than the Chief Justice (Blackshield 2002f). 46 the Court’s output (Simpson and Simpson 2002). Each of the members of the first Griffith Court was dedicated to the protection of state’s rights (Botsman 2000). The puisne judges typically assented to opinions, which were mostly written solely by Griffith (Gibbs 2002). The Griffith Court managed to prove wrong those High Court critics who anticipated a weak and useless tribunal. In fact, Griffith managed to solidify the Court’s position as the paramount Australian legal institution in just a few years (Gibbs 2002). The first Court successfully confronted the Attorney-General (Priest 2002), the Commonwealth Parliament (Mason 2002b), and even the Privy Council (Bennett 1980). The Australian political climate was strongly majoritarian at the time; citizens and politicians alike became wary of the large role the High Court was assuming, especially in exercising judicial review of legislation and executive action (Galligan 1987). Many onlookers, especially Commonwealth Parliamentarians, began to wish for the impotent tribunal against which they once campaigned. It was the Commonwealth Parliament itself, in the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth) that provided for the High Court’s power of judicial review (Mason 20020). While these concerns were not center stage in the parliamentary debates over the bill, they began to reveal themselves as the Court began to assert its substantial role (Bennett 1980). By 1906, the Court’s workload had increased such that its members requested an enlarged bench. Their request was answered, and the Protecti oni st Party government appointed Justices Isaac Isaacs and Henry Higgins (Bennett 1980). With this addition, however, the personal and professional goodwill on the Bench deteriorated markedly (Gibbs 2002). The main point of professional contention was the intergovernmental 47 immunities doctrine established by the foundation members of the Court (Mason 2002b). This doctrine held that the Constitution contained an implied protection of the reserved state powers against Commonwealth interference, and vice versa (Coper 2002b). This arrangement was derived from American Supreme Court principles in cases like McCulloch v. Maryland (1819),31 and followed nicely from Griffith’s vision of the appropriate structure of coordinate federalism (Zines 1997). In its first year, the High Court cited the US. Supreme Court’s decision in McCulloch when it struck down a state tax on a federal officer’s income.32 The newer Justices disagreed, and began to write a large number of dissenting opinions (Gibbs 2002). Part of the problem centered on the method of constitutional interpretation instituted by the Court’s founding members. The reasoning behind the doctrine of intergovernmental immunities involved distinctly political considerations (Patapan 2000c). This was largely a result of the characters on the Bench at the time. The first three Justices were all senior statesmen, heavily involved in the creation of the federal system found in the Constitution (Galligan 1987). Griffith, Barton and O’Connor shared a common political vision, namely of a strong system that divided powers between the states and the Commonwealth (Patapan 2000c). For this reason, they often agreed on a balanced, political approach to distributing powers between levels of government. Because the first Justices were among the framers of the document, their interpretive approach “relied more heavily on the sagacity and authority of the Justices than on logical consistency or a literal construing of the constitution’s text” (Galligan 1987, 80). 31 17 US. (4 Wheat) 316. 32 D 'Emden v. Pedder, 1 CLR 91 (1904). 48 They tended to approach the question as politicians allocating power, and not as lawyers interpreting the law. Neither Isaacs nor Higgins accepted the doctrine of intergovernmental immunities established by the founding members of the Court (Cowen 1955). There is some scholarly disagreement, however, on the substance of their complaint. It is clear that Isaacs and Higgins were both involved in the framing of the constitution. Some argue, however, that these men saw the Constitution in terms of its legal consequences, and not in political terms (Goldring 1997). According to this view, their legalistic perspective kept them from agreeing with the holistic interpretation style of the founding members of the Bench, instead preferring a strictly legal approach (Patapan 2000c). Others argue that it was not the interpretation style that troubled Higgins and Isaacs, but the political vision that was supported by its use. Galligan notes that “they were both ardent federalists intent upon expanding commonwealth powers,” 3 position distinctly opposed to the existing High Court doctrine (Galligan 1987, 84). Isaacs and Higgins were both unimpressed by the doctrines of immunity and reserved powers. Higgins was particularly and vocally critical of the doctrine of implied immunities, and took to berating American Chief Justice John Marshall for his landmark opinion on the issue (Zines 1997). Soon after their appointments, Isaacs and Higgins also expressed dismay at the methods of constitutional interpretation favored by the other members of the Bench. In Baxter ’3 Case,33 the Court was charged with determining the extent to which the High Court must be bound by the decisions of the Privy Council. The majority in this case 33 (1907) 4 CLR 1087. 49 refused to apply the Privy Council’s decision in Webb v. Outtrim (1907).34 Griffith’s majority opinion in Baxter’s Case, joined by Barton and O’Connor, embraced a contextual strategy for interpreting the constitution: There is no doubt as to the meaning of the words used, but the circumstances under which the power was intended to be exercised must be discovered from some other source. That source is to be found in a consideration of the whole purview of the Constitution, and the answer to the question cannot be given without having regard to its history. (Baxter’s Case, 1103) In his dissenting opinion, Isaacs argued that such external information is at the very least unnecessary in this case: I know of no clearer words in the Constitution, or words having a more obvious purpose. Sec. 74 is one of the pillars of the Constitution. Unless it stands firm, much of the true meaning of that document is lost. (Baxter ’5 Case, 1151-52) Higgins conceded that he would agree with the majority as a statesman, but asserted that his role on the Bench required something decidedly different. In his words: I admit that, before taking my seat on this bench, I thought that it would be wiser to leave, as far as possible, the interpretation and the application of Australian laws to Australian Courts But my duty here is to accept the law as I find it. (Baxter’s Case, 1166) This increase in disagreement on the Court was a matter of great concern for the press (Bennett 1980). There were only four dissents before the expansion of the Bench in 1906 (Lynch 2002b), but the appointment of Isaacs and Higgins led almost immediately to an increase in individual concurring opinions and, eventually, dissenting opinions (Mason 2002b). This new tradition of disagreement and individual opinion authorship is one that continues to the present day (Lynch 2002b). Griffith’s hold on the direction of Court doctrine was further diminished with the replacement of O’Connor by Frank Gavan Duffy and the 1913 expansion of the Bench (Mason 2002b). Charles Powers and George 34 (1906) 4 CLR 356. 50 Rich35 filled the two newly created seats on the Court. All three of these Justices were appointed by the Australian Labor Party government. By the time of Griffith’s resignation in 1919, the Court’s thinking had changed substantially, especially in terms of constitutional interpretation (Bennett 1980). Growing Pains (1919-1950) Settling on a replacement for Griffith was difficult. Griffith’s resignation date was postponed twice as the government debated whether to elevate a sitting puisne Justice or to choose from outside the Court (F ricke 1999). The Cabinet preferred to give the job to Justice Barton, but his old age and ill health led Griffith to recommend against the idea. Finally, the Nationalist Party Cabinet settled on Adrian Knox. Shortly thereafter, Barton died. Hayden Starke was appointed by the Nationalist government to replace him. Although Knox was the Chief, Isaacs had a commanding personality and largely dominated the Court during this time (F ricke 2002d). On the Griffiths Court, Isaacs was a frequent dissenter, but things had changed by the early 1920s. Isaacs’s expansive view of Commonwealth power began to win a majority on the Court (Kirby 2005b). He penned a long line of joint opinions, to which Knox, Rich, and Starke generally concurred. In the aftermath of World War I, the Commonwealth government was enjoying a strengthened position in Australian federal politics. The founding members of the Bench had generally sought to protect the states from the Commonwealth’s encroachment into their reserve powers (Bennett 1980), but had also interpreted the Commonwealth defense 35 Before Rich’s appointment, Albert Bathurst Piddington was appointed to the second new seat. He resigned before taking his seat, however, amidst criticism that neither he nor Powers were of the keenest contemporary legal minds (Bennett 1980). Rich was then appointed to replace Piddington. Powers did not seem to be dissuaded by the popular criticism. 51 power in extraordinarily broad terms (Galligan 1987). The expansion of Commonwealth defense power, followed with the introduction of Justices who favored the expansion of Commonwealth power over the states, led to what is largely regarded as the foundation of Australian constitutional law: The Engineers’ Case.36 The Griffith Court had largely approached constitutional interpretation in terms of political and legal context, and the doctrines of intergovernmental immunities and reserved state powers were the results. Engineers’ swept these doctrines aside and replaced them with a doctrine derived from a literal approach to constitutional interpretation (Blackshield 2002d). Substantively, the decision gave the commonwealth government the power to bind the states under legislation passed concerning the conciliation and arbitration of industrial disputes. The joint opinion found no legal basis for the Court’s earlier decisions protecting the states from the legislative power of the Commonwealth (Bennett 1980). While this result might have been achieved by augmenting the doctrines of immunity and reserved powers, the Court dismissed these doctrines altogether, claiming: They are sometimes at variance with the natural meaning of the text of the Constitution; some are irreconcilable with others, and some are individually rested on reasons not founded on the words of the Constitution or any recognized principle of the common law underlying the expressed terms of the Constitution but on implication drawn from what is called the principle of ‘necessity’, that being itself referable to no more definite standard than the personal opinion of the Judge who declares it. (Engineers ’, 141-42) This decision served to greatly expand the Commonwealth govemment’s legislative powers under section 92 of the Constitution (Zines 1997). This is especially true in regard to trade, commerce, and arbitration (Fricke 2002d). Engineers ’ marked the 36 Amalgamated Society of Engineers v. Adelaide Steamship C 0. Ltd. (1920) 28 CLR 129. 52 introduction of a newly legalist approach to constitutional interpretation, and largely resulted from the replacement of the early politicians on the Court with purportedly apolitical lawyers (Galligan 1987; Patapan 2000c). Engineers ’ reliance on legalism, however, is seen by some as a strategic decision rather than a philosophical one: One cannot escape the view that in the Engineers’ case, as elsewhere, reliance on ‘express provisions’ and the ‘golden rule’ of interpretation was emphasized because it suited a purpose and was a means of advancing the vision he had of Australia and its governmental institutions. (Cowen and Zines 2002, 426) Whatever the reason it was employed, however, legalism remained the dejure method of interpretation on the Court for decades to come. As one scholar notes, “Engineers ’ can be seen as the decisive juncture where conventional rules of interpretation asserted their dominance over the innovation of federalism” (Patapan 2000c, 250). Justice Kirby agrees with this assessment, arguing that Isaacs merely used the rhetoric of the legalistic style of interpretation “and applied it with uncompromising rigour” (Kirby 2005b, 27). During the Knox Court, several procedural changes were introduced. Attorney- General John Latham proposed an amendment to the Judiciary Act. This amendment provided pensions for Justices on the High Court. It also discussed the High Court’s need for a permanent home in the seat of government, although action would not be taken on this recommendation for more than fifty years (Bennett 1980). The Court also adopted several changes to the High Court Rules, the most memorable of which was the method for conducting the delivery of opinions. Instead of requiring the Justices to read the text of their written opinions aloud in open court, these changes allowed the Justices to simply state their opinion briefly and then deliver the written reasons to the clerical staff in open court (F ricke 2002d). 53 As the 1920s drew to a close, Isaacs lost his hold on the majority of the Court (Fricke 2002d). Subsequent challenges to state law under section 92 were largely handled through statutory interpretation as opposed to constitutional interpretation. Many of these cases began to whittle away at the extreme centralization of government power advocated by the Engineer ’s decision (F ricke 2002d). With the death of Higgins and the resignation of Powers in 1929, Isaacs’ views became more isolated (Fricke 2002d). Owen Dixon was appointed by the Nationalist government to replace Higgins, but the Labor Party was back in office before Powers could be replaced. Soon after, Chief Justice Knox retired. The new Labor government appointed Herbert Evatt and Edward McTieman as replacements for Knox and Powers, and elevated Isaacs to the position of Chief Justice. Evatt was, at age 36, the youngest ever to be elevated to the High Court (Bayne 2002). McTieman and Evatt had both been involved in Labor politics, and the pair of appointments attracted significant criticism from the media (Bennett 1980). Neither Evatt nor McTieman sat on the Court during Isaacs’ tenure as Chief Justice, as he would remain in this position for a mere 42 weeks (F ricke 2002c). Effectively, the Isaacs Court was a Bench of five. As the Great Depression took hold, the once steady flow of taxation cases was replaced by an increasing number of bankruptcies (F ricke 2002c). Overall, though, the work of the Court diminished significantly during this period. As Isaacs was uncharacteristically ill during much of his Chief Justiceship, the considerable influence of Owen Dixon was allowed significant space to flourish (F ricke 2002c). Isaacs resigned in 1931 in order to accept the vice-regal position of Govemor- General. Despite rumors that Evatt would be elevated to succeed him, the position 54 instead went to the seventy-eight year old Gavan Duffy.37 Some historians believe that this choice was the Labor govemment’s reaction to criticism of its previous appointments, which were perceived as politically motivated (F ricke 2002a). During the same year, under pressure to economize, the Labor government officially reduced the number of seats on the High Court Bench from seven to six, leaving unfilled the empty seat vacated by Isaacs (F ricke 2002b). The circuit system, which required that the judges travel regularly to each of the state capitals, was suspended during this time in an attempt to save money (Del Villar and Simpson 2002). The Gavan Duffy Court was unspectacular by most accounts. Tensions rose as alliances between the Justices shifted, and the rivalry between the Court’s two leaders, Dixon and Evatt, flourished (F ricke 2002b). The work of the Court was still dominated by Depression-related litigation, including many bankruptcy, taxation and corporations law cases. Gavan Duffy’s retirement in 1935 led to the appointment of John Latham by the United Australia/Country Party coalition government.38 For the first time since Griffith’s departure, the Court enjoyed a capable and effective Chief Justice (Cowen 2002) The Latham Court enjoyed an unmatched measure of membership stability. All four of the longest-serving Justices sat during this time, and the Court saw only one retirement and two appointees during the fourteen year period (Douglas 2002). Evatt . retired in order to stand for the 1940 commonwealth parliamentary elections. He was successful, and went on to serve as Attorney-General and Minister for External Affairs 37 Frank Gavan Duffy may have been seventy-eight years on the earth, but had only celebrated 20 birthdays, as he was born on February 29, 1852, 38 . . . . . The United Australia Party changed rts name to the Liberal Party 111 1944. 55 for the Labor government until 1949 (Bayne 2002). He was replaced on the Court by Dudley Williams, a United Australia Party appointee. William Webb was appointed in 1947 by the Labor government to fill the newly reinstated seat on the High Court bench, bringing the Court back to its previous size of seven.39 Additionally, Justices Latham and Dixon each took leave from the bench in order to serve as Foreign Ministers (Douglas 2002). The stability of membership on the High Court, however, was accompanied by stable conflicts between members of the Court. As Roger Douglas explains, The most bitter conflicts were those between Starke on one hand and the two former Labor politicians, Evatt and McTieman on the other — but Starke was also resentful towards Dixon, somewhat contemptuous of Rich, and cool towards Latham. Evatt reciprocated Starke’s hostility and his relations with Latham could sometimes be prickly. (Douglas 2002, 421) This severe fragmentation effected a notable decline in the frequency of joi nt opinions, which until this time had been relatively frequent (Cowen 2002). Votes dissenting from the case outcome were present in 42% of cases during the Latham Court, and in an astounding 72% of cases in 1944 (Blackshield 1972). This, coupled with the even number of judges on the Bench until 1946, meant that a large number of decisions were handed down by an evenly divided Court (Bennett 1980). The idea of holding conferences among the Justices was abandoned as an impossibility, in great contrast to the daily lunches enjoyed by the Court’s first three members (Bennett 1980). Starke seems to have been the instigator of much of this trouble, refirsing to circulate draft 39 The relevant amendment to the Judiciary Act 1903 (Cth) was introduced by the Commonwealth Attorney-General, Herbert Evatt. Thus, the new appointment would be made by the Labor government, of which he was a member. 56 opinions and making “no attempt to conceal his personal animosities” (Cowen 1967, 117) The Latham Court did manage to make a mark on several important social issues brought forward by World War II. These issues were important to lawyers, but they were also the most widely salient issues of the day among the citizens generally (Hayne 2003). Many of the Court’s decisions in these cases knocked back Labor government plans for increasing the power of the Commonwealth to nationalize industry (Galligan 2002). In the Bank Nationalisation Case,40 the Court struck down Labor Prime Minister Chifley’ 5 plan to nationalize all of the banks in Australia. In the Communist Party Case (1951) the Court held the Communist Party Dissolution Act 1950 (Cth) unconstitutional, despite Dixon’s best efforts to uphold the anti-communi st legislation (Dawson and Anderson 1996). In this decision to limit the use of defense power during peacetime—and to prevent its use to curtail the expression of pro-communi st sentiment—Latham was the lone dissenter (Botsman 2000). Through his tenure, Latham was seen as the epitome of a legalistic judge. Some blame this legalism for his position as a dissenter in the critical cases of his day (Cowen and Zines 2002, 429), but Dixon criticized Latham’s opinion in the Communist Party Case as being an abrogation of the judicial duty to uphold the law (Dawson and Anderson 1996). 40 Bank of New South Wales v. The Commonwealth (1948) 76 CLR 1. 57 Time to Regroup (1950-1964) In the twilight years of the Latham Court, both Rich and Starke resigned. They were replaced in 1950 by the Liberal Coalition41 government appointments of William Fullagar and Frank Kitto. On Latham’s retirement in 1952, Owen Dixon was elevated to the Chief Justiceship and Alan Taylor was appointed by the Liberal Coalition government. Dixon presided over a notably harmonious bench, and much credit is often given to the new appointees (Simpson and Simpson 2002). As most of the dissenters had been replaced with more “likeminded” Justices, a spirit of friendliness and cooperation grew quickly, and helped to support the stature of the Court in the public eye (Bennett 1980). The Dixon Court, however, did endure a great deal of change over the years. Before the end of his tenure, Fullagar would be replaced by William Owen, Webb by Douglas Menzies, and Williams by Victor Windeyer. All were appointees of the Liberal Coalition government, though, furthering the homogeneity of thought and experience on the Bench (Simpson and Simpson 2002). Although Dixon’s leadership ability had been apparent nearly from the time of his appointment, it flourished to an unprecedented degree during his tenure as Chief (Bennett 1980). He was adept at forging consensus on the Court, both through his facilitation of professional cooperation and his negotiation of personal relationships (Smyth 2003b). Dixon is often associated with the term ‘strict and complete legalism.’ Indeed, Dixon noted that “[t]here is no other safe guide to judicial decisions in great conflicts than a 41 The Liberal Coalition at this time was made up of the Liberal Party (once the United Australia Party) and the Country Party. The Country Party adopted the name “National Country Party” in 1975, and further amended its name in 1982, becoming simply the “National Party.” The Liberal Coalition today is made up of the Liberal and National Parties. 58 strict and complete legalism."42 Some interpret this remark to mean that Dixon favored an approach to constitutional interpretation that sidelines the consideration of practical policy consequences (Bhattacharya and Smyth 2001b). The legalist reputation of the Dixon Court is enhanced by the perception that Douglas Menzies’s appointees also favored this approach (Sawer 1975). Others argue that this reputation for legalism may be due more to the famous comment being taken out of context than a mechanistic view of the judicial task on Dixon’s part (Hayne 2002). In this view, Dixon rejected the notion that judges had to ignore information about the implications following from judicial decisions (Cowen and Zines 2002). The Dixon Court, according to many scholars, remained flexible and even creative in the face of difficult challenges (Zines 2002a). During this period, the Commonwealth government was dominated by the Liberal Coalition. Unlike Labor governments past, the Liberal Coalition government was generally happy to stay within the express powers granted by the Constitution (Zines 2002a). For this reason, the Court had little reason to strike down Commonwealth legislation.43 This light use of the judicial review power contributed to the Dixon Court’s reputation as a legalistic bench. This is not to say that the Dixon Court was inactive. Great innovations were made during this time, especially regarding the interpretation of section 92 of the Constitution. This section provides for freedom of interstate commerce, and had previously been interpreted as a limitation only on protectionist mechanisms among the states. The Dixon Court continued the evolution begun by the Bank Nationalisation Case, giving section 92 7 4" (1952) 35 CLR xi, xiv. 4 . . . . . 3 One notable exception rs the Boilermaker’s Case (1956), in which the Court expanded the operation of separation of powers at the Commonwealth government level. 59 a distinctly laissez-faire flavor (Sawer 1957). The Court overturned previous rulings, instead holding that the Constitution confers an individual right to free trade, subject only to reasonable regulation (Zines 2002a). In the Second Uniform Tax Case (1957), the Court affirmed the power of the Commonwealth government to tax to such a degree as to make it politically impractical for the states to levy additional taxes (Bennett 1980). All of this, coupled with the increase in Commonwealth defense powers during the Latham Court, contributed to a further erosion of state powers. The Modern High Court With the appointment of Chief Justice Garfield Barwick in 1964, the High Court began a period of transformation. The membership of the Court shifted dramatically through Barwick’s tenure, and he instigated several important changes in jurisdiction and procedure during this time (Mason 2002a). The Court physically took its place among the other branches of Australian government, leading to “a new national vision of the Court” (Kirby 1996). More than his predecessors, Barwick emphasized the High Court’s role as the final arbiter of the important questions of the day (Mason 2003b). The Barwick Court (1964—1981) Chief Justice Barwick’s term was a time of transformation for the High Court in a number of important ways. The Barwick Court saw many changes in jurisdiction and procedure. Some of these changes were due largely to the work of Barwick himself, both as Chief Justice and in his previous role of Commonwealth Attorney-General. During his tenure as Chief, the Court gained greater independence from the Privy Council, dramatically decreased its nondiscretionary docket, and obtained administrative control over the affairs of the Australian judiciary (Mason 2002a). Barwick was even instrumental in securing a permanent home for the High Court, which prior to 1980 was a 60 traveling tribunal. The new retirement age of 70, however, was the brainchild of the Commonwealth Parliament, not Barwick. The Court also saw huge membership shifts during this time and ended the period much younger than it began (see Table 1). Secondly, many jurisdictional and procedural changes dramatically altered the nature of the Court’s work. Finally, due in part to the first two changes, the role of the Court and its Justices began its own transformation. These changes began to build momentum as politicians, the public, and the Justices themselves began to re-examine the position of the High Court in the government and society. Garfield Barwick was appointed Chief Justice by Liberal Coalition Prime Minister Robert Menzies. Although Barwick had an impressive resume, he had a difficult time fitting in on the High Court. As one scholar has noted, Barwick did not slip easily on to the bench. Rather, he was an intruder in the club. (Marr 1980, 213) His reputation at the bar was extraordinary, so much so that he was knighted in 1953 (W interton 2002). Immediately prior to his appointment to the High Court, he was serving as the Liberal Party Member of Parliament for Parramatta, Minister for External Affairs,44 and Commonwealth Attorney-General.45 Many of his contemporaries believed that Barwick had aspirations to assume the Prime Mini stership on the retirement of Barwick had mixed reviews at best in terms of his role as Minister for External Affairs. In one instance, he mistakenly claimed that America would be necessarily drawn into any potential Australian-Indonesian conflict as a result of its treaty obligations. This caused a stir among Australians and members of the Johnson administration alike (Galligan 1984). 45 In Australia, the Commonwealth, state, and territory Attorneys-General are members of their respective parliaments, and are ministers of state. For this reason, the Commonwealth or State Attorney-General is always an elected politician. Barwick was not the first former Commonwealth Attorney-General to serve on the High Court, as Henry Higgins, Isaac Isaacs, and John Latham had also previously served in this position. The last such appointee to date was the controversial Justice Lionel Murphy in 1975. 61 Robert Menzies, but the retirement of Owen Dixon forced Barwi ck to choose between the two prestigious jobs (Winterton 2002). Following Barwick’s appointment, there were several more changes in the Court’s membership. In fact, not one of the Justices who began the Barwick Court would remain until its end. Two Justices served their entire High Court careers within the space of Barwick’s tenure. This was due largely to Barwick’ s unprecedented seventeen-year stint as Chief Justice. For this reason, legal scholars tend to split the Barwick Court into distinct periods (Mason 2002a). Near the beginning of the Barwick Court, the Liberal Coalition government made several appointments to the Bench. Cyril Walsh was appointed after Taylor’s death in 1969. After graduating at the top of his class at the University of Sydney, Walsh had acquired a substantial law practice, sharing chambers with Barwick. Unlike many Liberal party appointees, Walsh had never been involved in legal academia, and he had never taken silk (F ricke 1986). Shy and modest, Walsh was appointed to the New South Wales Court of Appeal at the recommendation of his admiring colleagues at the Bar (McLaughlin 2002). He held this position until his elevation to the High Court. The following year, Kitto resigned and was replaced by Harry Gibbs. The son of a successful lawyer, Gibbs excelled in his academic career. Shortly after beginning his law practice, Gibbs enlisted in the military during World War 11. Subsequently, he helped to plan a post-war government for Papua and New Guinea. After returning to practice, where he quickly developed great prestige, he was appointed to the Queensland Supreme Court (Jackson and Priest 2002). He was then promoted to the Chief Justiceship, and 62 later to the Supreme Court of the Australian Capital Territory and the Federal Court of Bankruptcy. It was from this position that he was elevated to the High Court. In 1972, Windeyer resigned and Owen died. They were replaced by Ninian Stephen and Anthony Mason. Stephen, like Gibbs, enlisted in the military at the beginning of his law career. He returned to join the Melbourne Bar, and from there was appointed to the Supreme Court of Victoria. Two years later, he was elevated to the High Court. Mason served in the Royal Australian Air Force before completing law school. After a distinguished career in legal practice, he was appointed to the New South Wales Court of Appeal. He was elevated to the High Court shortly thereafter. The Labor Party came into power in 1972. Labor’s first new appointment to the Barwick Court was Sydney Jacobs in 1974, in the seat left vacant after Walsh’s death. Jacobs enlisted during World War II, and was appointed as a military intelligence officer. Upon his return, he completed law school and developed a legal practice. He stood for a New South Wales Parliament vacancy, but his campaign failed by a single vote (Blackshield and Mackrell 2002). He was then appointed to the Supreme Court of New South Wales, where he worked with Mason and Walsh. He became that court’s president before being elevated to the High Court. Soon thereafter, Menzies died at a New South Wales Bar Association function and the Labor government appointed the Commonwealth Attorney-General Lionel Murphy to replace him. Murphy, who first earned a degree in organic chemistry, sat for the New South Wales Bar exam before actually graduating from law school. He passed, and proceeded to make a name for himself in labor law. He was elected to the Commonwealth Senate in 1961, and subsequently was selected to be 63 $582 toned SE52 2:: DZ; 5::8 do 5250 2: $3 $562 3&on or :80 x2255 Eiwco 2: mo mconEoE 3:365 * 07: EB: impasse; ocoz 82 Hansen 32 mm 82 tonnes 07: a ccoméaéezé 9;: 0-0 oooz Baas; <3 om 8% 82:5 024 N. Emboéé oooz a; E asmeoi >62 8 8% in», oz; N. szozoé oooz a E 23885 52 cm 32 12%.; 024 m. .£02.3\mm0m5>o 0:02 .mbn N ESmBOr—m U~> xv mNQ— cosmoam oz; Eon: ocozefifi 252 a; a “cameos >32 5 on: 225 mi ,5 :53 amassed EB o-< 82 2658 32 S S2 39:: oz; :23: ens—2.2253 252 2oz Ensues; 65 cm 82 22.252 5< m2 ES Emsofisoo 9&6 o-< 252 29:6 >32 3 N3: 225%: 024 a Eméoaéa 29 on a; m 22:6 262 2 82 cos: 024 a images 252 onoz Essex. 52 3 82 *ozg S< Eon: amass E 252 a; E asses amz om. :2 £82 075 a 20229:; ocoz a; x _ 59865 30 m :2 Bee 024 N. .eozjoséo 252 252 Benson 0; oo 22 canon m2 EB: .3228; 2Q o-< 8oz nausea amz $23.3 523; .23.. _. EC :7; __..5:::. :29 Tax .5391 :30 its: 2: no 3.2:: 8:2... - _ 2...; Es: 64 leader of the opposition and later Attorney-General. Against Barwick’s protests, Murphy was appointed to the High Court. After sustaining a fractured hip at the age of 84, McTieman was confined to a wheelchair.46 Because the High Court had no accessible entrances, McTieman ended hisretumed to Australia and built a reputation as a capable practitioner. He declined an offer to replace Taylor on the Court, but accepted another invitation a few years later. After another two years of the Barwick Court, Jacobs retired and was replaced by Ronald Wilson. Wilson left school after his tenth year and started work as a messenger in his local Western Australia courthouse. He enlisted in the Royal Australian Air Force and flew Spitfires in England. After the war, when he could not secure a position as a flying clergyman, he abandoned hope at joining the ministry and chose to study law instead. After graduating, he worked in Western Australia’s state prosecutor’s office. He studied briefly in the United States on a Fullbright Scholarship. He returned to the Crown service, and was appointed Solicitor-General of Western Australia. He served in this position for ten years before being the first Western Australian ever appointed to the High Court. These changes in membership resulted in a Bench that resembled very little of the original Barwick Court. These changes affected a shift in approach that was at first subtle, but set the groundwork for the more marked departures that would occur in later Courts (Botsman 2000). The Barwick Court, though, is probably best known for its extraordinarily literal interpretation of tax law under section 90 of the Constitution. Most 46 Apparently, McTieman sustained his injury while “trying to squash a bug on the floor of his bedroom” (Callinan 1999). Chief Justice Barwick denied McTiernan’s request for a ramp to be built, leaving him physically unable to continue his record-breaking tenure on the High Court. 