two-fol frightf a Way w aura of is born “amely. "Qt gen ABSTRACT AN INVESTIGATION OF SELF-DECEPTION By Charles Bruce The problem to which this dissertation addresses itself is two—fold: (1) Why does the concept of self-deception seem so frightfully paradoxical? (2) How can the concept be elucidated in a way which is at once true to the concept and which dissipates the aura of paradox? These questions presuppose a proposition which is born out by an investigation of the concept of self-deception, namely, that the concept of self-deception is a coherent one and not genuinely paradoxical. Self-deception seems paradoxical because we misconstrue it. We think of it in ways appropriate only to the deception of others. Thus we see the self-deceiyer's pretense as efforts to take himself in; we even see the self-deceiver's effort to push thought of the truth from his mind as part of an attempt to hide the truth from himself. What we fail to realize clearly is that these descriptions make little sense on other than a metaphorical plane. Taken literally, they presuppose a contradiction, that the self-deceiver knows the truth and does not know it. AS deceiver he must know the .v~ ‘1! A." '4' 1’! 'F-. l.‘ tr DJ '4. do we th: dec aim tru seli Charles Bruce truth, but as victim he must not know it, for deception always aims! even when it is not successful, at preventing someone who does not know the truth from coming to know it. Similarly, if we view the self-deceiver as having literally deceived himself, this description entails the same contradiction, for, again, as deceiver he must know the truth, and, having succeeded in his aims, he must have prevented himself from coming to know the truth. I call this contradiction, 'the first major paradox of self-deception.‘ This contradiction does not seem to arise only because we are misled by figurative expressions. It has its source deep in a way of thinking about consciousness, a way of thinking which I call, 'the vehicular theory of consciousness'. This theory holds that all consciousness must have a 'vehicle', e.g., a mental image, words, or a sensuous impression. Applied to self-deception this theory yields the view that the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth. This lack of consciousness of the truth even while he knows the truth cannot be explained, however, as due to his own purposive efforts, for such efforts would entail that he is conscious of the truth, and thus we would be confronted with a second contradiction, that he is and is not conscious of the truth. This contradiction is 'the second major paradox of self-deception'. To avoid this paradox and explain the self-deceiver's lack of consciousness, we view him as prevented from becoming conscious of the a p wit res‘ ignc once Coun cons Corr: have CODSC effor deCeL PUrPO: SeConc true t 0f sel philos, analyt; which h I Charles Bruce the truth by forces beyond his control: either forces directed by a personal agency within his mind or impersonal, mechanical forces within his mind. This way of viewing him in turn strengthens the resemblance between the self-deceiver and someone who is genuinely ignorant of the truth, we are taken in by this resemblance, and once again land in the first major paradox of self-deception. The way out is to deny the vehicular theory of consciousness. Counter-examples abound, and they allow us to distinguish between consciousness and explicit consciousness of the truth. The latter corresponds roughly to consciousness with a 'vehicle'. Once we have made this distinction, we can allow that the self-deceiver is conscious of the truth even though, as a result of his own purposive efforts, he is never explicitly conscious of the truth. The self- deceiver's metaphorical 'hiding' and 'deception' is just this purposeful avoidance of explicit consciousness. This answers our second question, for the latter account of self-deception, while true to the concept, does not entail either of the major paradoxes of self-deception. This dissertation is well within the analytic tradition in philosophy. It begins with a consideration of the work of other analytic philosophers on the concept of self-deception. This work, which began with a paper entitled,'Lying to Oneself', by Raphael lDemos, is found wanting primarily because Demos misconstrued other; deception. He was followed in this by others in the tradition, and that firs diss Charles Bruce thus the whole discussion went off in a wrong direction, failing to provide satisfactory answers to the questions posed above. It is not until we come to Herbert Fingarette's book, Self-Deception, that we get back on the track. Fingarette clearly exposes the first major paradox of self-deception. The view defended in this dissertation, while critical of certain aspects of Fingarette's work, is still greatly indebted to it. AN INVESTIGATION OF SELF-DECEPTION by Charles Dawson Bruce A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Philosophy 1975 CHAPTER II III IV NOTES -- TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE I. Demos' Analysis of Self-Deception -------------- 1 II. Self-Deception and Other-Deception ------------- 30 III. Self—Deception and Wishful Thinking ------------ 88 IV. Fingarette's New Model of Consciousness --------- 105 V. Over-Riding Reasons - — — - 177 NOTES --------------------- —- 198 CHAPTER ( Section 2 In appeared of self- 'the ana analytic PaPer re much of some to 1969, u effort 1 philosc CHAPTER ONE. Demos' Analysis of Self-Deception. Section 1. In 1960 a paper by Raphael Demos entitled, 'Lying to Oneself', appeared. The paper sparked a series of interchanges and discussions of self-deception which, together with Demos' paper, I shall call 'the analytic tradition before Fingarette', or, more briefly, 'the analytic tradition'. Of the papers in this tradition, Demos' paper remains the most important, for it set the limits within which much of the ensuing discussion was confined. It is only when we come to Herbert Fingarette's book, Self-Deception, published in 1969, that we find a criticism of these limits and a sustained effort to pass beyond them. Certain elements in the framework provided by Demos are especially noteworthy. It is a consequence of Demos' analysis of self-deception that the self-deceiver knows and believes some proposition not-P while at the same time believing that P - that is, the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs. Demos felt that this seemed puzzling and called for special explanation. Later writers in the tradition responded in two ways. Some of them found the idea of a person holding incompatible beliefs to be downright paradoxical, and they set about to provide analyses of self-deception which did not entail that the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs. These philosophers agreed with Demos that the self-deceiver believes a falsehood entails t; writers 6 incompati maintaini while at other por includinvi; knows th; latter v, I The deception (1) (2) This narr hid r9cog' His Paper implicit] Pc'lreldgxiC becauSe : the hOId While ev. Part of . Fingaret falsehood, but they rejected that part of Demos' analysis which entails that the self-deceiver knows and believes the truth. Other writers did not find the suggestion that the self-deceiver holds. incompatible beliefs quite so disturbing. They followed Demos in maintaining that the self-deceiver knows and believes that not-P while at the same time believing that P, though they did reject other portions of Demos' account. No one, on the other hand, including Fingarette, advanced the view that the self-deceiver knows that not-P and does not hold the belief that P. It is this latter view which will be advanced and defended in this dissertation. The result of Demos' paper was that the discussion of self- deception was sharply focused on two questions: (1) Is it paradoxical, perhaps inconsistent, to 'maintain that a person holds incompatible beliefs? (2) Does the self-deceiver know or believe the truth concerning which he is deceiving himself? This narrowing of the discussion also involved a loss. Demos had recognized that self-deception often appears deeply paradoxical. His paper contained not only an analysis of self-deception, but implicitly, at least, an account of why self-deception seems paradoxical. On his view self—deception seems to be paradoxical because it involves the holding of two incompatible beliefs, and the holding of incompatible beliefs seems to be logically impossible. While every writer appearing later in the tradition rejected some part of Demos' analysis of self-deception, absolutely no one until Fingarette called into question Demos' explanation of why 1n Ul'flc'l“ in 4 decept as par analys the pr and it true w self-d distin eXplan first L9 X of Dem evalua that 1 though it is deCept a“3le parade: self-deception seems to be deeply paradoxical. It was because they accepted this explanation that they concentrated so sharply on questions (1) and (2) above, and gave the analyses which they did give. The two accounts which Demos gives - his analysis of self- deception, and his explanation of why self—deception strikes us as paradoxical - are very closely linked. This is because the analysis of self-deception which he expounds and defends entails the proposition that the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs, and it was the seeming impossibility of this proposition being true which was taken to be at the root of the paradoxical air of self-deception. In our own dealings with Demos' paper, we shall sharply distinguish between Demos' analysis of self-deception and his explanation of why self-deception seems to be paradoxical. The first account could very well be false and the second true, or vice versa. In Section 2 of this chapter I shall give an exposition of Demos' analysis of self-deception. In Section 3 I shall evaluate this analysis. I shall argue that he is correct in holding that in general the having of incompatible beliefs is non-paradoxical, though I shall try to show that there are particular cases in which it is paradoxical, and these cases include instances of self- deception. Next I shall consider an argument to show that Demos' analysis entails a particular inconsistency which I call 'the minor paradox of self-deception'. Demos somewhat dimly perceived the minor par and it is that it _s_ beliefs, as deeply Speaking, only when not expli self~dece Con none the inadequat 0f self-d dec‘i‘Ption proPOSiti his analy decelition Heh This does deception e”plenalti arun tha of Selfid radially minor Par. he does In minor paradox of self—deception in connection with his analysis, and it is, I believe, this paradox which lies behind his saying that it segm§_logically impossible for a person to hold incompatible beliefs, and which influenced later writers to view this suggestion as deeply paradoxical. However, Demos' analysis does not, strictly speaking, entail the minor paradox of self-deception, and it is only when we read into his analysis certain things which he does not explicitly include in it that we derive the minor paradox of self-deception. Consideration of the minor paradox of self-deception does, none the less, reveal another respect in which Demos' analysis is inadequate, for one of the propositions of which the minor paradox of self-deception consists states a necessary condition of self- deception, yet Demos' analysis does not contain or imply this proposition, and, indeed, Demos tried to include its negation in his analysis in order to ward off the minor paradox of self- deception. Hence Demos' analysis of self-deception is unacceptable. This does not mean, however, that his explanation of why self- deception seems to be paradoxical is unacceptable, and it is this explanation which we shall consider next, in Chapter Two. I shall argue that his explanation, while hinting at one of the paradoxes of self-deception - the minor paradox of self-deception, is radically defective. Not only does he not clearly bring out the minor paradox, but there are two majgr_paradoxes as well which he does not even hint at. The cause of this defect in his explanation on the dec»: one for the of self-deg consequence major para: the value c paradoxical One < feels com, mlilies so COV-‘P‘e‘lled decePliion this lead This is w Self‘dem it On otl one can“ construe T: of othe. dict-pm explanation lies in the fact that while Demos models self-deception on the deception of others, and while this procedure is the correct one for the purposes of drawing out and displaying the paradoxes of self-deception, Demos misconstrues gthgrfdeception, and in consequence, the modeling does not yield either the minor or the major paradoxes of self-deception. This error diminishes greatly the value of his explanation of why self-deception appears to be paradoxical. One of the earmarks of a philosophical paradox is that one feels compelled or strongly inclined to accept an account which implies something, e.g., a contradiction, which one feels equally compelled to reject. I believe that when we reflect on self- deception, we do feel compelled to model it on other-deception, and this leads to intolerable - though rarely made explicit - results. This is why I said above that for the purpose of explaining why self-deception seems to be paradoxical, Demos was right to model it on other-deception. But because he mis-construed other-deception, one cannot, by modeling self-deception on other-deception as he construes the latter, see what these results are. This difficulty is removed when we correct Demos' treatment of other-deception. Beginning with a corrected model of other- deception and applying it to self-deception, we shall be able to generate the paradoxical consequences which we often feel when we reflect on self—deception. Moreover, once we have seen these consequences, we shall then be able to make explicit those features of self-dec This shall self-decept adequate ac of such an connection which bear Befc culties w‘ of analys reaction beliefs, “0?. know incompat not be a self-dec Plausib. 0f cert “an: of self-deception which incline us to model it on other-deception. This shall be the first step in removing the inclination to view self-deception on the model of other-deception and to provide an adequate account of self-deception which is non-paradoxical. A sketch of such an account will be given towards the end of Chapter Two in connection with a discussion of certain aspects of Freud's theories which bear directly on the topic of self-deception. Before expanding this skeleton account and considering the diffi- culties which confront it, we shall, in Chapter Three, consider a group of analyses in the analytic tradition. All of these analyses arose in reaction to Demos' claim that the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs, all reject this claim and all hold that the self-deceiver does ‘not know or believe the truth though he does believe a falsehood incompatible with the truth. I shall argue that these analyses can- not be adequate precisely because they deny a necessary condition of self-deception, namely, knowledge of the truth, and that their plausibility depends on their having certain affinities with analyses of certain hyperbolic uses of 'reflexive—deception' expressions and of a phenomenon known as 'wishful thinking'. In Chapter Four we shall consider Fingarette's analysis of self-deception, and in the course of doing so we shall refine and modify the account sketched out in Chapter Two. Not only did Fingarette first recognize the limitations on the discussion of self- deception imposed by Demos' paper and reject these limitations, but he also clearly identified the major paradox of self-deception and set about to give an analysis which would avoid this paradox. This led . -‘\l"\' Alf Vii-1"?" It"!"‘ him to foo knowledge ‘ mnsciousnl deception. Much our own. 1 account. 1 altogether truth, but truth excel does this . the self-d. in Chapter n8cessary that the s SeCo exPlicit c all COnSci with other of the Pro Paradox by notion of clear that consciOUS’ cons“C analysis 0 him to focus on the self-deceiver's consciousness rather than his knowledge or beliefs, and he elaborated an account of explicit consciousness which was then incorporated into his analysis of self- deception. Much of Fingarette's useful account will be assimilated into our own. However, we shall reject certain aspects of Fingarette's account. First, though he seems at times to be avoiding the question altogether the question of whether or not the self-deceiver knows the truth, but his real view is that the self-deceiver does not know the truth except in a non-literal, idiomatic sense of 'know'. Not only does this conflict with other parts of his account which entail that the self-deceiver does know the truth, but, as I shall try to establish in Chapter Two of this dissertation, knowledge of the truth is a necessary condition of self-deception. So Fingarette's contention that the self-deceiver does not know the truth must be rejected. Secondly, we shall have to clarify Fingarette's account of explicit consciousness. Fingarette's remarks suggest at times that all consciousness is necessarily explicit consciousness. In connection with other parts of his view, this contention leads us into another of the prominent paradoxes of self-deception. We shall avoid this paradox by re-defining, along lines suggested by Fingarette, the notion of explicit consciousness. This definition will make it clear that to be conscious is not necessarily to be explicitly . conscious, though it is true that to be explicitly conscious is to -be conscious. Once this is recognized and taken into account in the analysis of self-deception, the paradox vanishes. In Che; reason a per: falls within since a nece: have a reaso of the other to provide a someone dece breaking the In Chapter Five I shall offer an account of the kind of reason a person may have for deceiving himself. This account still falls within the task of analyzing the concept of self-deception, since a necessary condition of being a self—deceiver is that one have a reason of this kind. Moreover, since one of the attractions of the other-deception model for self-deception is that it seems to provide an answer to the otherwise difficult question of why someone deceives himself, this account shall be our final step in breaking the hold of the other-deception model. lie Section 2. As : deception a relatic whether c B a in (a When 8 a have a c then it between latter 1 former , I 1Yinq 6 them: the 861 9 Section 2. As noted earlier, Demos models self-deception on other- deception. He begins his paper with a definition of deception as a relation which may hold between any person B and any person C, whether or not B is the same person as C. I will say that 'B lies to (deceives) C' means: B intends to induce a mistaken belief in C, B succeeds in carrying out this intention, and finally B knows (and believes) that what he tells c is false.2 When B and C are distinct persons, and B deceives C, then we have a case of other-deception. When B and C are the same person, then it is self-deception. ’In essence, then, there is no difference between self-deception and other-deception except that in the latter deceiver and deceived are different persons, while in the former, deceiver and deceived are the same person. It should be noted that in his definition Demos treats lying and deceiving as equivalent. The reason is that Demos intends the definition to assimilate lying to deceiving. He recognizes that in "ordinary language" lying and deceiving are not the same. Thus, in 'deceiving', it is the effect that counts-- inducing an erroneous belief in C's mind. But in 'lying', the intention is part of the meaning. I have lied to you although you have not believed me and so have not been misled by me.3 But this difference has the - for Demos - "odd consequence" that "B, in lying to C, may in fact induce a true belief in C's mind."4 I see nothing odd about this consequence nor any advantage to be —--"-w-| Al: gained by to redefir is both a new meanii to explai; A n and the s that B de induce a 3 must '1: know and that he to be fa ElieVe finally. that p. D Wuld S. m'nrrmr—ar-rm In L4- a. "It 10 gained by removing it, but Demos does, and to avoid it, he proposes to redefine 'lying' for his own usage. Thus the above definition is both a stipulative definition of 'lies', intended to impart a new meaning, and an explicative definition of 'deceives', intended to explain an established meaning. A number of consequences follow from the above definition and the supposition that B deceives himself, i.e., the supposition that B deceives C, where B = C. First, since B must intend to induce a false belief in himself and succeed in this intention, B must induce a false belief in himself. Further, since he must know and believe that what he tells himself is false, it follows that he induces a belief in himself which he knows and believes to be false. Thus for some proposition that P, B must know and believe that not-P and induce in himself the belief that P. Hence, finally, B must know and believe that not-P, and also believe that P. Demos thought that this last consequence of his analysis would seem to be paradoxical. Self-deception exists, I will say, when a person lies to himself, that is to say, persuades himself to be- lieve what he knows is not so. In short, self-deception entails that B believes both P and not-P at the same time. Thus self-deception involves an inner conflict, perhaps the existence of a contradiction. But this would seem to be an impossibility...5 Later he says: Believing and disbelieving are pro and con attitudes; they are contraries and therefore it is logically impossible for them to exist at the same time in the same person in the same respect. When B lies to himse to ac admit The f incompatibl "would see! is much no to hold in “descripti a Violatic clearly t} a person ‘ Yet in the Se again how t0 put it It on: ll himself he comes to believe what he knows to be false; to accept this as the description of a fact is to admit a violation of the law of contradiction.6 The first passage above does not state that the holding of incompatible beliefs is logically impossible. Demos says that it "would seem" to be an impossibility. In the second passage he is much more emphatic, and he states that it i§_logically impossible to hold incompatible beliefs at the same time, and also that the "description" that B comes to believe what he knows to be false is a violation of the law of contradiction. This seems to show quite clearly that Demos himself holds that it is logically impossible for a person to hold incompatible beliefs at the same time. Yet I do not think that Demos really held this. Apparently in the second passage as well as the first, he was merely stating again how things 'would seem' to be. And he immediately goes on to put it in those tenms. It would seem, then, that self-deception--lying to oneself--is logically impossible in the way it has been formulated.7 Moreover, if Demos did hold that it is logically impossible for someone to have incompatible beliefs, one would expect him to reject his own analysis of self-deception, for if an inconsistent statement follows from the statements which make up an analysis, then not all of the statements making up the analysis can be true. Demos recognized this, but he did not give up his analysis of self-deception, and one can only reasonably conclude from this that he did not really think that the holding of incompatible beliefs [I4 is a logic he goes or wrong wit} analyses: Per (a) sa: del di m 0c is This pas an anal' YEt he theh h, 12 is a logical impossibility. Immediately after the last statement, he goes on to consider the possibility that there is something wrong with the analysis, and he considers two alternative analyses: Perhaps, then, the description given of it is wrong. (a) A redescription which would avoid violating the sacred law might take the following form: In self- deception, believing P and disbelieving P occur at different and successive times...(b) A further view would be that in self-deception the agreeable belief occupies the conscious mind while the unpleasant one is repressed into the unconscious.8 This passage suggests quite strongly that Demos recognized that an analysis which entails an inconsistent statement must be rejected, yet he did not do so, but instead rejected the two alternatives ‘ n9 mentioned above as not being "in accordance with the evidence , and then he reasserts his own analysis. I conclude that both of the suggested hypotheses are false; the belief and disbelief are simultaneous and both exist in the consciousness of the person.9 Evidently, then, it was not Demos' view that having two incompatible beliefs is logically impossible. He did, however, find the idea of someone holding incompatible beliefs puzzling, and felt that it called fer special explanation. To provide that explanation and remove the puzzle, Demos distinguishes between two "levels of awareness". ...one is simple awareness, the other awareness to- gether with attending or noticing...I may be aware of something without, at the same time, noticing or focus- ing my attention on it. This comes about because I may be distracted by something else, or because I may deliberately ignore it, or because I may not wish to think about it. The not-noticing need not be something that just happens to me.10 it’ll do 13 What makes the holding of incompatible beliefs possible in self- deception is that ...there is an impulse favoring one belief at the expense of its contradictory; and the person who lies to himself, because of yielding to impulse, fails to notice or ignores what he knows to be the case...we are saying that the person who lies to himself be- lieves both P and not-P, and is capable of doing so because he is distracted from the former.11 As we shall see later, there is something quite right about Demos' idea of levels of awareness, the role that attention and distraction play in relation to these levels of awareness, and the part played by impulse. The self-deceiver, while knowing the truth, tries desperately to avoid explicit consciousness of the truth, though he may tolerate, and sometimes pursues, non- explicit consciousness of the truth. To aid him in avoiding explicit consciousness of the truth he tries to preoccupy and distract himself, often going to great extremes to do so. Finally, there is an impulse - fear of explicit consciousness of the truth - which impels the self-deceiver to avoid explicit consciousness of the truth. Demos is wrong, on the other hand, in suggesting that these different levels of consciousness make it possible for the self-deceiver to hold a belief incompatible with what he knows to be true, for the self-deceiver holds no such belief which is relevant to his self-deception. Set a l par ph. of th 14 Section 3. It seems strange, at first sight, that anyone, but especially a philosopher, should find the holding of incompatible beliefs paradoxical or puzzling. After all, one of the tools of the philosophical trade is picking out the inconsistencies in the views of other philosophers. Nor are only philosophers subject to the malady of inconsistency. Theories of nature and mathematical theories are also affected by inconsistency from time to time. For example, the intuitive set theory developed by the mathematician Cantor was shown to be inconsistent. Sometimes we hold incompatible beliefs as a result of our acceptance of two fundamental and incompatible views of the world. For example, many people who know that the earth is roughly spherical in shape persist in thinking at times that travel on the surface of the earth proceeds along straight lines. Sometimes a fundamental and central view buried deeply within the way of life of a people is strikingly incoherent to outsiders. The Azande of Northeastern Africa, for example, hold beliefs in witchcraft which are incompatible. They believe that a limited number of persons in their society are witches. Yet they also believe that the powers of witchcraft can be inherited, and their views as to how it is transmitted commit them to holding that everyone in their society is a witch. Yet almost every fact of their daily lives, both personal and social, is ordered around these beliefs in witchcraft. inco: whic such appr of a one prO} pro; the bel is be: 15 At second sight the resistence to the idea of holding incompatible beliefs is not so surprising. It matters very much whigh_beliefs are involved. For there are pairs of propositions such that one cannot believe (or know) either of them without appreciating their incompatibility. Yet a necessary condition of appreciating the incompatibility of two propositions is that one 22E believe both of them. Hence one cannot believe b2£h_ propositions in an incompatible pair of propositions with the property that one cannot believe either of them unless one appreciates their incompatibility. I shall say that a pair of propositions such that one can believe neither of them unless one appreciates their incompatibility is a flagrantly inconsistent pair. Examples of such pairs would be: Jones is sitting. (a) ' Jones is not sitting. Jones has a hand. (b) Jones has no hands. The tree is burning. (c) The tree is not burning. (d) The ground is damp. The ground is dry. Water is close by. (e) . No water is close by. If an and i he be chan< Stan: bili P088 self so is 90 is 16 If anyone were to utter both propositions in one of these pairs, and we were convinced of his sincerity, we would not say that he believed both propositions. Rather we should say that he changed his mind, or that he mis-spoke, or that he did not under- stand what he was saying and so did not appreciate the incompati- bility in what he said. The existence of flagrantly inconsistent pairs of propositions poses a difficulty for Demos' analysis of self—deception because self-deception frequently involves such pairs: what we want to say that the self-deceiver knows and what we want to say he believes are both members of such a pair. This difficulty explains in part, - perhaps, Demos' saying that it seems logically impossible for someone to hold incompatible beliefs. He had in mind beliefs which are members of a flagrantly inconsistent pair of propositions. It also helps to explain the resistance to his analysis 'by other philosophers. Frederick Siegler, for example, reacted very strongly against Demos' claim that the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs. In his paper, 'Self-Deception'lz, he asks the reader to consider the hypothetical case of Jones, a man who is to die within ten days of an incurable disease. What is in question is whether it is possible for Jones to believe that he is going to die within ten days and also to believe that he is not going to die within ten days. As Siegler notes, a man's own death is something about which he is quite likely to deceive himself. Yet it is impossible, by manipulating the details of the example, 17 to turn it into a case in which we want to say that Jones holds both beliefs. The reason for this is, I suggest, that both of these propositions are members of a flagrantly incompatible pair of propositions. If Jones holds either one of these beliefs, then he cannot fail to appreciate their incompatibility, and so he cannot believe both of them. The existence of flagrantly incompatible pairs of propositions, then, constitutes a solid objection to Demos' analysis of self- deception. But it is not the only objection which can be made along these lines. As Fingarette suggestsl3, Demos apparently recognized that self-deception can only occur under circumstances exceptional enough to allow that the self-deceiver does not appreciate the incompatibility between his beliefsl4; and this is why he felt that the self-deceiver's having incompatible beliefs calls for special explanation. He added to his analysis the statement that the self-deceiver fails to notice or attend to what he knows while noticing and attending to his false belief in order to make clear that the self—deceiver does not appreciate the incompatibility between what he knows and what he falsely believes, and to make clear why the self-deceiver fails to appreciate this incompatibility. For, failing to notice or attend to what he knows, the self-deceiver does not compare what he knows and what he believes, and thus he fails to appreciate their incompatibility. 18 Here is where the second objection to Demos' analysis comes in. As Demos recognized, it is a consequence of his analysis that the self-deceiver believes both P and not-P, and this entails that he does not appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P. But it also segm§_to be a consequence of his analysis that the self-deceiver does appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P. If this is right, Demos' analysis is inconsistent. To see the argument for this, let us consider the kind of other-deception on which Demos models self-deception. Necessarily, when an other—deceiver of this sort sets out to deceive someone through lying to them, the deceiver himself fully appreciates the incompatibility between the false proposition that P and the truth that not-P. He must appreciate this incompatibility if he is to have the purpose of deceiving the other person. For, as purposeful deceiver, his aim is to prevent his intended victim from knowing or believing the truth that not-P by inducing the false belief that P in the victim. The deceiver expects that his victim also fully appreciates the incompatibility between P and not-P, and he counts on this in order to succeed in his aim of keeping the victim from knowing or believing the truth. For if the victim does not appreciate the incompatibility, then there is nothing to prevent him from knowing or believing the truth even if the self-deceiver does induce the false belief that P in him, and thus the deceiver will not have succeeded in his aim of keeping the victim from knowing or believing the truth. On the other 19 hand, if the victim does appreciate the incompatibility and the deceiver succeeds in inducing the false belief that P in him, then he will also have succeeded in keeping him from knowing or believing the truth, for so long as the victim appreciates the incompatibility and believes that P, it will be logically impossible for him to know or believe that not-P. Thus, for the form of other-deception on which Demos models self-deception, the other-deceiver cannot be truly described as purposely inducing a false belief in his victim i2_9£dg£_to deceive the victim unless the other-deceiver appreciates the incompatibility between the truth and the false belief which he induces in the victim. In addition, the other deceiver cannot succeed in his aim, and so cannot be a deceiver, unless the victim appreciates this incompatibility. And when we transpose this feature of the model to self—deception, we get the result that as both purposeful deceiver and as actually deceived, the self-deceiver must appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P, and yet as deceiver he knows and believes the truth that not-P while as deceived he believes that P, and this entails that he does not appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P. For reasons which will become clear later, I shall