65 notably, the Barwick Court majority gutted section 260 of the Income Tax Assessment Act 1936 (Cth) (Mason 2002a). This section was meant to be an anti-avoidance provision. In cases like F C T v. Commonwealth Aluminium47 and Slutzkin v. F C 7148 the Barwick Court set the groundwork for the creation of numerous tax avoidance schemes by reading section 260 very narrowly (Kobetsky and Krever 2002). This process added complexity to the tax code, and purposefirlly failed to consider the intent of the legislatures. Barwick himself argued against any civic or moral duty of citizens to comply with tax laws, citing only a legal obligation (W interton 2002). Criticism of this interpretation came from the Court’s onlookers, but also from within the Court. Justice Murphy was the most outspoken of the dissenters. Later, he noted that: The [Barwick] Court used to read Acts of Parliament absolutely literally - the words were all important - the spirit was often ignored. This made it easy for any competent lawyer or accountant to devise schemes to turn profits into tax losses. Because of this many of the rich ceased to pay tax and the burden fell on the workers and the scrupulous. (Murphy 1983, 1) Chief Justice Barwick’s large personality shaped a good deal of the public’s opinion of the Court (Mason 2002a). He twice gave informal constitutional advice to the Governor-General, both instances seen by the public as morally dubious at best. The second and most famous of these is the advice he gave to Governor-General John Kerr surrounding the 1975 dismissal of Prime Minister Gough Whitlam. When it appeared that Whitlam would not be able to get the budget passed in the Senate, the Govemor- General solicited Barwick’s extra-judicial advice on the situation. Barwick responded in writing that he agreed with Kerr’s unprecedented plan to sack the Prime Minister and 47 (1980) 143 CLR 646 48(1977) 140 CLR 314 66 invite the opposition leader to form an interim government (Blackshield 2002c). Barwick continued to defend his role in the dismissal, but many of the Court’s observers maintain that the advice was controversial at best (W interton 2002). Additionally, the modicum of civility maintained prior to Barwick’s tenure eroded significantly over this period. Especially tense was the relationship between Barwick and Murphy. They differed in a firndamental way in their approach to law and their conception of the nature of democracy (Hocking 1997). Barwick had opposed Murphy’s appointment, and was unabashed in his criticism after Murphy joined the bench. One scholar has observed that the Court was “. . .dominated by the increasingly erratic behaviour of its Chief Justice, Garfield Barwick” (Hocking 1997, 227). The Gibbs Court (1981-1987) As compared with the Barwick Court, there were fewer changes in personnel during the Gibbs Court (see Table 2). Upon Barwick’s 1981 retirement, Liberal Coalition Prime Minister Malcolm Frasier appointed Harry Gibbs to the position of Chief Justice. Gerard Brennan was selected to fill the resulting vacancy. This pair of appointments was meant to help depoliticize the Court after the controversy of the Barwick Court (Galligan 1987). The son of a Justice of the Supreme Court of Queensland, Brennan passed his high school exams at age 16. After university, he worked as an associate to his father. He had a very successful practice in Queensland before his appointment as the first President of the Administrative Appeals Tribunal. He was also appointed to the Federal Court, but stayed only a short time before being elevated to the High Court. Soon thereafter, Justice Stephens resigned in order to take up the Govemor- Generalship. Justice Keith Aickin died as a result of injuries sustained in a car accident 67 (Holloway 2001). William Deane succeeded Stephens, and Daryl Dawson joined the Bench shortly thereafter, both appointed by conservative Prime Minister Malcolm Frasier. Daryl Dawson was appointed to the High Court from his position as Solicitor General for the state of Victoria. In this role, he had argued 60 cases in the High Court, some of them critical in the development of Australian constitutional law. William Deane, who was knighted by the Queen of England in 1988, has gone on to become a very popular figure in Australian public life. Born to a strict Catholic family, Deane excelled in a string of prestigious private schools and colleges (Holloway 2001). He went on to become a university lecturer, a prominent lawyer, and finally a judge before his appointment to the High Court Bench. His only participation in party politics was his short-lived membership in the Democratic Labor Party—a ri ght-win g anti-communist party founded in the late 19505 (Stephens 2002). He, like his predecessor, would later resign in order to accept an appointment as Governor-General. These High Court appointments, along with the growing tension between Gibbs and Murphy over Murphy’s legal troubles, changed the dynamics of the Bench. In November of 1983, information was leaked to the press about illegally recorded telephone conversations between a Sydney solicitor and an unnamed judge. It was not until three months later that the judge on the tapes was identified as now High Court Justice Lionel Murphy. At this time, a series of allegations—most politically motivated—were leveled against Murphy (Blackshield 2002a). Among these charges was the allegation that he gave legal advice to and attempted to influence the judge in the trial of an acquaintance. 68 A _ com oct— wcm :oamEmUV 853m HEEEEooAEm 2; do :32 a 3 meme 2: E acorn bus; csoan-o_§ooEoQ of 02:3 2.on * .350 76%? team 582 Enzgmzlx 2: :o 83 8:28ng 366:3,5955 or 07: a ==oo.<3_:\o=€._ 23v 0-0 0.52 asses <3 3 82 823 3< N. .<3_:\o=o56 252 a; 2 32:8 <3 on or: 32.83 024 Nt .n_®2.3\mnoeo>o 0:02 .mbm N ESmBOgL U—> wv Mm©_ cosmoum A3< m: :53 202235 29 0-< 2:2 22:8 3mz mm S2 3%: 024 a Engage; 29 0-m a; m 2658 3% 2 82 Ea: 07: ._. Embozoaoo 252 .23 m 2658 3mz s :2 2.80 07: a o_§.£o2.0\o=o§ 8oz 5; 2 nausea 0; we 22 8min 07: a. mo§_§oe\o=o§0 oooz a:2 m 2056 30 mm 32 52:55 07: a. £22225 oooz ocoz asses 0; 8 22 €32 07: 5 20.0225 252 a; : assess So 9 :2 3&0 :20 :35 o... .5 3.2:: 822:. - N osfi 69 Two separate Senate committees looked into charges against Murphy, the second of which resulting in his prosecution. At the first trial, in 1985, he was convicted of attempting to pervert the course of Justice. On appeal, the conviction was quashed and a new trial ordered. At the second trial in April of 1986, Murphy was acquitted of all wrongdoing. In light of the fact that Murphy had recently been diagnosed with terminal cancer, impeachment hearings against him had been halted (McGarvie 1999). Nevertheless, Chief Justice Gibbs wrote to Murphy and suggested that he refrain from returning to the Bench. He indicated that he thought Murphy’s return undesirable, and that he thus had no intention of listing Murphy to sit (Campbell and Lee 2001). Notwithstanding the wishes of the Chief Justice, Murphy returned to the Bench until his death later that year (Blackshield 2002a). It was during this turbulent time that some of the most provocative cases in the Court’s history made their way to the Justices (Twomey 2002). The often-divided Court began to expand the powers of the Commonwealth government at the expense of the states. The proposal to dam the Franklin River may not sound politically controversial, but it lead to the infamous Tasmanian Dam Case (1983).49 In this case, the majority of the Court dealt a crushing blow to state sovereignty by preventing Tasmania from building a dam on land entered in a ‘World Heritage List’ at the federal govemment’s request (Twomey 2002). The opinions in the case, for both the majority and the minority, were “replete with policy considerations and value judgments” (Zines 2002c, 14). 49 Commonwealth v. Tasmania, 158 CLR 1 7O In Koowarta ’5 Case (1982),50 the Court expanded the Commonwealth govemment’s external affairs power. The Commonwealth govemment’s conciliation and arbitration powers were also expanded during this time, especially in the C YSS Case (1983).51 The Court’s role in the centralization of government power did not go unnoticed, even by a previously disinterested public (Walker 2002b; Zines 2000). During the Gibbs Court, the High Court’s place at the pinnacle of the Australian legal system was finally secured. The Court severed its remaining ties to the Privy Council. In Caltex Oil v. X1 Petroleum (1984),52 the Court asserted that its decisions should prevail over Privy Council decisions on the same subject matter. Additionally, the Australia Acts 1986 (Cth) were enacted at the end of the Gibbs Court, abolishing appeals to the Privy Council from the state courts. In 1984, by an amendment to the Judiciary Act of 1903, appeals as of right were replaced with a system requiring special leave to appeal. This gave the High Court an almost completely discretionary agenda. Perhaps in part because of this newfound docket control, the Court began to take on a more flexible approach to jurisprudence. In the process, Australian scholars point to the Gibbs court as the beginning of the end of strict legalism in the High Court, and a move toward a “more expansive view of Commonwealth legislative power” (Twomey 2002, 305). The Mason Court (1987-1995) Ifthe Gibbs Court began to move away from strict legalism, then the Mason Court might be said to have abandoned it altogether (Doyle 1996). While the eight years of the 50 Koowarta v. Bjelke-Petersen, 153 CLR 168 51 R v. Coldham; Ex Parte Australian Social Welfare Union, 159 CLR 297 52 155 CLR 72 71 Mason Court enjoyed a relatively stable membership (see Table 3), very little else was without tumult. Lionel Murphy lost his battle with cancer in October of 1986, leaving a vacancy on the High Court. Shortly thereafter, Gibbs reached the newly instituted retirement age of 70. This left a good deal of space for the new Labor Party Prime Minister, Bob Hawke, to alter the composition of the Court. Anthony Mason, by this time knighted by the Queen of England, was elevated to the position of Chief Justice to replace Gibbs. Mary Gaudron and John Toohey rounded out the first wave of Mason Court appointments. Mary Gaudron was the first woman ever appointed to the High Court. Born in a country town in New South Wales, Gaudron’s interest in the Australian Constitution developed early. She witnessed protests against a proposed amendment meant to ban the Australian Communist Party (Kalowski 2002). She attended law school on scholarship after getting married and becoming a mother. By most reports, she faced a good deal of resistance in a legal profession that was quite chauvinistic at the time (Blackshield et al. 2002). Despite the obstacles, she had developed a blossoming legal practice in New South Wales. She was appointed a Deputy President of the Arbitration Commission by age 31. She left the commission to lecture at the University of New South Wales, and was quickly appointed Solicitor-General of New South Wales in 1981. Her appointment to the High Court as Murphy’s replacement was greeted with near universal prai se.53 Like Mary Gaudron, John Toohey grew up in the country. Only the second appointee from Western Australia, he left his profitable law practice in Perth to establish the Aboriginal Legal Office in Port Hedland (Edelman and Gray 2002). At the same 53 Among the few opponents of this appointment was a local gossip sheet accusing her of having “an emotional disposition inappropriate in a holder of judicial office” (Kalowski 2002, 294). 72 time, he served on the benches of both the Federal Court and the Supreme Court of the Northern Territory. For the remainder of his time on the bench—and beyond—he has been best known for his passionate defense of Aboriginal Rights. Moreover, he has proven to be willing to bend the traditional judicial role in order to achieve his goals. In an interview shortly before his retirement, he noted that: the decision not to change or not to develop the law is just as ‘activist’ as a decision to change the law and can have consequences just as dramatic. (Edelman and Gray 2002,675) The only other personnel change during the Mason Court was the retirement of Wilson in 1989. Michael McHugh was appointed by Prime Minister Bob Hawke to replace Wilson. McHugh’s career got off to a shaky start when he dropped out of school at age fifteen to pursue various blue-collar jobs. At age 22, he began taking night classes, and soon finished his law degree (Guilfoyle 2002). Taking time to build a successful career in Newcastle, he was eventually appointed Judge of Appeal in the New South Wales Court of Appeal. The Mason Court reinvented the role of the High Court, all the while shaping the interpretation of the Australian Constitution for a new era (Lavarch 1996). The establishment of the video link system in 1988 allowed the Court to hear special leave petitions from the comfort of their own Canberra building. This reduced the need for the Court to travel, while still maintaining accessibility (Jackson 1996). With the passage of the Australia Acts of 1986, the last avenues for appeal to the Privy Council were severed. The High Court, finally the only final court of appeal in all Australian Cases, turned its back on the Dixonian doctrine of legalism in favor of what has been described as a more practical and realistic approach (Galligan 1995). Leading the charge was Mason himself. He was not afraid to speak in public about judges and judging, and in the process 73 .88 3:: 035230 on 00: 2:03 02:95. .380 ,2me 2: 9 0850090 22000 Eu 2: £3 08030 H .EoEmEam 00 $852 been 593 a 0883 082 0:3 00.0000 03052 02:08 amaze—z * 07: 2.. 22.<3.:\23§ 230 0-0 202 Ease; <3 2 82 823 mi 2.. .<3.2£220 202 a; 2 £220 <3 2 3.2 280 S< .. 2022230 202 a; m £230 3% mm 22 2:082 312 2.. 223.5 @2230 A390 0-m a; a £25 32 3. 0.2 H 2230 07: 2022230 202 a; w £230 3% a :2 280 024 2.. 83.22.2232 2oz .2» S 22865 02> a. me 825 07: 2222092230 252 a; m £230 50 9. £2 2255 :2: 5;; z. 55?. 202222 300 01m .23 m ,7; 5;. ., 55 2:32;. £230 2:03:01 262 25:11.02 50 mag Es: 0822 0.0.1: _. taco fleas—Z 2: no 03:55:. 00:2; - n 933,—. 74 introduced the idea that policy has an important role to play in the Court’s decision- making process (Brennan 1996a).54 The Chief Justice’s outspoken personality came as a bit of a surprise to onlookers, especially given Anthony Mason’s cautious beginnings on the Bench (Doyle 1996). As apuisne Justice, Mason and Barwick issued many legalist-minded joint opinions (Walker 2002c). At the beginning of his tenure as Chief, the Court decided one of the most important cases in its history: Cole v. Whitfield.55 In this case, the Court abandoned the various legalistic tests which had previously been developed for the application of section 92 of the Constitution. Instead it adopted a test based on the underlying purpose of section 92, which was, of course, to provide a free trade area throughout Australia. (Lavarch 1996, 15) In its unanimous decision, the Court considered the political and economic history dating back to Australia’s pre-federation experience (Selway 2002). They also considered modern context and values, arriving at a simple and lucid solution to the longstanding quagmire of free-trade jurisprudence (Coper 2002a). Then, in 1992, the Court addressed the controversial native title issue in Mabo.56 In this case, the Court incorporated the native title doctrine into Australian law. In the process, the majority overturned the longstanding policy that Australia was terra nullius on the arrival of the European settlers. Instead, they gave legitimacy to the society of indigenous people that existed here before colonization. This decision overturned 200 54 The one sitting Justice most clearly opposed to this new approach was Daryl Dawson, who expressed his distaste for the new radical approach on several occasions (Dillon and Doyle 2002). 55 (1988) 165 CLR 360 56 Mabo v. Queensland [Na 2] (1992) 171 CLR 1 75 years of ostensibly settled law and unleashed a good deal of social and political unrest, albeit with a delay of a couple of years (Solomon 1999). The Mason Court’s new approach to constitutional interpretation was also used to secure implied rights and freedoms (Dillon and Doyle 2002). As Leslie Zines observed: The decisions of the Court in respect to implied rights and freedoms, together with the minority views of Deane and Toohey JJ, led to some speculation whether Australia would finish up with something like a Bill of Rights without the necessity of actually enacting one. (Zines 2000, 226) In the Free Speech Cases,57 the majority held that a fundamental freedom of speech could be implied from the principle of representative government laid out in the Constitution. In these cases, the Court overturned legislation that was intended to limit political speech. The resulting doctrine falls far short of the American First Amendment standard, and is instead meant to encompass mainly political speech. Because of this, politicians were the most vocal critics of these new implied rights (Solomon 1999). The Court also increasingly referenced international law in its opinions. As the Australian Constitution has no written statement of individual rights, Australia’s commitment to various international treaties provided the Mason Court with another avenue through which to secure the protection of such rights (Patapan 2000a). While international treaties are not automatically incorporated into Australian domestic law, the ratification of the treaty can be seen as an obligation under international law (Joseph and Castan 2001). In T eoh,58 the Mason Court prevented the deportation of a convicted drug dealer. He was the father of several children, and his deportation would have left them 57 Nationwide News v. Wills (1992) 177 CLR 1;.4ustralian Capital Television v. Commonwealth (1992) 177 CLR 106 58 Minister for Immigration and Ethnic Affairs v. Tech (1995) 183 CLR 273 76 without any parents. Although the UN Convention on the Rights of the Child had not yet been specifically incorporated into law, the Court held that ratification had generated a legitimate expectation that the treaty would be honored (Solomon 1999). This new legitimate expectation approach allowed the High Court to police the Commonwealth government, effectively bypassing the Parliament in the incorporation of these treaties.59 Through all of the doctrinal tumult, the Mason Court enjoyed a collegial workplace. Cooperation among judges on opinions was common and, as Brennan later recalled: Suggestions for changes in a draft judgment were freely given or received with full recognition of the independence and intellectual integrity of the other Justices. It is no wonder that the members of the Court remained on the most agreeable terms, though we often divided on issues of the greatest importance. (Brennan 1996a, 13) Although the Court faced some of the most difficult issues in Australian law, it openly acknowledged its perennial law-making role. This allowed the Court to avoid haphazardly squeezing novel situations into tired and outdated precedent (Doyle 1996). This fell in line nicely with Mason’s developing belief that the Court’s primary firnction is to keep Australian law up to date with the changing conditions of the country (Galligan 1995) The Brennan Court (1995-1998) On Mason’s retirement in 1995, Gerard Brennan was elevated to the Chief Justice position by Labor Prime Minister Paul Keating. During the course of Brennan’s short tenure as Chief, the Court went through a transitional period, both in terms of membership (see Table 4) and of administrative difficulties. This is not to say that the 59 See also Dietrich v. The Queen (1992)l77 CLR 292. 77 Brennan Court did not accomplish great things, but simply that the discontinuity of membership made the process more difficult (Jackson 2002a). The first addition to the Brennan Court was William Gummow. He was appointed in April of 1995 by Prime Minister Keating to fill the vacancy left by Brennan’s elevation. Gummow attended private school until university, when he attended the University of Sydney and graduated with honors. Gummow went on to teach in the Faculty of Law at the University of Sydney until his appointment to the Federal Court in 1986. While active in academic circles, he also maintained a diverse law practice before becoming a judge. His work included serving as junior counsel to then Commonwealth Solicitor-Genera] Maurice Byers (Lehane 2002). The following year, Justice Deane announced that he would retire early in order to serve as Governor-General. His replacement, Justice Michael Kirby, would soon be the most talked-about judge since Justice Murphy.60 Like most High Court appointees, Kirby was an exceptional student. After graduating with numerous degrees from the University of Sydney, he maintained an active academic life. Additionally, he was chairman of the Australian Law Reform Commission. Following this, he served as the special representative of the Secretary-General of the United Nations for Human Rights in Cambodia. The assignment allowed Kirby to pursue one of his most passionate causes: the fight against discrimination and human rights abuses. His experience as an openly homosexual professional “taught him the pain and distress that discrimination causes” (Sheller 2002, 394). 60 Justice Kirby was awarded the “Judicial Oscar” by journalist John Henningham for Kirby’s excessive mentions in newspaper articles in 2003. According to Henningham, Kirby was mentioned in 303 stories about the High Court (Albrechtsen 2003). 78 Justices Dawson and Toohey also retired during the three years of the Brennan Court. Their replacements were appointed by Liberal Coalition Prime Minister John Howard. Justice Dawson was replaced by Kenneth Hayne. Hayne was a Rhodes Scholar, but defied the predictions of his peers by eschewing a career in academia. After a wildly successful commercial law practice spanning two decades, Hayne was appointed to the Victorian Supreme Court and Court of Appeal. From here, he was elevated to the High Court. Justice Toohey was replaced by Ian Callinan. Callinan took an unusual path to the High Court bench. After completing the equivalent of a high school education, he worked as an Immigration Department clerk. He subsequently studied law part-time at the University of Queensland, and later embarked on a very successfirl nation-wide practice in civil litigation. He was also called upon in 1985 to join the prosecutorial team in the case against Justice Lionel Murphy, which he did.61 His interest in the law did not keep him from a second passion—fiction. He authored two novels and a series of plays which drew on his experience with jurisprudence and the related issues of ideology and morality (Hasluck 1998). In 1998, he became the first High Court Justice in two decades to be appointed directly from private practice. The replacement of three Justices in as many years caused a great deal of technical difficulty on the Court. High Court protocol requires that the Court hand down opinions prior to the departure of any participating Justice. This made scheduling hearings very difficult, and resulted in a number of important constitutional issues being decided by a six-member Bench. Additionally, the members had little opportunity to familiarize 61 Callinan secured a conviction on the first instance, but in the retrial mandated by the appellate court, Murphy was acquitted. 79 themselves with the style and idiosyncrasies of their colleagues, and thus endured times of noticeable tension (Jackson 2002a). Despite these diffi culties, the Brennan Court managed to accomplish a lot more than many onlookers had expected (Haultain 1997). As a Chief Justice, Brennan was “generally non-interventionist and invariably polite” (Kirby 2003, 6). The Court under Brennan’s leadership worked mainly to consolidate the law. In this, it was quite successful (Baker and Gagel er 2002). One of the most notable areas clarified by the Brennan Court is the freedom of political speech. In Lange v. ABC and Levy v. Victoria,62 the Court unanimously confirmed an implied constitutional protection of political speech related to both defamation and non-verbal political protest. This move helped to clarify the deep divisions among the members of the Mason Court regarding the effect of implied free speech on the defamation of public figures and non-verbal political speech (Blackshield 2001). The Lange decision, despite its acceptance of an implied freedom of communication, is sometimes seen as the beginning of the Court’s retum to a more conservative, doctrinal approach to constitutional jurisprudence. This is due not to the substance of the opinion, but the more traditional, legalistic arguments surrounding the substantive conclusions (Zines 2000; Stone 2000). Observers of the Court anticipated that this shift in tone and language was an attempt by the Brennan Court to distance itself from the perceived activism of the Mason Court, while sustaining the substance (Stone 2000) 62 Lange v. Australian Broadcast Corporation (1997) 189 CLR 520', Levy v. Victoria (1997) 189 CLR 579 80 woom 00 mm 2300 :wi 05 :0 8:2; 3:088:20: 22:03 22:0 0:0 5:0 05 E Eth sh .288 £29 22:2 .23 22 9 e22 22 38:22 352 * 2.2 2.. .<3.02£22e0 2oz a; 2: £220 <3 2 082 2283 2:2 20022222220 252 22,. m £22220 3mz mm 22 222%: 22.2 ._. Embezeee 2oz .22 2 2382922 3mz 2 3.2 Z2252 024 2.. 28202220202295 252 a; m 28855 02> S 9.9 232 22.2 2.. 03229.5 252 a; e asses 3mz mm as. 32:20 5< 2 2.235 £26.20 236 02 .22 e £230 3% 3. 0.2 8230 02.2 202022230 252 a; m £230 3mz : :2 280 02.2 2.. 2.332020222222222 252 a; S 23855 02> we .82: 22838 07: 2. .Eobesée 252 2oz seaweed So 8 :2 2220 07: 2.. 22222232002220 252 .222 m £220 30 mm 2282 2220 9:50 53:95 2: .5 335.532 8:2... . v 035. 81 The Brennan Court also attempted to refine the application of the doctrine of intergovernmental immunities. The Cigamatic63 case held that the Commonwealth government maintained a wide exemption from state-levied taxes. Since the Cigamatic Case, the Court had not yet managed to unify behind a specific area of governmental immunity (Dominello 2001). It was not until Henderson’s Case“ in 1997 that the Court began to resolve the issue. Here, the majority reduced the extent to which the Commonwealth would be free from taxes levied on its agencies by the various state governments. In Ha v. NS W,65 though, the Brennan Court found that state-instituted tobacco taxes were to be classified as excise duties. Thus, the power to tax these items remained solely with the Commonwealth government. These decisions taken together worked to keep the states “out of the traditional areas of taxation” (Haultain 1997, 2). Another important topic clarified by the Brennan Court is the area of native title. In Mabo,66 the Mason Court had determined that pastoral leases did not necessarily extinguish native title. If this were true, then up to 42% of Australia might be redistributed through native title claims (Patapan 2000b). This very question came to the Brennan Court in the Wik67 case. The majority held that, to the extent that pastoral leases were in conflict with native title rights, the leases would prevail. In this way, the 63 Commonwealth v. C igamatic Pty Ltd (1962) 108 CLR 372 64 Residential Tenancies Tribunal (NS W), Re; Ex parte Defence Housing Authority (1997) 190 CLR 410 65 Ha v. New South Wales (1997) 189 CLR 465 66 See 11. 56. 67 Wik Peoples v. Queensland (1996) 187 CLR 1 82 Brennan Court acknowledged native title rights, but reigned them in (Baker and Gage] er 2002) The Gleeson Court (1 998-present) Chief Justice Brennan retired in 1998. His replacement, Murray Gleeson, was elevated directly to the Chiefs position from the Supreme Court of New South Wales. While some early assessments assumed that the Gleeson Court would continue the consolidation of the jurisprudential changes of the Mason Court (Patapan 2000b), the substantial imprint of John Howard’s more conservative appointees leads some to question this assumption (Came 2002). Although Australian legal scholars had once declared the demise of legalism, the Gleeson Court has at least resurrected the debate (McHugh 2004) much to the chagrin of some observers (Canigan 2003). Murray Gleeson was raised in a Catholic family in New South Wales. Not only did he excel in his academic studies, but as a youth he also played cricket and raised piranhas (Kirby 1998b). After graduating with honors from Sydney University, he began a very successful law practice. He very quickly became a highly sought-after barrister. In 1980, he won the last appeal by leave from Australia to the Privy Counsel in England (Walker 2002a).68 In 1988, he was appointed Chief of the Supreme Court of New South Wales. This appointment was popular among members of the law profession (Walker 2002a). Ten years later, he was elevated to the High Court Bench by Liberal Coalition Prime Minister John Howard. He was certainly not a new face in the High Court, as he had appeared as counsel in 70 reported cases (Blackshield et al. 2001). 68 See Port Jackson Stevedoring v. Salmond & Spraggon (1980) 144 CLR 300. 83 244< 33.322230 252 a; m £230 32 mm 39 233222 244< 3302233 252 .222 2 3332822 32 em 22 254 024 2.. 35320232033222 252 a; m 3332822 04> mm 22 23: L114. K... fizmfi<3w>tm 0:02 .850 acmwmoaoum amz NW NVO~ 2505530 e4< 2.. 3.32235 @2230 2320 0-m 3: 20 £230 32 a. 9.2 83230 024 3 35.033222 252 252 22332822 040 8 22.: 23230 024 2 33.02230 e2 .3; 2 £230 32 em 2282 25320 «.500 .8305 2: :0 38.3332 332:. - m 03:. 84 The Gleeson Court is mostly seen as relatively conservative, quite a change from the more adventurous Benches of the recent past. Generally, the main point of departure cited is a renewed emphasis on the text and structure in statutory and constitutional interpretation (Zines 2002b; Patapan 2002). Indeed, Chief Justice Gleeson has been anything but shy in advocating a return to Dixonian legalism (Gleeson 1998, 2001b, 2002b), and Sir Anthony Mason has taken note of this shift (Mason 2000). This focus is not shared by all members of the Court, however, and “there is an interpretation debate occurring on the High Court and how it unfolds may have a significant impact on the trajectory of our future constitutional jurisprudence” (Meagher 2002, 14). The High Court Centenary and Beyond The analysis of the High Court presented here extends from Chief Justice Barwick’s 1964 ascension to the High Court through Justice Gaudron’s retirement in 2003. While the three subsequent appointees are not included in the analysis, a few words about them can help to paint a picture of the future of the High Court under Chief Justice Gleeson and beyond. Indeed, these changes to the Court have likely consolidated the Gleeson Court’s return to legalism (Pelly 2008). While it is too soon to know for sure, some observers argue that all three new appointees are likely to follow Gleeson’s favored path of Dixonian legalism (Ackland 2007). Dyson Heydon was appointed in 2003 after Justice Gaudron’s early retirement. An avid crusader for a return to a more traditional style of judicial decision making, he gave a lecture entitled “Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law” mere months before his appointment to the High Court (Heydon 2003). In this piece, he lamented two tendencies working to pull the judiciary fidrther from Dixonian ideals. 85 The first is the desire to litter judicial decisions with the judge’s opinions on every subject which may have arisen, however marginal. The second is the desire to state the applicable law in a manner entirely unconstrained by the way in which it has been stated before because of a perception that it ought to be different. (Heydon 2003, 12) As for Justice Susan Crennan, the picture is much less clear. Crennan was appointed to replace Justice McHugh upon his mandatory retirement in 2005. She was one of “McHugh’s Angels,” as the ten women named by McHugh as suitable replacements have been dubbed (Pelly 2005). There has been some early speculation that she may be more of an activist than John Howard’s Liberal Coalition bargained for. In her swearing-in speech she noted that legal developments in the High Court have occurred against a background of significant social change, and major shifts in public and private values. But the images to which I have referred, of a judiciary which transfuses fresh blood into our polity and of the law as a living instrument conjure up the human qualities needed for the impartial dispensation of Justice according to law. (Donald 2005) The most recent appointee to the High Court was a favorite among McHugh’s Angels to replace McHugh, and had also reportedly missed the nod to replace Justice Gaudron by a small number of cabinet votes (Pelly 2005). After being passed over twice, Susan Kiefel was appointed in 2007 to replace Justice Callinan. Justice Kiefel’s appointment has been regarded as largely uncontroversial and relatively apolitical (Bradford 2007). She was appointed to the High Court by Liberal Attorney-General Philip Ruddock, but was previously appointed to the Federal Court bench by Labor Attorney-General Michael Lavarch. One reporter explains that, while she is “regarded as conservative, Kiefel is not expected to be captive to either side of politics” (Marriner 2007, 1). She has been described by a conservative commentator as having “earned a reputation as a fine black-letter lawyer” (Albrechtsen 2007, 14). 86 In 2004, the High Court celebrated its centenary amidst the thunderous roar of two Royal Air Force F-l 1 1 jets setting excess fuel ablaze in the Canberra night sky. The reaction to this exercise was mixed.69 Justice Kirby later pondered the symbolism of the two streaks of light stretching across the horizon in a speech at the University of Notre Dame. He indicated that, in many respects, this display represented a distinct change from the past to the future (Kirby 2004). It remains to be seen whether the centenary becomes an historical turning point. In the span of its first hundred years, though, the High Court has changed dramatically. From a roving band of three constitutional framers traveling the Australian continent, the High Court has become a highly respected and very important part of the Australian political system. That said, the increasing willingness for members of the Court to embrace a less legalistic vision of the High Court’s decision-making process has raised more than a few eyebrows. While some members of the current Bench are making a concerted effort to reinstate a less activist reputation, they still find themselves needing to defend their actions to an ever-more-critical media and public. Legal scholar Anthony Blackshield noted in a recent panel discussion that the Court “has been subjected to what really were unprecedented political attacks” over the course of the last decade (Blackshield in Jackson 2003). In part as a reaction to this, the High Court has appointed a Public Information Officer to help improve the Court’s relationship with the media. Another suggestion aimed at improving the Court’s approval ratings is to alter the format of its opinions. One prominent legal scholar advises the Court to “consider 69 . . . . Havrng been an unsuspecting wrtness, the author was among those extremely startled by the srght of the fiery sky. 87 making a greater effort to produce joint judgments” (Williams 1999, 145). Observers lament that the Court’s adherence to a seriatim opinion tradition makes the Court’s output unnecessarily confusing, especially given that the Court’s most important role is to clarify the law (Willheim 2002; Campbell 2003). After a review of the High Court’s practices and procedures, the remainder of this analysis will examine the role of j oint opinions on the High Court of Australia. 88 CHAPTER THREE: EXISTING TI-IEORIES OF JOINING BEHAVIOR Despite much progress during the past few decades in the study of courts and judicial behavior, most theory and data developed by social scientists for understanding legal systems still remain very much the product of: and thus bound to, the inevitable peculiarities of the US. context. —— Burton Atkins (1991, 881) The study of j oining behavior has become an important part of the judicial behavior scholarship. Certainly, joining behavior on the United States Supreme Court is the main focus of what Epstein and Knight call the “strategic revolution” in the study of law and courts (2000). As Segal and Spaeth point out, the decision whether or not to join the majority opinion is “among the most important decisions a justice makes” (2002, 387). A good deal of evidence has been amassed in the study of j oining behavior on the Supreme Court. Researchers have identified numerous factors that contribute to the formation of opinion coalitions. These include the policy positions of the individual judges (Rohde 19723), the selection of a majority opinion author (Brenner and Spaeth 1988), the content of the opinion itself (Schwartz 1992), workload considerations (Spriggs et al. 1999), and issue specialization (Brenner and Spaeth 1986). The mere presence of opinion coalitions, of course, is related to the norms and traditions of the Court and the interpretation of these by the individual judges (Grossman 1968). As the previous chapter demonstrates, the High Court of Australia has institutional differences—most notably the seriatim opinion tradition—that may give joining behavior a significantly different purpose and meaning. The American Literature The quest to fashion a complete theory of judicial decision making has been going on for quite some time. In many respects, it has been successful. The major contributors 89 have been proponents of the traditional legal model, the personal attribute model, the attitudinal approach, and various rational actor models. Together, these have yielded an enormous list of factors that have been hypothesized to contribute to the understanding of judicial behavior, with various degrees of empirical support. The legal model of Supreme Court decision making is traditionally associated with the legal positivist tradition, emphasizing the mechanical role of the judge in the application of the law. More recently, judicial behavior scholars have developed a more sophisticated contemporary version of this tradition, most often referred to as post- positive legalism. This perspective shares one thing in common with its more deterministic predecessor—namely, the assertion that decisions of the Justices should be understood largely in terms of the dictates of the laws that speak to the dispute in question. All told, the legal model’s understanding of judicial decision output is most significantly derived from knowledge of the relevant laws (in the legal positivist tradition) or, alternatively, from knowledge of the judge’s understanding of the relevant laws (in the post-positivist tradition). The traditional legal model, holding that case facts and precedent serve as the sole determinants of the outcome of litigation, was called to task by Pritchett’s The Roosevelt Court (1948). Pritchett identified policy preference as an important explanatory variable, along with some of the traditional legal factors involved in understanding judicial outcomes. He stopped short of an empirical test of such factors, but other researchers quickly stepped in to conduct statistical analyses (Baum 2003). The attitudinal model represents a significant break from the legalist traditions. Developed in response to the American legal realist movement, the attitudinal model is 90 the culmination of a large and varied behavioralist tradition. Political scientists, intrigued by Pritchett’s introduction of legal realist theory to the discipline, sought to find ways to empirically validate or invalidate this politicizing revelation about the judiciary. The earliest attempts to scientifically analyze judicial behavior led researchers to probe such explanatory variables as social background characteristics (e. g., Nagel 1961; Schmidhauser 1962), policy-oriented attitudes and values (e.g., Schubert 1965; Spaeth and Parker 1969), conception of the judicial role (e.g., Grossman 1968), and the dynamics of small-group membership (e.g., Snyder 1958; Ulmer and Nicholls 1978). Each of these approaches arose out of the search for satisfactory statistical evidence. Small-group dynamics research is arguably closer to the rational choice tradition than the others are, while the role orientation approach is closer to the legalist tradition. This diversity of behavioral measures illustrates the rapid innovation of the field in the late 19503 through the 1960s. It is also a demonstration of the willingness of behavioralist researchers to pursue numerous avenues in an effort to gain an empirical handle on the issue. In terms of Supreme Court research, the attitudinal model has survived the others, largely because of its impressive ability to explain behavior. The attitudinal model derives its leverage by concentrating on individuals—specifically on the dtflerences between individuals in terms of policy orientations. The rational choice tradition, like the attitudinal tradition before it, grew largely out of theoretical advances in other fields of research. Rational choice theorists, most notably William Riker (1962), were beginning to develop a positive political theory, applying the assumptions of rational choice to political behavior and phenomena. These assumptions, although stated differently by different researchers, largely center on 1) the 91 ability of actors to rank alternatives in terms of their goal preferences, and 2) the ability of actors to select from available alternatives in order to maximize the attainment of these goals (see Epstein and Knight 2000). The focus of the theory is on the individual, but the theory emphasizes the similarities between individuals instead of their differences. In the context of judicial decision making, this difference is usually manifested in the concentration on strategy as shaped by institutions. Although this is different from the attitudinal model, most incarnations of judicial strategy include explicit provisions for individual attitudes and goals. Because of the Supreme Court’s majority opinion tradition, eliciting joining behavior is a crucial part of judicial strategy. While the seeds of rational choice can be found in the early work of Schubert (1965) and Pritchett (1961), the first explicit application of rational choice theory to judicial decision making is found in Murphy’s Elements of Judicial Strategy (1964). Although the trend toward rational choice theory in the other American political science sub-disciplines grew at a fever pitch, judicial scholars largely abandoned the approach. The empirical rewards of the more behavioral strategies were more immediately apparent. It was not until the work of economist Brian Marks (1989) that rational choice once again grabbed the attention of the judicial subfield. Marks, followed by reputable political scientists from various sub-disciplines, reintroduced rational choice theory to the judicial subfield (F erejohn and Shipan 1990; Ferej ohn and Weingast 1992). Some argue that there is now a distinct trend toward ‘ rational choice theory in the study of Supreme Court decision making (Epstein and Knight 2000). Certainly, with a number of significant strategy-based models of decision making emerging in the last decade, the approach occupies an important space in the 92 contemporary literature (Epstein and Knight 2000; Hammond et al. 2005; Maltzman et al. 2000) The result is a renewed debate about the appropriate paradigm for understanding judicial decision making on the Supreme Court. Traditional proponents of the attitudinal model have been reinvigorated, responding to the challenge of the rational choice theorists (i.e., Segal and Spaeth 2002). While compelling reasons for employing a rational choice approach in lower court studies are well understood, the case for abandoning the attitudinal model at the Supreme Court level is not nearly as clear-cut. But while the attitudinal model tells us how Supreme Court Justices are expected to vote on the merits, it has a harder time helping us understand processes that happen before, during, and after the merits stage. Proponents of the rational choice approach to studying judicial politics have developed many theories about the constraints on US. Supreme Court Justices. Constraints are imposed either by external actors limiting the expression of judicial preferences (Epstein and Knight 2000), or by the judges upon themselves and each other (Maltzman et al. 2000). Proponents of applying strategic, rational choice-based theories to the Supreme Court largely argue that such an application affords researchers the ability to describe more than simply the votes on the merits (Epstein and Knight 2000). For example, the decision of a litigant to pursue a remedy through the filing of a petition for a writ of certiorari is an external constraint on the judges that is not explicitly addressed by the attitudinal model McGuire et al. 1999). Other such external constraints include the effects of public opinion, congressional policy positions, and more. In addition to this, there are internal constraints on the Justices such as collegiality, equity, efficiency, and 93 strategic considerations of the positions of others. The adoption of the rational choice approach allows for an understanding of judicial constraints, while not abandoning the idea that judges have (and use) policy preferences to make decisions (Shapiro 1995). Proponents of the attitudinal model do not concede much to this argument. Segal and Spaeth (2002) take up the cause against using rational choice models of Supreme Court behavior. First among their criticisms of this approach is the stringency of the assumptions that are inherent in rational choice models. This is a familiar argument from critics of rational choice theory as applied to political behavior generally (Green and Shapiro 1994). Perhaps more damning, however, is their contention that the empirical evidence simply fails to bear out the hypotheses derived from these strategic theories , (Segal and Spaeth 2002). The research has begun to come full circle. Several scholars have started to take a fresh look at the traditional legal model variables, integrating them with the lessons learned from other empirical work. Segal (1984) has examined Supreme Court search and seizure cases from the perspective of the legal model. In this research, he uses a multivariate model in an attempt to bring order to the seemingly chaotic realm of Fourth Amendment litigation. His findings suggest that traditional legal characteristics do matter in these particular cases. Aliotta (1988) applies a similar approach to equal protection cases. Although her legal variables do not correspond in any meaningful sense with those used by Segal (1984), she does find that they add explanatory power to the attitudinal variables. George and Epstein (1992) also find evidence to support the inclusion of traditional legal variables in models of capitol punishment cases. 94 The lesson here, of course, is that competing models of judicial decision making are only “competing” to the extent that they are incompatible in their approach to a particular task. A reliance on attitudes is important in most fiinctioning strategic models, and this pairing can be extremely helpful in understanding decision-making behavior in courts other than the United States Supreme Court. Ifnothing else, it reminds the researcher to be aware of potentially significant internal, external, or legal positivism- inspired constraints on judicial behavior. It also instructs the researcher how to go about accounting for the impact of any of these constraints once they are identified. Judicial scholars should not be deterred from considering these resources in other judicial decision-making contexts; to the contrary, there is reason to believe that such considerations would carry significant explanatory power across national borders. The fact that these theoretical resources have been little used in the comparative context, it seems, is mostly a sign of the relative infancy of the comparative judicial research program. Judging Across the World The business of courts around the world is to settle disputes in accordance with some sort of written or understood set of laws or norms (Tate et al. 1990). While courts tend to have similar broad goals, they pursue these goals in diverse ways. Some courts have the power only to decide small matters of legal application. Others are given the responsibility of judging the laws created by the legislature against some higher or constitutional norm. In any case, courts are always situated within a particular social and political context, and they always have a particular set of institutional features and procedures that shape the way they administer justice in their own society. 95 Even courts embedded within democratic systems of government have widely different methods, responsibilities and contexts. As Australian High Court Chief Justice Murray Gleeson put it, “democracy itself can hardly be said to contain an inherent definition of the role of the judiciary” (Gleeson 1997). These differences can have important consequences for the application of the standard American judicial behavior models even to courts in other liberal democratic countries. With a few notable exceptions, though, judicial behavior scholars have virtually ignored courts outside the United States. While Tate (2002b) traces the tradition of studying non-American courts as far back as the late 18005, the first modern examples of systematic research on the judiciaries of other nations were written in the 19603. Some of the eariiest works were translations of behavioralist work from native scholars. The first research programs that actively compared more than one country in the modern tradition began to emerge in the late 19605 (e. g., Sheldon 1967). Shortly thereafter, Glendon Schubert began his global odyssey, applying jurimetrics techniques to courts in various corners of the world, inspiring others to do the same. Two major collections of comparative (and quantitative) judicial behavior research appeared at the end of the decade, setting the stage for what seemed likely to be a major movement in the subfield (Grossman and Tanenhaus 1969; Schubert and Danelski 1969). From these dramatic beginnings, however, the resulting trickle of comparative empirical work has been less than impressive (Tate 2002a). Despite the repeated pleas of Tate and others, comparative judicial research remains a sub-sub-discipline, with little acknowledgement from American judicial scholars generally. Indeed, from 1960-1991, Tate (1992) found that comparative court research occupied less than five percent of the 96 published work in major political science journals. Many wondered what all of the fuss was about in the first place, why studying courts in other countries may be important, or even why it could be interesting. Despite the promise of travel to exotic locations, many gave up on this line of research because of the difficulty in obtaining data—especially the non-unanimous decisions that were critical to the existing American judicial theories of the time. The benefits of comparing judicial institutions across countries should seem obvious to the student of comparative politics. By studying the American courts almost to the exclusion of other systems, we have developed intricate models that may not be generalizable to any other system (see Sartori 1970). Even if we desire only a way to understand the American system, though, this myopic case-study method may rob us of potentially useful information. By failing to observe more than one system, we fail to gain a handle on the importance of a myriad of institutional, cultural and political variables in the judicial decision-making process.70 One purpose of comparative judicial research may be to relieve the United States Supreme Court of its most prevalent stigma: that of the Western high courts, it is alone in its overtly political decision making. Outside of the United States, the legal positivist model is widely held by lawyers and social scientists alike (Haynie and Tate 1998). Without systematic empirical analysis, researchers will continue to be unable to identify those countries that may share this dubious distinction. While our experience in America has led us to suspect that ours is not the only political high court in town, empirical 70 In the early 19808, Tate observed that the study of comparative judicial politics had yet to be integrated into the study of comparative politics more generally (1981a). Although he provides several concrete steps toward achieving this goal, progress on this front has remained sporadic at best. 97 evidence is only now beginning to confirm this (Epp 1998; Magalhaes 1998; Smithey 2002; Stone 1992; Tate and Vallinder 1995; Volcansek 1993; Waltrnan and Holland 1987) Comparative judicial research can also be a worthy pursuit in its own right. The one area where the study of courts has been taken up by comparative politics scholars is in the area of democratization research. One section of this literature examines the relationship between institutional arrangement (i.e., presidential or parliamentary system) and the independence of the judiciary (F erej ohn 1995). Ferej ohn’s findings support the idea that presidential systems afford the judiciary more independence, which is associated in other research with the destabilization of fragile democracies (Tate et al. 1990). Other research shows that single party dominance begets low levels of judicial independence (Ramseyer 1994; Ramseyer and Rasmusen 1997), which in turn presents complications for democratic consolidation (Rose and Shin 2001). In short, the comparative study of courts can assist not only in the validation and refinement of models of American judicial behavior, but it can also assist in the understanding of political systems generally. Australian Jurimetrics and Beyond While many comparative judicial scholars lament the lack of attention to courts outside of the United States (Tate 1996), it may be unfair to conclude that the Australian High Court has been neglected completely. The field of jurimetrics was especially well- received by a handful of Australian legal scholars. Jurimetrics, or the application of quantitative mathematical methods to legal problems, arose from the behavioralist focus on “attitudinal” variables in the study of judicial decision-making behavior. Very quickly following the behavioral revolution in the study of American courts, like-minded researchers abroad began to apply similar techniques to the Australian High Court. 98 After his book The Judicial Mind (1965) inspired the behavioral approach to studying American courts, Glendon Schubert himself contributed much to the early jurimetrics work in Australia. In the late 19605, Schubert published two articles on the High Court (Schubert 1968; 1969a), largely in an attempt to verify the findings of his work on the US. Supreme Court. He identifies two significant ideological scales for the tenure of Chief Justice Dixon (1952-1964). The first is called the “X—scale,” and is made up of issues including support for economic underdogs, religious morality, security, socialism, and government regulation of business. The “Y-scale” is made up of more broad theoretical divides including adherence to a strict interpretive theory of the constitution, perspective on the role of judicial review, and judicial and federal government centralization (Schubert 1969a). He finds that a judge’s position on these two scales is related to that person’s age, state of residence, and score on a conservatism/liberalism scale. This work was closely followed by Australian researchers, some of whom conducted their own research in this vein (Blackshield 1972; 1978; Douglas 1969). By the end of the 19705, nearly forty year’s worth of High Court data had been analyzed for decision-making patterns (Blackshield 2002c). The result of these studies had some findings in common with Schubert’s — most importantly that at least two distinct dimensions of decision making existed in the High Court during the analyzed years. One of these dimensions, according to Blackshield (1972), roughly corresponds to the familiar left-right dimension of policy preferences. His findings also pointed to a second relevant dimension, this one corresponding with differences in attitudes about the distribution of legal control of the institutions of government. 99 The systematic study of the Australian High Court was not limited to Schubertian- style endeavors. A parallel line of Australian jurimetrics research was inspired by the work of American researcher Fred Kort (1957; 1963). This research applies mathematical methods in an attempt to create models of judicial votes, thus predicting future court outcomes. Kort’s models place heavy emphasis on the importance of case facts in the production of judicial outcomes. Prediction-minded researchers like Alan Tyree (197 7; 1981) have analyzed the High Court in this way (Blackshield 2002c). Tyree attempted to salvage the practice of using content analysis to model case facts by relaxing the strict deterministic assumptions of previous research (Tyree 1981). In doing so, he finds evidence to support the idea that case facts are at least related to decision output, even in Australia’s highest court. He also offers an alternative to the Schubertian classification of similarities and differences between judges. By using a fact-based distinction, he created issue-specific multidimensional maps in ideological space. In this way, he is more confident that he is, indeed, comparing apples to apples (Tyree 1977). He concludes that this non-metric multidimensional scaling method allows structure to emerge in data that were previously devoid of any obvious pattern. In the 19705 and 19805, as interest in comparing courts waned among American scholars (Tate 2002a), a similar trend formed in Australia. Australian researchers turned away from this type of research for practical and theoretical reasons. The limits of the factor analysis techniques had largely been reached, especially at a time where computing power was at a premium. Additionally, Australian legal scholars were faced with a general lack of statistical training and doubts about the ability of the methodology to add significantly to the existing knowledge (Blackshield 2002e). 100 This lack of confidence in statistical methodology may be due to the ‘legalist’ culture among Australian scholars and High Court observers at the time. From the legalist perspective, judges are constrained in large part by legal precedent, and outside influences are irrelevant to the decision-making process. Legalism does not deny the political nature of the questions before the Court, nor does it eschew the policy implications of the Court’s decisions (Gageler 2002b). Instead, it simply denies the use of such non-legal factors in the decision-making process. Members of the High Court have been known to perpetuate the idea that decisions are made exactly this way (Galligan 1987), and that creating law on the basis of extra-legal concerns is simply beyond the scope of the High Court’s role (Gageler 2002b). The Court has traditionally held fast to the legalist framework as its sole method for interpreting common law, statutory law, and the constitution (Thompson 1982). The High Court was not conceived until well after the famed Marbury v. Madison (1803) case. The constitution that created the High Court modeled it largely after the US. Supreme Court as it operated in the late 19th century, and gave it the power of judicial review outright (Galligan 1991). Unlike the US. Constitution, though, the Australian Constitution does not have an explicit list of individual rights. The existence of the Bill of Rights means that “each Justice is inevitably drawn deeply into its boiling brew of politics, the attributed or perceived social values of innumerable groups” of American politics (Callinan 1999, 3). The absence of such a constitutional document in Australia means that the Australian High Court Justices are not directly subjected to the aforementioned fate. On the other hand, the role of the High Court in determining which rights are implied in the document is necessarily more ambiguous than in the United 101 States (Kirby 1999). In most other ways, though, the Australian Constitution is much more explicit than the American Constitution, making it less necessary for the High Court to appear to be divining the true meaning of the document (Crawford 1993). In this way, with the exception of civil rights cases, the judges in the Australian system have an easier time maintaining the air of legalism. Before ascension of Sir Anthony Mason to the High Court Chiefship, the High Court generally stayed away from addressing civil rights cases beyond assenting to the will of Parliament, making their claims of legalism nearly airtight. For this reason, legalism is particularly important in the context of the High Court. Not only is it the traditionally accepted interpretation strategy but it is also one of the few defenses the Court has against its particular political context. Because of the history of conflict between the Labor and Liberal parties, the liberal consensus enjoyed in America is not a guarantee in the Australian context. The Labor party was virtually excluded from the drafting and ratification process of the Australian Constitution, and their main political goals remain outside the scope of the constitutional framework. Since the ratification of the US. Constitution, political debate in America has generally taken place inside the framework of the institutions prescribed by the Constitution. In Australia, however, the main points of contention between the parties run much deeper—to the very core of the liberal institutions contained in the Australian Constitution. The authors of the Australian Constitution were decidedly anti-centralist, and the labor movement’s interests in creating a strong central authority were generally excluded from the discussion (La Nauze 1972). The labor movement saw the Australian Constitution as an obstacle to its objectives, and approached it with a degree of hostility (Hirst 1995). This 102 debate has continued into modern times, and the High Court has often been drawn into the debate (Walsh 1997). Because of this unique political difficulty, the Justices rely on the popular legalist rhetoric in order to show that they remain impartial in the face of this potentially divisive conflict (Crawford 1993). This is not to say that the US. Supreme Court does not need the support of the people in order to maintain its power. On the contrary, the constitutional weakness of the Supreme Court means that it needs the support of the public in order to keep its legitimacy (Franklin and Kosaki 1989). Research has shown that Justices, especially the moderate ones, are sensitive to the ebbs and flows of public opinion (Mishler and Sheehan 1993; 1996). Justice Kirby warns that any dissatisfaction with the US. Supreme Court might foreshadow similar feelings about the Australian High Court: Nowadays, abuse and insult are not unknown. Every judge can accept criticism and acknowledge that sometimes it is warranted. But Australians must be careful to avoid the perils of damage to our institutions that the judiciary faces in the United States. (Kirby 2001) That this observation comes from one of Court’s leading critics of Australian legalism is of particular interest. The commonly accepted way to defer criticism of the Australian judiciary has been to invoke a legalist perspective — whether in practice or only in rhetoric. Indeed, analysis of mid-20th century Communist Party cases indicates the High Court was particularly unresponsive to public opinion (Sheldon 1967). Although the legalist culture has begun to wither among Australian legal scholars and casual court observers alike, the concern for legitimacy remains. This has left a significant rift among members of the Court, both past and present. While some Justices adamantly believe that legalism is the only way to secure public confidence in the judiciary (e.g., Gleeson 2000a), others argue that a failure to accept the duty to craft law 103 in the best interests of the Australian people might be detrimental to the Court’s legitimacy (Kirby 1996). No matter which of these camps is correct, experts and citizens alike have begun to speculate that some set of extra-legal factors influences the policy output of the Court (e.g., Galligan 1987; Haultain 1997). Some of the opposition to the traditional legalist view likely comes from cues given by some members of the Court. Like the US. Supreme Court, the High Court decides many cases in which all of the members fail to agree on what should be the proper outcome. In these cases, both the majority and the dissenters put forth logical arguments to support their positions. In most cases neither argument is logically necessary, and each is logically feasible (Sawyer 1967). As witnesses to the empirical studies of the US. Supreme Court, Australian legal scholars are beginning to protest loudly against the idea that even a relaxed version of the traditional legalist model is an appropriate way to characterize the work of the High Court (Galligan 1987). This realist critique of legalism is now coming not only from onlookers but also from the members of the Court (Kirby 1983). The High Court under Chief Justice Mason (1987—1995) moved down a path of innovation and activism. Some of the Justices began to embrace their roles as policy-makers, and they tipped their hand by showing willingness to undertake sharp departures from the status quo. Many of the Mason Court Justices were taught by prominent legal realists. Some even publicly acknowledged the work of jurimetrics scholars directly, taking seriously the patterns of social attitudes in judicial decisions that these scholars had uncovered (Murphy 1980). 104 More recently, Australian scholar Russell Smyth has almost single—handedly reinvigorated the empirical study of judicial behavior in Australia. The High Court itself publishes basic information in its annual reports including workload data in various breakdowns and budget expenditures, despite the strains this puts on the Court’s data management system (Popple 1999). Sometimes, the judges themselves make use of these data in their speeches or extra-judicial writings (Gleeson 2004b). A number of interesting hypotheses, many derived from the American literature, have also been tested using empirical data about the High Court. Research has found a relationship between case complexity and the reliance on citations of authority in judicial decisions (Smyth 2003a). One analysis fails to find support for party capability theory (Smyth 2000), but another finds evidence to the contrary (Haynie et al. 2001). The number and type of interveners in the High Court have been evaluated over time (Pierce 2006), and these data have been systematically compared to the Supreme Court of Canada (Williams 2000). The role of the associates has been compared to the US. Supreme Court clerks using survey data (Leigh 2000). The use of American precedents in the High Court over time has been examined (von Nessen 1992). An analysis of voting blocs on the Latham Court presents an interesting (if somewhat problematic) assessment of coalition success (Smyth 2001), and a later incarnation of this work finds support for the application of many American judicial behavior theories to the Latham Court (Smyth 2002b). Another area of interest to scholars has been the prestige and productivity of judges at different stages of the judicial life cycle. Valiant attempts have been made to quantify judicial performance according to productivity, citations, extra-judicial writings and reversals (Smyth 2005a). Judicial productivity has been found to follow a life-cycle 105 trend, rising to a peak and then declining again near the end of the judicial career (Bhattacharya and Smyth 2001a). Judicial productivity, along with ideological compatibility between the judge and the current administration, may also help to predict the timing of retirements (Maitra and Smyth 2005). Previous judicial experience, combined with youth and a conservative appointing prime minister, have been associated with judicial prestige, measured in terms of citation rates (Bhattacharya and Smyth 2001b) A very popular line of research attempts to define (Lynch 2002a) and to explain variations in dissent rates (Smyth 2004) and other separate opinions (Groves and Smyth 2004) over time. Fluctuation in nonconsensual behavior have been explained as a function of institutional changes and different leadership styles (Smyth and Narayan 2004), as well as attitudinal factors (Smyth 2003b; 2005b), acclimation effects (Smyth 2002a) and consensual norms (Narayan and Smyth 2005; 2007; but see Smyth 2002c; Wood 2008). It is on this line of research that the present analysis builds. Conceptualizing Joining Behavior In a situation where a number of different people are asked to come to a decision on a topic, there will likely be some level of disagreement between the parties. This is also true in the case of judges. Unless we are willing to accept the legalist doctrine that the outcome of each case is logically derived from the law and stare decisis, there is the potential in each case for some level of disagreement between the judges. This level of disagreement can be thought of as a continuous variable, with no necessary limits on its value. The extent of these disagreements cannot be directly observed by the researcher, though, or even by the Justices themselves. 106 Decision Patterns In Australia, as in the United States, there is an institutionalized proxy measure for such disagreement. If the level of disagreement reaches a certain critical level on a given case, judges will cast dissenting votes. From a strict legalist perspective, dissents are the result of the breakdown of the process of finding the legally necessary outcome. Critics of the legalist model, however, see the dissent as a result of ideological disagreement among the judges (Brace and Hall 1993). Because of the independence of the judiciary and the design of the court system, it is not necessary for judges in the United States or Australia to assent to decisions with which they do not agree. This leaves the researcher with an observable measure of disagreement between the judges, the importance of which has been well documented in the study of judicial behavior in the American court system (Segal and Spaeth 1993). In the American system, concurring opinions might also add an important piece of information to this puzzle. Indeed, much of the research on Supreme Court judicial behavior concentrates on voting behavior, typically omitting the distinction between a concurrence and assent to the majority opinion. A scale could be constructed using information about both concurrences and dissents to incorporate this additional opinion agreement information (see Handberg 1978). The exact role of the concurring opinion in the American context, however, is not altogether clear. Typically, concurring Opinions are assumed to be a middling option, indicating less agreement with the majority than a vote for the majority opinion, but more agreement than the filing of a dissenting opinion (Segal and Spaeth 1993). The precise mechanism, however, is very difficult to understand in the American context, especially from the perspective of current models of judicial decision making (Maveety 2003). 107 The seriatim format of the Australian High Court decisions makes the concurrence/maj ority opinion distinction nearly impossible. Each judge tends to write a separate opinion, whether or not the opinion expressed supports the final majority vote. In any case, a Justice writing a concurring opinion still votes with the majority of the members of the Court, even though there is usually no single majority opinion with which to concur. For this reason, concurrences and majority opinions typically look exactly alike in the vote totals. This fact removes from practicality the option of using concurring opinions as a refinement to an agreement/disagreement scale. It does introduce another possible avenue: the phenomenon of j oint opinions. Without the institutionalized motivation to produce a majority opinion, why do the judges engage in such behavior? The decision to join or not to join is subject to far fewer constraints in the absence of the majority opinion tradition. In this way, patterns of “inter-agreement in opinions makes possible the discrimination of differences among the justices” in all cases, be they unanimous or not (Schubert 1969b, 339). Joining Behavior in the US. Supreme Court The motivation to join the opinions of other judges is easier to explain in the American context than in the Australian context. The majority opinion “is the core of the policy-making power of the Supreme Court” of the United States (Rohde 1972b, 653). When a joint opinion carries additional force beyond that of an individual concurrence or dissent, the desire to achieve a joint Opinion is to be expected. In the US. Supreme Court, there is a tradition “which generally encourages each justice to join the majority opinion whenever possible” (Atkinson and Neuman 1969, 273). This pressure, coupled with the need to establish and maintain a relatively coherent body of precedent, serves as a force to keep judicial individualism at bay (Kelman 1985). 