call this inconsistent result 'the miggg paradox of self-deception'. I believe that Demos sensed the minor paradox of self-deception as being bound up with his analysis, and that this paradox lies 20 behind his saying that the self-deceiver's holding of incompatible beliefs seems to be logically impossible. He tries to ward off the paradox which he sensed by hypothesizing that the self- deceiver does not notice or attend to the truth that not-P. But if the foregoing argument is correct, this move cannot work. The statement that the self-deceiver appreciates the incompatibility is implied by the modeling of self-deception on a certain form of other-deception, and the only way to eliminate this statement is to reject that modeling. Demos, on the other hand, tries to remove the statement by adding £2 the modeling, and so at best he could only succeed in repeating one of the inconsistent statements making up the paradox, without eliminating the other statement. At this point the claim that someone cannot hold two incompatible beliefs and appreciate their incompatibility may be met with more skepticism than before, since one way of getting * Demos out of difficulty would be to deny this claim. First, it might be asked that some argument be given to back up this claim, since it was introduced without any backing. Well, suppose that in the course of a discussion, X were to sincerely assert that Q. Not only does he assert it, but he argues convincingly for it. An hour later, without at all having changed his mind, he sincerely affirms another statement that R and defends it, again with a convincing argument. But Q and R are incompatible. If we appreciate this incompatibility and have taken 21 the discussion all in, we are likely to be somewhat puzzled and will want some explanation for X's inconsistent assertions. In searching for this explanation, we rule out dishonesty on his part, since he seemed to be sincere, he lacked any motive or apparent reason for dishonesty, and he was in general scrupulously honest. Thus we could not conclude, for example, that he had affirmed and defended the proposition that R without caring that it was incompatible with his earlier assertion, and solely for the purposes of displaying his powers of argument, or to defeat the argument of someone he disliked, or to ingratiate himself with someone whose favor he sought and who would be offended if he denied that R. We also rule out the possibility that he mis-spoke when he asserted that Q or when he affirmed that R. The fact that he defended both propositions with arguments militates against this possibility, and we confirm that he did not mis-speak by asking him if he meant to stand by both propositions. Further, we rule out the possibility that he did not understand what he was asserting or what he was affirming. These propositions are not flagrantly incompatible, and so even if he did not appreciate their incompatibility, this would not show that he does not understand them. Moreover, the fact that he argues for both of them so well, knew what evidence counted in favor of them and what evidence counted against them, knew how to meet and defeat the objections offered against them, tends very strongly 22 to show that he understood what he was asserting and affirming. Finally, the possibility that he changed his mind is ruled out both by the fact that he did not remark on such a change, and by the fact that when asked if he stood by both propositions, he answered affirmatively. What alternatives are left open to us now? It seems to me that there are none. By ruling out all of the above possibilities, we can only conclude that he believes both that Q and that R. But once we have concluded this, then mustn't we also conclude that he does not appreciate the incompatibility between Q and R? It seems to me that we must. Suppose that we found out that he had appreciated the incompatibility all along. Wouldn't this auto- matically rule out that he believed both that Q and that R, and throw us back on one of our earlier alternatives, say, that he was being dishonest, or that he mis-spoke in the case of one of these propositions, or that he had changed his mind? The above argument seems very persuasive to me, but to counter it, it might be objected that fully appreciating the incompatibility between Q and R is simply knowing that Q and R are incompatible. But one can certainly believe that P, believe that not-P and know that S, where S is a proposition which does not express any logical relation between P and not-P. So why cannot one know or believe that not-P, believe that P, and know that P and not-P are incompatible? Does the fact that the latter proposition concerns a particular logical relation between P and not-P count for so much? 23 I believe it does. We can gain a better understanding of this if we go further into the other—deceiver's reliance on his victim's appreciation of the incompatibility between P and not—P. The other—deceiver does not just count on this to insure that his victim will be kept ignorant once he believes that P. He also relies on it during the course of inducing in the victim the belief that P. If the victim initially believes that not-P, the deceiver attempts to change his mind. And, because the victim appreciates that P and not-P are incompatible, everything which the deceiver does to make it more credible in the victim's eyes that P simultaneously serves to make it less credible in his eyes that not-P. Otherwise the victim could not be truly said to appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P. Similarly, everything that the deceiver does to make it seem less credible to the victim that not-P serves at the same time to make it more credible that P. The victim's appreciation of the incompatibility between P and not-P is like the hub of a wheel which, if the deceiver is successful in his aims, he manages to turn 180 degrees. If the victim neither believes that P nor believes that not-P at the outset, then the deceiver does not have to turn the wheel so far, say only 90 degrees. And if the victim already believes that P, the deceiver does not have to turn the wheel at all - he tries to lock it in place. Thus one's appreciation of the incompatibility between two propositions is not at all like one's knowledge that S, where 24 S is a non-logical proposition. If the propositions that P and not-P turn in one's mind around one's knowledge that S' in the way they turn in the victim's mind around his appreciation that P and not-P are incompatible, this could only be because 3' i§_ the proposition that P and not-P are incompatible. At this point someone might want to lodge a quite different objection to the charge that Demos' analysis is inconsistent. For I have claimed - a claim which I shall argue for at the beginning of Chapter Two - that when one person aims to deceive another by inducing a false belief in him, the would-be deceiver must necessarily aim at keeping his victim from knowing or believing the truth, and he only succeeds in deceiving the victim if he does keep him from knowing or believing the truth. It was when we transposed this claim onto self-deception that the inconsistency arose. Yet one cannot find this claim mentioned in Demos' analysis of deception, nor is it entailed by Demos' analysis. He explicitly states that the deceiver aims only at inducing a false belief in his victim and that he succeeds if this false belief is induced in the victim. And one cannot get the inconsistency which I have called the 'minor paradox' of self- deception by applying this statement to self-deception. So, even though my claim about the deceiver's aims and the conditions of deception are perhaps correct, and even though Demos perhaps implicitly recognized their correctness and saw dimly the minor paradox which results from applying this claim to self-deception, 25 it seems unfair to charge his analysis of self-deception with inconsistency when the inconsistency does not strictly follow from his analysis. I agree with this objection that the minor paradox of self-deception, however keenly we feel it in connection with his analysis, does not follow from his analysis, and we only sense it there when we read into the analysis something of what we know about the deceiver's essential aims or the conditions necessary for someone's being deceived. But noting this only reveals a quite different difficulty which confronts Demos' analysis of self-deception. The concept of self-deception, quite independently of the other-deception model, requires us to suppose that the self-deceiver appreciates the incompatibility throughout the entire period that he is deceiving himself. If a person who believes that not-P also, failing to appreciate the incompatibility, believes that P, then we would expect him to assert, affirm, and defend both propositions, and certainly we would not expect him to assert, affirm, or defend one of them while refusing to assert, affirm, or defend the other. Yet the latter is typical of the self-deceiver, and it is hard to see how this could be if the self-deceiver does not appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P. This particular problem is only symptomatic of a much larger difficulty. Invariably the self-deceiver satisfies all or most of the behavioral tests for appreciating the incompatibility 26 between P and not-P, including the strongest of such tests. Just as he consistently affirms that P and refuses to affirm that not-P, so he will assent to the proposition that P and not-P are incompatible, he will take arguments in favor of P as arguments against not-P, he will attack arguments in favor of not-P and offer arguments to show that P, he will try to discount evidence favoring not-P and attempt to muster evidence in favor of P. In many cases of self-deception, the suggestion that the self-deceiver does not appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P could only strike one as utterly incredible, and so for those cases at least, Demos' analysis presents a false picture. But my point here is not merely that in some cases of self- deception, the self-deceiver appreciates the incompatibility. It is much more important to note that the connection between a person's being a self-deceiver and his appreciating the incompatibility is not a contingent one. We would not be willing to apply the concept of self-deception to someone who believes that P and believes that not-P, and thus who behaves in the expected way, affirming, asserting, and defending both P and not-P. Unless someone refuses to assert, affirm, and defend one of these propositions while asserting, affirming, and defending the other, or at least gives us the impression that he would behave in this way under appropriate circumstances, we would not be willing to describe him as a self-deceiver. The only conclusion that we can reasonably draw from all of this is that it is a part of the concept of 27 self-deception - as a necessary condition - that the self- deceiver fully appreciates the incompatibility between P and not-P. Thus Demos' analysis of self-deception can never apply to any case of self-deception since it contains the negation of a necessary condition of self-deception. His statement that the self-deceiver believes both P and not-P entails that the self- ~deceiver does not appreciate the incompatibility between P and not-P, and his analysis can be made to apply to cases of self- deception only at the price of inconsistency. Moreover, this same objection will apply to any account which, like Demos', holds that the self-deceiver knows or believes that not-P while also believing that P. Such accounts of self-deception may with propriety be called 'conflict theories' of self-deception, because they all ascribe to the self-deceiver a conflict between what he knows and what he believes. One such conflict theory has been offered by David Pugmire in his article, "Strong' Self—Deception'.15 Pugmire rejects much of Demos' analysis of self-deception, including Demos' suggestion that the self-deceiver purposely 'induces' a false belief in him- self, and also Demos' view that the self—deceiver is able to retain conflicting beliefs because he fails to notice or attend to one of the beliefs. Pugmire does retain that part of Demos account which claims that the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs, and he goes on to ask: 28 What is it, then, about one (grudging) belief which precludes a contrary (cherished) belief? Logic prevents them from both being true, but not from being heid.16 His answer is that one makes the grudging belief "abstract" by not attending to the details of the belief, and here by 'details' he tells us that he does not mean the evidence for the belief, but details of the content of the belief.17 The importance of this capacity to render a belief abstract by keeping in abeyance many details of what makes it true, is that attention to these is what annuls any contrary belief. For, again, it is not absurd to hold conflicting beliefs as such... ...a man who has lost his third government job for alledged incompetence may nurse his self-respect by occupying himself with thoughts of the unfair adversi- ties and mitigating circumstances peculiar to each job and thus keep alive the belief that incompetence was never the reason. At the same time he is haunted by the thought, or awareness (not, in this example, merely the fear) that the charge is correct. At the back of his mind he realizes all along that he is incompetent, but while this may give him a sinking feeling even when he reflects that his excuses are, after all, true, it is remote and lacks the force to destroy altogether his.faith in the excuses. 'Back of the mind' and 'remote' here signify that he believes in, or accepts, his incompetence, but without allowing the full weight of this belief to come to bear. How does he manage this? By shrinking from reminisence about the wrong things. By committing to recall the particulars of the history of painful episodes - tardiness, misplaced documents, grievously mistaken briefs submitted, warnings, the dismissals - which lurk, half obscure, in his memory. To delve into these memories fully and thus grant equal attention to all the acknowledged facts about his past, would be finally to expel the stubborn belief in his past competence, or else he would be mad.18 This passage is interesting, for, as we shall see later, it contains a vivid account of how the self-deceiver controls his thoughts and his consciousness in the face of his knowledge of the 29 truth. But it is confusing too, for it seems that what the self-deceiver does ignore after all is the evidence favoring the repugnant belief, and not only the details of the content of the belief. Moreover, Pugmire tacitly assumes that the self- deceiver appreciates the incompatibility between his beliefs, else how could he expect that attending to the evidence in favor of one of the beliefs would serve to expel the contrary belief? Finally, the whole process of rendering a belief 'abstract' seems to be directed, as with Demos' suggestion that the self— deceiver does not attend to one of his beliefs, towards making clear that the self-deceiver does not appreciate the incom- patibility between his beliefs. And, since Pugmire claims that the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs, this does follow from his analysis. However, it only does so at the expense of making his analysis inapplicable to any cases of self-deception, since a necessary condition of self-deception is that the self- deceiver appreciate the relevant incompatibilities.19 CHAPTER TWO. Self-Deception and Other Deception. Section 1. We noted earlier that the self-deceiver necessarily aims at keeping the deceived from knowing or believing the truth, and he is successful in deceiving his victim only if the victim is kept from knowing or believing the truth. This does not mean, of course, that deceivers achieve their aims only by means of inducing a false belief in their victim, for there are many other ways of deceiving someone than inducing a false belief in him: through various sorts of concealment, through pretending, through failing to mention something which one knows the deceived would take an interest in and would want to know. This view of deception contrasts strongly with Demos' own view, which maintains that purposely inducing a false belief in the deceived is essential to deception and which omits altogether mention of purposely keeping the deceived from knowing of believing the truth as a necessary condition of deception. This error in Demos' analysis of deception does not directly affect his analysis of self-deception, but it does greatly diminish the value of his explanation of why self-deception strikes us as being paradoxical. Before showing why this is so, however, I shall try to make good the claim that Demos' analysis of other-deception is mistaken. Suppose that Johnny has broken his mother's prized antique vase. He hides the pieces, and stands between his mother and the 30 31 table on which the vase stood, thus blocking her view of the table. As a consequence of his doing these things, Johnny's mother does not know or believe that her vase has been broken. Moreover, assuming that his mother appreciates the incompatibility between her vase's being broken and its not being broken, the mother may continue to believe that her vase has not been broken, and we can say that she does so in consequence of Johnny's actions, since had he not done these things she would have learned that her vase was broken, and, appreciating the incompatibility, would cease to believe that her vase was not broken. This is not, however, to