108 If a judge finds the majority opinion acceptable, there is “little need for a justice to push assertively to change it or to write separately” (Spriggs et al. 1999, 489). When a judge finds the majority opinion unacceptable, he faces a number of potential options. The first and most obvious choice is to simply dissent from the majority. Dissenting behavior is not uncommon on the Supreme Court, and is firmly rooted in the history of Anglo-American jurisprudence (Bergman 1991). Historically, Supreme Court onlookers saw dissenting opinions as a useless and unnecessary drain on the Court’s legitimacy (Stager 1925). While there is still a bias against dissenting among some members of the legal community (Campbell 1983), the practice is now generally understood to be a natural part of the decision-making process (Maveety 2003). As William 0. Douglas puts it, When judges do not agree, it is a sign that they are dealing with problems on which society itself is divided. It is the democratic way to express dissident views. (Douglas 1948, 106) The modern Supreme Court, with its discretionary jurisdiction and its position at the apex of the judicial system, is far more likely to deal with these divisive issues than most other American courts (Post 2001). Evidence has shown that judges become more likely to dissent once they are elevated to the Supreme Court bench (Gerber and Park 1997). Indeed, some dissenting opinions have become “canonized,” or received by the legal community as among the “highly authoritative legal texts that command special reverence in the law” (Krishnakumar 1999, 781). As a second option, the Justice may choose to author a concurring opinion. This may take the form of either a regular concurrence or a special concurrence (Kinnan 1995). In a regular concurrence the judge agrees with the majority on the result of the case and the reasons, but decides to write separately anyway. A concurrence is what the 109 term “concurrence” is more commonly used to describe. This type of concurrence, also called a “concurrence in judgment,” indicates agreement on the disposition of the case but not the reasons of the majority. The writing of a concurring opinion, however, is not without its own costs. Besides the extra time it may take to assemble a concurring opinion, the practice is seen as particularly distasteful, even among members of the Court (Maveety 2003). The third option is to bargain with the author of the opinion seeking accommodation for his views. Ifthe differences are not extreme, the judge may have a strong incentive to pursue this path. The higher precedential value of the majority opinion may entice fence-sitters to attempt to shape that opinion to better reflect their own preferences (Spriggs et al. 1999). Indeed, numerous researchers have found evidence of such bargaining, or strategic behavior, on the Court (Epstein and Knight 1998; Murphy 1964; Wahlbeck et al. 1998). In an attempt to secure accommodation, Justices can exercise various levels of pressure on the majority opinion author. These actions, when combined with the majority opinion author’s desire to keep a majority, may lead to accommodation. Absent the need for a majority opinion, however, this may not be the case: The collaborative nature of the opinion-writing process stems largely from the author’s need to have a majority of justices join the opinion once it is circulated before it becomes the opinion of the Court. This institutional rule therefore provides incentives for justices to bargain with the majority opinion author and for the author to sometimes accommodate their concerns. (Spriggs et al. 1999, 486) Since the end of the seriatim opinion tradition on the US. Supreme Court, the absence of a single majority opinion has been frowned upon (Novak 1980). In the event that a majority opinion cannot be agreed upon, the Court typically produces a plurality opinion — or an opinion assented to by a plurality of the Justices. Plurality opinions lack 110 the precedential force afforded to majority opinions, and are often criticized for creating chaos in the legal community (Novak 1980). Concurring behavior itself has been criticized for emasculating the Opinion of the Court, regardless of whether or not the behavior leads to a plurality decision (Davis and Reynolds 1974). Participation in a special opinion leading to a plurality outcome can work against a Justice’s self-interest (Hammond et al. 2005). This is not to say that all joining behavior on the Supreme Court is easily categorized as a rational compromise in an attempt to further policy goals. In order to qualify as the “Opinion of the Court”—or the majority opinion—the opinion must be joined by a majority of the Justices. In most instances, this means that the minimum number of j oiners necessary for a winning coalition is five (opinion author included). The author of the majority opinion, then, will need to gather four additional coalition members. As Rohde notes, The opinion he drafts will be shaped by his own preferences, but he is not a free agent. If he is to attain a winning coalition, he must gain the assent of at least four other justices in the opinion. The opinion writer is thus forced to bargain with the other justices. (Rohde 1972a, 214) Once this minimum winning coalition number of five is reached, though, the motivation for additional compromise or joining behavior is slightly more difficult to explain. While the majority conference coalition needs to maintain a minimum winning coalition, there is little need to entice more than the minimum number of j oiners to sign the opinion. From the joiner’s perspective, why Opt to join the majority opinion once a minimum winning coalition has already been reached? Rohde finds some evidence that the existence of larger than necessary majority opinion coalitions is related to a threat or perceived threat to the Court as an institution (Rohde 1972a). Other researchers, though, 111 have discounted the empirical evidence surrounding this claim (Brenner 1979; Giles 1977), suggesting that the minimum winning coalition hypothesis finds no support regardless of the presence of a threat. Saul Brenner (2003) outlines several possible explanations for unnecessary joining behavior. Many of his hypotheses are specifically relevant only to joining a majority opinion, and do not adequately explain the decision to join a special opinion—any opinion that is not the majority opinion. The simplest explanation for unnecessary joining behavior is an attitudinal one: that the judge agrees with the reasons expressed in the opinion. One way to illustrate this is to look at situations where a judge decides to join a colleague’s special opinion. While there is institutional pressure to achieve a majority for the opinion of the Court, there is no such pressure to form coalitions for other types of opinions. Indeed, Segal and Spaeth argue that, because there is no institutional pressure to join in concurring or dissenting opinions, these opinions “reflect the strongly held policy views of their authors” (2002, 395). The bargaining and accommodation needed to attract joiners to a majority opinion is not likely to occur in the absence of the institutional pressure to achieve at least a minimum winning coalition. Because there are no institutional benefits to assembling a coalition for these special opinions, the strategic motivations to join fall away and leave policy preferences as the most obvious explanation. Judges are more likely to join a concurring opinion when they are ideologically distant from the majority opinion writer (W ahlbeck et al. 1999). When judges do join a special Opinion, they usually join an opinion written by a close ideological ally (Segal and Spaeth 2002). Even still, judges with similar policy goals are likely to disagree to some extent about the precise details of the reasons. 112 Brenner (2003) also cites a number of strategic motivations for joining an opinion when there is no institutional pressure to do 50. First, a judge may join an opinion if his views have been accommodated by the writer. Indeed, this seems to imply strategy on the part of the opinion author, and not on the part of the joiner. If the joiner’s views have been accommodated, then joining the opinion is merely an exercise in pursuing policy preferences. There is some reason to expect a majority opinion writer to accommodate the views of an additional joiner once the minimum winning coalition has been assembled. Evidence from the Warren Court indicates that minimum winning coalitions were more likely to break up prior to the final disposition, giving majority opinion writers a reason to solicit additional joiners (Brenner and Spaeth 1988). Because the majority opinion sets forth the rationale for subsequent decisions, a larger-than-minimum winning coalition may convey a consistency and certainty in the reasons given by the Court (Murphy 1964). The 5-4 decision set a precedent “which might be overturned if membership changes or if one of the justices in the majority changes his mind” (Brenner et al. 1990, 309). Additionally, the compliance of lower courts may be more likely when the majority opinion coalition is larger (Benesh and Reddick 2002; Woodward and Armstrong 1979; but see Johnson 1979). The classic example of an accommodation strategy to achieve a unanimous opinion is the effort of Earl Warren in Brown v. Board of Education.71 In this case, it was the likelihood of widespread external resistance to the Court’s ruling that motivated Warren’s pursuit of a unanimous decision. There is less reason to believe, though, that the author of a special Opinion would be interested in courting joiners (O'Brien 1999). 71(1954) 347 US. 484. 113 Additional signatures on a special opinion may say something about the ability of the author to persuade his colleagues (Segal and Spaeth 2002); concerns about institutional legitimacy and providing a unified front to external actors are less relevant to special opinions. A second strategic reason for unnecessary joining given by Brenner (2003) suggests that the joiner may concede some policy ground in an attempt to achieve this gain in legitimacy. He hypothesizes that a Justice may join a majority opinion after the minimum winning coalition has been solidified as a way to strengthen the decision in the eyes of outside actors. Because he lists this hypothesis separately from the previous one, it implies that a Justice may join for this reason even if his policy positions have not been accommodated. For the same reason that a special Opinion writer is unlikely to solicit joiners, though, Justices would be unlikely to join a special opinion that does not reflect his policy preferences. Thirdly, Brenner (2003) suggests that a judge may strategically join a majority opinion because the presence of a separate opinion may raise the salience of the majority opinion. This reason seems to contradict the previous one. In the previous hypothesis, a unanimous opinion is assumed to strengthen the holding in important and controversial cases. In the present hypothesis, though, the presence of a special opinion is assumed to call attention to the majority opinion, which supports something other than the potential joiner’s ideal policy. There is empirical evidence indicating that winning coalitions in nonsalient cases tend to attract more joiners than those in salient cases (Brenner et al. 1990; Maltzman et al. 2000). In the Burger and Rehnquist Courts, 80% of cases without a majority opinion were in the highly salient area of civil rights and liberties (Segal and 114 Spaeth 2002). This hypothesis says nothing about joining behavior for special opinions. Ifthe Justice believes that the presence of a separate opinion detracts from the majority Opinion, joining a special opinion has essentially the same effect as writing his own. There would seem, then, to be little reason to accept and join a sub-optimal special opinion. The fourth strategic explanation given by Brenner (2003) is that a Justice may join a majority opinion in order to increase the chance that the author will return the favor in future cases. Because the Justices on the Court are in an iterative game, it is reasonable to expect that their long-term interest can be furthered by working to secure cooperative relationships with their colleagues, even if it may mean compromising (Axelrod 1984; 1986; Murphy 1964). Empirical evidence suggests that such a cooperative strategy can provide real payoffs for the joiner in future attempts to marshal a majority coalition (Collins 2007; Wahlbeck et al. 1999). In this research, though, the measure of cooperation is a firnction of “the percentage of time that the author joined another justice’s separate opinions” (W ahlbeck et al. 1999, 500). In other words, this research finds that joining a special opinion—not a majority opinion—can yield benefits in later attempts to form a majority coalition. Ifthe Justices perceive that this is true, this may provide a motivation to join a special opinion he might not otherwise join. Small group theory implies that judicial behavior is motivated in part “by considerations of group solidarity and intragroup harmony” (F esta and Vichules 1968, 540). The last group of hypotheses put forward by Brenner (2003) is derived from this perspective. First, he suggests that a Justice may choose to join the majority opinion because he has an interest in being on the winning side. Certainly, this is one common 115 characterization of Justice Sandra Day O’Connor’s approach (Maveety 1996). Early small group research argued that an individual member’s power is related to the probability that he would be the pivotal member of a minimum winning coalition in any given decision (Schubert 1964; Shapley and Shubik 1954). Maveety argues that O’Connor’s experience in the Arizona state legislature taught her “that the nature of a compromise can be greatly affected by those who consistently ally with the majority coalition (Maveety 1996, 4). As the majority opinion contains legal rules with fiiture precedential value, Justices may decide to join in an effort to influence the substance of these rules (Spriggs et al. 1999). Once the minimum winning coalition has been assembled, all those remaining Justices who wish influence the text of the final majority opinion would find it prudent to join the majority. This approach worked for O’Connor at least, and her “propensity to join the winning coalition and to retain majority-side membership has kept O’Connor from being marginal to the Court’s discussions of policy” (Maveety 1996, 69). This interest in contributing to the majority opinion, along with an institutional bias against unnecessary concurring opinions, might encourage Justices to refrain from writing separate reasons when they agree with the majority’s result (Rohde 1977; Caldeira and Zorn 1998). Implementation of this strategy, though, seems to preclude the unnecessary joining of special opinions. If the goal is to be a part of the winning coalition, then nothing is to be gained from joining in concurrences or dissents. The second small group hypothesis presented by Brenner is that a Justice may join the majority opinion because everyone else has, and “the remaining justice feels uncomfortable as the sole hold—out” (2003, 277). Howard associates this behavior with a 116 freshman effect, noting that Justice Cardozo “frequently [voted] alone in conference before ultimately submerging himself in a group opinion” (Howard 1968, 45). Indeed, empirical research on voting fluidity between the conference vote and the final case disposition finds that a lone dissenter is twice as likely to join the majority than is a Justice who is part of a three-member dissenting coalition (Maltzman and Wahlbeck 1996b) In very important cases, this change in opinion may be a result of the accommodation efforts undertaken by the majority Opinion author and/or the Chief Justice. Howard argues that this happened in many cases, including the Japanese internment cases, with Justice Murphy suppressing a dissent in Hirabayashi and Douglas withholding a dissent in licortmt'azsu72 (Howard 1968). Joining as a way to avoid being the lone dissenter provides an explanation for unnecessary joining of a majority opinion, but does not help to explain the joining of a special opinion. Brenner’s third small group hypothesis seems to predict very different behavior from his second. Here, he asserts that a Justice may join because “she does not care a great deal whether the Court’s opinion is written one way or another or because the case is not particularly salient to her” (2003, 277). It is difficult to measure the salience of a particular case to a particular judge, and researchers usually resort to general measures deriving from contemporaneous (Epstein and Segal 2000), or post hoc assessments of case salience (Brenner and Arrington 2002). As such, the empirical research on this issue is generally at the level of the Court and not the individual Justice. Much of the evidence from voting fluidity analyses finds that judges are more likely to sign on to majority 7 2 Hirabayashi v. United States (1943) 320 US. 81; Korematsu v. United States (1944) 323 US. 214. 117 opinions in less salient cases (Dorff and Brenner 1992; Spriggs et al. 1999). Again, this hypothesis does not provide as much traction when we are considering unnecessary joining behavior involving special opinions. Ifthe judge is relatively ambivalent as to the outcome, other considerations may drive the decision to join the majority opinion, including the first and second hypotheses derived by Brenner (2003) from small group theory. The last hypothesis concerns the practical cost of authoring separate opinions. Brenner suggests that Justices may join to avoid spending “the time and effort necessary to write a persuasive concurring or dissenting opinion” (2003, 277). Because this hypothesis is separated out from the third small group hypothesis, we can assume that it is not intended to convey simply a lack of interest in the material. Instead, this argument implies that a Justice is responding to workload pressures. Baum (1997) includes minimizing workloads among the important judicial goals. Unlike the other small group hypotheses, the interest in easing workload pressures may apply to unnecessary joining behavior involving both majority and special opinions. Some argue that Justice Brennan’s attempt to organize joint opinions for the minority bloc succeeded because the other members of the minority felt significant workload pressures (Cook 1995; O'Brien 1999). While the author of a special opinion may have less motivation to accommodate potential joiners, the benefit to the joiner is likely the same. While some empirical research supports the assumption that heavy workloads can factor in to opinion-writing decisions, the evidence is far from decisive. Justices in the minority are more likely to acquiesce to the majority opinion without first circulating special opinions when their workloads are heavy (Spriggs et al. 1999). On the other 118 hand, majority opinion authors with heavy workloads may be less willing to accommodate his colleagues (W ahlbeck et al. 1998). Individual workload does not seem to increase the likelihood that a Justice will join the majority, although this likelihood does increase at the end of the term (Maltzman et al. 2000). A large number of cases on the Court’s docket does not seem to increase the likelihood that a member of the minority will switch sides to join the majority opinion (Epstein et al. 2001). As this discussion illustrates, most of the joining behavior research concerning the Supreme Court has to do with the decision to join the majority opinion. Much of the evidence outlined above suggests that, for various reasons, Justices will join majority opinions even if they do not match their most preferred ideological preferences. This makes sense, given the importance of the majority opinion in this particular institutional context. The need to amass a majority opinion coalition changes the calculation for judges. Because of the unique importance of the majority opinion, the existing American research spends little time investigating other types of unnecessary joining behavior. In addition, the rate of j oining behavior on special opinions is quite low on the Supreme Court (Segal and Spaeth 2002). Because of the seriatim opinion tradition in Australia, however, all joining behavior in the High Court resembles this type of unnecessary joining behavior. As such, all joining behavior on the High Court takes place in the absence of a clear institutional incentive to bargain and accommodate. 119 Joining Behavior in the Context of the High Court As the previous chapter indicates, the High Court is producing joint opinions at a much higher rate than it did several decades ago.73 Explaining the reasons behind the decision to join is quite difficult, especially in the absence of a majority opinion tradition. This growing number of joint opinions may reflect a desire of the Justices to clarify important points of law for lower cOurts or to build legitimacy in contentious areas. Certainly, it is easy to imagine that efficiency concerns may have instigated this shift. Some of this recent increase may have to do with the personal relationships between the judges (Coper 2002c). One High Court observer notes that Justice Gaudron often joined with Justice Gummow because she thought he was quite clever (McMillan 2003). An individual’s prior experience or issue expertise may well contribute to a tendency to join. It is also important to consider the role of ideological agreement in the decision to join. Once we take away the structure of opinion assignments, we should able to see a clearer picture of the “justice’s attractiveness to other justices” in terms of opinion writing (Handberg 1978, 373). Without the institutionalized pressure to negotiate a majority opinion, there is less reason to expect the judges to accommodate the views of his colleagues in order to obtain a joint opinion. Ifthis is the case, things like workload concerns, issue expertise and clarity should not satisfactorily explain the incidence of joint opinion production on the High Court. Instead, these joint opinions, like the special opinions of the US. Supreme Court, would comprise “a much richer source of information about judicial relationships” (Segal and Spaeth 2002, 395). 73 By contrast, the US. Supreme Court is producing fragmented decisions at a growing rate (Segal and Spaeth 2002). 120 Before we can investigate these hypotheses, however, it is important to address some of the recent empirical research on consensual norms in the High Court. Although the High Court formally operates using a seriatim opinion—writing tradition, some researchers have suggested that this tradition is being subverted by a defacto norm of consensus (Narayan and Smyth 2005). If this is true, then High Court Justices are increasingly subject to an institutional norm encouraging joint Opinions just as Supreme Court Justices are. For this reason, the next chapter investigates this question in depth. 121 CHAPTER FIVE: CONSENSUAL NORMS ON THE HIGH COURT Unlike their position in America, concurring judgments are simply the usual method by which judges in the English tradition express agreement with each other, despite occasional instances of welcome unanimity. —Andrew Lynch (2003a) This analysis begins with the premise that, with the existence of the seriatim opinion tradition in Australia, there is no functioning consensual norm to encourage judges on the High Court to produce joint Opinions. Ifthis is the case, the presence of joint opinions would be unexpected given the standard explanations used in the American attitudinal and strategic decision-making models. These joint opinions would either be expressions of attitudinal congruence between judges, or attributable to some other mechanism (such as workload pressures, deference to issue experts, etc.). The first step to approaching the question, then, is to determine the extent to which the premise is reasonable. To do this, it is necessary to examine the extent to which the High Court as a whole subscribes to some sort of consensual norm. A norm is “a social rule that does not depend on government for either promulgation or enforcement” (Posner and Rasmusen 1999, 369). The consensual norm—at least in its American formulation—is a social rule that causes judges to feel “obliged to mask their differences from public view by working them out via a single majority opinion” (Epstein et al. 2001, 364). Certainly, the seriatim tradition is also a norm, in that under it judges feel “a very strict obligation under the constitution to express their individual opinions” (Clark 2003, 10). It is reasonable to assume that the High Court’s seriatim opinion tradition precludes any type of functioning consensual norm (Smyth 2002c), but this is an empirical question. This chapter will approach this question by adapting the relevant Supreme Court research to accommodate 122 the High Court’s unique institutional setting. This is helpful for the present analysis, as it provides an institutional-level baseline of normal joining behavior. It will also provide evidence as to whether joining behavior is largely norm driven (as it seems to be on the Supreme Court), or if it may be driven by some other mechanism. Defining Types of Opinion-Writing Behavior Before considering the factors influencing joining behavior in the High Court, it is necessary to address an important practical concern. In the High Court of Australia, it is nearly impossible to distinguish a joiner from an author. In the US. Supreme Court, a measure of writing behavior is easy to create. With the exception of per curium opinions, the writer of a Supreme Court opinion is typically identified in the written reports. This makes it possible to attribute writing behavior to those judges who have written an opinion, be it the majority opinion or some other opinion. The traditions and reporting style of the High Court, however, create significant differences that make the process more complicated. Terminology Even among Australian legal scholars and practitioners, the use of opinion-writing terminology is far from precise (Lynch 2002a). To complicate matters further, the American and Australian literature often use the same words to describe very different things. The American use of opinion-writing vocabulary is more consistent, and provides a solid point of comparison for settling on terminology to accurately describe Opinion- writing on the High Court. Describing opinion-writing on the US. Supreme Court In the common law tradition, the written opinion is an explanation (or set of explanations) of the Court’s disposition of a particular case. These reasons are published 123 in the relevant reports, and are made available to lawmakers, lawyers, and the general public. The Court’s decision as to the disposition or outcome of the case—what actually happens to the litigants—is called a “judgment,” while the associated reasons are called “opinions.” In the Supreme Court, members of the majority vote coalition all agree with the disposition of the case at hand. Justices who disagree with the majority as to the outcome of the case will author or join a dissenting opinion. These dissenting opinions support an alternative disposition for the case, and they provide reasons for this conclusion. Members of this coalition typically join (or author) the opinion of the Court. The opinion of the Court is also called the majority Opinion, as it is a set of reasons that a majority of Justices have joined. Ifthe majority voting coalition fails to secure a majority of j oiners, the resulting opinion is a plurality opinion and is called a “judgment of the Court.” While the reasons contained in the opinion of the Court carry the weight of precedent, the reasons in a judgment of the Court do not (Hochschild 2000). Ifthey are dissatisfied with the reasons of the majority opinion, members of the majority vote coalition may choose to author or join a concurring opinion. If a Justice agrees with the reasons contained in the majority opinion and simply wishes to add additional observations or reasons, she may author or join a regular concurrence. Justices writing or joining a regular concurrence are also part of the majority opinion coalition. If a Justice agrees only with the outcome but not with the majority’s reasons, that Justice may write or join a special concurrence. A special concurrence is essentially an alternative set of reasons to that presented by in the majority opinion. When a Justice authors or joins a special concurrence, he is not part of the majority opinion coalition. In 124 this way, a special concurrence diminishes the majority coalition in a way that a regular concurrence does not (Maveety 2003). A lexicon for describing High Court opinion-writing First, it is important to note that the common Australian use of the term “judgment” is different from the American usage. Although some purists protest (Kirby 2006), most legal commentators and practitioners use the terms “judgment” and “opinions” interchangeably. Justice Kirby points out that the word “judgment” is used in the Constitution to refer to the orders handed down by the Court, and he suggests using either “opinion” or “reasons” to denote the written explanation of the Court’s orders (Kirby 2007b). The term “opinion” will be used here to refer to the written explanations of the case disposition, which will be termed the “judgment” or “outcome.” All separate opinion-writing behavior on the Supreme Court is described relative to the majority opinion. Regular concurrences concur with the majority opinion, special concurrences concur with the majority’s disposition of the case, and dissenting opinions disagree with both. In the absence of a majority opinion tradition, these terms lose their moorings. The classic seriatim-style disposition of a case is a collection of separate sets of reasons—one set for each participating Justice. Dissenting Opinions express the reasons for disagreement with the outcome favored by the majority. The use of the term “concurring opinion” is much more problematic. In a sense, a unanimous decision handed down in the traditional seriatim style is much like a collection of what Americans call special concurrences. The main difference, of course, is that the seriatim tradition leaves no central explanation of reasons with which to concur. When Australians use the term “concurrence,” they are actually referring to a separate Opinion that supports the majority 125 vote coalition’s disposition of the case. Because precedential weight is distributed among all of the opinions in support of the majority, the concurring opinions essentially are the Australian version of a majority opinion. The term “concurrence” is somewhat problematic in this context, as it implies the existence of a single majority opinion. The other descriptor commonly used in Australia—the term “separate opinion”—is even more problematic. This term is over-broad, as it incorporates separate opinions in the minority as well as the majority. The more precise alternative may be “separate opinion in support of the majority vote coalition,” but this is far too cumbersome. As such, the term “concurrence” will be used here to denote the separately-delivered opinions that, together, make up the reasons for the majority’s disposition of the case. The High Court does not always dispose of cases using the classic seriatim style. Indeed, the intent of this research project is to explain the Court’s production of j oint opinions in the absence of an American-style majority opinion tradition. For this reason, some additional terminology is needed to describe the full range of opinion-writing behavior of the High Court Justices. On occasion, the Court will publish a single set of reasons, with which all the Justices agree. In the Supreme Court, this would be a majority opinion. The use of that term, however, implies the unique precedential weight that American majority opinions carry. In Australia, these Opinions do not carry additional weight. To avoid this confusion, the Australian version will be called a “single-opinion disposition.” Often, smaller opinion coalitions will form on the High Court. Instead of a single- opinion disposition, many cases will have one or more Opinions coauthored by a subset of the panel. These are often called “joint judgments” in the Australian literature but, for 126 consistency, they are referred to as “joint opinions” here. These joint opinions can be in support of the majority or in dissent. On occasion, Australian researchers refer to joint Opinions in support of the majority as “joint majority opinions” or simply “majority opinions.” As this chapter will demonstrate, this can lead to serious measurement and equivalence problems. Instead, the term “joint opinion” will be used to refer to any instance where more than one Justice coauthors an opinion. The single-opinion disposition is a specific kind of joint opinion, and is included in analyses of joint opinions unless otherwise specified. Consensual Norms in the Literature At its heart, a consensual norm in the judicial context is an institutional tradition of deference on the part of the individual judge to the decisions of the majority. At the height of the consensual norm in the US. Supreme Court, “[i]ndividual expression was kept to a minimum and within a relatively consistent range” (Walker et al. 1988). Essentially, this means that dissenting and specially concurring opinions were somewhat unusual, even if private difference of opinion was not (Epstein et al. 2001). In the American context, the decision to author a concurring opinion is seen as “strategic devices that further short-term individual ends at the expense of institutional integrity” (Schwartz 1992, 241). Researchers have documented the decline of the consensual norm in the Supreme Court (Best 2000; Caldeira and Zorn 1998; Haynie 1992; Walker et al. 1988). This decline has long been lamented as being harmful to the institutional legitimacy of the Supreme Court (Hand 1958; Pritchett 1954). The reasons given for the decline are varied. Much of the blame is laid on the shoulders of the Court’s leadership (Caldeira and Zorn 1998), Chief Justices Stone (Danelski 1960; Walker et al. 1988) and Hughes (Haynie 1992) especially. Others 127 attribute the decrease in consensual behavior to practical considerations, and not to an underlying consensual norm. The increase in discretionary jurisdiction created by the Judges’ Bill of 1925 has been cited as a reason (Halpem and Vines 1977), along with the subsequent decrease in routine cases (Wood et al. 1998b). Others point to an actual increase in ideological disagreement among members of the Court, especially in the areas of civil rights and civil liberties (Hurwitz and Lanier 2004). Even technological and organizational advances in Court administration have been cited as a cause for the proliferation of separate opinions (Martin and Soroka 2004). Whatever the cause, the declining levels of consensual behavior are manifested in the decreasing propensity of the Justices to deliver joint opinions with their colleagues. If this is due to norm-related behavior, identifying a changing consensual norm on the Supreme Court first requires an identification of what constitutes a deviation from consensus. Often called a measure of “dissensus,” this can be little more than a count of occurrences of non-j oining behavior (Caldeira and Zorn 1998). Most times, this amounts to a calculation of the proportion of dissenting or concurring Opinions per opinion written (Haynie 1992; Hurwitz and Lanier 2004; Walker et al. 1988).74 Clearly, this method measures only that level of dissensus that can be seen in the final opinion tally (Atkins and Green 1976). It acts as a proxy for the actual level of disagreement existing among the members of the Court. This can be problematic for researchers interested in determining the root cause of the measured dissensus, and its relationship to some more general consensual norm. In short, an increasing incidence of separate opinions does not necessarily mean that a norm of consensus that once existed 74 Caldeira and Zorn (1998) do not standardize the dissents and concurrences, but argue that the results would have been similar if they had. 128 has now weakened (Epstein et al. 2001). If