say that Johnny 'induced' the belief in her, because she already had the belief prior to Johnny's effort to deceive her.. This is clearly a case of purposeful deception. The example can be manipulated to show that the deceived believing a false- hood is not a necessary condition of deception. Let us suppose that Johnny is a clumsy and careless boy, prone to accidents. Knowing this, his mother is afraid to leave him alone in the house with her prized vase, but on this particular day she feels it is necessary to go out of the house and leave him unattended in it. ‘She returns home full of apprehension, not at all sure that her vase has survived her absence, and, indeed, suspecting the worst - suspecting, that is, that misfortune in the guise of her awkward and careless son has overtaken her dear vase. Let us further add that Johnny broke the vase in his mother's absence. He hid the pieces, and when his mother returned he 32 anticipated her concern and her intention of immediately checking up on the vase. ‘He met his mother at the door, engaged her in conversation and managed to unobtrusively precede her into the room where the ill-fated vase had been kept. Moreover, fortune was smiling on Johnny, for during his mother's absence, the new set of curtains which she had ordered and long awaited had arrived. Johnny mentioned the delivery, and this distracted her both from her intention of checking on the vase and from noticing the obvious- ness with which Johnny was positioning himself between her and the table on which the vase had stood. She hurried to the new drapes and spent the rest of the afternoon putting them up. Again a case of deception. But certainly it would be wrong to say that Johnny's mother believed that her vase was not broken, for she had no such belief. Both before returning home and afterwards, she neither believed that the vase was broken nor believed that it was not broken. She wasn't sure one way or the other, and this caused her concern. Johnny managed to remove the concern by replacing it with a new and very different one, but he obviously did not make her more certain than before that her vase had not been broken. So Johnny's mother did not believe that her vase was not broken, yet Johnny did deceive her, for he aimed at and succeeded in keeping her from knowing or believing the truth. That keeping the deceived from knowing or believing the truth is a necessary condition of deception can also be shown by £3 33 manipulating the example. If we suppose that Johnny's mother does, in spite of his efforts to prevent it, learn that her vase has been broken upon returning home, then we cannot say that Johnny deceived her, though it would be true that he attempted to deceive her. Or, if we suppose that she does not know or believe that her vase was broken, but that this is not a consequence of Johnny's efforts - because, say, she was distracted from the first, was not concerned about the vase, had no intention of checking up on it, did not even look in the direction of the table on which it had stood - then we cannot truly say that Johnny has deceived her, though again he attempted to deceive her. The errors in Demos' account of other-deception greatly diminish the value of his explanation of why self-deception strikes us as paradoxical. Had Demos not commited these errors, then he might have been able to bring to light in a much clearer way the minor paradox of self-deception. Demos was right in thinking that we do tacitly model self-deception on other-deception. Once we have done so, the minor paradox of self-deception follows, and we often feel its bite. However, this is by no means the only nor the most troublesome paradox we feel in connection with self- deception, but because Demos had misconstrued other-deception, one does not even find a hint in his explanation of these other paradoxes. There are, in fact, two such paradoxes, which I shall call, respectively, 'the first major paradox of self-deception', and, 'the second major paradox of self-deception'. We can clearly display the first major paradox of self- deception if we transpose the corrected analysis of other-deception 34 onto self-deception, and then assume, as Demos does, that the self- deceiver knows and continues to know the truth. It follows immediately that the self-deceiver both knows and does not know the truth, since as deceiver he knows the truth, and as deceived, he is kept from knowing the truth. What I am suggesting is that we tacitly model self-deception on other-deception, we feel compelled to do so, and this leads us directly to the contradictory conclusion - the first major paradox of self-deception - that the self-deceiver knows and does not know the truth. We tacitly, and sometimes explicitly, recognize this contradiction. Once we have done so, ,we have only two alternatives. First, we can deny that self-deception ever does occur on the grounds that it is logically impossible for anyone to deceive himself. At most, a person could only attempt to deceive himself, but he could never succeed since this would entail his knowing and not knowing the truth. This alternative is closed off to us, however, because we recognize that there are self-deceivers, that people not only attempt to deceive themselves, but frequently succeed in doing so. The second alternative would be to deny the premises from which the contradiction obtains, that is, to reject the modeling of self-deception on other-deception. This alternative also seems to be closed off to us, though, since we feel strongly compelled to model self-deception on other-deception. Part of the difficulty is that the modeling is tacit. We do not recognize that we are 35 modeling self-deception on other-deception. But this is not the whole of it, for the construal of self—deception on the model of other-deception seems to be demanded by certain features of the self—deceiver's behavior, thought, and circumstances. These features confirm both sides of the contradiction that the self? deceiver knows and does not know the truth, and even confirm that he purposely keeps himself from knowing the truth. This compels us to model self-deception on other-deception, to think of it in a certain way, and because we feel compelled to think of it in this way, we view the contradiction as following from the nature of selfrdeception by logical necessity. Then, because we do see it as a matter of logical necessity, we do not recognize that we are only thinking of it in a certain way, on the model of other- deception, and we do not recognize alternatives to this way of thinking, we do not recognize that the contradiction can be eliminated by changing the way we think about self-deception., The result is that we view the self-deceiver as someone with impossible aims who achieves the impossible. We are left in a state of tension, for we feel that self—deception cannot exist, and yet we must also recognize that it does exist. It is when we are in this state of tension that self-deception strikes us as deeply and inherently paradoxical. Freud displays this tension in one of his earliest psycho- «analytic works, Studien fiber Hysterie, which he co—authored with .Josef Breuer. In conjunction with several essays on hysteria, the 52’ (n tn 36 book presents a number of case histories, all but one by Freud. The remarks Freud makes in the course of one of these concern us most here. As Freud tells us, Miss Lucy R was a governess for the children of a factory superintendent whose wife had died and left him a widow. She came to Freud complaining of mild depression, lassitude, and being persistently tormented, by certain smells, most noticeably the odor of burnt pudding. Freud took these 'subjective sensations' of smell to be hallucinatory and diagnosed them to be symptoms of hysteria. In trying to determine their origin, Freud learned from Miss Lucy R that the smell of burnt pudding had an objective basis, and had first occurred two months earlier, when she was teaching the children to cook. A letter arrived from her mother, but the children came running.out of the room and playfully snatched it from her hand, refusing to give it back to her. While they were playing, the pudding they were cooking began to burn, and gave off an intense odor. Freud also learned that at the same time, Miss Lucy R had been planning to leave her position as governess. She had had 'some difficulties with the housekeeper, the maid, and the cook, and when she complained to the father and to the grandfather of the children, she did not receive the support she expected, so she liad given them her resignation. The children's father reluctantly éaccepted her resignation, asking her to reconsider it for two vweeks before making a final decision. It was during this period c>f time that the letter from her mother arrived, and as she intended tun return to live with her mother, the letter reminded her of her 37 intention. At the same time she was touched by the affection which the children were displaying towards her, and saddened at the thought of leaving them. Yet Freud did not think that this connection between her feelings and the odor of burnt pudding could adequately explain her hysterical symptoms. There was as yet nothing in this story to explain why these contrary affects - her sorrow at leaving the children, and the mortification she felt from her treatment by members of the household - should be converted into hysterical symptoms. Freud writes: Now I already knew from the analysis of similar cases that before hysteria can be acquired for the first time one essential condition must be fulfilled: an idea must intentionally bg_§epressed from consciousness and excluded from associative modification. In my view this intentional repression is also the basis for the conversion, whether total or partial, of the sum of excitement. The sum of excitation, being cut off from psychical association, finds its way all the more easily along the wrong path to somatic innervation. The basis for the repression itself can only be a feeling of unpleasure, the incompatibility between the single idea to be repressed and the dominant mass of ideas constituting the ego. The repressed idea takes its revenge, however, by becoming pathogenic. I accordingly inferred from Miss Lucie H's having succombed to hysterical conversion at the moment in question that among the determinants of the trauma there must have been one which she had sought intentionally to leave in obscurity and had made efforts to forget. If her fondness for the children and her sensitiveness on the subject of the other members of the household were taken together, only one conclusion could be reached. I was bold enough to inform my patient of this interpretation. I said to herz'I cannot think that these are all the reasons for your feelings about the children. I believe that you are really in love with your employer, the Director, though perhaps without being aware of it yourself, and that you have a secret hope of taking their mother's place in actual fact. And then we must remember your sensitiveness towards the servants after having lived with them peacefully th: he Se 38 for years. You're afraid of their having some inkling of your hopes and making fun of you.‘ She answered in her usual laconic fashion: 'Yes, I think that's true.‘ 'But if you knew you loved your employer, why didn't you tell me?‘ - 'I didn't know - or rather, I didn't want to know. I wanted to drive it out of my head and not think of it again; and I be- lieve latterly I have been successful.‘1 There are two things which are especially worthy of note at this point. First, Miss Lucy R has apparently been deceiving herself about her love for her employer and her hopes towards him. Secondly, as Freud concludes, she apparently knew that she was in love with her employer and that she harbored these hopes. Even though she at first denies this - 'I didn't know' - she immediately retracts this statement, saying, 'or rather, I didn't want to know.‘ To the last paragraph quoted above, Freud indexes an interesting footnote. The footnote indicates the extent to which he himself had been thinking of self-deception on the model of other-deception and the puzzlement which he felt as a result. I have never managed to give a better description than this of the strange state of mind in which one knows and does not know a thing at the same time. It is clearly impossible to understand it unless one has been in such a state oneself. I myself have had a remarkable experience of this sort, which is still clearly before me. If I try to recollect what went on in my mind at the time I can get hold of very little. What happened was that something did not fit in at all with my expectation; yet I did not allow what I saw to disturb my fixed plan in the least, though the perception should have put a stop to it. I was unconscious of any contradiction in this; nor was I aware of my feelings of repulsion, which nevertheless must un- doubtedly have been responsible for the perception producing no psychical effect. I was afflicted with that blindness g£_the seeing eye, which is so astonishing in the attitude of mothers to their daughters, husbands to their wives, and rulers to their favorites.2 39 This passage leaves little doubt that the "strange state of mind" of which Freud speaks is self-deception,"that blindness of the seeing eye," and it is clear that he regarded Miss Lucie R as being in this state. What is remarkable about the passage is that Freud chooses to describe this 'state' in a contradictory fashion, as a state "in which one knows and does not know a thing at the same time." I suggest that the reason he chose this contradictory mode of description is because he had been thinking of self- deception on the model of other-deception. This hypothesis is born out by other parts of the passages quoted above, and by the views that Freud elaborated in Studien fiber Hysterie, In these passages we find Freud already appealing to embryonic concepts of resistance and defence, and to the concept of repression. These concepts were to mature and play a central role in his later, more fully developed theory of the unconscious. As Freud puts it in Studien fiber Hysteria, resistance comes about because "a psychical force in the patients" has "opposed the pathogenic idea from becoming conscious (being remembered)."3 This psychic force had "driven the pathogenic idea out of association [with the ideas united in the ego] and was not opposing its return to memory."4 This psychic force Freud termed 'repression', and at this point in the development of his ideas, Freud thought of the repression of such an idea as intentional and conscious on the part of the patient, as "a 'not wanting to know' - a not wanting which :might be to a greater or less extent conscious."5 40 Moreover, repression has a motive, a purpose, and its purpose is defence against an unbearable idea. Freud found that repressed ideas "were all of a distressing nature, calculated to arouse the affects of shame, of self-reproach, of psychical pain, and the feeling of being harmed; they were all of a kind that one would prefer not to have experienced, and that one would rather forget."6 These painful affects will be felt by the patient if he allows the unbearable idea to become associated with the rest of the ideas which constitute the ego. Freud speaks of an idea which evokes such a "feeling of unpleasure"7 when united with the ego as incompatible with the ego, and this is why he speaks of the dis- agreeable feeling itself as an 'incompatibility' between the idea and the ego.8 In order to prevent feeling the unpleasure, the patient represses the idea, thus preventing it from becoming united with the rest of the ideas in the ego, and thus preventing the idea from becoming conscious. In short, repression is a defence against feeling the painful affect which accompanies an idea. But the patient must pay a price for this defence, In hysteria the painful affect (which Freud thought of as containing a quantitative element, a 'sum of excitation') does not simply cease to exist even though it is stifled and prevented from expression through speech or action - the normal roads to "somatic innervation".9 Rather, on Freud's view, the sum of excitation is squite literally converted into the hysterical symptoms, e.g., into 'hallucinatory smells of burnt pudding. Thus the sum of excitation 41 is quite literally the 'stuff' from which hysterical symptoms are made, and in exchange for not feeling unpleasure, the patient must put up with the symptoms.10 Thus hysteria is always bound up with self-deception. The hysterical patient knows something, e.g., that she is in love with her master, but consciousness of what is known is unbearable, i.e., is accompanied by unpleasure. To avoid this disagreeable feeling, the patient represses the idea, crowds it out of his mind, and so enters into that "peculiar state in which one knows something and at the same time does not know it." To be fair to Freud, I do not think he intended this statement to be construed literally. There is implicit in his view a solution to the first major paradox of self-deception, for repression need not be construed as 'not knowing' in anything more than a' metaphorical sense of 'not knowing'. Freud indicates that he has such a solution in mind, for he tells us that "The not knowing‘ of the hysterics was really a 'not wanting to know' - a not wanting which might be to a greater or less extent conscious."ll My aim here has been to show that Freud was puzzled about self-deception, that the source of his puzzlement was the first major paradox of self-deception, that the paradox arose because he ‘was thinking of self-deception on the model of other-deception, and thus that for him there was a problem for which the above remark ,provides a solution. That he was puzzled is shown by the fact that ‘he chose to describe self-deception in such seemingly self- contradictory terms, that he speaks of it as a "strange state" - I ..