changes in agenda composition are the root cause of increased dissensus, it would be reasonable to believe that a norm of consensus never existed in the first place. In that case, the increasingly contentious cases may have brought disagreement to a Court that experienced little real disagreement in the past and, thus, had no need of a consensual norm to discourage the expression of individual opinion. Several researchers have provided qualitative documentation of an active culture of consensual norms in the pre-1940 Supreme Court (Schaefer 1966; Wood et al. 1998b). Epstein, Segal and Spaeth (2001) address this problem directly through an empirical investigation of Chief Justice Waite’s docket books. They utilize an independent measure of dissensus: the votes of the Justices during the Court’s private conferences. They compare these private votes to the reported votes that, of course, provide the public face of unanimity during the Waite Court (1874-1888). While they find evidence that the nondiscretionary caseload muted disagreement all around, they also find that “a norm of consensus did, in all likelihood, exist” (Epstein et al. 2001, 376). Caldeira and Zorn (1998) test the consensual norm hypothesis from a different angle. They begin from the theoretical stance that, if a norm of consensus is the underlying cause of shifting levels of public disagreement, this norm should similarly impact both dissent rates and rates of concurring opinions. They analyze rates of dissent and concurrence between 1800 and 1991. They find a cointegrated relationship between rates of concurrence and dissent, with changes in the former following changes in the latter. They argue that this specific type of relationship demonstrates that “a common element underlies levels of both dissents and concurrences, and thus provides more direct 129 evidence for the existence and influence of consensual norms” (Caldeira and Zorn 1998, 888) In this view, concurrences and dissents are both types of nonconsensual behavior. In the Supreme Court, though, dissents and concurrences serve very different purposes. While dissents express more complete dissatisfaction with the judicial outcome, they also fit with the policy-oriented predictions of the attitudinal and strategic models of decision- making behavior (Maveety 2003). These models focus on the policy importance of the case outcome, and argue that doctrinal rules contained in the Opinions “merely rationalize decisions; they are not the causes of them” (Segal and Spaeth 1993, 66). For this reason, as Maveety explains, “to concur is to agree but to disagree, yet to disagree about matters which judicial behaviori sm discounted as superfluous: the legal content of the majority opinion” (Maveety 2003, 176). Concurrences can result in plurality opinions (or “judgments of the Court”), undercutting the precedential value of the opinion without tangible policy-related benefits (Davis and Reynolds 1974). In this way, the attitudinal and strategic models would predict different causes for dissents as compared to concurrences. For each, dissenting behavior is a reflection of dissatisfaction with the substantive outcome of the case. Strategic theorists have predicted that concurrences will be used as a negotiating tool (Murphy 1964), and attitudinalists have speculated that concurrences are essentially throw-away votes cast in cases involving less-strongly-held policy preferences (Segal and Spaeth 1993). Indeed, both camps seem skeptical of their own post hoc attempts to explain concurrences, and instead seem to coalesce around a norm-based explanation (Maveety 2003). Caldeira and Zorn (1998) argue—implicitly, at least—that rates of these two distinct types of 130 nonconsensual behavior would not trend together unless an underlying consensual norm were responsible. Investigating the possibility of consensual norms on the High Court can provide insight into the aggregate patterns of separate opinions and joining behavior. This is critical for the present research project, beginning as it does with the assertion that joining behavior in a seriatim institution is something unusual and deserving of explanation. Consensual Norms in the Australian Context Investigations of the norm of consensus on the US. Supreme Court usually begin with the tenure of Chief Justice John Marshall. While this is appropriate for the kinds of questions asked by observers of the Supreme Court, it starts fi'om a premise that is inappropriate for courts operating under the British tradition of seriatim opinion production. Marshall “eliminated the practice of seriatim opinions that allowed each Justice to voice his individual views on every case,” believing that this would best protect the institutional legitimacy of the Court (Walker et al. 1988, 362). The norm of consensus that would result from a wholesale repudiation of the seriatim tradition, then, would be one in which the expression of both dissenting and concurring opinions would be discouraged. It is this sort of norm that is identified in the work of Caldeira and Zorn (1998) Given the Australian High Court’s adherence to the seriatim opinion tradition, however, such a norm would be quite unexpected. In Australia, judges conform to a much different norm. By definition, the seriatim opinion tradition tolerates concurring opinions. In the context of this tradition, a norm of consensus would not likely include pressure to join an opinion for the Court. However, this does not preclude a different sort of consensual norm—one that values individual voices that agree with the disposition of 131 the case. Such a norm may encourage consensus by suppressing dissenting votes, while treating separately-written Opinions in support of the vote consensus as consensual behavior. Of course, this is of less immediate concern in the context of a model of joining behavior on the High Court. Ifthe writing of concurring opinions is truly suppressed by a consensual norm, the joining behavior on the High Court can be explained in the same way as it is on the Supreme Court. Ifnot, then an alternative model of j oining behavior will be necessary to explain why unconstrained judges choose to join. The Norm of Concurring Opinions The simplest definition Of a concurring opinion is a separate opinion in favor of the majority vote coalition’s judgment in the case. Such an opinion advocates for the same case outcome as the majority of the judges on the bench. In contrast, a dissenting opinion is one that advocates a case outcome different from the outcome of the majority. While this is a relatively straightforward classification system in the context of the United States, these concepts “are more than a little difficult to apply due to the seriatim tradition followed by the Australian courts” (Lynch 2002a, 471). Indeed, a concurring opinion in Australia often has no single majority opinion with which to concur. In other words, Australian cases are disposed of with what would be called a plurality opinion in the United States: a collection of opinions in support of a particular outcome, but with no single opinion signed by a majority of the judges. The individual responsibility for one’s own reasons is seen to trump the need for the institution to produce a unified Opinion of the court (Coper 2002c). This follows more closely the opinion of Thomas Jefferson on the matter, who notes that the seri atim tradition 132 shews whether every judge has taken the trouble of understanding the case, of investigating it minutely, and of forming an opinion for himself, instead of pinning it on another’s sleeve. (Jefferson 1822, 1) The result of this tradition is that judges frequently author—and are expected to author— separate opinions, regardless of the degree to which they agree with the majority on the disposition of the case. In the United States, this practice is frowned upon. Researchers describe the task of sorting out the mess of seriatim-style opinions as Herculean (Gerber and Park 1997). They lament the lack of clarity in cases without a unified majority opinion, as well as the danger they pose to the legitimacy of the Court as an institution (Davis and Reynolds 1974). In the High Court of Australia, however, this lack of clarity is not seen to be a critical problem. While some legal practitioners continue to call for a more united front (McMillan 2003 ), the practice is generally accepted. In Australia, “the law is not the function of a majority opinion but instead of the highest common factor among the opinions supporting the judgment” (Rosenberg and Williams 1997, 443). Ever since the addition of the independent-minded Higgins and Isaacs to the High Court in 1906, the decision-making process on the Court has been characterized by this “rugged individualism” (Smyth and Narayan 2004, 404). Indeed, each judge is seen to have a duty under the judicial oath to produce reasons for which he can be held individually accountable (COper 2002c). While some Justices have occasionally expressed an interest in creating more joint opinions where the judges are already inclined to agree with one another (Gleeson 2004b; Mason 2003a), “there does not seem to be even an informal policy against separate judgments” (Bagaric and McConvill 2005, 5). 133 Of the little empirical research there is on decision making in the High Court, much of it concerns voting behavior as opposed to opinion-writing behavior (e. g., Blackshield 1972; Schubert 1969a). There is, though, some empirical evidence supporting the claim that the institutional norms allow the writing of separate concurring Opinions. In a study of joining behavior on the Latham Court (1935-1950), Smyth (2002b) reports that nearly 60% of cases reported were delivered in the seriatim style. Narayan and Smyth (2005) explain that the seriatim tradition creates what they call a “low consensus equilibrium,” in which there is a lack of consistent and significant promotion of j oint opinion production. There are several ways to assess the level of support for this norm of concurring opinions. One way, in keeping with the measurements used by Narayan and Smyth (2005), is to look at concurring opinions as a percentage of all written opinions over time. They do not count cases, but instead count opinions—individual statements of reasons, be they in support of the majority or not. In the data analyzed in the present study, from 1965 to 2002 an average of 53% of all opinions written were separate opinions in support of the majority disposition of the case.75 As Figure 6 illustrates, this number has decreased slightly over time, with a distinct dip between 1981 and 1996. In contrast, joint opinions in support of the majority represent 29% of all opinions written. This measure, however, fails to account for the fewer opportunities for joint majority opinions as compared to concurring opinions. Iffour Justices decide to join, the resulting opinion is only counted as one joint opinion. Ifthe same judges decide to write separately, this is counted as four separate opinions. This significantly undercounts joint opinions—a problem which will be addressed at some length in the next section. Ifthe 5 Judgments written in cases drsposed of by a Single judge are removed from thrs analysrs, as they provrde no opportunity for joining, concurring or dissenting behavior on the part of the judge. 134 Figure 6 - Concurring and Joint Opinions in Majority per 100 Reported, 1965-2002 100 804 604 U1 C 0 IE 0. 9 40« E “6 . (D ’f “ ,"“.;“ ’1---- 2 20“ _ g Concurrences U .-.. g 0 .Jornt Oplnlons 19555710 '7'1 '73 '7'5 '7'7 is '8'1 '8'3 '0'5 '87 '59 '91 '93 '95 '57 '99 '01 frequency of concurring and joint opinions in the majority by case is substituted for the opinion-based measure, the joint opinions are no longer undercounted. Figure 7 shows the percentage of cases per year with at least one concurring opinion. On average, 70.1% of cases have at least one concuning opinion filed. Additionally, Figure 7 shOws the percentage of cases with a joint opinion in the majority. A joint opinion in support of the majority can be penned by a coalition of as few as two Justices. A case can easily have a mixture of j oint opinions and concurrences in support of the majority. Taken together, these two accounts of consensual behavior indicate that, for the period investigated, concurring opinions are not successfully discouraged on the High Court. These opinions account for over half of the opinions filed, and are present in the majority of cases heard by the Court. That is not to say, however, that joint opinions are effectively discouraged, either. Clearly, the incidence of j oint opinions in the majority has remained high through this period, and especially so since the early 19805. 135 Figure 7 - Percentage of Cases with Concurrences and Joint Opinions in Majority, 1965-2002 ..... 100 .. 7 . U) 8 8 __ .5 At Least One in Concurrence ,8 20« _ _ - . 8 At least One :5” Joint Opinion 0. 0 1955 '57'759 '71 '7th '75 '77 '79 '51 '53 '55 '57 '55 '51 '53 '55 '57 '55 '51 Of course, the evidence above is descriptive in nature, and represents only an account of the observable incidence of such behavior. Determining whether this stems from a norm is much more difficult. As the research on the US. Supreme Court indicates, finding empirical evidence of an underlying norm accounting for observable behavior is rarely a simple matter. The cause can be advanced by identifying external confirmation of such a norm, or by failing to find evidence of independent causes for the behavior. The task of identifying dynamism over time, however, will be reserved for later in the chapter. The self-conscious maintenance of the seriatim tradition is, in itself, evidence that there is an institutional norm at work. Chief Justice Gleeson argues that the practice of encouraging joint majority opinions “involves a formal discipline that has never been accepted in the High Court” (Gleeson 2004b). Chief Justice Mason agrees, arguing that shoehoming divergent legal perspectives into a single opinion risks compromising judicial integrity (Mason 2003a). Justice Kirby attributes a similar sentiment to Justice 136 Kitto, who argued that, “on balance, the writing of individual judgments tends to produce the better work” (Kitto, as quoted in Kirby 1998c, 29). Still, the fact remains that several Justices, especially those in leadership positions, have sought to facilitate the joint majority opinion. Chief Justice Griffith’s very early leadership has been described as unity seeking. in the mold of John Marshall (McGinley 1987). More recently, Chief Justices have attempted to facilitate the production of j oint opinions. Gleeson has instituted regular conferences that, while informal, “provide for the exchange of views [and] the reaching of consensual opinions and judgments” (Callinan 1999). Chief Justice Mason also made “a more concerted effort to achieve that result, particularly by inviting one of our number to write an initial judgment or draft” (Mason 2003a). Even those Justices who would like to see more joint opinions are quick to defend the seriatim tradition. Chief Justice Gleeson explains, I welcome joint judgments when we can get them and I’m anxious to promote the writing of joint judgments but not at the expense of people feeling obliged to compromise or to join in what is not really an expression of their own opinion. (Gleeson, CJ, quoted in Clark 2003, 10) Indeed, observers of the Court have seen these attempts at encouraging joint opinions as lackluster at best. According to Kildea, Australian courts “have not adopted, in any methodical way, a practice that encourages joint judgments” (Kildea 2003, 61). It seems, then, that a separate opinion norm may indeed exist on the High Court. Despite the rhetoric encouraging joint opinions, the Justices themselves seem reluctant to compromise individual ”accountability to facilitate them. Joint opinions seem welcome when they happen to emerge, but a culture of encouraging negotiation and compromise appears to be absent on the Court. While separate concurring opinions may not be openly 137 encouraged, they seem clearly not to be actively discouraged. As Justice Callinan noted early in his High Court career, “no justice seeks to exert any pressures on the others” (Callinan 1999). In short, the seriatim tradition should result in particular patterns in concuning behavior over time. Namely, we should expect that concurrence is frequent and that this rate is relatively stable over time. Ifthis is the case, it provides support for the claim that the seriatim tradition is a functioning norm on the Court that at least accommodates (and at most encourages) the production of concuning opinions. The previous section provides some confirmation that concurring opinions are produced at a relatively high rate over time (see Figure 6 and Figure 7). The following section will address this in more detail. First, however, it is necessary to consider the meaning of the phrase “consensual norm” as we would expect it to apply to a court with an active seriatim tradition. By evaluating the various existing approaches to the study of consensual norms in the US. Supreme Court and in the High Court of Australia, an alternative measure of concurrence and dissent emerges. By using this insight, it is possible to develop a comprehensive analysis of patterns of concurrence and dissent that applies to the unique institutional configuration of the High Court. Dissent and the Consensual Norm Identifying an underlying norm of consensus requires more than looking at the patterns of opinion writing in support of the majority. Many of the approaches used by American researchers to identify an underlying norm have utilized information about both dissenting and concurring opinion production (e. g., Epstein et al. 2001; Haynie 1992). This certainly makes sense, as the most obvious breach of a consensual norm is to dissent. In the context of the US. Supreme Court, the incidence of concurring and 138 dissenting opinions are both used as proxy measures for a failure to reach consensus. In essence, “dissenting and concurring opinions and votes represent modes of conflict on the Supreme Court” (Caldeira and Zorn 1998, 877). In the seriatim opinion tradition, though, concurring opinions are the norm. Certainly, some Chief Justices of the High Court have been inspired to pursue joint majority opinions, usually in response to pressure from the legal community (Clark 2003). Unlike the Supreme Court, however, the High Court does not view concurring opinions as an expression of conflict. The dissenting opinion in the High Court, though, does represent a distinct break from the majority on the part of the individual dissenter. For this reason, if we are to expect any sort of consensual norm in a court with a seriatim opinion tradition, we would expect this norm to extend to dissenting opinions and not concurrences. Researchers have attempted to discern whether there has been a norm of consensus in Australia. Mirroring the approach of Caldeira and Zorn (1998), Smyth and colleagues have attempted to find evidence of an underlying consensual norm guiding the High Court’s behavior over time. In an early version of the research, Smyth (2002c) applies a cointegration analysis to aggregate-level data on High Court opinion production rates from 1903-1975. Smyth looks for a cointegrated relationship between concurring opinions and dissenting opinions on the High Court, but fails to find one. As such, analysis fails to yield support for the hypothesis that the same underlying process drives both concurring and dissenting behavior in Australia. Instead, Smyth concludes that “a single consensual norm does not underlie decision making in the High Court” (Smyth 2002c,255) 139 Given what we know about the role of concurring opinions in Australia, however, this is not terribly surprising. The seriatim opinion tradition is itself a norm, guiding the High Court’s institutional view of concurring opinion production. Ifthis seriatim tradition fails to discourage concurring opinions, it can do so in one of two ways. First, the tradition may lump separate concurring opinions together with dissenting opinions, classifying both as institutionally acceptable outlets for judicial expression. In this way, the tradition would be tolerant of judicial dissensus. In such a situation, a norm of consensus would clearly not exist. Alternatively, the seri atim tradition may distinguish between concurring opinions and dissenting opinions, accepting the former but discouraging the latter. Such a norm can be considered a norm of consensus, but must be differentiated from the American version by the way consensus is defined. In the Supreme Court since Marshall, the concurring opinion has been seen as an expression of dissensus. This Australian version of the consensual norm, a seriatim consensual norm, could include concurring opinions as expressions of consensus. In a more recent revisiting of the consensual norm question, Narayan and Smyth (2005) find some support for a more understated version of the American-style consensual norm in the High Court. In an analysis spanning 1904-2001, they reinterpret the meaning of the consensual norm, this time looking for “some norm on the issue of dissent in operation on the Court at most times,” with this norm prescribing “either high or low dissent” (Narayan and Smyth 2005, 165). They are not looking for a seriatim consensual norm as defined above, but instead seek to find a common norm underlying the changes in both concurring and dissenting behavior. 140 They find some evidence for a cointegrated relationship between dissenting and concurring opinions on the High Court. In other words, they find a long-memoried relationship between changes in dissent rates and changes in rates of concurrence. Because of the institutional differences between the High Court and the Supreme Court, Narayan and Smyth (2005) use slightly different measures from those in Caldeira and Zorn (1998). First, Narayan and Smyth decide to “treat the majority joint opinion in any given case as the de facto opinion of the Court” (2005, 155). By joint majority opinion, they mean any joint opinion written in support of the majority vote coalition. As such, what they call a “majority joint opinion” is not usually signed by a majority of the Justices. They concede that joint majority opinions in the High Court have a substantially different connotation from the Supreme Court counterpart, but argue that this “comes closest to representing the opinion of the Court with a system of seriatim opinion writing” (2005, 155). There is no added precedential weight given to joint majority opinions in the High Court (Gleeson 2004b). Additionally, a substantial percentage of cases will have no joint majority opinion with which a judge could concur, if he should so desire. What this means, in a sense, is that the opinions classified as “concurring” are actually part of the majority. Andrew Lynch gives the following example of this difficulty: It has certainly not been uncommon for all seven members of the Court to deliver their own individual opinions in firll. In such instances it is, to an extent, quite meaningless to regard concurrences and dissents as being of the same ilk— judgments which together stand ‘separate’ from a clearly identified and concerted majority. Rather the collection of concurrences amounts to a majority and it is the dissents alone which are on the outer. (Lynch 2003a) This is not to say that the decision to measure concurrence this way is incorrect. Instead, this definition of the concurring decision as a distinctly nonconsensual behavior may be 141 misleading in that it includes opinions written in situations similar to the one outlined above. The second place where the Narayan and Smyth (2005) piece diverges from Caldeira and Zorn’s (1998) methodology is essentially a consequence of the first, and has to do with the way opinions are counted. Previous research on consensual norms in the Supreme Court typically used weighted concurrence and dissent rates, or the number of opinions per 100 majority opinions (Haynie 1992; Walker et al. 1988). In other words, the data consisted of the number of separate opinions per 100 decided cases. Caldeira and Zorn (1998) use the raw number of opinions with concurrences and dissents. They do not standardize their data by the number of cases per year, but they do consider the concurrence and dissent rates on the case level. Perhaps as a way to simplify the data collection process in light of the seriatim opinion tradition in the High Court, Narayan and Smyth (2005) analyze the number of concurring and dissenting opinions per 100 opinions. This differs from the aforementioned studies because it does not consider the concurrence and dissent rates on the case level. This works to overemphasize the variation in concurrence rates, weighting the cases delivered seriatim more heavily than those delivered in joint opinion style. Consider two types of unanimous cases in the High Court: the first type is delivered seriatim, with seven different opinions all supporting the majority, the second type is disposed of with an opinion signed by all five judges and two separate concurring opinions. Next, imagine that there were fifty instances of each type in one year. The Narayan and Smyth methodology weighs the seriatim cases two and one-third times more heavily than those delivered in joint opinion style. The fifty seriatim cases yield seven 142 opinions each, for 350 total opinions. For this half of the agenda, one hundred percent of opinions are concuning opinions. The fifty joint opinion style cases, on the other hand, yield only 150 opinions total: 100 concurring opinions and 50 joint opinions. For this half of the agenda, two-thirds of the opinions are concurring. Taken as a whole, the Smyth and Narayan methodology would determine that 90% of opinions from this hypothetical year are concurring opinions. While this is indeed true, it fails to capture the phenomenon more relevant to the study of consensual norms: the number of judge-level opinion-writing opportunities leading to concurring Opinions. Using the above example, weihave seven judges with one hundred opinion-writing opportunities each, for 700 total. In the fifty seriatim cases, all opinion-writing opportunities resulted in concurring opinions, or 350 in all. In the joint opinion cases, 250 of the opinion-writing opportunities resulted in joint opinions. The remaining 100 led to concurring opinions. Total, this makes for 450 concurring opinions out of 700 opinion-writing opportunities, or 64.3%. The difference between 90% and 64.3% is substantial. Using the opinion-writing opportunities standardization allows for a more precisely targeted measure. This operationalization also helps to account for differences in panel sizes both case-by-case and year-by-year. It is true that, when the panel system is working correctly, there will be more opinion-writing opportunities in constitutional cases and other cases deemed important by the Chief Justice (Brennan 2002a). This is because these important cases will be heard by a firll bench, while other cases will be heard by a smaller panel. What is of interest here, though, is the individual-level judge behavior. This behavior is more 143 accurately captured by investigating the choices judges make for each decisional opportunity. For this reason, the investigation of the consensual norm in the High Court will focus on the opinion-writing opportunity, although the Narayan and Smyth (2005) measure will be presented for purposes of comparison. This investigation is intended to accomplish two goals. First, it will revisit the relationship between concurrence and dissent in the High Court. Specifically, it will provide a replication of Smyth (2002c) and Narayan and Smyth (2005). Second, it will investigate the longitudinal patterns of concurrence and joining behavior. Taken together, these analyses will provide insight into whether joining behavior is something that occurs in the High Court for reasons other than the “consensual norm” that has been described in the literature. An Underlying Norm of Consensus in Australia? As the previous section explains, past research has attempted to find evidence of a norm of consensus on the High Court (Narayan and Smyth 2005; Smyth 2002c). This norm of consensus, if it exists, would have significant consequences for our evaluation of the seriatim tradition in the Court. Indeed, such a finding would implicate a waning tradition of separate opinion writing. Additionally, the presence of such a norm would suggest that joining behavior is not something particulariy unusual given the institutional context of the Court, as joining in the US. Supreme Court is not particularly unusual. Caldeira and Zorn (1998) suggest a very specific operational definition of the consensual norm in the judicial context. Because this consensual norm is something driving both dissents and concurrences, they argue that finding a cointegrated relationship between rates of concurrences and dissents over time “is good circumstantial evidence” of the existence of the consensual norm (Caldeira and Zorn 1998, 881). As such, the opinion- 144 writing data from the High Court of Australia from 1965-2002 will be evaluated for such evidence. Stationarity and cointegration A cointegrating relationship exists between two series of order 1(1) if the difference between them yields an 1(0) series. In other words, two non-means stationary series are cointegrated if a linear, means stationary combination of these variables exists. In this case, the series share a linear attractor, and tend to trend together. If a shock occurs in one series, the other exerts a gravitational pressure of sorts on it, pulling it back in line. This provides an avenue for a very intuitive indicator of theoretical constructs like institutional norms, as such a norm could be the origin of the trend in each series. Surely, this is the application intended by those applying cointegration techniques in search of consensual norms in judicial institutions (i.e., Caldeira and Zorn 1998; Smyth 2002c; Narayan and Smyth 2005; 2007)}. No pair of series can be cointegrated if either series is stationary—in other words, both series must trend in order for them to be trending together. For a time series to have second-order stationarity which is the customary assumption for normally distributed data, the process must have a constant mean and variance over time (Maddala and Kim 1998).76 In mathematical notation for series y,, this can be represented as EO’z) = 1507-1): -~ = EO’l-n) = 71 Vol) = Vtm) = = Vein) = oz 76 . . . . . . . . . . . Thrs rs contrasted wrth first-order statronarrty, which requrres that the distribution of the series would be unaffected by an arbitrary shift in time. This is not the customary assumption because it is “defined in terms of the distribution” (Maddala and Kim 1998, 10). 145 COVO’t) = cor/m.» = = cor/em) = 72 Variance stationarity is fairly straightforward to diagnose and correct. While there are tests for variance stationarity, simply looking at the data is a reasonable approach to diagnosis (Granger and Newbold 1977). Ignoring it can lead to overparameterized models (Milionis 2004), but correcting for variance nonstationarity can be as simple as computing a log transformation for the series (Box and Cox 1964). Indeed, this is the approach used by Narayan and Smith (2005). Once the variance is stationary, the stationarity of the means can be assessed. A means-stationary process is one in which the data exhibit no trend. Diagnosing means stationarity is important in order to satisfy the assumptions of many analytical models, and also as a first step in cointegration analysis (Zivot and Wang 2006). There are many ways to accomplish this, the most famous being the Augmented Dickey-Fuller (ADF) (Said and Dickey 1984) test (Elder and Kennedy 2001). Like other unit root tests (e. g., Phillips and Perron 1988), the null hypothesis of the ADF test is non-stationarity, or first- order integration. More specifically, the ADF test is a test for random walk, random walk with drift, or random walk with deterministic trend, k Ay, = A + [17+ 704-1 + Z 7,- AyH + 8, i=1 where ,60 is a constant (representing drift), ,6 is the constant on time trend 1 (representing deterministic trend), and y is the test statistic with a non-standard t distribution. This augmented version of the original Dickey-Fuller (1979) test contains a lagged 146 endogenous variable to help ensure that there is no information left in the residuals of the test equation. The Elliot, Rothenberg and Stock (ERS) test (1996) is a modified version of this type of autoregressive unit root test, improving on the difficulty the ADF test and other unit root tests have in detecting alternative, non-unit root hypotheses (Zivot and Wang 2006). This test, also called the DF-GLS test, essentially uses a process of GLS detrending to derive the test statistic more efficiently. The error term is less constrained, and can be specified using different formulation. This allows for the removal of the deterministic terms in the ADF test, giving it more power to distinguish between persistent 1(0) series and those containing a unit root. Stationarity tests, including the popular KPSS test (Kwiatkowski et al. 1992), begin with a null hypothesis of stationarity. The KPSS test is a test of parameter constancy, with the null hypothesis being that the parameter for trend is equal to zero. More precisely, the KPSS is actually two different tests: a test for stationarity in level form (Hu) and a test for stationarity with deterministic trend (Ht). This test is often used in conjunction with unit root tests as a confirmatory step, as in Narayan and Smyth (2005). Like the ERS test, the KPSS test was designed to more effi ciently distinguish the persistent I(0) series from the 1(1) series.77 Identifying a unit root in a series is important, as analysis of two means non- stationary series is likely to yield evidence of relationships that are actually spurious (Granger and Newbold 1977; Yule 1926). The standard treatment of such a series is to render them stationary through the process of first differencing. While this process can 77 . . . . . . . For a drscussron of issues surroundrng unrt root dragnosrs, see Campbell and Perron (1991). 147 help us avoid the problems of spurious regression results, it eliminates information contained in these series pertaining to their possible long-run relationship. Engle and Granger (1987) identify an alternative which involves the identification and examination of possible cointegration between the series. There are several ways to identify cointegration between a pair of series. Engle and Granger (1987) present a two-step method. This method involves regressing one series on the other, then examining the residuals of this cointegrating regression for stationarity. Ifthe residuals are stationary, the null hypothesis of no cointegration between the series can be rejected. The Johansen and Juselius (1990) procedure is a pair of maximum likelihood tests evaluating two different measures of cointegration. Evaluating the High Court data for unit roots Of course, a cointegrated relationship necessarily requires that both series have a long run pattern in the first place. If either series is 1(0), there is no cointegrated relationship by definition. For this reason, the first step in any such analysis is to identify the order of integration for the relevant series. Before testing the means stationarity of the two series, it is critical to identify and correct for possible variance nonstationarity. Figure 7Error! Reference source not found. demonstrates that the series of concurring opinions is likely to be variance nonstationary. To correct for this, it is customary to apply a natural log transformation to the data (Tabachnick and Fidell 2001 ). A series of unit root tests, as described above, can now be run on the transformed series. To be sure, the results for the KPSS stationarity tests for each series are not entirely consistent with the results of the various unit root tests (see Table 6). This is not a terribly unusual result. As one researcher notes, “much of the problem with the unit root literature arises from the belief that estimates or test statistics would provide the 148 answer in themselves” (Smith 2000, 200-201). There is, however, a good deal of evidence that the log transformation of the concurring opinion series contains a unit root. Figure 8 - Concurring and Dissenting Opinions per Opinion-Writing Opportunity 100 80- 60« m . g 40‘ ‘ . . O . ”<5 - 81 .9 20‘ _ E, Concurrences U ff 0 Joint Opinions V V” U 1965 '57 '5'9 '7'1 '7'3 '7'5 '77 '79 '91 '93 '9'5 '97 'u '91 '93 '95 737 99 '01 The dissenting opinion series, however, does not appear to have a unit root. The results for the unit root tests of the log-transformed Narayan and Smyth (2005) measure yield similar results (see Table 7). Narayan and Smyth calculate the number of concurring and dissenting opinions per one hundred written opinions. As was discussed earlier in the chapter, this measure tends to weight separate opinions much more heavily. The present analysis finds that, like the measure weighted by opinion-writing opportunity, the measure of concurring opinions contains a unit root. This is also consistent with the findings in Narayan and Smyth’s analysis (2005). The present results differ, however, when it comes to the evidence of the means stationarity of the measure of dissenting opinions as displayed in Table 7. There are several possible explanations for this difference. Certainly, the present study uses a smaller sample than the Narayan and Smyth (2005) piece, which traces 149 separate opinions from 1904-2001. The earlier piece by Smyth (2002c) analyzed separate opinions from 1903-1975 and, while it failed to find a cointegrated relationship, Table 6 - Unit Root Tests on Log-Transformed Separate Opinions per OWO i)l\'.\t‘lll.\ ('tiiit‘iil‘icrrt‘os ('i‘iiit'nl \riliit' l/' ("1 Dickey-Fuller Tests . .. Constant, No Trend -3.90* -1.94 -2.94 Constant, Trend -3.92* -1.96 -3.53 Augmented Dickey-Fuller (ADF) Tests No Trend -3.68* -1.47 -2.94 With Trend -3.59* -1.46 -3.53 (# of Lags) 0 0 Elliot, Rothenberg and Stock (ERS) Tests DF-GLS No Trend -3.96* (0) -1.60 (0) -1.95 DF-GLS With Trend -4.03* (0) -2.18 (0) -3. 19 Kwiatkowski et al. (KPSS) Tests Lags =0 0.17 0.38 0.15 Lags=2 0.11* 0.17 0.15 Lags=4 0.10* 0.13* 0.15 Lags = 8 009* 0.13* 0.15 Mean -2. 17 -1.22 Standard Deviation 0.19 0.39 N 38 38 * Indicates rejection of the null hypothesis. DF, ADF and ERS critical values are based on MacKinnon (1991). Optimal lags for ADF selected on the basis of Schwartz’s Information Criterion. Optimal lags for ERS based on Ng-Perron (1995) sequential t-test. KPSS results are eta(,u) statistics. it did find evidence that both the concuning and dissenting opinion series contained a unit root. The sample in the present analysis is 38 years, which means that there are fewer time points analyzed in the unit root tests. Shorter time spans have been demonstrated to result in decreased power in traditional unit root tests, making it harder for them to identify correctly a stationary series (Campbell and Perron 1991). The 150 Table 7 - Unit Root Tests of Log-Transformed Separate Opinions per 100 Opinions l)l\\t‘lll\ ('rint'in'it'nt't's (‘i‘itltxil \ LllllL‘ l/’ 1'51 Dickey-Fuller Tests Constant, No Trend -3. 17* -2. 13 -2.94 Constant, Trend -4.43* -2.35 -3.53 Augmented Dickey-Fuller (ADF) Tests No Trend -2.15* -1.71 -2.94 With Trend -2.33* -1.80 -3.53 (# of Lags) 3 0 Elliot, Rothenberg and Stock (ERS) Tests DF-GLS No Trend -1.76 (2) -1.80 (0) -1.95 DF-GLS With Trend —4.55* (1) -2.54 (0) -3.19 Kwiatkowski et al. (KPSS) Tests Lags = O 0.17 034* 0.15 Lags=2 011* 017* 0.15 Lags=4 010* 013* 0.15 Lags = 8 009* 013* 0.15 Mean -1.65 -0.70 Standard Deviation 0.22 0.23 N 38 38 * Indicates rejection of the null hypothesis. DF, ADF and ERS critical values are based on MacKinnon (1991). Optimal lags for ADF selected on the basis of Schwartz’s Information Criterion. Optimal lags for ERS based on Ng-Perron (1995) sequential t-test. KPSS results are etan) statistics. decreased power leads to a lessened ability to correctly identify persistent non unit root series (Elliot et al. 1996). In the present situation, however, the question is whether the series representing dissent has been mistakenly diagnosed as a non-unit root series. Whatever the reason, the failure to find evidence of a unit root in the dissenting opinion series does not mark the end of the search for a cointegrated relationship. Instead, the series can be tested for a fiactionally cointegrated relationship by loosening the assumption that the series must be 1(0) of 1(1). 151 Testing for fractional cointegration A means-stationary process is one in which the data exhibit no trend. Diagnosing means stationarity is important in order to satisfy the assumptions of many analytical models, and also as a first step in cointegration analysis (Zivot and Wang 2003). Many researchers argue, however, that series compiled through the aggregation of data created through disparate individual-level data generating processes are likely to be fractionally integrated (Box-Steffensmeier and Tomlinson 2000; Granger 1980; Lebo et al. 2000). Instead of the series being characterized by the traditional “knife-edged” classification of 1(0) or 1(1), the order of integration is allowed to vary. The fractionally integrated series is said to be I(d), such that 0.:__ 33:22:: 575:2“: :::___:.v :31933 ...—SD .5326 2: .5 hertz—om 9:53. .3 20.52 1523—...— - S 036,—- 245 ......__:..:. .122 25.2: 5:: :_ .... taco 2835 2: .8 332—»: ”£53. be £252 352:. ...—.22....— gosuom - w— 93:. :31: :3 :::_::.v ...}...z: 02 SN 02 mom 2: 42 oz a o3; :2 $3— omow Se 34.: we} use a a: ME. ME. at. N2. 08. 3a. 8N. 8:332 as.” omaNN .22.. barrom 3.3.. OOVMN as 9%.: .13.. $3.0m .12.. ovmdv as... :bdm BSEEO *3: 3. G: 8. § .v 3. £3 3.. E .v 2;. ...-*6: S. t? .V 3. 82.80 :3 2.. GS :. fig 2.- 83 3.. GS 2.- ......GS we.- ttsme 8.- sea 20.9.50 63 mm- :3 we- 63 Q.- 83 8. :3 on $3 3- $3 mu.- {50 .Bm 83 3. Q3 on- $3 5.. ASC S .- tame E7 135 8.7 ...-...?3 E7 toe GE 2. ...QE ”N7 33 mn- 83 5.- $3 on- $3 on- 9:; 8.- .acou . cocozem a3 8. $3 8.- 243 8. .289 8. ...?3 mo. 33 8. $3 8. Ems-J bioEEoU 83 mm. :3 3. a3 8. 1.5:» :33 3. $3 8. 83 we. 8a? awe—002 $0. a :. 8N: S7 so: an. QIV 8. GM: §- §: 0: an: 8a 8928 246 Another way to evaluate the joining behavior of the Gleeson Court Justices is to represent their positions graphically. Each Justice has many opportunities to join with all of his colleagues on the bench, and the goal of these analyses is to isolate the factors contributing to the decision to join. Pairs of Justices who tend to join when they have the chance can be conceived as being ‘close’ to each other in terms of some set of criteria relevant to opinion writing. Those who tend not to join with each other are ‘far’ from each other in the same sense. By observing the patterns of these interactions, a spatial representation of the distances between them can be created. Multidimensional scaling uses a matrix of dissimilarities in order to reverse- engineer a spatial representation of the Justices. This matrix can be constructed using the proportion of potential joining opportunities in which each pair of Justices does not join. In a general sense, a pair of Justices will be closer together in joining behavior terms when they vote together frequently. In other words, analysis of a matrix like the one described above would conflate the effects of j oining decisions with voting decisions. For this reason, it is appropriate to condition the joining decision on vote compatibility. Iftwo Justices do not end up on the same side of the vote, their opportunity to join is essentially lost for that case. For this reason, the entries in the matrix represent joining distances conditioned on votes. Each element pi, represents the proportion of cases in which Justice i and Justice j voted together but did not join. Because this matrix is symmetrical—with the list of Justices forming both the row and column entries, it is amenable to multidimensional scaling analysis (Davison 1983). 247 Figure 23 - Scree Plot for Gleeson Court Conditional Distance Matrix 5 4. 3. 2 .- g .6 1 .'> C (D O) [I o 1 2 3 4 5 a 7 Component Number For the purposes of this analysis, the values of the dissimilarities matrix are conceptualized as distances in Euclidean space. Calculations are made with the goal of creating spatial representations of the relative positions for each of the Justices. In order to determine which representation best represents the distances between the Justices without adding unnecessary complexity, it is important to identify the smallest level of dimensionality necessary to depict accurately the judges in Euclidean space. The most common method is to evaluate a scree plot—a plot of eigenvalues against the dimensions in order of extraction. Typically, dimensions with eigenvalues smaller than one considered unnecessary. Figure 23 presents the scree plot for the Gleeson Court conditional distance matrix, and two dimensions are above the cutoff eigenvalue of one. 248 The two-dimensional representation of the Gleeson Court Justices is presented in Figure 24.107 The orientation of these dimensions is based only on the distances in the data, and not on any external metric (such as party affiliation, activism, etc). This arrangement depicts the degree to which Justices join with one another, given that they agree on the vote. When Justices agree on the disposition of the case, Justices who are close together on the map are more likely to join with each other. If judges are far from each other on the map, they are relatively unlikely to join with each other even when they vote together on the merits. The most obvious feature of Figure 24 is Kirby’s position to the far left. To find Kirby this far away from the other Justices may not be much of a surprise, given his reputation as an “outsider” (Banham 2003; Pelly 2008). Kirby’s dissent rate over this Figure 24 - Derived Configuration of Joining Behavior Conditional on Votes McHugh I Hayne , ' Gaudron Kliby Gummow I Gleeson I Callinan I 107 The MDS calculations reported here were made using the ALSCAL procedure in SPSS 11.0, and very similar results were obtained using SAS 8.2. For a review of the procedure, see Davison (1983). For a defense of the two-dimensional representation of voting behavior on the High Court of Australia, see Wood (2002) 249 period was the highest, followed by McHugh and then Callinan (Lynch 2003b). While Kirby and Callinan appear distant from the others—and from each other—McHugh appears in the core group in the top-left corner. Of course, this spatial representation does not include information about dissent rates. As such, McHugh is more likely than the other dissenters to join when he is in agreement with other Justices—even if this does not happen very ofien. Legal scholar Andrew Lynch concludes that “[t]he Court seems to have a solid core led by Justice Gummow and comprising in rough order of influence Chief Justice Gleeson, Justice Hayne and Gaudron” (Lynch 2003b). In this analysis, though, McHugh appears to be closer to this group than Gleeson. The difference is that the scaling procedure has controlled for the vote on the merits. Lynch’s analysis uses percentage tables of opinion-writing rates, and conditioned joining behavior cannot be detected in this way. Patterns of voting behavior are important, but they are not the main subject of this analysis. Certainly, there are patterns of agreement in terms of vote outcomes that coincide with ideology—or at least with the party of appointing prime minister, which is an accepted proxy measure of ideology. The liberalism score used in the above models was derived from voting behavior, and not from joining behavior. The scores for the Gleeson Court Justices are presented in Figure 25, separated by appointing prime minister. Gleeson, Callinan, and Hayne are the Liberal appointees; the rest were appointed by Labor prime ministers. Comparing this arrangement with Figure 24, it becomes clear that ideology has at least some relationship with joining patterns on the Court. Gleeson, Hayne, McHugh, and Gummow appear in a tight cluster in Figure 25, 250 Figure 25 - Liberalism Scores of Gleeson Court Justices by Party of Appointing Prime Minister108 Callinan Gleeson o e Hayne McHugh Gummow Kirby :- a A a Gaudron PARTY oLNC - - ' _ - ' _ . - ' . AALP 02 0.00 .02 .04 .06 .00 .10 .12 .14 .16 .18 .20 .22 Liberalism Score indicating that they tend to favor the same ideological case outcomes. Each of these Justices appears near the others in Figure 24 as well, with Gleeson slightly farther from the rest. In other words, these Justices tend to favor similar ideological outcomes, and they also tend to coauthor opinions on a more regular basis. The ideological agreement also performs well in many of the logistic regression models of j oining behavior. Table 19 summarizes the performance of the various hypotheses in each of the seven reduced models. Ideology does not seem to play a part in single-opinion dispositions, but it is an important explanatory factor in each of the other models. Liberal panels produce more joint opinions. The Justices are more likely to join when they agree with the ideological outcome of the case, and less likely to join when 108 The liberalism score for each Justice has been assembled from his entire tenure on the High Court. Some Justices had served long before the beginning of the Gleeson Court. For example, Justice Gaudron was appointed in 1987, and Justice McHugh in 1989. During this time, the Court made more liberal decisions. This is how Gaudron can appear to the liberal side of Kirby, even though Kirby’s dissent rate is legendary. Over the course of their respective careers, a greater proportion of Gaudron’s votes supported liberal outcomes than did Kirby ’s. 251 Table 19 - Performance of Hypotheses in Seven Models of Joining Behavior Model Number Workload la Late Oral Argument - - - lb Retirement Near * 1c Cases This Term Chief Justice *** 1"ka tilt *** *Itntr 2a Gibbs *** * -. - - - 2a Mason *** ** *** *** _ - _ Brennan . . - - - Gleeson =- -. - - - 2b New Chief Justice - - - Ideology Measures 3a Panel Liberalism u an: - - _ - - _ - - - 3b Panel Diversity * 4a DiStanoe from Mean - - - - - — - - - _ - - antral: first: 13*..- 4b Agree with Direction - - - - - - - - - - - - *M Hut: anus Complexity 5a Long Oral Argument *** *** * an: us: an: 5b AVg.OpinionLength can our: on - can nor: an 5c Number of Matters ** ** *** 5d No Leave asofRight --- .... --- Salience 6a Nonparty Participants ** 6b NGO as a Party . Mar 6c Constitutional Issue *** * M * *** 6d Tort Cases - - - a sun- 7a Fed. Gov’t as a Party ** ..- u Litigation History 8a Admin/Specialized - - - 8b Federal Jurisdiction - - - Case Outcome 9a Nonunanimous Vote - - - - - - *** -- - - - - - - - - - 9b Liberal Outcome - - - - - - - - - 9c Allow Appeal ** H .- Judge Characteristics 10a Gov’t Attorney Exp. - - - - - - - - - - - - ”at un: am 10b Prior Judicial Exp. - - - - - - - - - - - - *1" Hull 10c Freshman(1"50) --- --- --- --- ..- 10d Predisposition to Join - - - - - - - - - - - - Hut snu: an: 11a Catholic --- --- --- --- 11b FromNSW --- --- --- --- an: 11c LaborP.M. --- --- --- --- a... .. Control Variables C1 Panel Size Hut: ant: Hut: :tnlut: an" an: C2 Coalition Size - - - - - - - - - - - - an ml: taut: * p505, ** p501, *** p$.001; the character - is substituted when the relationship is in the opposite direction proposed by the hypotheses. Variables omitted from equations are denoted by - - -. 252 they are ideologically distant from the panel’s mean. Figure 24 suggests that even when voting agreement is controlled for, the Justices tend to join with their ideological kin. Certainly, ideological compatibility alone does not provide a satisfactory explanation of the joining patterns found in these analyses. For example, Kirby and Gaudron have very similar liberalism scores, but they appear on opposite ends of the spectrum in Figure 24. While the salience and complexity of the case seems to drive joining behavior—as does the leadership of the Chief Justice—these are controlled for in Model 7, presented in Table 16. Instead, judge-specific‘characteristics seem to play a role in the Justices’ joining behavior. The predisposition-to-join variable provides some insight here. The predisposition- to-j oin variable is a running average of the last five cases in which each Justice has joined. Figure 26 shows the average value of this variable for each Justice, multiplied by five. This yields the average number of times the judge has joined over the previous five cases. The horizontal reference line is at the average, which is 2.14 cases. Gaudron’s average is far above the mean, while Kirby’s is far below. The predisposition-to-j oin variable is related to several of the other Justice-specific background variables. The predisposition variable is significantly higher among Justices with experience as a judge or government attorney, Justices who are not Catholic or from New South Wales, and Justices who are not freshmen on the bench.109 This may introduce multicollinearity into the regression models, although several of the measures involved consistently performed strongly. 109 Independent samples t-test not assuming equal variances rejects the null hypothesis that these scores are not different from each other when divided by government attorney experience (t=lO.852, p=.000), judicial experience (t=21.078, p=.000), Catholicism (t=-18.275, p=.000), being from New South Wales (t=4.445, p=.000), and freshman status (t=12.181, p=.000). 253 Figure 26 - Average Number of Decisions to Join over Previous Five Cases, by Justice DWindeyer E: Menzies CE McTieman McHugh n 3.5d ' C! m 25 2D 1.5 10 5 91591 01 peuior' 5999:) jo # SW 254 Overall, joining behavior on the High Court seems to be related to several factors familiar to students of judicial behavior. The production of a single-opinion disposition is related to the leadership of the Chief Justice and the complexity of the case. Justices are less likely to join in cases that are salient or complex. Liberal panels are more likely to produce joint opinions, and Justices who are closer to the panel mean are more likely to be involved in a joint opinion. Justices are also more likely to join when they agree with the ideological direction of the outcome. In addition to these factors, the Justice’s approach to the working environment seems to be critical to the production of joint opinions. In short, some Justices are simply more comfortable with the collaborative process. It is likely that Justices on the US. Supreme Court also differ in their affinity for the process of collegial opinion production. These differences, though, are largely masked by the majority opinion tradition in that court. In the absence of this institutional pressure to join, the differences among the Justices in this regard are more obvious. 255 CHAPTER NINE: CONCLUSION AND FUTURE RESEARCH Truth is still elusive when she wears mathematical robes. — Anthony Blackshield (1972, 62) In a 2005 speech, Justice Kirby echoed Professor Blackshield’s sentiment, commenting that, “on their own, statistics tell little” (Kirby 2005a). These comments acknowledge that quantitative methods must be supplemented with carefully considered theories in order to gain explanatory traction on complex judicial behaviors. Blackshield notes that international comparisons are particularly hard, “and if comparison is to be attained realistically at this level, specificity is out of the question” (Blackshield 1972, 64). But statistical methods and data availability have improved dramatically since Professor Blackshield made this comment. The distribution of information-rich datasets like the High Courts Judicial Database (Haynie et al. 2007), coupled with advanced methodological theory and computing power, allow for more targeted and fruitful analyses. This dissertation is but one example. While the results are preliminary, some important trends stand out. The main driving force behind joining behavior on the Supreme Court—the precedential weight of the majority opinion—is absent on the High Court. But, like the US. Supreme Court, the leadership of the Australian Chief Justice is strongly related to joining behavior levels. Chiefs who are able to maintain a cooperative atmosphere and regular interactions among the Justices are likely to see joining behavior increase during their tenure. Additionally, judge-specific characteristics are related to the propensity to participate in joint Opinions. Most notably, Justices who have experience with a cooperative approach to the working environment are more likely to join than are Justices with a more distinctly “barrister outlook.” Joining behavior is less likely in complex cases, where there are aspects of the 256 case on which the Justices may disagree. Joining behavior is also less likely in salient cases, where Justices are less willing to assent to sub-optimal expressions of the reasons for judgment. Perhaps most importantly, judicial policy preferences do seem to matter. Justices who are farther from the ideological mean of the panel are less likely to join in judgment than those who are near the mean. In other words, a Justice is more likely to join when there are more ideologically compatible colleagues from which to choose. So, why do High Court Justices join the opinions of their colleagues when they don’t have to? It is not because they want to save time, nor because there is a source of institutional pressure to join. Instead, Justices join because 1) the Chief Justice facilitates joining behavior, 2) they are able to find coauthors with similar policy views, 3) a case is simple and not of great importance, and 4) because they are accustomed to the process of collegial decision making. Evaluating the Findings In his assessment of empirical legal scholarship, Heise presents a helpful framework to address a number of data collection and methodological problems in the existing literature (Heise 2002). Heise notes that using only the universe of published Opinions can be problematic in judicial behavior research. These published opinions represent “only an exceedingly small percentage of cases filed,” (Heise 2002, 844) and are likely to be significantly different in many ways from those cases not disposed of with published opinions (Atkins 1992). In this way, making generalizations from findings using reported decisions to all decisions of the court may be problematic (Tate 1983) The focus in this analysis is on the joining behavior of judges. Case salience is included as an explanatory factor, but the cases reported in the Commonwealth Law 257 Reports are likely to represent salient cases much more heavily. To isolate fully the effect of case salience on joining behavior, then, it would be helpful to analyze a dataset that includes all cases to identify the differential application of the model to published and unpublished decisions. Another limitation mentioned by Heise is the application of issue-specific explanations to “series of unrelated cases in general areas of the law” (Heise 2002, 844). Heise levels this criticism at research attempting to use social background characteristics to explain judicial votes for and against certain litigants or outcomes. While social background characteristics are used as explanatory variables in this analysis, though, they are not employed to explain judicial votes. Instead, they are analyzed in relation to the propensity of an individual judge to join with his or her colleagues. A related cause for concern is the categorization of cases into broad issue areas. This may be somewhat problematic in the data analyzed here. These categorizations are only helpful if cases in an individual issue area similar enough that we can assume judicial behavior in one such case “reflects a general judicial attitude rather than an individualized resolution of the unique facts in each particular case” (Heise 2002, 845). The coding scheme for issue areas is contained in Section 2 of Appendix B. Clearly, each issue category contains a relatively broad range of cases. Generally, though the subject matter classifications have been constructed following Spaeth’s (1997) lead, grouping like with like to the highest extent possible in a comparative database. In addition to this, drawing comparisons using a cross-sectional database requires an assumption that cases in one point in time are comparable to similar-looking cases at another point in time. Heise notes that many studies rely on the “assumption that 258 different cases over a period of years are sufficiently similar that the results are both comparable and generalizable” (Heise 2002, 845). Certainly, institutional changes over time have changed the nature of High Court cases. In this analysis, several dummy variables have been included in an attempt to group like cases with like. There are some avenues for further research, the results of which might may clarify the findings reported here. Here, I will address the two most promising (and achievable). First, the attitudinal dimension of j oining behavior might be better understood using an analysis of judge dyads. This data arrangement would create a much larger sample size, combating the effects of multicollinearity in the models. It would allow for the identification of shared characteristics that the panel distance variable in the current analysis measures indirectly. Ideological scores and other judge-level characteristics could be compared with each other, and it would be possible to determine, for example, if Justices who share the same religious background (or experience, or party affiliation, etc.) are more likely to join in judgment. This approach would also allow for the identification of issue specialists and stable opinion coalitions. A second avenue for future research is to develop a more precise indicator of judicial policy preferences. In this analysis, because the dependent variable was opinion behavior and not ideological outcome, the attitudinal measures were derived from the ideological directionality of the votes cast by the individual Justices. While this avoids the tautology problem, it is not an ideal measure. Certainly, the directionality coding strategy‘for the HCJD project (Haynie et al. 2007) is not as precise as the Spaeth’s (1997) scheme, and the meaning of the various outcomes may not be equivalent across countries (see Appendix B, Section 3). It is possible simply to limit the issue areas subject to 259 analysis, as many analyses of the Supreme Court do, but this leaves precious few data points to include. A measure akin to the Segal and Cover (1989) scores of Supreme Court Justices would be ideal and could be achieved more easily using content analysis techniques on information available in digital format. The Australian legal community has divided on the issue of joint opinions. Some argue that they are critical for the coherence of law and the legitimacy of the institution (Kildea 2003) while others argue that separate opinions preserve the integrity of the decision-making process (Bagaric and McConvill 2005) and that joint opinions can amount to an abdication of judicial duty (Blackshield 2004). The Court’s production of joint opinions has increased regardless, despite the apparently lack of institutional motivation to engage in the accommodation necessary to craft joint reasons. By creating a generalization of existing research on joining behavior on the US. Supreme Court, this analysis has identified some concrete factors to help explain why. 260 APPENDD( A: JUDGES OF THE HIGH COURT OF AUSTRALIA BY SEAT .533 83:... 3 ago. am»? 3:590 8.62. 2 $92 ..0. 538 ago 25. ea .35. 83o 5&3 355; megs; gem gamma ascem 3228 :25 w 5.5.8 >202 as: age. as; 83:22 as; 88.. a; a? 533 _. . 32.530 coma-2 :25 33...“. 9.36 mo. ‘8. _mm. To. Tm. _om. :wEQL-o—z mm. _oh _mm. .8. _mm. _om. We. Vow. mm. _om. TN. 0 d C. T, _2. T9: 261 APPENDIX B: CODING CLASSIFICATIONS Section 1- Administrative Agencies & Specialized Tribunals State Agencies Appeals Costs Board Building Tribunal Civil and Administrative Tribunal Commercial Tribunal Community Services Appeals Tribunal Consumer Claims Tribunal Criminal Injuries Compensation Tribunal Dust Diseases Tribunal Equal Opportunity Tribunal Fair Trading Tribunal Independent Commission Against Corruption Industrial Relations Commission Lands and Mining Tribunal Mentally Impaired Defendants Review Board Parole Board Residential Tenancy Tribunal Retirement Villages Disputes Tribunal Social Security Appeals Tribunal State Administrative Decisions Tribunal Strata Titles Referee Supervised Release Review Board Victims Compensation Tribunal Federal Agencies Administrative Appeals Tribunal Australian Industrial Relations Commission Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission Immigration Review Tribunal Native Title Tribunal Refugee Review Tribunal State Special Courts Children’s Court Compensation Court Drug Court Environmental Resources and Development Court Family Court Industrial Appeal Court Industrial Relations Court Land and Environment Court Liquor Licensing Court Local Government Court Youth Court Federal Special Courts Family Court (as a trial court) Industrial Relations Court (1994-1997) 262 Section 2 - Issue Area Classifications Criminal Cases murder killing without intent (e.g., manslaughter, reckless homicide) attempted murder or homicide rape other crimes of violence against persons (e.g., assault, child abuse, armed robbery, kidnap, arson, sexual assault) attempted crime of violence (including attempted rape) property crimes - serious (theft, burglary, forgery, fraud, destruction of property) . ' property crimes - minor drug offenses crimes against morality (liquor, obscenity, disorderly conduct, gambling) religious crimes (including blasphemy, heresy) business regulation & license violations govermnent corruption or attempts to corrupt government officials political crimes (rebellion, subversion, sedition, illegal political activities or demonstrations, disloyalty, WAR CRIMES) other (perjury, contempt of court, DUI) not able to classify crime Civil Rights Cases civil rights claims by prisoners (does not include challenges to their sentence) (includes claims of cruel and unusual punishment while in prison, habeas corpus for convicted prisoners) equal treatment under the law (discrimination on account of gender, race, religion, age, ethnic, language) . voting rights speech, press, assembly, right to petition religion rights (both challenges to restrictions on religion and challenges to government aid to religion that discriminate against other religions) privacy (include abortion) access to public information civil rights of juveniles rights of indigenous peoples other civil rights — including legality of detention for the non-convicted Public Law Cases government health & safety regulation government environmental regulation and natural resources other government regulation of business government regulation of agriculture land reform and government regulation of land use (includes eminent domain and condemnation) government regulation of races (e. g., apartheid) government regulation of unions or associations or business/labor relations other government regulation taxation, tariffs government benefits (medical insurance, welfare, unemployment benefits, old age pensions or social security) 263 Public Law Cases (continued) worker's compensation abuse of governmental authority (other than those in topics included in the civil rights or tort categories) public employment including disputes between employees about promotions, etc. immigration, deportation, citizenship disputes over elections disputes over appointments to office disputes related to removal of government officials disputes between different units of government (Federalism) special laws dealing with indigenous peoples religious or customary law language or cultural issues other public law (NOT government contract disputes) Economic Cases creditor-debtor disputes (collection; bankruptcy; insolvency cases; etc). insurance disputes other contract disputes, breach of contract, franchise agreements, including disputes over government contracts land possession disputes landlord - tenant disputes - agricultural landlord - tenant disputes - commercial or residential (and default) copyrights, patents, trademarks corporate law - disputes over control or mismanagement of corporations; stockholders and creditors rights; securities fraud labor/ management disputes (in private business) other private economic disputes Tort Cases motor vehicle accidents injured workers professional malpractice (legal, medical, etc.) government tort liability product liability (not shipping or service liability) other personal injury libel or defamation other torts (including shipping) Family Law Cases marriage, divorce, and family disputes inheritance, probate, succession disputes other family law Other Cases regulation of bar and judiciary other issue unable to classify 264 Section 3 - “Liberal” Directionality of Decisions and Votes Criminal Cases Civil Rights Cases Freedom of Speech & Religion Cases Public Law Cases Economic Cases Tort Cases Bar/Judiciary Cases Outcome supports the position of the defendant. Outcome supports the position of the person alleging that their civil rights have been violated. Outcome supports the expansion or protection of the right of free expression or free exercise of religion. Outcome supports benefit claims of public employees or other recipients of government benefits. Outcome supports the incumbent in electoral disputes. Outcome supports the national government over the states in federal disputes. Outcome supports the right of the government to regulate labor relations. Outcome otherwise supports the position of the government. Outcome supports the position of the economic underdog. Outcome supports the position of an individual over that of the government in government contract disputes. Outcome supports the claim of the person alleging infringement of copyright, patent or trademark. Outcome supports the position of the labor union over that of the corporation. Outcome supports the party alleging the injury. Outcome supports the position of the attorney or judge accused of wrongdoing. 265 BIBLIOGRAPHY Ackland, Richard. 2003. "All Rise: Judges, Last of the Secular Gods." Sydney Morning Herald, August 30, 1, 5-6. . 2007. "Rudd has Two High Court Spots to be Sorted Out. " Sydney Morning Herald, Nov. 30. Albrechtsen, Janet. 2003. "Leave Policy to the Law-Makers. " The Australian, October 15, 15. . 2007. "May the Best Person Preside. " The Australian, Aug. 14. Aldrich, J. H., and F. D. Nelson. 1984. Linear Probability, Logit and Probit Models. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Aliotta, Jilda M. 1988. "Combining Judges' Attributes and Case Characteristics: An Alternative Approach to Explaining Supreme Court Decision-Making." Judicature 71 :277-81. Allen, James. 2008. "When it Comes to Picking High Court Justices, Give the Little Guys a Go." The Australian, May 9. Alvey, John, and Neal Ryan. 2005. "The Separation of Powers in Australia: Implications for the State of Queensland." Paper read at Australasian Political Studies Association Conference, Sep 28-30, at Dunedin, NZ. Atkins, Burton. 1991. "Party Capability Theory as an Explanation for Intervention Behavior in the English Court of Appeal." American Journal of Political Science 35 (4):881-903. . 1992. "Data Collection in Comparative Judicial Research: A Note on the Effects of Case Publication upon Theory Building and Hypothesis Testing." Western Political Quarterly 45 (3):?83-92. Atkins, Burton, and Justin J. Green. 1976. "Consensus on the United States Courts of Appeals: Illusion or Reality? " American Journal of Political Science 20 (4)2735- 48. Atkinson, David N., and Dale A. Neuman. 1969. "Toward a Cost Theory of Judicial Alignments: The Case of the Truman Bloc." Midwest Journal of Political Science 13 (2):271. Australian Law Reform Commission. 2000. "The Judicial Power of the Commonwealth: A Review of the Judiciary Act 1903 and Related Legislation." Sydney: Australian Law Reform Commission. 266 Axelrod, Robert. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books. . 