__ SUIT soul lies: 5 5 (1“ al of how him do fo re ti. "(j 42 surely an expression of perplexity - and by his saying that it could only be "understood" if one had oneself been in such a state. Apparently his conviction that this state even exists had been difficult to obtain, and he anticipated that others would encounter a like difficulty. Clearly Freud's perplexity has nothing to do with the attribution of incompatible beliefs to his hysterical patients. This illustrates how far off the track were Demos and the philosophers who followed him in locating the paradoxes of self-deception in the seeming impossibility of holding incompatible beliefs. This could not help but leave a deep mark on the discussion to follow. Philosophers do not attempt to elucidate or analyze concepts aimlessly or simply for the fun or interest of it. One, though only one,of their reasons for analysis and elucidation is that a concept is perplexing, that it seems to be bound up in paradox. The aim of elucidation and analysis is to remove the perplexity and the paradox. But the first step in doing this must always be to make explicit precisely what is paradoxical about the concept, and the next step must be to make clear what it is about the concept which invites a paradoxical construal of it. Then, and only then, can the paradox Jbe removed and an analysis of the concept be provided which does justice to the misleading features of the concept without plunging (one into perplexity. Neither Demos nor, until Fingarette, any of the philosophers Vvho followed him questioned the view that self-deception is in! of ('1‘ 43 paradoxical because of the seeming impossibility of holding incompatible beliefs. The consequence of this is that in much of their work, paradox and analysis pass one another by. For the most part these philosophers were oblivious to the features of self-deception which invites one to construe it on the model of other-deception. The result was predictable. Their analyses of self-deception do not do justice to these features, and little headway was made toward resolving the major paradoxes of self- deception. Moreover, even when, as with Demos and Pugmire, their attention was drawn to some of these features, they were misconstrued, and seen, for example, as part of an effort which makes possible the holding of incompatible beliefs. Demos' misconstrual of other-deception contributed directly to this state of affairs. Had he provided an adequate account of it, the first major paradox of self-deception would have been glaringly obvious to him and all concerned. Yet no one who followed Demos, except John King-Farlow, questioned Demos' treatment of other- deception, and King-Farlow does not raise the crucial objections mentioned above.12 44 Section 2. What is it about self-deception which so strongly inclines us to view it on the model of other-deception? Or, to put the question in another way, what are the features of self-deception which compel us to view it within the Conceptual frame-work of other- deception, and to describe and analyze it in the terminology appropriate to other-deception? Indeed, why do we want to speak of self~deception as 'deception' at all? Part of the answer to these questions is given in the fact that some of our criteria for saying that someone is deceiving him- self are that he knows the truth, that he is feigning ignorance of the truth, pretending not to know it, and, if he gives the impression of believing the contradictory or contrary of what he knows to be true, that he is only pretending to believe it and does not really believe it. To see this, consider the following example, the case of N who has been deceiving himself in 'thinking' that his wife has been faithful to him. Let us consider just what our grounds for the saying that he is deceiving himself might be. First, we should typically know that N is quite aware of a large body of evidence which points strongly, perhaps overwhelmingly, to his wife's unfaithfulness. Not only does this supply fuel for our suspicion that N knows that his wife has been unfaithful, but it supports our view that N is feigning ignorance of this, that he is only pretending 45 not to know that she has been unfaithful, and that he is pretending to believe that she has remained faithful to him. Note, however, that it is not merely a matter of fact, perhaps coincidental, that these grounds support the claim that N knows that his wife has been unfaithful as well as the claim that N is deceiving himself. If for some reason these grounds ceased to support the former claim, they would automatically cease to support the latter claim as well. Thus, for example, if it became clear to us that N does not appreciate the force of the evidence, as he would have to if his knowledge of the evidence were to provide support for the claim that he knows that his wife has been unfaithful to him, then not only does his awareness of the evidence cease to support the claim that he knows that she has been unfaithful, but it also ceases to support the claim that he is deceiving himself. This shows that these grounds are relevant to the attribution of self-deception because they are relevant to the attribution of knowledge. Moreover, this connection does not exist because we know, as a matter of observation and experience, that all or most self-deceivers know the truth. For unless there are some grounds such as those mentioned above, or those to be mentioned below, which do support the attribution of knowledge, there is no justification at all for making an attribution of self-deception as opposed to an attribution of simple ignorance and belief in a falsehood. This can only mean that knowledge of the truth is a necessary condition of self-deception. 46 In addition to the above grounds, we might also have discovered that N consistently avoids or tries to avoid situations in which he would or is likely to become aware of further evidence that his wife has been unfaithful, e.g., he tries to avoid situations in which he might surprise his wife and her lover alone together. Few people would deny, I think, that this is relevant and supports the attribution of self-deception. But here again, the question is what makes his avoidance of these situations relevant. And the answer is that it supports the contention that N is identifying these situations as such, and avoids or tries to avoid them because each fresh piece of evidence of which he becomes aware makes it more difficult for him to maintain the pretense that he believes his wife to have been faithful and does not know of her infidelity to him. But if, for example, we found out that the only reason he avoided these situations is because in each case he believed that he would meet up with a woman whom he intensely despised, then his avoidance of these situations would cease to support the claim that he is deceiving himself. The fellowing passage, pointed out by Martin Benjamin of Michigan State University, aptly illustrates the self-deceiver's avoidance of evidence situations. The passage is from Albert Speer's memoirs, Inside the Third Reich. One day, sometime in the summer of 1944, my friend Karl Hanke, the Gauleiter of Lower Silesia, came to see me. In earlier years he had told me a great deal about the Polish and French campaigns, had spoken of the dead and wounded, the pain and agonies, and in talking about these things had shown himself a man of sympathy and directness. This time, sitting in the green leather easy chair in my 47 office, he seemed confused and spoke falteringly, with many breaks. He advised me never to accept an invitation to inspect a concentration camp in Upper Silesia. Never, under any circumstances. He had seen something there which he was not permitted to describe and moreover could not describe. I did not query him, I did not query Himmler, I did not query Hitler, I did not speak with personal friends. I did not investigate--for I did not want to know what was happening there. Hanke must have been speaking of Auschwitz. During those few seconds, while Hanke was warning me, the whole responsibility had become a reality again. Those seconds were uppermost in my mind when I stated to the international court at the Nuremburg Trial that as an important member of the leader- ship of the Reich, I had to share the total responsibility for all that had happened. For from that moment on, I was inescapably contaminated morally; from fear of dis- covering something which might have made me turn from my course, I had closed my eyes. This deliberate blindness outweighs whatever good I may have done or tried to do in the last period of the war. Those activities shrink to nothing in the face of it. Because I failed at that time, I still feel, to this day, responsible for Auschwitz in a wholly personal sense.13 Speer's confidence also echoes the cryptic confession of self- deception made by Freud in the footnote quoted on page 37. If our example is a typical one, there will be a third form of evidence which supports the attribution of self-deception to N, which I shall call 'bad acting'. What ties this otherwise quite heterogeneous form of evidence together and makes it supportive of the claim that N is deceiving himself is that it represents a flaw in N's portrayal of himself as a man who doesn't know of his wife's infidelity and who believes that she has been faithful. N tries to say and do only what he would say and do if he did not know that his wife has been unfaithful to him, and if he believed her to be faithful. But unlike a man who really acts in such ignorance and on the basis 48 of such a belief, N must guide his behavior in conformity to his conception of how he would behave if he were such a man. If his conception is flawed or unrealistic, or his ability to realize it limited, or if he is prevented from exercising this ability or forgets to do so, then this will be reflected in his behavior. As I said above, such evidence is otherwise quite diverse. It ranges from the ways in which he treats his wife to the things which he says and the ways he says them, to aspects of his physical bearing and composure. Thus, e.g., N may become intensely angered at his wife over a very trifling matter. Because this not only represents a departure from the way he treated her prior to her infidelity, but represents a departure from the way we expect some- one to respond to such a trifle, we may suspect that the trifle is only being used as a pretext by N, that the real cause of his anger is his wife's infidelity, and that he has seized this opportunity to vent the anger and take some small measure of revenge. It is true, of course, that this need not necessarily be the reason for his angry outburst; he may, e.g., be taking out on his wife anger at a fellow employee or his boss. But we must keep in mind that for us at present it is not a question of whether the interpretation we place on his anger is ultimately the correct one. What matters is that it is because we can place such an interpretation on his anger without its being ruled out by other considerations, that it supports the claim that N is deceiving himself. If we believed otherwise, if we believed, e.g., that N was just taking out on his wife anger 49 at his boss because she is a convenient target, then we should no longer regard this episode as supporting the claim that N is deceiving himself. There are also aspects of N's behavior which might be dubbed 'overacting'. Here N resembles Sartre's waiter. Let us consider this waiter in the cafe. His move- ment is quick and forward, a little too precise, a little too rapid. He comes forward toward the patrons with a step a little too quick. He bends forward a little too eagerly; his voice, his eyes express an interest a little too solicitous for the order of the customer.’ Finally there he returns, trying to imitate in his walk the inflexible stiffness of some kind of automaton while carrying his tray with the recklessness of a tightrope walker by putting it in a perpetually unstable, perpetually broken equilibrium which he perpetually re-establishes by a light movement of the arm and hand. All his behavior seems to us a game. He applies himself to chaining his movements as if they were mechanisms, the one regulating the other; his gestures and even his voice seem to be mechanisms; he gives himself the quickness and pitiless rapidity of things. He is playing, he is amusing himself. But what is he playing? We need not watch long before we can explain it; he is playing at being a waiter in a cafe.14 Thus, N, in contrast to his surliness described above, may at times appear overly considerate of his wife, overly solicitous of her feelings and comfort, and overly congenial toward her. Again this conflicts both with how N has treated her in the past and with our expectations concerning how men in general treat their wives. Insofar as we can construe N's exaggerated behavior as an attempt to cover up his real feelings towards his wife, and ultimately his knowledge of her infidelity, we take it to support the claim that he is deceiving himself. 50 In this category of overacting also belong those performances which would lead us to characterize N as "trying too hard to be convincing". In a discussion,for example, he might seize upon an oblique reference to marital relationships to deliver a protracted speech about the importance of trust in marriage, culminating in an emotional declaration of hi§_wife's trustworthiness and fidelity. Such a performance can be both astonishing and embarrassing. It supports the attribution of self-deception just because it tends to show that N does not believe what he is telling us, and that he knows or believes that his wife has been unfaithful. Indeed, even if we had no other evidence that N was deceiving himself, we might begin to strongly suspect it as a result of this performance, for it tends to show that N himself does not believe her to have been faithful, and we would regard him as in a position to know about his wife. Finally, we should note that certain aspects of N's demeanor and bearing support the claim that he is deceiving himself when these can be construed as indications that he is only pretending not to know that his wife has been unfaithful and that he is only pretending to believe that she has been faithful. All of these aspects are either expressions of emotion, or indicate that N is trying to inhibit the expression of some emotion, or are recognized behavioral or physiological concommitments of concealment, and when they are considered in conjunction with other features of N's circumstances and behavior, they tend to support the claim that he is deceiving himself. Here we may include such things as blushing, perspiration, stammering, changes in the pitch or loudness of the voice, rapid or 51 labored breathing, tapping of the fingers or feet, fidgeting, inability to look at others, sheepish glances, fixed smiles, and defensive postures such as drawing in the neck and shoulders, holding the arms close to the body, crossing of the legs or holding them tightly together. Suppose, for example, that a friend visits N at his house. When the friend asks the whereabouts of N's wife, who is not present, he evokes a curious reaction in N. N blushes slightly, looks away from the friend, and haltingly answers, in a slightly strained, low- pitched voice, that his wife is out shopping. At the same time, he changes position in his chair, crosses his legs, and, slightly, almost imperceptibly, hunches in his neck and shoulders. N may not be specifically aware of any of these reactions - feeling mainly tension and discomfort, but the friend, who knows of the wife's infidelity, and who would probably have difficulty saying precisely what it was about N's response which caught his attention, may surmise that the question caught N by surprise, that it embarrassed him, that it aroused his anger, and that he was concealing something, not only his anger but the truth of his wife's whereabouts. He may further surmise that N did not believe that his wife was out shopping, but knew or suspected that she was with her lover, was angered by this, and was concealing both the truth of her whereabouts and his anger. 52 Section 3. There are other sorts of evidence we might have fer saying that N is deceiving himself, but enough has been said to show that the evidence we have considered is evidence because it supports the contentions that N knows his wife has been unfaithful to him, that he is concealing this knowledge, and that he is feigning ignorance of her infidelity in order to conceal his knowledge of it. These contentions state necessary conditions of self-deception. This explains in part why we want to use the words 'deceive' and 'deception' in describing the self-deceiver. To conceal something is to attempt to deceive, though it is not necessarily to succeed in deception. Hence, necessarily, the self-deceiver attempts to deceive concerning his knowledge of the truth. Emphasizing this raises a further and more crucial question. From whgm_is the self-deceiver concealing his knowledge of the truth? Whgm_is he trying to deceive? Almost everything we have said so far about the self-deceiver would support the claim that he is concealing his knowledge of the truth from others and that he is trying to deceive others. We must now look at those features of self-deception which show or tend to show that he cannot be concealing the truth or his knowledge of the truth from others, and that he can only be concealing these things from himself. However, I should make clear before going into this that whereas I accept the foregoing arguments and their conclusions, I do not accept either the arguments to follow or their conclusions. In every case they are either fallacious arguments S3 or they contain false premises, and in some cases these defects are hard to conceal when the argument is made explicit. This obviousness of their defects does not, so far as I can see, diminish my claim that we are often persuaded by these arguments or similar ones, for these arguments are never made explicit. They are sometimes alluded to in the sketchiest terms or one finds hints here and there by means of which the arguments can be reconstructed, but they have never been laid out fully. When they are in this shadowy state, they can be most insidiously persuasive. In trying to resolve the paradoxes of self—deception, our task will be to expose these arguments, and so, to refute them. First, we should note that the self-deceiver appears not only to be concealing his knowledge of the truth, but the truth itself. There are a number of considerations which contribute to this appearance. If, for example, the self-deceiver is feigning belief in the Opposite of the truth, he will deny the truth, assert its opposite, rationalize away the evidence supporting the truth, provide evidence and arguments in support of the opposite, and so on. Such behavior is typical of someone who is concealing the truth. More- over, even if he is not feigning belief in a falsehood, his very reticence and apparent obliviousness to the truth seem to be an effort not to provoke attention to it or an effort to draw attention away from it. Furthermore, in otherfdeception concealing one's knowledge of the truth is typically secondary to concealing the truth. One conceals one’s knowledge of the truth in order to conceal the truth. The reason for this is obvious enough, since if X is concealing 54 the truth that Q from Y, and Y discovers that X holds or believes that Q, then Y may begin to suspect that it is true that Q and that X is trying to conceal this from him. And, of course, if X is concealing the truth that Q from Y, and Y discovers that X knows that Q, then gg_ip§2_Y will have discovered that Q, since Y cannot know that X knows that Q unless Y knows that Q. Finally, the self- deceiver is actually concealing the truth as well as his knowledge of the truth in certain circumstances. We find, then, that we can construe the self-deceiver's behavior as an attempt not only to conceal his knowledge of the truth but the truth itself, and this construal is reinforced by expectations derived from typical cases of other-deception. As a result, we want to see the self-deceiver as concealing the truth, and this becomes, as it were, a datum for us. But now we run into a problem. A striking feature of many cases of self-deception is that the truth is obvious to everyone, except, apparently the self- deceiver. In N's case, for example, everyone else may be fully aware that N's wife has been unfaithful to him. Only N presents the appearance of being unaware of this. But under these conditions N would know that he has little hope of concealing his wife's infidelity from others. There would be no point to it. So from whom is he trying to conceal the truth and his knowledge of it? It can only be himself. This is reinforced from a different direction, for we have a pretty good idea of what the self-deceiver's purposes are. Often self-deceivers themselves confess, as did Spear and Miss Lucy R, 55 that they did not want to know the truth, either because this knowledge was painful to them, or because they feared that knowing it would divert them from some pre-determined purposes, courses of action, or even a way of living. And they they also report that in order to escape the pain or continue on their courses they "blinded" themselves to the truth. As with Speer, they have avoided becoming acquainted with fresh evidence, they have not sought it out, and they did not seek out details of the truth. As a result of his friend's visit, even if he did not know it before, Speer knew that atrocities were being committed in a certain concentration camp in Upper Silesia. Yet Speer carefully avoided investigation of this, he carefully avoided further substantiation, and he carefully avoided learning any details about what was going on in this camp. Moreover, like Pugmire's incompetent official, the self-deceiver avoids dwelling on the evidence and details which he does possess. If he thinks about the matter at all, he dwells on those pieces of evidence which support the opposite of the truth. Finally, as did Miss Lucy R, the self-deceiver tries to "crowd" thought of the truth from his mind, never to think of it at all. In Freud's terminology, the self-deceiver intentionally represses the idea of the truth from his consciousness. Henceforth, however, I shall say that the self- deceiver suppresses the idea of the truth from his consciousness or that he suppresses his thought of the truth. The reason for this different tenm is that Freud altered his concept of repression as his views developed, and I do not want suppression to be confused with repression as it was to be later understood. 56 The self-deceiver, then, does not want to know the truth, and his avoidance of evidence and details, his suppression of his thought of the truth seem to have only one object: to blind himself to the truth, and thus to escape the pain accompanying this knowledge or to allow him to continue in pursuit of certain aims, on a certain course of action, or in a particular way of life. Thus his purposes in concealing the truth have nothing to do with deceiving others: they are aimed at deceiving himself. This seems even more clear when we come to focus on certain details of the self-deceiver's suppression of his thought, for then we find apparently conclusive reasons for saying that the self-deceiver cannot be concealing the truth or his knowledge of the truth from others, but must be concealing these things from himself. Suppression of thought is an essential component of self-deception. As we have seen the self-deceiver's behavior and circumstances indicate he is concealing something. But from whom? We have already seen that there are strong reasons for saying that he is not concealing something from others, but from himself. The self-deceiver's suppression of his thought clinches this interpretation, for thoughts are secret and private: others may have access to the self-deceiver's speech and behavior, but not his thoughts - unless, of course, he wishes them to have such access, and conveys his thoughts to them. But he need not do so, he can withhold them if he likes, and so his suppression of his own thoughts cannot be directed towards concealing something from others. Yet, since he is 57 concealing something, surely he must be concealing it from someone. And since his efforts extend to those private realms to which only he has access, he must be concealing it from himself. Take Pugmire's incompetent official, for example. We can well understand why he would withhold evidence of his incompetence from others if he wanted to conceal his incompetence from them. But if his purpose is to conceal his incompetence from others, why should' he refuse to dwell on this evidence in the privacy of his thoughts? Others will not learn of this evidence or have their attention re-directed to it in a revealing fashion if he only thinks about it. Hence his suppression of this evidence seems to have only one object. We seem forced to regard him as withholding this evidence from. himself, in an attempt to keep himself from being reminded of it, and so from seeing it in.a revealing way. Once we have reached this conclusion, we pass almost immediately over into the self-deceiver's willful ignorance. In cases of other-deception there is a difference between concealing the truth from someone and actually deceiving him. X may conceal the truth from Y, but this concealment may not have its intended effect, Y may not be taken in, and Y may learn the truth in spite of ~the fact that X is concealing it from him. But in self-deception there seems to be no room for hitches of this kind at all: to conceal the truth from oneself, to attempt to deceive oneself, seems to carry with it a guarantee that one will succeed. we are others; under small Once or by has e no or does see Plac tel. pr< an te 58 One of the reasons that we see such a guarantee is because we are struck by an analogy with the concealment of the truth from others. Suppose a man has a gun which he conceals on his body under his clothes. No one knows that he owns a gun. The gun is small and it is placed in a light holster to keep it from shifting. Once he has arranged the gun in place, one cannot tell by looking or by touching him that he has it on his person. Finally, after he has concealed it, he does nothing to give himself away. He tells no one that he possesses a gun or that he has it on his person. He does not allude to it in his speech. He does not grope at it to see if it's still in place, nor does he furtively look down at the place where it is hidden. Under these circumstances no one could tell by any normal means that he is carrying a gun. True, he might slip, or one could find it by thoroughly searching him, but this does not contradict the point being made: the point is that, providing he does not make a slip, providing he is not searched, and providing he continues to conceal the gun, there is no way to tell that he has the gun on him. Normally other people would be unable to learn this. The situation is similar for the self-deceiver, but, because he has such a willing victim, his position is much stronger. Having thoroughly concealed the truth from himself, he cannot see the truth, cannot come to know it by any normal means. Moreover, even if he should slip or if he should come to know the truth by some extraordinary means, this does not mean disaster, for he need only redouble his efforts, and once again the truth will be hidden from his v1’ by con denial the qr ration ignori evider fear, he sh thing to (3 repe that But abl his 59 his view, he will not know it because he is unable to see it. This picture of the self-deceiver is thoroughly reinforced by considerations of his thought, speech, and behavior. His denials, his intractability in the face of evidence and argument, the great extremes to which he goes to discount the evidence and rationalise it away, to defeat arguments favoring the truth, his ignoring the evidence which he does possess and avoidance of new evidence, and the evident emotion which he shows at these times - fear, anger, anxiety, frustration - or the evident relief which he shows when topics broaching on the truth are dropped: these things make us want to say that he is unable to admit the truth, to confirm it, state it, concede it, etc. The same picture is repeated within the private confines of his mind. We want to say that he is unable to think on the truth, to become conscious of it. But surely anyone who is unable to admit the truth, who is not able to think about it or become conscious of it, to being it into his reflections, reasonings, deliberations, and so forth, does not_ kngw_the truth. For anyone who knows the truth is able to admit it, concede it, state it, think on it, become conscious of it. So, as a result of his own efforts, the self-deceiver blinds himself to the truth, cannot see it, and so does not know it. The picture is completed by a comparison of the self-deceiver's thought, speech, and behavior with the thought, speech, and behavior of someone who is unquestionably ignorant of the truth. We think we know the self-deceiver and we expect him to behave in certain ways. Hedm behave mype but th nah and sd hints or al he a] beca of k nag of 01: 60 He does not do so; he behaves in the way we would expect him to behave if he did not know the truth. Or we think we know how any person would behave in his situation if they knew the truth, but the self-deceiver does not behave in these ways. He seems, as a result, to be oblivious to the truth, the evidence, its force, and so on. Moreover, his speech is free from allusions, references, hints of the truth. He does not admit, concede, state, affirm, or allow the truth. In fact, he is more likely to deny it, and he always resists efforts to get him to do these things. Finally, because thought of the truth does not enter his mind, the blankness of his mind rivals the blankness of the mind of someone who is unquestionably ignorant of the truth. The self-deceiver does not know the truth, he is ignorant of it. This proposition now comes to the forefront and dominates our view of him. Still, it is a shifting, troubled view. Traces of the self—deceiver's knowledge still show through. Not only do we catch glimmers of it in the self-deceiver's behavior, but it is an essential part of our picture of him even though it now hovers in the background. Not only is the supposition that he knows the truth a premise in our argument to show that he does not know it, but a necessary condition of his concealing the truth is that he knows it. We cannot truly speak of him as concealing the truth unless he does know it. As Sartre puts it, ...I must know in my capacity as deceiver the truth which is hidden from me in my capacity as the one deceived. 61 Better yet I must know the truth very exactly in_ order to conceal it more carefully-~and this not at two different moments, which at a pinch would allow us to establish a semblance of duality--but in the unitary structure of a single project.15 62 Section 4. What we do now is a matter of our own relation to the picture we have constructed. We can leave it as it is, not look at it too closely, and, even though we cannot believe it, we can still use it. It has a use: it explains the self-deceiver's behavior and mental condition. Even though the picture is self-contradictory, even though, for example, we must construe the same piece of behavior - say, the self-deceiver's denial of the truth - as both a purposeful bit of feigning and as a sincere expression of belief resting on genuine ignorance, still we have no other way of explaining his state which is readily available and easily understood. If we have a more theoretical interest in the self-deceiver and if we find it difficult to ignore the contradictoriness of the ,picture, then we are likely to look for a way out of the contradiction. we may see, with Freud, two intelligences, two personalities at ‘work in one individual: The first and most powerful impression made upon one during such an analysis is certainly that the pathogenic psychical material which has ostensibly been forgotten, which is not at the ego's disposal and which plays no part in association and memory, nevertheless in some fashion lies ready to hand and in correct and proper order. It is only a question of removing the resistances that bar the way to the material. In other respects this material is known, in the same way in which we are able to know anything; the correct connections between the separate ideas and between them and the non-pathogenic ones, which are frequently remembered, are in existence; they have been completed at some time and are stored up in the memory. The pathogenic psychical material appears to be the property of an intelligence which is not necessarily inferior to that of the normal ego. The appearance of a second personality is often presented in the most deceptive manner.1 Freud sometimes speaks as if he were giving serious consideration 63 to the idea of such a second person. However, the individual subject/agent is not split up into two persons of roughly equal standing. Rather, the individual subject/agent is the deceived, but he carries another person, the deceiver, within him. The deceiver does not share the deceived's mind or consciousness with him; rather, the deceiver is a part of the deceived's mind. He controls what thoughts or ideas shall enter into the deceived's consciousness, and thereby controls indirectly the deceived's behavior, for only conscious thoughts can be translated into behavior. This control is exercised by determining what thoughts or ideas shall be made available for consciousness. Thoughts thus made available of which the deceived is pp£_conscious are said to be preconscious, while they become conscious only if the individual actually avails himself of them. Thoughts which continue to exist but which are not preconscious, i.e., not available for consciousness, are said to be repressed. Both repressed ideas and thoughts and ,preconscious ideas and thoughts are said to be unconscious, i.e., .not conscious, but only repressed unconscious ideas belong to that .part of the mind called the Unconscious. Freud called the deceiver the 'censor'. And here there is *good reason for us to speak of the censor as a deceiver of the .individual of whose mind the censor is a part, even though Freud axticular the fine hand of the vehicular theory of consciousness, ajad the careless and cursory manner in which their argument is set curt. Moreover, we should note that this recognition of the self- decneiver's knowledge would have been inconsistent with the analysis Of Eself-deception to which they had been led by their acceptance 0f [Memos' analysis of gphggfdeception, and by the seeming paradox in l1c>lding incompatible beliefs. 