1986. "An Evolutionary Approach to Norms." American Political Science Review 80 (4): 1095-1 1 1. Bacon, Rachel. 2002. "Rewriting the Social Contract? The SSAT, the AAT and the Contracting Out of Employment Services." Federal Law Review 30 (1)239-68. Bagaric, Mirko, and James McConvill. 2005. "The High Court and the Utility of Multiple Judgments." High Court Quarterly Review 1 (1)21. Bailey, Michael A., Brian Kamoie, and Forrest Maltzman. 2005. "Signals from the Tenth Justices: The Political Role of the Solicitor General in Supreme Court Decision Making." American Journal of Political Science 49 (1):72-85. Baker, Belinda, and Stephen Gageler. 2002. "F. G. Brennan." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Banham, Cynthia. 2003. "Kirby the High Court Outsider. " Sydney Morning Herald, February 24. Barwick, Sir Garfield. 1995. A Radical Tory: Garfield Barwick's Reflections and Recollections. Sydney, NSW: The Federation Press. Baum, Lawrence. 1981. "Comparing the Implementation of Legislative and Judicial Policies." In Eflective Policy Implementation, ed. D. A. Mazmanian and P. A. Sabatier. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. . 1997. The Puzzle of Judicial Behavior. Edited by J. Aldrich, B. Bueno de Mesquita, R. W. J ackman and D. Rohde. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. . 2003. "C. Herman Pritchett: Innovater with an Ambigious Legacy." In The Pioneers of Judicial Behavior, ed. N. Maveety. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan. Bayne, Peter. 2002. "Herbert Vere Evatt." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Beaumont, Bryan. 2002. "Federal Court of Australia." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Benesh, Sara C., and Malia Reddick. 2002. "Overruled: An Event History Analysis of Lower Court Reaction to Supreme Court Alteration of Precedent." Journal of Politics 64 (2):534-50. 267 Bennett, David. 2002. "Argument Before the Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbome: Oxford University Press. Bennett, J. M, ed. 1969. A History of the New South Wales Bar. Sydney: The Law Book Company. Bennett, John Michael. 1980. Keystone of the Federal Arch: A Historical Memoir of the High Court of Australia to 1980. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. ' Bennett, L. 1989. "Ideology in Australian Judicial Practice: A Non-Reductionist Account of a Jurisdictional Issue in Labour Law." International Journal of the Sociology of LAW 17:207. Bergman, Matthew P. 1991. "Dissent in the Judicial Process: Discord in Service of Harmony." Denver University Law Review 68:79. Best, Bradley J. 2000. "Rethinking the "Chief Justice Effect" and the Role of Ideology in the Decline of Consensual Norms on the United States Supreme Court." Speech delivered to Midwest Political Science Association on, at Chicago. Bhattacharya, Mita, and Russell Smyth. 20013. "Aging and Productivity among Judges: Some Empirical Evidence from the High Court of Australia." Australian Economic Papers 40 (2): 199-212. . 2001b. "The Determinants of Judicial Prestige and Influence: Some Empirical Evidence from the High Court of Australia. " Journal of Legal Studies 30 (1):223- 52. Black, Ryan C., and James F. Spriggs, H. 2007. "An Empirical Analysis of the Trends, Determinants, and Effects of the Length of Majority Opinions of the US. Supreme Court." Paper read at Conference on Empirical Legal Studies, Nov. 9- 10, at New York. Blackshield, Anthony. 1980. "The High Court: Change and Decay." Legal Service Bulletin 5:107. . 2001. "Free Speech Cases." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002a. "The Murphy Affair." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2004. "Judicial Activism and Judicial Restraint: Where Does the Balance Lie? " Speech delivered to Constitutional Law Conference on February 20, at Sydney. 268 Blackshield, Anthony, Michael Coper, Graham Fri cke, and Troy Simpson. 2001. "Notable Counsel." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Blackshield, Tony. 1972. "Quantitative Analysis: The High Court of Australia, 1964- 1969." Lawasia 3:1. . 1978. "X/Y/Z/N Scales: The High Court of Australia." In Understanding Lawyers, ed. R. Tomasic. Sydney: Law Foundation of New SouthWales. . 2002b. "Australia Acts." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002c. "The Dismissal of 1975." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002d. "The Engineer's Case." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002e. "Jurimetrics." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of A ustralia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002f. "Puisne Justices." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. C0per and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Blackshield, Tony, Michael Coper, and John Goldring. 2002. "The Judicial Committee of the Privy Council." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of A ustralia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Blackshield, Tony, and Mark Mackrell. 2002. "Kenneth Sydney Jacobs." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Blaikie, Norman W. H. 2003. Analyzing Quantitative Data. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Bollerslev, Tim, and Richard T. Baillie. 1994. "Cointegraton, Fractional Cointegration, and Exchange rate Dynamics." Journal of Finance 49 (2):73 7-45. Botsman, Peter. 2000. The Great Constitutional Swindle. Annandale, NSW: Pluto Press. 269 Box-Steffensmeier, Janet M., and Andrew R. Tomlinson. 2000. "Fractional Integration Methods in Political Science." Electoral Studies 19 (1)263-76. Box, George, and David R. Cox. 1964. "An Analysis of Transformations." Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 26 (B):21 1-52. Brace, Paul, and Melinda Gann Hall. 1993. "Integrated Models of Judicial Dissent." Journal of Politics 55 (4):914-35. . 1997. "The Interplay of Preferences, Case Facts, Context, and Rules in the Politics of Judicial Choice." Journal of Politics 59 (4): 1206-31. . 2005. "Is Judicial Federalism Essential to Democracy? State Courts in the Federal System." In The Judicial Branch, ed. K. L. Hall and K. T. McGuire. New York: Oxford University Press. Bradford, Gillian. 2007. "Kiefel Appointment Makes High Court History." ABC News, Aug. 14. Branson, Catherine. 1995. "Equal Opportunity: The Next Twenty Years." Speech delivered to Equal Opportunity Commision of South Australia Mitchell Oration on October 6, at Adelaide. . 1997 . "Running on the Edge." Speech delivered to Women Lawyers’ Association of NSW Speaker Series on October 15, at Sydney. Brennan, Gerard. 1996a. "A Tribute to Sir Anthony Mason." In Courts of F inal Jurisdiction: The Mason Court in Australia, ed. C. Saunders. Annandale, NSW: Federation Press. . 1996b. "A Tribute to Sir Anthony Mason." In Courts of Final Jurisdiction: The Mason Court in Australia, ed. C. Saunders. Sydney, NSW: The Federation Press. . 2002a. "Composition of Bench." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002b. "Decision-Making Process." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Brenner, Saul. 1979. "Minimum Winning Coalitions on the US. Supreme Court: A Comparison of the Original Vote on the Merits with the Opinion Vote." American Politics Quarterly 72384-92. . 2003. "David Rohde: Rational Choice Theorist." In The Pioneers of Judicial Behavior, ed. N. Maveety. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. 270 Brenner, Saul, and Theodore S. Arrington. 2002. "Measuring Salience on the Supreme Court: A Research Note. " Jurimetrics 43 :99-1 13. Brenner, Saul, and Timothy M. Hagle. 1996. "Opinion Writing and Acclimation Effects." Political Behavior 18 (3)223 5-61 . Brenner, Saul, Timothy M. Hagle, and Harold J. Spaeth. 1990. "Increasing the Size of Minimum Winning Original Coalitions on the Warren Court." Polity 23 (2)2309- 18. Brenner, Saul, and Harold J. Spaeth. 1986. "Issue Specialization in Majority Opinion Assignment on the Burger Court." Western Political Quarterly 39 (3)2520. . 1988. "Majority Opinion Assignments and the Maintenance of the Original Coalition on the Warren Court." American Journal of Political Science 32 (1):72. Burmester, Henry. 2002. "Interveners and Amici Curiae." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Butler, Des. 2005. "A Tort of Invasion of Privacy in Australia?" Melbourne University Law Review 29:339. Caldeira, Gregory A., and Christopher J. W. Zorn. 1998. "Of Time and Consensual Norms in the Supreme Court." American Journal of Political Science 42 (3):874- 902. ’ Callinan, Ian. 1999. "Courts: First and Final." Speech delivered to Speakers' Forum on August 17, at Sydney . 2000. "A Toast to the New Silks." Speech delivered to New Silks Ceremony on January 31, at Canberra. Campbell, Enid. 2003. "Reasons for Judgment: Some Consumer Perspectives." Australian Law Journal 77:62. Campbell, Enid Mona, and H. P. Lee. 2001. The Australian Judiciary. Cambridge, UK. ; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Campbell, J. Louis. 1983. "The Spirit of Dissent." Judicature 66:305. Campbell, John Y., and Pierre Perron. 1991. "Pitfalls and Opportunities: What Macroeconomists Should Know about Unit Roots. " NBER Macroeconomics Annual 62141-201. Cane, Peter. 2003. "Reforming Tort Law in Australia: A Personal Perspective." Melbourne University Law Review 27:649. 271 Cannon, Bradley C. 1974. "Reactions of State Supreme Courts to a US. Supreme Court Civil Liberties Decision." Law & Society Review 8: 109-35. Cannon, Bradley C., and Michael Giles. 1972. "Recurring Litigants: Federal Agencies before the Supreme Court." Western Political Quarterly 28: 183-91. Came, Greg. 2002. "A Compelling Consideration of Law and Politics in the High Court of Australia." Melbourne University Law Review 26 (1):224-35. Carney, Gerard. 1997. "Comment - The Role of the Attorney-General." Bond Law Review 9:1-10. Carrigan, Frank. 2003. "A Blast From the Past: The Resurgence of Legal Formalism. " Melbourne University Law Review 27 (1):163-85. Castles, Alex C. 1971. An Introduction to Australian Legal History. Sydney: The Law Book Company. Childs, Kevin. 2001. "Open Process for High Court Judges, Urges Justice Kirby." Law Institute of Victoria, October 14. Clark, Andrew. 2003. "In the Court of Murray Gleeson." Australian Financial Review, August 22, 10-2. Clarke, Harold D., and Matthew Lebo. 2003a. "Fractional (Co)integration and Governing Party Support in Britain." British Journal of Political Science 33 2283-301. Clarke, Harold D., and Matthew J. Lebo. 2003b. "Fractional (Co)integration and Governing Party Support in Britain." British Journal of Political Science 33 :283- 301. ' Cohen, Jacob, Patricial Cohen, Stephen G. West, and Leona S. Aiken. 2003. Applied Multple Regression / Correlation Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences. 3rd ed. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Cohen, Linda R., and MAtthew L. Spitzer. 1994. "Solving the "Chevron" Puzzle." Law and Contemporary Problems 57 (2)265-110. Collins, Paul M. 2005. "Mobilizing Dissensus on the US. Supreme Court." Speech delivered to Annual Meeting of the New York State Political Science Association on April 15-16, at Niagara, NY. Collins, Paul M., Jr. 2006. "Transforming the Original US. Supreme Court Judicial Database: An Alternative Approach For Use With Stata." Law & Courts 16 (1)222-4. . 2007. "Amici Curiae and Dissensus on the US. Supreme Court." Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 5 (1)1143-70. 272 Cook, Beverly Blair. 1995. "Justice Brennan and the Institutionalization of Dissent Assignment." Judicature 79: 17. Coper, Michael. 2002a. "Cole v. Whitfield." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002b. "Intergovernmental Immunities." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002c. "Joint Judgments and Separate Judgments." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of A ustralia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2003. "The Seven Habits of a Highly Effective High Court." Alternative Law Journal 25:59-64. . 2004. "The High Court and the Parliament: Partners in Law-Making or Hostile Combatants?" Speech delivered to The Distinctive Foundations of Australian Democracy on, at Canberra. Coper, Michael, George Williams, and Anthony Blackshield. 2002. The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia. Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Comall, Robert. 2007. "Redefining the Role of Government Lawyers in Today's Public Service." Speech delivered to ACLA National Conference on November 2, at Canberra, ACT. Cowen, Zelman. 1955. "A Comparison of the Constitutions of Australia and the United States." Buffalo Law Review 4: 155-80. . 1967. Isaac Isaacs. Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002. "John Greig Latham." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Cowen, Zelman, and Leslie Zines. 2002. Cowen and Zines '5 Federal Jurisdiction in Australia. 3rd ed. Annandale, N.S.W.: Federation Press. Craske, Rebecca, and Harry Gibbs. 2002. "Business of Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Craske, Rebecca, and Richard Haigh. 2002. "Judgment Production." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. 273 Crawford, James. 1993. Australian Courts of Law. 3rd ed. Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Creyke, Robin. 2001. "Tribunals: Divergence and Loss." Federal Law Review 29 (3):403-26. Danelski, David J. 1960. "The Influence of the Chief Justice in the Decisional Process." In Courts, Judges, and Politics, ed. W. M. Murphy and C. H. Pritchett. New York: Random House. Davis, Jessica Milner, and Troy Simpson. 2002. "Humour." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Davis, John F., and William L. Reynolds. 1974. "Juridical Cripples: Plurality Opinions in the Supreme Court." Duke Law Journal 1974 (l):59. Davison, Mark L. 1983. Multidimensional Scaling. New York: Wiley. Dawson, Daryl, and Grant Anderson. 1996. "Dixon, Sir Owen (1886-1972)." In Australian Dictionary of Biography. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press. Dawson, Robert Macgregor, and Norman Ward. 1987. Dawson 's the Government of Canada. 6th ed. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. de Vaus, David. 2002. Analyzing Social Science Data: 50 Key Problems in Data Analysis. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Deen, Rebecca E., Joseph Ignagni, and James Meernik. 2001. "Executive influence on the US. Supreme Court: Solicitor General Amicus Cases, 1953-1997." American Review of Politics 22 (1)23-26. Del Villar, Gim, and Troy Simpson. 2002. "Circuit System." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Dickey, David A., and Wayne A. Fuller. 1979. "Distribution of the Estimators for Autoregressive Time Series With a Unit Root." Journal of the American Statistical Association 74 (3 66):427-3 l . Dillon, Michelle, and John Doyle. 2002. "The Mason Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Dominello, Francesca. 2001. "Intergovernmental Immunities and Judicial Reasoning." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of A ustralia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. 274 Dominello, Francesca, and Eddy Neumann. 2002. "Background of Justices." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Donald, Peta. 2005. "Susan Crennan Sworn in as New High Court Judge." The World Today, November 8. Doogan, Christopher M. 2004. "High Court of Australia Annual Report: 2003-2004." Canberra: High Court of Australia. Dorff, Robert H., and Saul Brenner. 1992. "Conformity Voting on the United States Supreme Court. " Journal of Politics 54 (3):762-75. Douglas, Roger. 1969. "Judges and Policy on the Latham Court." Politics 4:20. . 2002. "The Latham Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. C0per and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Douglas, William O. 1948. "The Dissent: A Safeguard of Democracy." Journal of the American Judicature Society 32:104. Doyle, John. 1996. "Implications of Judicial Law-Making." In Courts of Final Jurisdiction: The Mason Court in Australia, ed. C. Saunders. Annandale, NSW: Federation Press. Duxbury, Neil. 2001. Jurists and Judges: An Essay on Influence. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Edelman, James, and Natalie Gray. 2002. "J. L. Toohey." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Elder, John, and Peter E. Kennedy. 2001. "Testing for Unit Roots: What Should Students be Taught?" Journal of Economic Education Spring: 137-46. Elliot, Graham, Thomas J. Rothenberg, and James H. Stock. 1996. "Efficient Tests for an Autoregressive Unit Root." Econometrica 64 (4):813-36. Engle, Robert F ., and Briton Clive W.J. Granger. 1987. "Cointegration and Error Correction: Representation, Estimation and Testing." Econometrica 55:251-76. Epp, Charles R. 1998. The Rights Revolution: Lawyers, Activists, and Supreme Courts in Comparative Perspective. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Epstein, Lee, and Jack Knight. 1998. The Choices Justices Make. Washington DC: Congressional Quarterly Press. 275 . 2000. "Toward a Strategic Revolution in Judicial Politics: A Look Back, A Look Ahead." Political Research Quarterly 53 (3):625-61. Epstein, Lee, Jack Knight, and Andrew D. Martin. 2003. "The Norm of Prior Judicial Experience and Its Consequences for Career Diversity on the US. Supreme Court." California Law Review 91 (4):903 -65. Epstein, Lee, and Jeffrey A. Segal. 2000. "Measuring Issue Salience." American Journal of Political Science 44 (1)266-83. Epstein, Lee, Jeffrey A. Segal, and Harold J. Spaeth. 2001. "The Norm of Consensus on the US. Supreme Court." American Journal of Political Science 45 (2)2362. Epstein, Lee, and Thomas G. Walker. 2001. Constitutional Law for a Changing America: Rights, Liberties and Justice. 4th ed. 2 vols. Vol. 2. Washington, DC: CQ Press. Epstein, Lee, Jeffrey A. Segal, Harold. J. Spaeth, and T. G. Walker. 1996. "The Supreme Court Compendium: Data, Decisions, and Developments, Washington: Congressional Quarterly." Washington, DC: Congressional Quarterly. Etherington, David. 2005. "Life at the Bar. " Legal Week Student, March 11. Evans, Simon. 2002. "Appointment of Justices." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Ferejohn, John. 1995. "Law, Legislation and Positive Political Theory." In Modern Political Economy, ed. J. Banks and E. Hanushek: Cambridge University Press. F erej ohn, John, and Charies Shipan. 1990. "Congressional Influence on Bureaucracy." Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 6:1. F erej ohn, John, and Barry Weingast. 1992. "A Positive Theory of Statutory Interpretation." International Review of Law and Economics 122263-79. Festa, Linda, and Leo D. Vichules. 1968. "Cliques on the Supreme Court: Myth or Reality." Sociological Quarterly 9 (4):540-54. Franklin, Charles H., and Liane C. Kosaki. 1989. "The Republican Schoolmaster: US. Supreme Court, Public Opinion, and Abortion." American Political Science Review 83 (3):751-71. Fricke, Graham. 1999. "The Knox Court: Exposition Unnecessary." Federal Law Review 27 (1). . 2002a. "Frank Gavan Duffy." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. 276 . 2002b. "The Gavan Duffy Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002c. "The Isaacs Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002d. "The Knox Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Fricke, Graham L. 1986. Judges of the High Court. Melbourne, Vic.: Hutchinson of Australia. Gageler, Stephen. 2002a. "Jurisdiction." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002b. "Legalism." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002c. "Role of Counsel." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Galligan, Brian. 1987. Politics of the High Court : A Study of the Judicial Branch of Government in Australia. St. Lucia ; New York: University of Queensland Press. . 1991. "Judicial Activism in Australia." In Judicial Activism in Comparative Perspective, ed. K. M. Holland. New York: St. Martin's Press. . 1995. A Federal Republic .' Australia's Constitutional System of Government. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press. . 2002. "World War II." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of A ustralia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Gardiner, David, and Frances McGlone. 1998. Outline of Torts. 2nd ed: Butterworths. Gaudron, Mary. 2002. "Speech for Women Lawyers Association of New South Wales." Speech delivered to Women Lawyers Association of New South Wales Conference on June 13, at Sydney. George, Tracey, and Lee Epstein. 1992. "On the Nature of Supreme Court Decision Making." American Political Science Review 86:323-37. 277 Gerber, Scott D., and Keeock Park. 1997. "The Quixotic Search for Consensus on the US. Supreme Court: A Cross-Judicial Empirical Analysis of the Rehnquist Court Justices." American Political Science Review 91 (2)390. Gibbs, Harry. 1986. "Appellate Procedures in the High Court." Australian Bar Review 2: 1. ' . 2002. "Samuel Walker Griffith." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Giles, Michael W. 1977. "Equivalent Versus Minimum Winning Opinion Coalition Size: A Test of Two Hypotheses." American Journal of Political Science 21 (2):405. Gillman, Howard, and Cornell W. Clayton. 1999. The Supreme Court in American Politics: New Institutionalist Interpretations. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas. Ginsburg, Ruth Bader. 1994. "Gifts of Speech." Speech delivered to Annual Dinner of the American Law Institute on May 19, at Sweet Briar, VA. Gleeson, Anthony Murray. 1998. "The Role of the Judge and Becoming a Judge." Speech delivered to National Judicial Orientation Programme on August 16, at Sydney. . 2000a. "Judicial Legitimacy." Speech delivered to Australian Bar Association Conference on July 2, at New York. . 2000b. "The Keystone of the Federal Arch." In Radio National 's Boyer Lectures. Australia: Australian Broadcasting Corporation. . 2001a. "A Changing Judiciary." Speech delivered to Judicial Conference of Australia on April 7, at Uluru. . 2001b. "Courts and the Rule of Law on November 7, at Melbourne. . 2002a. "The Birth, Life and Death of Section 74." Speech delivered to The Samuel Griffith Society on June 14, at Sydney. . 2002b. "Global Influences on the Australian Judiciary." Speech delivered to Australian Bar Association Conference on July 8, at Paris. . 2002c. "The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia." Speech delivered to Launch on February 13, at Canberra. . 2003a. "Judicial Selection and Training: Two Sides of the Same Coin." Speech delivered to Judicial Conference of Australia on May 31, at Darwin. 278 . 2003b. "Legality - Spirit and Principle." Speech delivered to Second Magna Carta Lecture on November 20, at Sydney. . 2004a. "The High Court of Australia: Challenges for its New Century." Paper read at Constitutional Law Conference, February 20, at Sydney, NSW. . 2004b. "The High Court: Challenges for a New Century." Sydney Morning Herald, February 21. . 2005. "The State of the Judicature." Speech delivered to 19th Biennial Conference of Lawasia on March 24, at Gold Coast. Gleeson, Murray. 1997. "The Role of the Judiciary in a Modern Democracy." " Speech delivered to Judicial Conference of Australia Annual Symposium on, at Sydney, NSW. Glendon, Mary Ann, Michael W. Gordon, and Paolo Wright-Carozza. 1999. Comparative Legal Traditions in a Nutshell. 2nd ed. St. Paul, Minn: West Group. Glick, Henry R. 1983. Courts, Politics, and Justice. New York: McGraw Hill. Goldberger, A. S. 1991. A Course in Econometrics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Goldman, Sheldon, and Austin Sarat, eds. 1978. American Court Systems: Readings in Judicial Process and Behavior. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman. Goldring, John. 1997. "The Path to Engineers." In How Many cheers for Engineers?, ed. M. Coper and G. Williams. Sydney: Federation Press. Goldsmith, Henry. 2006. "No Bar to Employment: Judicial Appointment and the Employed Bar. " Speech delivered to Employed Barristers' Conference on March 17, at United Kingdom. Granger, Briton Clive W.J., and Paul Newbold. 1977. Forecasting Economic Time Series. New York: Academic Press. Granger, Clive W.J. 1980. "Long Memory Relationships and the Aggregation of Dynamic Models." Journal of Econometrics 14 (2):227-38. Green, Donald P., and Ian Shapiro. 1994. Pathologies of rational choice theory: a critique of applications in political science. New Haven: Yale University Press. Griffiths, John. 1985. "Australian Administrative LAw: Institutions, Reforms and Impact." Public Administration 63 (4):445-63. Grossman, Joel B. 1968. "Dissenting Blocs on the Warren Court: A Study in Judicial Role Behavior. " Journal of Politics 30 (4): 1068-90. 279 Grossman, Joel B., and Joseph Tanenhaus, eds. 1969. Frontiers of Judicial Research. New York: John Wiley. Groves, Matthew, and Russell Smyth. 2004. "A Century of Judicial Style: Changing Patterns in Judgment Writing on the High Court 1903-2001." Federal Law Review 11. Guamieri, Carlo. 2004. "Appointment and Career of Judges in Continental Europe: The Rise of Judicial Self-Government." Legal Studies 24: 169-87. Guilfoyle, Kate. 2002. "M. H. McHugh." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Hagle, Timothy M. 1993. "'Freshman Effects' for Supreme Court Justices." American Journal of Political Science 37 (4)21142-57. Halpem, Stephen C., and Kenneth N. Vines. 1977. "Institutional Disunity, the Judges' Bill and the Role of the US. Supreme Court." Western Political Quarterly 30 (4):471-83. Hammond, Thomas H., Chris W. Bonneau, and Reginald S. Sheehan. 2005. Strategic Behavior and Policy Choice on the US. Supreme Court. Stanford,CA: Stanford University Press. Hand, Learned. 1958. The Bill of Rights. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Handberg, Roger. 1978. "Opinion Behavior on the United States Supreme Court 1965- 1977. " Jurimetrics Journal 18:369. Harrell, Frank E. 2001. Regression Modeling Strategies: With Applications to Linear Models, Logistic Regression, and Survival Analysis. Hasluck, Micholas. 1998. "Deconstructing the High Court." Quadrant 42: 12. Haultain, Lynne. 1997. "The Changing of the Guard on the High Court." In The Law Report: Radio National Transcripts. Hayne, Kenneth. 2002. "Owen Dixon." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2004. "Advocacy in the High Court of Australia." Speech delivered to Western Bar Association on. Hayne, Kenneth M. 2003. "The High Court of Australia." Speech delivered to Round Table of the International Association of Constitutional Law on Oct. 4, at Melbourne. 280 Haynie, Stacia L, and C. Neal Tate. 1998. "Studying Judicial Behavior Comparatively: Theory and Methods, Sermons and Lessons." Haynie, Stacia L. 1992. "Leadership and Consensus on the US. Supreme Court." Journal of Politics 54:1158. Haynie, Stacia L., Reginald S. Sheehan, Donald R. Songer, and C. Neal Tate. 2008. High Courts Judicial Database 2007 [cited March 1 2008]. Available fi'om http://sitemason.vanderbilt.edu/site/dSYnTZ/data_sets. Haynie, Stacia L., C. Neal Tate, Reginald S. Sheehan, and Donald R. Songer. 2001. "Winners and Losers: A Comparative Analysis of Appellate Courts and Litigation Outcomes." Speech delivered to Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association on September 2, at San Francisco, CA. Heerey, Peter. 2004. "Aesthetics, Culture, and the Whole Damn Thing." Law and Literature 15 (3):295-312. Heise, Michael. 2002. "The Past, Present, and Future of Empitical Legal Scholarship: Judicial Decision Making and the New Empiricism." University of Illinois Law Review 20022819. Hellevik, Ottar. 2007. "Linear Versus Logistic Regression When the Dependent Variable is a Di chotomy." Quality and Quantity Online First. Hettinger, Virginia A., Stefanie A. Lindquist, and Wendy L. Martinek. 2003a. "Acclimation Effects and Separate Opinion Writing on the United States Courts of Appeals." Social Science Quarterly 84 (4):792. . 2003b. "Separate Opinion Writing on the United States Courts of Appeals." American Politics Research 31 (3):215-50. . 2004. "Comparing Attitudinal and Strategic Accounts of Dissenting Behavior on the US. Courts of Appeals." American Journal of Political Science 48 (1):123-37. Heydon, Dyson. 2003. "Judicial Activism and the Death of the Rule of Law." Quadrant 47 (2)210. Hirst, John. 1995. " Stuart Macintyre and Samuel Griffith: The Report of the Civics Expert Group." Paper read at Conference of the Samuel Griffith Society, March 31, at Sydney, NSW. . 1998. Discovering Democracy: A Guide to Government and Law in Australia. Carlton, VIC: Curriculum Corporation. Hochschild, Adam S. 2000. "The Modern Problem of Supreme Court Plurality Decision: Interpretation in Historical Perspective." Journal of Law and Policy 4:261. 281 Hocking, Barbara Ann, and Alison Smith. 1996. "The Potential of the Law of Torts to Assist in the Protection of Children." Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law 3 (1):7. Hocking, Jenny. 1997. Lionel Murphy: A Political Biography. Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Hodgins, Bruce W., Don 1. Wright, and W. H. Heick. 1978. Federalism in Canada and Australia: The Early Years. Waterloo, ONT: Wilfiid Laurier University Press. Hoekstra, Valerie, and Timothy R. Johnson. 2003. "Delaying Justice: The Supreme Court's Decision to Hear Rearguments." Political Research Quarterly 56 (3)2351- 60. Holloway, Ian. 2001. "Keith Arthur Aickin." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Horton, Jonathan. 2002. "Justices' Associates: Some Observations." University of Queensland Law Journal 22 (1):114. Howard, J. Woodford. 1968. "On the Fluidity of Judicial Choice." American Political Science Review 62 (1):43-56. Hudson, Phillip, and Annabel Crabb. 2002. "NSW Judge to Sit on High Court." The Age, Dec. 17. Hughes, Charles Evans. 1928. The Supreme Court of the United States: Its Foundation, Methods and Achievements, An Interpretation. New York: Columbia University Press. Hulme, S.E.K. 1994. "Hit and Myth in the Law Courts." Speech delivered to Upholding the Australian Constitution on, at Brisbane, QLD. Hunt, Erling Messer. 1930. American Precedents in Australian Federation. New York, Hurwitz, Mark S., and Drew Noble Lanier. 2004. "I Respectfully Dissent: Consensus, Agendas, and Policymaking on the US. Supreme Court, 1888-1999." Review of Policy Research 21 (3):429-45. Jackson, DE 2001. "The Australian Judicial System: Judicial Power of the Commonwealth." University of New South Wales Law Journal 24 (3)259. Jackson, David. 1996. "The ROle of the Chief Justice: A View from the Bar. " In Courts of Final Jurisdiction: The Mason Court in Australia, ed. C. Saunders. Annandal e, NSW: Federation Press. 282 . 2002a. "The Brennan Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002b. "Leave to Appeal." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Jackson, David, and Joan Priest. 2002. "Harry Talbot Gibbs." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Jackson, Elizabeth. 2003. High Court Discussion Panel. ABC Online, October 6, 2003 2003 [cited October 7 2003]. Available from http://www.abc.net.au/worldtoday/content/2003/s960836.htrn. Jefferson, Thomas. 1822. Seriatim Opinions and the History of Parties, October 27. Johansen, Saren, and Katarina Juselius. 1990. "Maximum Likelihood Estimation and Inferences in Cointegration - with Applications to the Demand for Money." Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics 52:169-210. Johnson, Charles A. 1979. "Lower Court Reactions to Supreme Court Decisions: A Quantitative Examination." American Journal of Political Science 23 (4):792. . 1987. "Law, Politics, and Judicial Decision MAking: Lower Federal Court Uses of Supreme Court Decisions." Law & Society Review 212325—40. Johnson, Rebecca, and Marie-Claire Belleau. 2006. "Judicial Dissent at the Supreme Court of Canada: Integrating Qualitative and Quantitative Empirical Approaches." Paper read at First Annual Conference on Empirical Legal Studies, June 30. Johnson, Timothy R. 1997. "Oral Arguments, Information, and Supreme Court Decision Making." Paper read at Annual Conference on the Scientific Study of Judicial Politics, at Atlanta, GA. ' . 2003. "The Supreme Court, the Solicitor General, and the Separation of Powers." American Politics Research 31 (4):426-51. . 2004. Oral Arguments and Decision Making on the United States Supreme Court. Albany, NY: SUNY Press. Jones, Frank. 2002. "Unreported Judgments." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Joseph, S., and M Castan. 2001. Federal Constitutional Law: A Contemporary View. Pyrmont, NSW: Lawbook. 283 Jucewicz, Joseph, and Lawrence Baum. 1990. "Workload Influences on Supreme Court Case Acceptance Rates, 1975-1984." Western Political Quarterly 43 (1): 123-35. Kalowski, Henrik. 2002. "Mary Genevieve Gaudron." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Kelman, Maurice. 1985. "The Forked Path of Dissent." The Supreme Court Review 19851227. Kenny, Susan. 2004. "Interveners and Amici Curiae in the High Court." Speech delivered to Public Law Weekend on, at Canberra, ACT. Kildea, Paul. 2003. "Federal Civil Justice System Strategy Paper. " Canberra: Attomey- General's Department. Kirby, Michael. 1983. Reform the Law: Essays on the renewal of the Australian Legal System. Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 1992. "Ex Tempore Reasons." Australian Bar Review 9:93. . 1996. "AP. Mason - From Trigwell to Teoh." Melbourne University Law Review 20:1087. . 1998a. "Kitto and the High Court of Australia - Change and Continuity." Speech delivered to Sir Frank Kitto Lecture on, at Armidale. . 1998b. "Murray Gleeson - Law Student." Speech delivered to Funtion to Honour the Appintrnent to the Office of Chief Justice of Australia the Hon. Murray Gleeson AC on July 16, at Sydney. . 1998c. "Times of Transition." Speech delivered to Kitto and the High Court of Australia - Change and Continuity on May 22, at Armidale. . 1999. "Constitutional Interpretation and Original Intent - A Form of Ancestor Worship? " Speech delivered to University of Melbourne Law Students' Society on September 9, at Melbourne. . 2001. "Good News, Bad News, No News." Speech delivered to Australian Institute of Judicial Administration on, at Sydney. . 2003. Interview. Canberra, ACT, ? . 2004. "A Blaze in the Sky - the Centenary Conference of the High Court of Australia." Speech delivered to University of Notre Dame Law Review on February, at South Bend, IN. 284 . 2005a. "Dissent and the Irnporance of Judicial Diversity." Speech delivered to Institute of Judicial Studies of New Zealand Conference: Equality and Diversity in Our Community on Aug. 18-19, at Rotorua, NZ. . 2005b. "Isaac Isaacs: A Sesquicentenary Reflection." Speech delivered to Samuel Alexander Lecture on Aug. 4, at Melbourne. . 2005c. "Judicial Dissent." Speech delivered to Law Students' Society of James Cook University on February 26, at Cairns. . 2006. "Dame Ann Ebsworth Remembered." Speech delivered to Dame Ann Ebsworth Memorial Lecture on Feb. 32, at London. . 2007a. "Maximising Special Leave Performance in the High Court of Australia." University of New South Wales Law Journal 30 (3 ). . 2007b. "Twelve Years in the High Court - Continuity and Change." Paper read at Michael Kirby Lecture Series, March 30, at Lismore, AU. Kirrnan, Igor. 1995. " Standing Apart to Be a Part: The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Concurring Opinions. " Columbia Law Review 95 (8)2083. Kirwin, Lucy, and Jeremy Masters, eds. 2002. Australian Guide to Legal Citation. 2nd ed. Melbourne: Melbourne University Law Review. Kluger, Richard. 1976. Simple Justice. New York: Random House. Kneebone, Susan. 1998. Tort Liability for Public Authorities. Sydney: LBC Information Services. Knoke, David, and Peter J. Burke. 1980. Log-Linear Models. Vol. 20. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications. Kobetsky, Michael, and Rick Krever. 2002. "Taxation Law." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Kort, Fred. 195 7. "Predicting Supreme Court Decisions Mathematically." American Political Science Review 51 :1. . 1963. " Simultaneous Equations and Boolean Algebra in the Analysis of Judicial Decisions." Law and Contemporary Problems 28:143. Krishnakumar, Anita S. 1999. "On the Evolution of the Canonical Dissent." Rutgers Law Review 52:781. Kwiatkowski, Denis, Peter C. B. Phillips, Peter Schmidt, and Yongcheol Shin. 1992. "Testing the Null Hypothesis of Stationarity Against the Alternative of a Unit 285 Root: How sure are we that economic time series have a unit root? " Journal of Econometrics 54:159-78. Kyri akakis, Joanna. 