99 Section 3. I noted earlier that the analyses of self-deception provided by Siegler, Canfield and Gustavson, and Penelhum all have a certain plausibility about them, and in this section I want to investigate the sources of this plausibility. In connection with Siegler's analysis, one source of this plausibility is quite easily ascertained: Siegler provides what are, in the main, perfectly acceptable accounts of ggmg_uses of "reflexive deception expressions", uses which are extraordinarily common and familiar to all of us. What he fails to appreciate fully is that at account of these uses have no bearing whatsoever upon the analysis and elucidation of the concept of self-deception. Indeed, for the latter purpose, an account of these uses is entirely superfluous. To see this, let us suppose that we have become quite perplexed about the concept of insanity. Along comes Siegler, and he points out the following uses of 'insanity expressions': (a) I am insane if I think I will win the race. (b) I am talking crazy when I talk about traveling to China. (c) I am insane if I think gifts will make her like me. (d) Look Brown, you are insane if you think that your wife has been faithful to you all this time. (e) You are insane when you think that my opponent would carry out his election platform. (f) You were insane when you thought that the opposition party would present a program for your benefit. In Gaach case, Siegler provides an account which parallels the aCC=<>unts which he gave for the corresponding sentences containing reflexive deception expressions. 100 Thus, we are told that uttering (a) or (b) is like giving oneself a very stropgyself-reprimand. Uttering (c) is like a vegy strong resolve not to give them any more. And in each of these cases, we are told, our utterance is accompanied by a reference to a time when we did something which we now regard as terribly silly, wrong, or highly unreasonable. In each case, it is like a reference to an attitude or action about which we certainly should E1 have known better but didn't. In connection with (d), we are told that White is telling é Brown that he has a severely erroneous belief and he is implying E; that it is highly unreasonable for Brown to have this belief. White's point is to strongly urge Brown to reconsider the evidence regarding his wife's relationship with her friend. In connection with (e) and (f), we are told that these uses of insanity expressions are like attributions of totally unwarranted beliefs, accompanied by ascriptions of responsibility for holding such beliefs. Now, I do not believe that we should find much fault with these accounts as accounts of certain uses of insanity expressions. These are familiar and established uses of these expressions, and the accounts given do a pretty good job of elucidating these uses. But we would certainly not find these accounts at all germane to our task of analyzing and elucidating the concept of insanity. Indeed, if they were put forward for that purpose, we should find them highly misleading. The reason for this is quite clear. Even though these are common and established uses of insanity expressions, they are figurative, hyperbolic uses of them. Brown would be lOl misunderstanding White if he thought that White meant that he was actually insane. The same thing holds true for the uses of reflexive deception expressions which Siegler explores. These are figurative, hyperbolic uses of such expressions. Indeed, these uses of reflexive deception expressions are just about identical to the uses of insanity expressions noted above. The most salient difference is that the pejorative force involved in the latter uses is somewhat stronger than that involved in the former. And in the same way that the above uses of insanity expressions shed no light on the concept of insanity ii and would be positively misleading if brought in for that purpose, so also the uses of reflexive deception expressions on which Siegler fixes shed no light on the concept of self-deception and are misleading when he introduces accounts of them for that purpose. Finally, we should note that the existence of the above uses of insanity expressions provide no grounds whatever for saying that there are two different senses of 'insane' or for saying that there are two distinct concepts of insanity. In the same way, the existence of the above uses of reflexive deception expressions in no way provides grounds for saying that there are two distinct senses of 'is deceiving himself(herself)' or for distinguishing two different concepts of self-deception. And so far as I can see, there are not two (or more) different senses of 'is deceiving himself (herself)' and there is only a single concept of self-deception. Another source of the plausibility of these analyses is that they seem, at first sight, to apply to a certain form of self-deception 102 called 'wishful thinking'. The reason they seem to apply to such cases is that if X is deceiving himself in thinking that P and this is a case of wishful thinking, then X strongly gives the impression of believing that P, and, moreover, it is not necessary that X know that not-P, though it is necessary that there be strong evidence pointing to not—P, that x know this evidence, see where it points, and appreciate its import. Thus the analyses of self-deception provided by Siegler, Canfield and Gustavson, and especially by Penelhum seem to fit cases of wishful thinking perfectly. Yet this 'fit' is illusory. In a case of wishful thinking where X is deceiving himself in thinking that P, the phrase 'in thinking that P' is misleading. Though it seems to do so, it does pg£_identify what X is deceiving himself about. What X is deceiving himself about in a case of wishful thinking is either the evidence or the fpggg_of the evidence. If the proposition that E states a piece of evidence, then X may be deceiving himself about the fact that E. Thus, while he knows that E, he feigns ignorance of it, suppresses all thought of it, ignores or tries to rationalize away the evidence favoring E, avoids situations in which he might become acquainted with fresh evidence favoring E. Or, if E is a body of evidence strongly supporting the proposition that not-P, then X may deceive himself about the force of E} either about the direction in which it points or its strength, or, usually, both. He knows that the evidence is strong, perhaps he knows it is conclusive, he knows where it points, yet he feigns ignorance of this, he suppresses all thought 103 of it, ignores or tries to rationalize away all arguments and reasons - though, I think, not 'evidence' - which support this, and avoids situations in which he might become acquainted with fresh arguments or reasons. Thus it is X's relationship to the evidence supporting the proposition not—P and not his relationship to the propositions that P and that not—P which makes it true that he is deceiving Ea himself. Even in cases of wishful thinking the self-deceiver must U know what he is deceiving himself about, and so the analyses of Siegler, Canfield and Gustavson, and Penelhum do not really apply Fr “1.. ‘t‘. D‘ to such cases. There is another reason as well why they do not apply. In many cases of wishful thinking, though not all, the self-deceiver does pgp_really believe that P; rather, he feigns belief that P for reasons quite similar to those which other self- deceivers have for feigning ignorance of the truth. In such cases of self—deception/wishful—thinking, the evidence is usually strong enough that one could not appreciate its force and continue to believe that P. Appreciating its force entails 92222 that P, and, hence, that one not believe that P, even though it need not entail that one believe that not-P. Here we should note that appreciating the force of evidence is quite similar in its implica- tions to appreciating incompatibilities, and, in particular, it has implications for our beliefs. In other cases of wishful thinking the evidence is not so strong that appreciating its force entails not believing. However, even in many of these cases the evidence is strong enough that, as a matter of fact, the wishful thinker does not believe that P. 104 Therefore, there are many cases of wishful thinking to which the formula endorsed by Siegler, Canfield and Gustavson, and Penelhum cannot be applied; the formula, namely, or 'belief in the face of evidence'. Before leaving this chapter I would like to point out that the connection between self-deception and wishful thinking helps to explain how one can have a 'motive' for believing in cases of wishful thinking. Believing is not something we do, even though we do assert our beliefs and act upon them, and so it is hard to see how one can have a motive for believing, how one can believe that P because one wants to or because one hopes or wishes that P. The answer is, I think, that even though believing is not something one can do, and so not something one can have a motive for doing or a purpose for doing, deceiving oneself is something one does, can have motives and purposes for doing. The same reasons one has for wishing or hoping that P or for wanting it to be the case that P may also be reasons for deceiving oneself about the evidence favoring not-P and going against P. It would be very interesting to explore this suggestion further, but I am afraid that there just is not space in this work. CHAPTER FOUR. Fingarette's New Model of Consciousness. Section 1. In the preceding chapters we have discussed at some length how Demos' statement of the source of paradox in Self-deception influenced and channeled the subsequent discussion of self-deception in the analytic tradition. The first analytic philosopher to appreciate that the discussion had gone far off in the wrong direction was Herbert Fingarette. In his book, Self-Deception,1 we ..,__.__ 2...}! Fingarette attacks the preoccupation with the question whether or not the self-deceiver holds incompatible beliefs. He argues that ...in their anxiety to resolve the supposed paradox in maintaining that a person holds two incompatible beliefs, Demos, Siegler, Canfield and Gustavson, and Penelhum all fail to appreciate that the deep paradox of self-deception lies not in this at most mildly odd condition, but in the element of knowing, ipten- tional ignorance. Moreover, as the above passage clearly indicates, Fingarette put his finger squarely on the first major paradox of self-deception: the self-deceiver's "knowing, intentional ignorance", and he justifiably criticizes Demos and the others for failing to see it. Fingarette then goes on in his own analysis of self-deception to give this crucial element of willful, purposeful ignorance its full cine, and he attempts to give what is, in effect, an account of how someone can make himself willfully ignorant of the truth. To acccmmflish this, he gives an explication of what it is to become lexplicitly conscious of something. Specifically, he proposes a new 105 100 "model" of explicit consciousness, "one in which we are doers, active rather than passive."3 Traditionally, both in philosophy and in everyday life, becoming conscious of something has not been thought of as something one can purposely do or purposely avoid doing, but this is because we have portrayed explicit consciousness in terms of the metaphor and idiom of "seeing--the essentially passive registration and reflection to the 'mind' of what the world presents to our eyes."4 Fingarette challenges this portrayal of explicit consciousness in terms of "passive, visual imagery." He argues that this is not necessarily the only way of portraying explicit consciousness, nor is it the best way of portraying it for the purposes of philosophical analysis. Just as we can characterize the 'feeling' of depression in terms of the imagery of heavy weight, or dark shadows, or degradedness and guilt, and yet be por- traying the 'feel' of the very same feeling, so too we can portray our consciousness, as consciousness, in more than one way. And just as the portrayal of depression in terms of the language and imagery of guilt is far more fertile, when we reflect analytic- ally on the matter, than is the imagery of weight, so too, I believe, the model of consciousness which I propose will prove far more fertile for philosophical analysis than is vision as a model of consciousness.5 The attractiveness of this move is immediately apparent. If becoming explicitly conscious of something is something one can ‘purposely do, for good reason or bad, then one can also purposely avoid becoming explicitly conscious of something, even refuse to become explicitly conscious, and also do so for good or bad reasons. The self-deceiver can then be described as someone who purposely avoids becoming explicitly conscious of the truth, and 107 his willful ignorance will consist, partially or wholly, in his successful avoidance of the truth. This is just the tact that Fingarette takes. The new model of becoming explicitly conscious of something which he. proposes is the exercise of a skill. To become explicitly conscious of something is to be exercising a certain skill...The specific skill I have particularly in mind as a model for becoming explicitly conscious of something is the skill of say - ing what we are doing or experiencing. I propose, then, that we do not characterize consciousness as a kind of mental mirror, but as the exercise of the (learned) skill of 'spelling-out' some feature of the world as we are engaged in it... I have purposefully chosen as the name of this skill a phrase, 'spelling-out', which could not in the context be taken literally but must be taken in something like its colloquial use... Colloquially, to spell something out is to make it explicit, to say it in a clearly and fully elaborated way, to make it perfectly apparent. Typical uses which I have in mind are: 'He is so stupid you have to spell everything out for him'; 'He let me know without actually spelling it out'; and 'you know perfectly well what I mean--do I have to spell it out for you?’ Applied to 'becoming conscious of something'. the phrase 'spelling-out' may refer, but need not, to the actual and elaborate saying out loud, or writing down, of that which one is conscious of. However, the phrase 'spell-out' is intended to suggest strongly an activity which has a close relation and analogy to linguistic activity. Sometimes-~but by no means always--the 'model' activity (literally making something explicit in language) is also an instance of the skill (becoming conscious) for which it serves as model. However it is clear that one often becomes explicitly conscious of something, or, to use the phrase which I now propose to use synonymously, one often spells-out something, without any evident utterance, even to oneself, or with only allusive or cryptic ones. What the exact connection is between spelling-out and perfectly straightforward examples of linguistic activity, I do not know. I think there is always a close relation. The point of my speaking of a 'model' here is that I wish to avoid even attempting a definitive account.6 108 After having made this connection between spelling-out and becoming explicitly conscious, Fingarette states what he calls his "first thesis concerning spelling-out": The thesis is that, generally speaking, the particular features of an individual's engagement in the world need not be, and usually are not spelled-out by him.7 The explanation for this lies in the fact that With exceptions (such as the performatives), there is always some special reason, over and above the simple fact of being engaged in some specific way, for taking the additional step of spelling-out this engagement. To refer to our model; we are not always saying all we are doing; we could not. Therefore we are selective in what we say, but not arbitrarily so. The same holds true, mutatis mutandis, for spelling—out. Once this is seen, it is then easy to appreciate that there can be situations "in which there is over-riding reason 223 to spell-out some engagement, where we skillfully take account of this and systematically avoid spelling-out the engagement, and where, in turn, we refrain from spelling—out this exercise in our skill in spelling-out.“9 This further realization takes us into the "region of self-deception"lo; In general, the person in self-deception is a person of whom it is a patent characteristic that even when normally appropriate he persistently avoids spelling- out some features of his engagement in the world...11 Moreover, once the self-deceiver has assessed a situation and committed himself to avoid spelling-out the engagement, ...the original reasons for refusing to spell-out the truth will also serve as reasons against spelling-out the prior assessment and commitment not to spell-out the truth. For to spell-out the assessment and the policy adopted would, of course, require spelling-out 109 the engagement at issue, the very engagement the self-deceiver has committed himself not to spell- out.12 In other words, it is logically impossible for the self-deceiver to avoid spelling-out his engagement and to at the same time spell- out his policy of avoiding spelling-out the engagement. Thus the reasons for not spelling-out the engagement will also serve as reasons for not spelling-out the policy of not spelling-out the engagement. 