2005. "Freeport in West Papua: Bringing Corporations to Account for International Human Rights Abuses Under Australian Criminal and Tort Law." Melbourne UniversityLaw Review 31 (l):95. La Nauze, John Andrew. 1972. The Making of the Australian Constitution. Carlton: Melbourne University Press. Lani er, Drew Noble, and Sandra L. Wood. 2001. "Moving On Up: Institutional Position, Politics, and the Chief Justice." American Review of Politics 22293-127. Lavarch, Michael. 1996. "The Court, the Parliament and the Executive." In Courts of Final Jurisdiction: The Mason Court in Australia, ed. C. Saunders. Annandale, NSW: Federation Press. Lax, Jeffrey R., and Charles M. Cameron. 2007. "Bargaining and Opinion Assignment on the US. Supreme Court." Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization 23 (2):276-302. LCA. 1997. "Formal Consultation Process for High Court Appointments Unnecessary." Canberra: Law Council of Australia. . 2001. "Challenges for the Legal Profession. " In Law Council of Australia Discussion Paper. Canberra. . 2003. "Snapshot of the Legal Profession." Canberra: Law Council of Australia. Lebo, Matthew J ., Robert W. Walker, and Harold D. Clarke. 2000. "You Must Remember This: Dealing With Long Memory in Political Analyses." Electoral Studies 19 (1)231-48. Lehane, John. 2002. "W. M. C. Gummow." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Leigh, Andrew. 2000. "Behind the Bench: Associates in the High Court of Australia." Alternative Law Journal 25 (6):295-99. Lijphart, Arend. 1999. "Australian Democracy: Modifying Majoritarianism?" Australian Journal of Political Science 34 (3):313-26. Lindgren, Kevin E. 2007. "Is the Australian Law Journal an Australian Law Journal?" Paper read at The Judges' Review Conference, Mar. 16, at Sydney. 286 Lindsay, David. 2002. "Protection of Privacy Under the General Law Following AB. C. v. Lenah Game Meats Pty. Ltd : Where to Now?" Privacy Law and Policy Reporter 2002245. Luntz, Harold. 2002. "Tort Law." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Luntz, Harold, and D. Hambly. 2006. T orts: Cases and Commentary. 5th rev. ed. Sydney: LexisNexis Butterworths. Lynch, Andrew. 2002a. "Dissent: Towards a Methodology for Measuring Judicial Disagreement in The High Court of Australia." Sydney Law Review 24:470. . 2002b. "Dissenting Judgments." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2003a. "Dissent: The Rewards and Risks of Judicial Disagreement in the High Court of Australia." Melbourne University Law Review 29. . 2003b. "The Gleeson Court on Constitutional Law - An Empirical Analysis of its First Five Years." University of New South Wales Law Journal 26:32. Lynch, Andrew, and George Williams. 2005. "The High Court on Constitutional Law: The 2004 Statistics." Paper read at Constitutional Law Conference, February 18, at Sydney. MacKinnon, James G. . 1991. "Critical Values for Cointegration Tests." In Long-Run Economic Relationships: Readings in C ointegration, ed. R. F. Engle and C. W. J. Granger. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Maddala, G. S. 1983. Limited-Dependent and Qualitative Variables in Econometrics. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Maddala, G. S., and In-Moo Kim. 1998. Unit Roots, Cointegration, and Structural Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Magalhaes, Pedro C. 1998. "Judicial Behavior in Constitutional Courts: The Case of Portugal." Speech delivered to Scientific Study of Judicial Politics on, at East Lansing. Maitra, Pushkar, and Russell Smyth. 2005. "Determinants of Retirement on the High Court of Australia." Economic Record 81 (254):193. Maltese, John Anthony. 1998. The Selling of Supreme Court Nominees. Edited by M. Nelson. Paperback ed. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. . 287 Maltzman, Forrest, James F. Spriggs, II, and Paul J. Wahlbeck. 2000. CraflingLaw on the Supreme Court: The Collegial Game. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Maltzman, Forrest, and Paul J. Wahlbeck. 1996a. "May It Please the Chief: Opinion Assignments in the Rehnquist Court." American Journal of Political Science 40:421-43. . 1996b. "Strategic Policy Considerations and Voting Fluidity on the Burger Court." American Political Science Review 90 (3):581-92. . 2004. "A Conditional Model of Opinion Assignment on the Supreme Court." Political Research Quarterly 57 (4):551-63. . 2005. "Opinion Assignment on the Rehnquist Court." Judicature 89 (3): 121-28. Marks, Brian. 1989. A Model of Judicial Influence on Congressional Policymaking: Grove City College v. Bell. Ph.D. Dissertation, Washington University. Marr, David. 1980. Barwick. Sydney: Allen & Unwin. Marriner, Cosima. 2007. "Straight-Shooter Jumps the Bar." Sydney Morning Herald, Aug. 18. Martin, Paul, and Stuart Soroka. 2004. "Dissent and the Decline of Unanimity on the US. Supreme Court: Methodological Issues and Alternative Explanations." Paper read at Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, September, at Chicago, IL. Mason, Anthony. 2000. "The Evolving Role and Function of the High Court of Australia." In The Australian Federal Judicial System, ed. B. Opeskin and F. Wheeler. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press. . 2002a. "The Barwick Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002b. "The Griffith Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002c. "Judiciary Act." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002d. "Role of the Chief Justice." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. 288 . 2003a. "Celebrating the High Court's Centenary." Speech delivered to Centenary of the High Court Conference on 21 February, at Sydney, NSW. . 2003b. "The High Court of Australia: A Personal Impression of its First 100 Years." Melbourne University Law Review 2003 :33. . 2003c. Interview. Sydney, March 10. Matson. 1993. "The Common Law Abroad: English and Indigenous Laws in the British Commonwealth." International and Comparative Law Quarterly 42 (4):753-79. Maveety, Nancy. 1996. Justice Sandra Day O'Connor: Strategist on the Supreme Court. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. . 2003. "Concurrence and the Study of Judicial Behavior in American Political Science. " Juridica International 12173-85. Mazzocchi, Jo. 2003. Australia's High Court All Male Again. Canberra, February 11. Mc Iver, John P. 1976. "Scaling Judicial Decision: The Panel Decisionmaking Process of the US. Courts of Appeals." American Journal of Political Science 20 (4):749. McCarthy, Alana 2004. "The Evolution of the Role of the Attorney-General." Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law 1 l (4):30. McCormick, Peter James. 1994. "Career Patterns and the Delivery of Reasons for Judgment in the Supreme Court of Canada (1949-1993)." Supreme Court Law Review 5 (2)2499-521. McDonald, Leighton. 2002. "The Myth of Legal Merit and Ability." Canberra Times, December 23. McGarvie, Richard D. 1999. Democracy: Choosing Australia's Republic. Melbourne: University of Melbourne Press. McGinley, GP]. 1987. "The Search for Unity: The Impact of Consensus Seeking Procedures in Appellate Courts." Adelaide Law Review 11:203. McGuire, Kevin T. 1994. The Supreme Court Bar: Legal Elites in the Washington Community. 1 ed. Charlottsville: University of Virginia Press. McGuire, Kevin T., Charles E. Smith, Jr., and Gregory A. Caldeira. 1999. "Ambiguities in Measuring and Modeling the US. Supreme Court." Speech delivered to American Political Science Association on, at Atlanta. McHugh, Michael. 2002. "The High court and the Oxford Companion to the High Court." Speech delivered to Constitutional Law Conference on February 15, at Sydney. 289 . 2004. "The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the High Court: 1989-2004." Speech delivered to Sir Anthony Mason Lecture in Constitutional Law on Nov. 26, at Sydney, NSW. . 2005. "Working as a High Court Justice." Speech delivered to Women Lawyers Association of New South Wales on 17 August, at Newcastle. McIntyre, Greg, David Ritter, and Paul Sheiner. 1999. "Administrative Avalanch: The Application of the Registration Test under the Native Title Act 1993 (Cth)." Indiginous Law Bulletin 4 (20):8-12. McLaughlin, John Kennedy. 2002. "Cyril Ambrose Walsh." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. McMillan, John. 2002. "Judicial Restraint and Activism in Administrative Law." Federal Law Review 30 (2):335. . 2003. Interview. Canberra, ACT, 24 February. Meagher, Dan. 2002. "Guided By Voices? Constitutional Interpretation on the Gleeson Court." Deakin Law Review 2002214. Meek, Michael. 1999. The Australian Legal System. 3 ed. Pyrmont, NSW: LBC Information Services. Miles, Jeremy, and Mark Shelven. 2001. Applying Regression and Correlation: A Guide for Student and Researchers. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Milionis, Alexandros E. 2004. "The Importance of Variance Stationarity in Economic Time Series Modelling: A Practical Approach." Applied Financial Economics 14 (4):265-78. Mishler, William, and Reginald S. Sheehan. 1993. "The Supreme Court as a Counterrnaj oritarian Institution? The Impact of Public Opinion on Supreme Court Decisions." American Political Science Review 87287-101. . 1996. "Public Opinion, the Attitudinal Model, and Supreme Court Decision Making: A Micro-Analytic Perspective." Journal of Politics 58 (1)2169-200. Moens, Gabriel A. 1997. "The Role of the States in High Court Appointments." Speech delivered to Upholding the Australian Constitution on March 7-9, at Canberra. Moisidis, Cosmas. 2002. "Achieving World's Best Practice in the Writing of Appellate Judgments." Law Institute Journal 76 (10):30. 290 Murphy, Lionel. 1980. "The Responsibility of Judges." In Law, Politics and the Labor Movement, ed. G. Evans. Melboum: Legal Service Bulletin in Association with the Australian Society of Labor Lawyers. . 1983. "National Press Club Speech on August 17, at Canberra. Murphy, Walter F. 1964. Elements of Judicial Strategy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Myers, R. F. 1990. Classical and Modern Regression with Applications. Boston: PW S- KENT. Nagel, Steward S. 1961. "Political Party Affiliations and Judges' Decisions." American Political Science Review 55:843-50. Narayan, Paresh Kumar, and Russell Smyth. 2005. "The Consensual Norm on the High Court of Australia: 1904-2001 ." International Political Science Review 26 (2)2147-68. . 2007. "What Explains Dissent on the High Court of Australia? An Empirical Assessment Using a Cointegration and Error Correction Approach." Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 4 (2)2401-25. Ng, Serena, and Pierre Perron. 1995. "Unit Root Tests in ARMA Models with Data- Dependent Methods for the Selection of the Truncation Lag." Journal of the American Statistical Association 90:268-81. Novak, Linda. 1980. "The Precedential Value of Supreme Court Plurality Decisions." Columbia Law Review 80 (4)2756. O'Brien, David. 1985. "Managing the Business of the Supreme Court." Public Administration Review 45 2667-78. O'Brien, David M. 1999. "Institutional Norms and Supreme Court Opinions: On Reconsidering the Rise of Individual Opinions. " In Supreme Court Decision- Making: New Institutionalist Approaches, ed. C. W. Clayton and H. Gillman. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. O'Brien, Robert M. 2007. "A Caution Regarding Rules of Thumb for Variance Inflation Factors." Quality and Quantity 41 (5)2673 -90. Ostberg, C. L., and Matthew E. Wetstein. 2004. "Equality Cases and the Attitudinal Model in the Supreme Court of Canada." Paper read at Canadian Political Science Association Meeting,Jun. 5, at Winnipeg. Ostberg, C. L., Matthew E. Wetstein, and Craig R. Ducat. 2002. "Attitudinal Dimensions of Supreme Court Decision Making in Canada: The Larner Court 1991-1995." Political Research Quarterly 55 (1):235-56. 291 . 2003. "Acclimation Effects on the Supreme Court of Canada: A Cross-Cultural Examination of Judicial Folklore." Social Science Quarterly 84 (3):704—22. Pacelle, Richard L., and Bryan W. Marshall. 2001. "Strategic or Sincere? The Supreme Court in Constitutional Decisions." Paper read at American Political Science Association, Aug. 30 - Sep. 3, at San Francisco, CA. Pampel, Fred C. 2000. Logistic Regression: A Primer. Edited by M. S. Lewis-Beck. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications. Parish, Ken. 2000. "The High Court and the Nature of Judicial Power." In Australian Public Law. Darwin. Patapan, Hai g. 2000a. "Governance and the High Court." In Institutions on the Edge? Capacity for Governance, ed. M. Keating, J. Wanna and P. Weller. St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin. . 2000b. Judging Democracy : The New Politics of the High Court of A ustralia. Cambridge [England] ; New York: Cambridge University Press. . 2000c. "The Politics of Interpretation." Sydney Law Review 22:247. . 2002. "High Court Review 2001: Politics, Legalism and the Gleeson Court." Australian Journal of Political Science 37 (2):241-53. Pearson, Linda. 2007. "The Impact of External Administrative Law Review: Tribunals." In University of New South Wales Faculty of Law Research Series. Sydney. Pelly, Michael. 2005. "McHugh's Angels: 10 Women Fit for High Court, Says Top Judge." Sydney Morning Herald, Aug. 19. . 2008. "Kirby the Outsiders Lonely Last Lap on a Bench where Legalism Rules." The Australian, Feb. 8. Perry, H. W., Jr. 1994. Deciding to Decide: Agenda Setting in the United States Supreme Court: Harvard University Press. Perry, H.W. 1991. Deciding to Decide: Agenda Setting in the United States Supreme Court. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Peterson, Steven A. 1981. "Dissent in American Courts." Journal of Politics 43 (2)1412. Phillips, Peter C. B., and Pierre Perron. 1988. "Testing for a Unit Root in Time Series Regression." Biometrika 75 (2):335-46. Pierce, Jason L. 2006. Inside the Mason Court Revolution. Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press. 292 Pinello, Daniel R. 1999. "Linking Party to Judicial Ideology in American Courts: A Meta-analysis. " Justice Systems Journal 20 (3)221 9-5 7. Popple, James. 1999. "Case Management in the High Court of Australia: The First Year of a New System." Paper read at Sixth National Court Technology Conference, 14-16 September, at Los Angeles. . 2003. "Number of Justices." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Posner, Richard A. 1995. Overcoming Law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Posner, Richard A., and Eric Bennett Rasmusen. 1999. "Creating and Enforcing Norms, with Special Reference to Sanctions." International Review of Law and Economics 19 (3):369-82. Post, Robert. 2001. "The Supreme Court Opinion as Institutional Practice: Dissent, Legal Scholarship, and Decisionmaking in the Taft Court." Minnesota Law Review 85: 1267. Powell, Lewis F., Jr. 2004. "What Really Goes on at the Supreme Court." In Judges on Judging: Views fiom the Bench, ed. D. O'Brien. Washington, DC: CQ Press. Priest, Susan. 2002. "Strike of 1905." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Pritchett, C. Herman. 1948. The Roosevelt Court: A Study in Judicial Politics and Values, 193 7-194 7. New York: Macmillian. . 1954. Civil Liberties and the Vinson Court. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. . 1961. Congerss versus the Supreme Court: University of Minnesota Press. Przeworski, Adam. 1995. "The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics: A Symposium." World Politics 48: 1-49. Przeworski, Adam , and Henry Teune. 1970. The Logic of Comparative Social Inquiry. Malabar, Fl.: Krieger Publishing Company. Quick, John, and Robert Randolph Garran. 1901. The Annotated Constitution of the Australian Commonwealth. Sydney: Angus & Robertson. Ramseyer, J. Mark. 1994. "The Puzzling (In) Dependence of Courts: A Comparative Approach." Journal of Legal Studies 23 2721-47. 293 Ramseyer, J. Mark, and Eric B. Rasmusen. 1997. "Judicial Independence in a Civil Law Regime: The Evidence from Japan." Journal ofLaw, Economics, & Organization 13 (2):256-86. Rehnquist, William H. 1983. "Oral Advocacy: A Disappearing Art." Mercer Law Review 35: 1015-28. . 2004. "The Supreme Court's Conference." In Judges on Judging: Views from the Bench, ed. D. O'Brien. Washington, DC: CQ Press. Richards, Alexandra. 2000. "Sir Harry Gibbs Wrong on Merit in Judicial Appointments." Canberra: Australian Women Lawyers. Riker, William H. 1962. The Theory of Political Coalitions. New Haven: Yale University Press. Robinson, Peter M. 1995. "Gaussian Semiparametric Estimation of Long Range Dependence." The Annals of Statistics 23 (5): 1630-61. Rohde, David. 1972a. "Policy Goals and Opinion Coalitions in the Supreme Court." Midwest Journal of Political Science 16 (2)2208. . 1972b. "Policy Goals, Strategic Choice and Majority Opinion Assignments in the US. Supreme Court." Midwest Journal of Political Science 16 (4):652. . 1977. "Some Clarifications Regarding a Theory of Suprrne Court Coalition Formation. " American Journal of Political Science 21 (2):405. Rose, Richard, and Doh Chull Shin. 2001. "Democratization Backwards: The Problem of Third-Wave Democracies." British Journal of Political Science 30 (2):299-3 22. Rosenberg, Gerald N., and John M. Williams. 1997. "Do Not Go Gently into That Good Right: The First Amendment int he High Court of Australia." The Supreme Court Review 1997:439-195. Rubenstein, Kim. 2002. "In High Court Selection, Like Promotes Like." The Age, December 20. Said, S. E., and David A. Dickey. 1984. "Testing for Unit Roots in Autoregressive Moving-Average Models with Unknown Order." Biometrika 71:599-607. Sartori, Giovanni. 1970. "Concept Mi sinformation in Comparative Politics." American Political Science Review 64 (4): 1033-53. Sawer, Geoffrey. 1957. Cases on the Constitution of the Commonwealth of A ustralia. 2nd ed. Sydney: The Law Book Co. of Australasia. . 1975. The Australian Constitution. Canberra: Australian Govt. Pub. Service. 294 Sawer, Marian. 1999. "Overview: Institutional Design and the Role of the Senate." In Representation and Institutional Change: 50 Years of Proportional Representation in the Senate, ed. M. Sawer and S. Miskin. Canberra, ACT: Department of the Senate. Sawyer, Geoffrey. 1967. Australian Federalism in the Courts. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press. Schaefer, Walter V. 1966. "Precedent and Policy." University of Chicago Law Review 34 (1):3-25. Schmidhauser, John R. 1962. "Stare Decisis, Dissent, and the Background of the Justices of the Supreme Court of the United States." University of Toronto Law Journal 14:194. Schubert, Glendon. 1959. Quantitative Analysis of Judicial Behavior. Glencoe, Ill: The Free Press. . 1964. "The Power of Organized Minorities in a Small Group." Administrative Science Quarterly 9 (2)2133-53. . 1968. "Political Ideology on the High Court." Politics 3:21. . 1969a. "Judicial Attitudes and Policy-Making in the Dixon Court." Osgood Hall Law Journal 7:1. . 1969b. "Two Causal Models of Decision-Making by the High Court of Australia." In Comparative Judicial Behavior: C ross-C ultural Studies of Political Decision-Making in the East and West, ed. G. Schubert and D. J. Danelski. New York: Oxford University Press. Schubert, Glendon A. 1965. The Judicial Mind : The Attitudes and Ideologies of Supreme Court Justices, 1946-1963. Evanston, 111.: Northwestern University Press. Schubert, Glendon, and David J. Danelski. 1969. Comparative Judicial Behavior: Cross- Cultural Studies of Political Decision-Making in the East and West. New York: Oxford University Press. Schuck, Peter H., and E. Donald Elliot. 1990. "To the Chevron Station: An Empirical Study of Federal Administrative Law." Duke Law Journal 1990:984. Schwartz, Edward P. 1992. "Policy, Precedent, and Power: A Positive Theory of Supreme Court Decision-Making. " Journal of Law, Economics and Organization 8 (2) :2 1 9. Scott, John T., James F. Spriggs, and James R. Zink. 2003. "Courting the Public: Judicial Behavior and Public Views of Court Decisions." Speech delivered to Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association on, at Chicago. 295 Seddig, Robert G. 1991. "John Marshall and the Origins of Supreme Court Leadership." Journal of Supreme Court History 1991 (1). Segal, Jeffrey A. 1984. "Predicting Supreme Court Cases Probabilistically: The Search and Seizure Cases, 1962-1981." American Political Science Review 78:891-900. Segal, Jeffrey A., and Albert D. Cover. 1989. "Ideological Values and the Votes of US. Supreme Court Justices." American Political Science Review 83 (2):557-65. Segal, Jeffrey A., Harold. J. Spaeth, Lee Epstein, and Thomas G. Walker. 2007. The Supreme Court Compendium: Data, Decisions & Developments. 4th ed: CQ Press. Segal, Jeffrey Allan, and Harold J. Spaeth. 1993. The Supreme Court and the Attitudinal Model. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press. . 2002. The Supreme Court and the Attitudinal Model Revisited. Cambridge ; New York: Cambridge University Press. Selway, Bradley. 2002. "The Use of History and Other Facts in the Reasoning of the High Court of Australia." University of Tasmania Law Review 20 (2):129-58. Selway, Bradley, and John M. Williams. 2005. "The High Court and Australian Federalism." Publius 35 (3)2467. Shapiro, Martin M. 1995. "From the Section Chair. " Law and Courts 5:1. Shapley, L. S., and Martin Shubik. 1954. "A Method for Evaluating the Distribution of Power in a Committee System." American Political Science Review 48:78 7-92. Sheehan, Reginald S. 1990. "Administrative Agencies and the Court: A Reexamination of the Impact of Agency Type on Decisional Outcomes." Western Political Quarterly 43 :875-85. . 1992. "Federal Agencies and the Supreme Court: An Analysis of Litigation Outcomes, 1953-1988." American Politics Quarterly 20:478-500. Sheldon, Charles H. 1967. "Public Opinion and High Courts: Communist Party Cases in Four Constitutional Systems." Western Political Quarterly 20:341. Sheller, Simon. 2002. "MD. Kirby." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Simpson, Amelia, and Troy Simpson. 2002. "Personal Relations." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. 296 Simpson, Troy. 2002. "Conferences." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Smith, R. 2000. "Unit Roots and All That: The Impact of Time-Series Methods on Macroeconomics." In Macroeconomics and the Real World, ed. R. Backhouse and A. Salanti. New York: Oxford University Press. Smithey, Shannon Ishiyama. 2002. "Activism on the South African Constitutional Court." Speech delivered to Midwest Political Science Association on, at Chicago. Smyth, Russell. 2000. "The 'Haves' and the 'Have Nots': An Empirical Study of the Rational Actor and Party Capability Hypotheses in the High Court 1948-99." Australian Journal of Political Science 35 (2):255-74. . 2001. "Judicial Interaction on the Latham Court: A Quantitative Study of Voting Patterns on the High Court 193 5-1950." Australian Journal of Politics and History 47 (3)2330-48. . 2002a. "Acclimation Effects for High Court Justices 1903-1975." University of Western Sydney Law Review. . 2002b. "Explaining Voting Patterns on the Latham High Court 1935-50." Melbourne University Law Review 200225. . 2002c. "Historical Consensual Norms in the High Court." Australian Journal of Political Science 37 (2):255-66. . 2003a. "Case Complexity and Citation to Judicial Authority: Some Empirical Evidence from the New Zealand Court of Appeal." Murdoch University Electronic Journal of Law 10 (1). . 2003b. "Explaining Historical Dissent Rates in the High Court of Australia." Commonwealth and Comparative Politics 41 (2)283-1 14. . 2004. "What Explains Variations in Dissent Rates?: Time Series Evidence from the High Court." Sydney Law Review 262221. . 2005a. "Do Judges Behave as Homo Economicus, and If So, Can we Measures Their Performance? An Antipodean Perspective on a Tournament of Judges." Florida State University Law Review 3221299-330. . 2005b. "The Role of Attitudinal, Institutional and Environmental Factors in Explaining Variations in the Dissent Rate on the High Court of Australia." Australian Journal of Political Science 40 (4): 5 19-40. 297 Smyth, Russell, and J ayaprakash Narayan. 2004. "Hail to the Chiefl Leadership and Structural Change in the Level of Consensus on the High Court of Australia." Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 1 (2):399-427. Snyder, Eloise. 1958. "The Supreme Court as a Small Group." Social Forces 36 (3)2232- 8. . 1959. "Uncertainty and the Supreme Court's Decisions." American Journal of Sociology 65 (3)2241. Solomon, David Harris. 1999. The Political High Court : How the High Court Shapes Politics. St Leonards, NSW, Australia: Allen & Unwin. Songer, Donald R, and Stefanie A. Lindquist. 1996. "Not the Whole Story: The Impact of Justices' Values on Supreme Court Decision Making." American Journal of Political Science 1049-1 063. Songer, Donald R. 1978. "The Relevance of Policy Values for the Confirmation of Supreme Court Nominees." Law & Society Review 132927-49. Songer, Donald R., and Martha Anne Humphries. 1999. "Law and Politics in Judicial Oversight of Federal Administrative Agencies." Journal of Politics 61 (1):207-20. Songer, Donald R., and Susan W. Johnson. 2002. "Attitudinal Decision Making in the Supreme Court of Canada on. . 2007. "Judicial Decision Making in the Supreme Court of Canada: Updating the Personal Attribute Model." Canadian Journal of Political Science 40:91 1-3 4. Spaeth, Harold J. 1989. "Consensus in the Unanimous Decisions of the US. Supreme Court." Judicature 72 (5):274-92. . 1997. The United States Supreme Court Judicial Database, 1953-1995 . Ann Arbor: Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research. Spaeth, Harold J ., and Douglas R. Parker. 1969. "Effects of Attitude Toward Situatio upon Attitude toward Obj ect." Journal of Psychology 732173-82. Spaeth, Harold J., and Jeffrey A. Segal. 2001. Majority Rule or Minority Will: Adherence to Precedent on the US. Supreme Court. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Spigelman, James. 2004. "Anniversary Dinner Address." Speech delivered to Federal Law Review - 40th Anniversary Dinner on Oct. 28, at Canberra, ACT. Spriggs, James F., 11. 1996. "The Supreme Court and Federal Administrative Agencies: A Resource-Based Theory and Analysis of Judicial Impact." American Journal of Political Science 40 (4)21122-51. 298 . 2008. "An Empirical Analysis of the Trends, Determinants, and Effects of Majority Opinions of the US. Supreme Court." In Selected Works of James F. Spriffs II: ExpressO. Spriggs, James F., Forrest Maltzman, and Paul J. Wahlbeck. 1999. "Bargaining on the US. Supreme Court: Justices' Responses to Majority Opinion Drafts." Journal of Politics 61 (2)2485. Spriggs, James F., and Paul J. Wahlbeck. 1997. "Amicus Curiae and the Role of Information at the Supreme Court." Political Research Quarterly 50 (2)2365. Stager, Walter. 1925. "Dissenting Opinions, Their Purpose and Results." Virginia Law Register 11 (7)395. Stephens, Tony. 2002. Sir William Deane: The Things that Matter. Sydney: Hodder. Stone, Adrienne. 2000. "The Freedom of Political Communication Since Lange." In The High Court at the Crossroads: Essays in Constitutional Law, ed. A. Stone and G. Williams. Leichhardt, N.S.W.: Federation Press. Stone, Alec. 1992. The birth of judicial politics in France .' the Constitutional Council in comparative perspective. New York: Oxford University Press. Stras, David R. 2007. "Why Supreme Court Justices Should Ride Circuit Again." Minnesota Law Review 91 : 1710-51 . Stretton, Dean. 2005. "The Birth Torts: Damages for Wrongful Birth and Wrongful Life." Deakin Law Review 16:10. Tabachnick, Barbara G., and Linda S. Fidell. 2001. Using Multivariate Statistics. 4th ed. Needham Heights, MA: Allyn & Bacon. Tanenhaus, Joseph. 1966. "The Cumulative Scaling of Judicial Decisions." Harvard Law Review 79 (8)21583-94. Tarr, G. Alan. 2003. Judicial Process and Judicial Policymaking. 3rd ed. Belmont: Thomson Wadsworth. Tate, C. Neal. 1981a. "Judicial Institutions in Cross-National Perspective: Toward Integrating Courts into the Comparative Study of Politics." In Comparative Judicial Systems, ed. J. R. Schmidhauser: Butterworths. . 1981b. "Personal Attribute Models of the Voting Behavior of US. Supreme Court Justices: Liberalism in Civil Liberties and Economics Decisions, 1946- 1978." American Political Science Review 75 (2):355-67. . 1983. "The Methodology of Judicial Behavior Research: A Review and Critique." Political Behavior 5 (1)251 . 299 . 1992. "The Development of Comparative Judicial Politics." Perspectives on Political Science 21 (3): 138-44. . 1996. "Comparative Judicial Politics in the 19903." Speech delivered to Western Political Science Association on, at San Francisco. . 2002a. "Past, Present, and Future with the "Comparative Advantage": Part II, 1990-2002 Interlogue." Law and Courts Section Newsletter 12 (3)21-13. . 2002b. "Past, Prsent, and Future with the "Comparative Advantage": Part I, 1892-1989." Law & Courts 12 (2):l-10. Tate, C. Neal, and Panu Sittiwong. 1989. "Decision Making in the Canadian Suprrne Court: Extending the Personal Attributes Model across Nations." Journal of Politics 51 (4)2900-16. Tate, C. Neal, Alec Stone, William Kitchin, Nils Stjernquist, Peter Russell, Mary L Volcansek, Carl Baar, David J. Danelski, and Donald W. Jackson. 1990. "Symposium on Judicial Review in Comparative Perspective." Policy Studies Journal 19 (1):76-171. Tate, C. Neal, and Torbj 'o’rn Vallinder. 1995. The Global Expansion of Judicial Power. New York: New York University Press. Thompson, Elaine. 1980. "The "Washminster" Mutation." Australian Journal of Political Science 15 (2):32-40. Thompson, J. 1982. "Principles and Theories of Constitutional Interpretation and Adjudication: Some Preliminary Notes." Melbourne University Law Review 132603. Twomey, Anne. 2002. "The Gibbs Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Tyree, Alan. 1977. "The Geometry of Case Law. " Victoria University of Wellington Law Review 4:403. . 1981. "Fact Content Analysis of Case Law: Methods and Limitations." Jurimetrics Journal 22: 1. Ulmer, S. Sidney. 1970. "Dissent Behavior and the Social Background of Supreme Court Justices." Journal of Politics 32 (3):580-98. . 1971. "Earl Warren and the Brown Decision." Journal of Politics 33 2689-702. 300 . 1973. "Social Background as an Inidcator to the Votes of Supreme Court Justices in Criminal Cases: 1947-1956 Terms." American Journal of Political Science 17:622-30. Ulmer, S. Sidney, and William Nicholls. 1978. "The Integration of Dissent Behavior in the United States Supreme Court." Jurimetrics Journal 19:170. Verba, Sidney. 1967. "Some Dilemmas in Comparative Research." World Politics 20 (1):111-27. Voigt, Stefan, Michael Ebeling, and Lorenz Blume. 2006. "Improving Credibility by Delegating Judicial Competencewthe Case of the Judicial Committee of the Privy Council." Journal of Development Economics 82 (2):348-73. Volcansek, Mary L. 1993. Judicial Impeachment: None Called it Justice. Champaign: University of Illinois Press. von Nessen, Paul E. 1992. "The Use of American Precedents by the High Court of Australia, 1901-1987." Adelaide Iflw Review 14:181. Wahlbeck, Paul J., James F. Spriggs, II, and Forrest Maltzman. 1998. "Marshalling the Court: Bargaining and Accommodation on the United States Supreme Court." American Journal of Political Science 42 (1):294-315. . 1999. "The Politics of Dissents and Concurrences on the US. Supreme Court " American Politics Research 27 (4):488-517. Wald, Patricia M. 1999. "A Response to Tiller and Cross." Columbia Law Review 99:23 5-61. Walker, Bret. 2002a. "A.M. Gleeson." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Walker, Geoffrey de Q. 2002b. "The Seven Pillars of Centralism: Federalism and the Engineers' Case." Speech delivered to Conference of the Samuel Griffith Society on June 14-16, at Sydney. Walker, Kristen. 2002c. "A. F. Mason." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Walker, Thomas G., Lee Epstein, and William J. Dixon. 1988. "On the Mysterious Demise of Consensual Norms in the United States Supreme Court." Journal of Politics 50 (2):361-89. 301 Walker, Thomas G., and W. E. Hulbary. 1978. "Selection of Capable Justices." In The First One Hundred Justices, ed. A. E. Blaustein and R. M. Mersky. Hampden, CT: Shoe String Press. Walsh, Peter. 1997. "Labor and the Constitution: Forty Years On." Paper read at Conference of the Samuel Griffith Society, Oct. 26, at Perth. Waltrnan, J erold L., and Kenneth M. Holland. 1987. The Political role of law courts in modern democracies. New York: St. Martin's Press. Wasby, Stephen L. 1970. The Impact of the United States Supreme Court: Some Perspectives. Homewood, IL: The Dorsey Press. Wells, William A. N. 1991. Law, Judges and Justice. North Ryde, NSW: Butterworths. Wetstein, Matthew E., and C. L. Ostberg. 2005. "Strategic Leadership and Political Change on the Canadian Supreme Court: Analyzing the Transition to Chief Justice." Canadian Journal of Political Science 38 (3):653-73. Wheeler, Fiona. 2003. Discussion. Canberra, ACT, 18 February 2003. White, Byron R. 1982. "The Work of the Supreme Court: A Nuts and Bolts Description." New York State Bar Journal 54:346. Willheim, Ernst. 2002. "Collective Responsibility." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Williams, George. 1999. "The High Court and the Media." University of Technology, Sydney Law Review 1999 (1): 136-46. . 2000. "The Amicus Curiae and Intervener in the High Court of Australia: A Comparative Analysis." Federal Law Review 282365-402. Williams, John M. 2002. "Lionel Keith Murphy." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. A. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Winterton, George. 1998. "Barwi ck the Judge." University of New South Wales Law Journal 21:109. . 2002. "Garfield Edward John Barwick." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. Wood, Rebecca. 2002. "Dimensions of Decision-Making: Determining the Complexity of Politics on the High Court of Australia." Speech delivered to Southern Political Science Association on November 7-9, at Savannah, GA. 302 . 2008. "Institutional Considerations in Locating Norms of Consensus: A Cross- National Investigation." Paper read at Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association, Apr. 4, at Chicago, IL. Wood, Sandra L., Linda Camp Keith, Drew Noble Lanier, and Ayo Ogundele. 1998a. ""Acclimation Effects" for Supreme Court Justices: A Cross-Validation, 1888- 1940." American Journal of Political Science 42 (2):690-7. . 1998b. "The Supreme Court, 1888-1940: An Empirical Overview." Social Science History 22 (2):201-24. Woodward, Robert, and Scott Armstrong. 1979. The Brethren. New York: Avon Books. Young, Neil J ., and Stephen McLeish. 2004. "Appellate Advocacy." Speech delivered to Victorian Bar Compulsory Continuing Legal Education Program on December 14, at Victoria. Yule, G. Udny. 1926. "Why do we Sometimes get Nonsense Correlations Between Time Series: A Study in Sampling and the Nature of Time Series." Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 89: 1-64. Zines, Leslie. 1997. The High Court and the Constitution. 4th ed. Sydney: Butterworths. . 2000. "The Present State of Constitutional Interpretation." In The High Court at the Crossroads: Essays in Constitutional Law, ed. A. Stone and G. Williams. Leichhardt, N.S.W.: Federation Press. - . 2002a. "The Dixon Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002b. "The Gleeson Court." In The Oxford Companion to the High Court of Australia, ed. T. Blackshield, M. Coper and G. Williams. South Melbourne: Oxford University Press. . 2002c. "Legalism, Realism and Judicial Rhetoric in Constitutional Law." Speech delivered to New South Wales Bar Association on October 16, at Sydney. Zivot, Eric, and Jiahui Wang. 2003. "Modeling Financial Time Series with S-PLUS." T echnometrics 45 (4):373-4. . 2006. Modeling Financial Time Series with S-PL US: Springer. Zorn, Christopher J. W. 2005. "A Solution to Separation in Binary Response Models." Political Analysis 13 (2):]57-70. 303