110 Section 2. The foregoing represents only a part of Fingarette's analysis of self-deception. He goes on to try to develop his account in a way which will at once explain ghy_the self-deceiver avoids spelling- out his engagement as well as some of the deeper aspects of self- deception. Briefly put, his view is that for the self-deceiver to spell-out his engagement would be to acknowledge his personal identity in a way that would be destructive of his unity as a person. However, this part of Fingarette's account, while stimulating and suggestive, is fraught with obscurity, and since it is not directly germane to our present purposes, we shall leave it out of consideration except for a few occasional asides. For our purposes, it is far more important to determine how successful Fingarette is in providing an account of self—deception which is free from paradox and which adequately accounts for the more prominent features of self-deception. His account is of special interest to us because it seems to coincide with the tentative sketch of self-deception which we gave at the end of Chapter Two. Saying that the self-deceiver purposely avoids becoming explicitly conscious of the truth does not involve us in the first major paradox of self-deception, while it does provide adequate recognition of the essential purposefulness of self-deception: we can explain the self-deceiver's lack of explicit consciousness as due to his lgurposeful avoidance, for over-riding reasons, of becoming explicitly 111 conscious of the truth. Moreover, this fits in well with our suggestion that we treat all talk of the self-deceiver's blindness, willful ignorance, and self-deception as metaphorical or idiomatic references to his purposeful avoidance of explicit consciousness of the truth together with his feigning ignorance of it. Before we can assimilate Fingarette's account to our own in the above fashion, however, we must deal with certain difficulties which it poses. The first of these concerns Fingarette's use of the term 'explicitly conscious'. Fingarette often speaks as though this phrase can be used interchangeably with the word 'conscious'. On the other hand, the adverb 'explicitly' would suggest that it cannot be so used, that to be conscious of something is not necessarily to be explicitly conscious of it. It makes a big difference to our account of self-deception in which of these two ways we construe the phrase. Let us suppose first that 'explicitly conscious' is to be taken as equivalent to 'conscious'. Then in accordance with Fingarette's other views, we can say that to become conscious of the truth is to do something, to be exercising a certain skill, that of 'spelling-out', and that the self-deceiver is someone who has an over-riding reason not to become conscious of the truth, who assesses his situation and determines that he has such a reason, who takes this into account in adopting a policy of not becoming conscious of the truth, and who then does not become conscious of the truth because to do so would violate this policy. 112 Unfortunately, we are now committed to a contradiction, that the self—deceiver is at times both conscious of the truth and not conscious of it. It is this contradiction, of course, which I call 'the second major paradox of self-deception'. The derivation of the second half of this contradiction is quite trivial. Since the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth because to do so would violate his policy, it follows that he is not conscious of the truth during his self—deception. On the other hand, we cannot explain the self-deceiver's not being conscious of the truth as due to the fact that becoming conscious of the truth would violate his policy of not becoming conscious of the truth unless he is at times conscious of the truth. For such an explanation to hold, it is not enough that he has the policy and simply does not become conscious of the truth. To see this, let us note first that a person may have a policy of never lying, and he may in fact not lie during a period of time. But it does not follow from this that he did not lie because to do so would violate his policy. In order for us to explain his not lying in this way, there must have been some occasion during this period of time in which he recognized that he had or thought that he had some reason to lie, and so was tempted to lie, but did not do so out of recognition that this would violate his policy of not lying. But for him to recognize that he had a reason to lie would be for him to be conscious that he had a reason to lie. Sometimes we use the term 'recognize' in a dispositional way. To say that X recognizes that P is to say that X knows that P and 113 would acknowledge it under appropriate circumstances. At other times, we use the term 'recognize' in a way in which it designates an ESE and is equivalent to 'acknowledge': e.g., we say he will not recognize him in his will. But in the above we are using the term 'recognize' in neither of these ways. We are using it in an episodic sense in which it is close to "He recognized Brown at his door", "He recognized the smell of garlic", "He recognized the work of his old enemy, Fu Manchu, in this hideous murder." I do not want to put too much stress on the term 'recognize' here. We could also use the term 'see', 'realize', 'be aware', 'know' to say the same thing. Thus instead of the above, we could say of the man with the policy of not lying that during this period of time there must of been some occasion on which he g3! that he had reason to lie (or "realized he had reason to lie", “was ag§£g_ that he had reason to lie", "kpgg_that he had reason to lie") if we are to explain his not lying as due to his adherence to his policy of not lying. But also, and this is the point I have been trying to make, we could equally well say that there must have been some occasion on which he was conscious that he had reason to lie. In this context all of these terms - 'recognize', 'see', 'aware', 'know', 'realize', apg_'conscious' - are equivalent. Hence, if we are to say of this man that he did not lie because doing so would violate his policy of not lying, then the man must have been conscious that he had a reason to lie, and also conscious that to do so would violate his policy of not lying. Suppose, for example, that Smith asks Jones to loan him a large sum of money. Jones 114 tells him that he may be able to loan him the money, though if he does, he will need it back within two weeks. Jones then asks Smith if he can repay the loan by that time. Smith has a policy of not lying, and he doesn't lie. He tells Jones that he cannot repay the money within two weeks. But we cannot say that Smith did not lie to Jones because to do so would violate his policy of not lying unless Smith was conscious (recognized, realized, knew, saw, was aware) that Jones would probably not loan him the money unless he lied, and so was conscious that he had reason to lie. If it did not even occur to him that he would probably not get the loan from Jones unless he lied, then — I am assuming that Smith was not conscious of any other reason to lie - it would be false that he did not lie because lying to Jones would violate his policy of not lying. Similarly, it must also be the case that Smith recognized - was conscious - that lying to Jones would violate his policy of never lying. Even though Smith was conscious of a reason for lying to Jones, had a policy of not lying, and did not lie, it still does not follow that he did not lie to Jones because lying to him was inconsistent with his policy, Jones, for example, may be a violent man, particularly hard on people who lie to him. Smith, while recognizing that he had reason to lie to Jones, may have refrained from lying out of regard for the regularity of his own features and a concern for his teeth, without its even having occurred to him that lying to Jones would violate his policy. If 115 so, we could not say that Smith did not lie because of his policy of not lying. Here I should like to make two points. First, nothing I have said commits me to saying that when, e.g., someone who has a policy of not lying does not lie, but is conscious neither of a reason to lie nor of the fact that lying would violate his policy, then there is no way of explaining his not lying. What explains it has already been noted: he did not lie because he was not aware of any reason for lying, even though, perhaps, there was a reason for him to lie which he did not see. Thus we are not forced back in such a situation to an explanation in terms of adherence to a policy. The second point is that nothing I have said about adhering to a policy conflicts with the fact that adherence to a policy may become habitual, 'second nature', as it were. There may seem to be such a conflict because we often say of someone for whom adherence to a policy has become second nature, e.g., of someone who rigidly adheres to a policy of honesty, that "it wouldn't even occur to him to lie", and this may seem to mean that the person is never conscious of reasons to lie. However, this is hyperbole. (The expression means that when he is conscious of such reasons, he (ices not give them serious consideration, does not hesitate for a Dmoment, but straight away adheres to his policy. The expression applies to people who are not moved nor inclined by such reasons; it Cicxes not apply to people who are not conscious of them. 116 Let us now consider a person, Brown, who has a policy of never becoming conscious that S. Again, in order for us to truly say that Brown does not become conscious that S because doing so would violate his policy, there must be some occasion on which he is conscious of some reason to become conscious that S, and on which he is also conscious that becoming conscious that 8 would violate his policy. There is, however, an important difference between this case and preceding ones. Providing that Brown knows that S (as opposed to simply believing that S), Brown could not be conscious of some reason to become conscious that S unless he were conscious that S, and he could not be conscious that becoming conscious that S would violate his policy of not becoming conscious that 8 unless he were conscious that S. A parallel example will be of some help in seeing this. Suppose that Smith knows that his son's birthday is on July 22d. He promises his son that he will be home early from work in order to attend his birthday party, but because such things have often slipped his mind in the past, he asks his wife to remind him on the morning of the 22d of the birthday party. Here we can say that Smith is conscious of some reason for becoming conscious (by being reminded by his wife) on the morning of the 22d that his :son's birthday party will be given later in the day. It does not .follow directly from this that Smith is conscious that his son's lbirthday party will be given on the 22d. Smith may be mistaken aflmout the date, and so only believe that his son's birthday party 143 on the 22d. But assuming that he is not mistaken, that he knows 117 that the birthday party is on the 22d, he could not be conscious of some reason for becoming conscious (by being reminded) on the morning of the 22d that his son's birthday party will be given later in the day without its being the case that he is conscious that his son's birthday party will be on the 22d. Now let us suppose that Thompson, vain and aging, and anxious about his declining virility, has adopted a policy of not allowing himself to become conscious of his own age wherever possible. He realizes that he ought to face up to the fact that he is 47 and growing older, and so he is conscious from time to time that he has good reason to become conscious that he is 47. But at the same time he is conscious that becoming conscious that he is 47 would violate his policy of not allowing himself to become conscious that he is 47 wherever it is possible to do so. And, assuming that he knows that he is 47, then he could neither be conscious that he has good reason to become conscious that he is 47 (during the course of facing up to his age) nor conscious that doing so would violate his policy of not allowing himself to become conscious that he is 47 unless he were conscious that he is 47. Brown's case is similar. Providing he knows that S, Brown could neither lae conscious of some reason for becoming conscious that S nor (:onscious that doing so would violate his policy unless he were conscious that S . Now, the self—deceiver is someone who knows the truth, but <3?! the view we are considering, he is not conscious of the truth because to become conscious of the truth would violate his policy we are con and not co we are con 0f self—de In re that it nc never bec< While the the truth become cc IEaSOn fc Thi: state of Paradox has a re Say that an Dyer- Of 50mg of Some and in 1 So this of sel f. He] 118 of never becoming conscious of the truth. But the latter could not hold unless he were conscious of the truth. So, on the view we are considering, the self-deceiver would have to be both conscious and not conscious of the truth at the same time. Thus, the view we are considering leads directly into the second major paradox of self—deception. In recognition of this, we might try to alter this view so that it no longer includes the notion of adhering to a policy of never becoming conscious of the truth. Instead, we might say that while the self-deceiver knows the truth, he is not conscious of the truth because on any occasion for which he has some reason to become conscious of the truth, he always has an over-riding reason for not becoming conscious of the truth. This way of putting things is, I believe, closer to the real state of affairs, but it does not get us out of the second major paradox of self—deception. If on some occasion the self-deceiver has a reason to become conscious of the truth, we still cannot say that he did not become conscious of the truth because he had an over-riding reason for not doing so unless he were conscious of some reason for becoming conscious of the truth and conscious of some over-riding reason for not becoming conscious of the truth, and in both of these cases he would have to be conscious of the truth. So this modified view also leads to the second major paradox of self-deception. Hence, while we may retain the view that the self-deceiver 11&5 a policy of not becoming conscious of the truth and that he has 119 strong reasons for not becoming conscious of the truth, we must reject the claims that he does not become conscious of the truth because to do so would violate his policy, and that he does not become conscious of the truth because he has an over—riding reason for not doing so. This does not mean that we must reject the claim that the self—deceiver is not conscious of the truth. To avoid the paradox we need only reject the explanation of his not being conscious of the truth in terms of a policy or over-riding reason. Though of course, if we did reject the claim that the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth, then, since there would be nothing for these explanations to explain, they would be rejected as well, and hence, the paradox could also be avoided in this way. Traditionally, however, the claim that the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth except in special circumstances has not been rejected, and only the explanation of his not being conscious in terms of his own purposes, policies, etc., has been rejected in order to avoid the second major paradox of self—deception. This left open the question why the self—deceiver, while knowing the truth, only became conscious of it in quite exceptional circumstances, and did not become conscious of it in circumstances in which we would normally expect someone who knows the truth to become conscious of it. The only explanation for this would seem to be that the self-deceiver does not become conscious of the truth because he is .prevented from doing so by forces operating beyond his control, .either by another person within him, or by impersonal forces operating blindly within him. 120 I indicated in Chapter Two that it is the claim that the self—deceiver is not conscious of the truth in normal circumstances together with the above explanation of this alledged fact which leass, yi§_argument (b)l"', to the conclusion that he does not know the truth. However, we need not take this step, and, indeed, if we wish to be consistent, we will not take it. For the explana- tion presupposes that the self-deceiver does know the truth, and without this presupposition, the explanation simply would not apply; we could explain his lack of consciousness in terms of his lack of knowledge. Still, the view that the self-deceiver, while knowing the truth, is not normally conscious of it because he is prevented from becoming so by forces operating independently of his own aim, wishes, desires, policies, etc., is not a very happy one. The reason for this is that this contention negates what Fingarette calls "the crucial element of purposefulness in the whole manoeuvre."l3 The only way of restoring this essential element is by denying what this view takes for granted, namely, that the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth under normal circumstances. However, before we can convincingly rid ourselves of this assumption, we shall have to refute the view of consciousness on which it rests, i.e., we shall have to refute the vehicular theory of consciousness. 121 Section 3. The phrase, 'vehicular theory of consciousness', is in a certain respect misleading, for what it refers to is more often a way of thinking about consciousness than an explicitly held and reasoned theory about consciousness. Even people who explicitly reject the theory as a theory about consciousness - I suspect, for example, that Canfield and Gustavson fit into this category - still fall into the trap of thinking about consciousness as though it required a 'vehicle'. This way of thinking often gives very misleading results, as in the case of self-deception. The self- deceiver is often conscious of the truth, but his consciousness never has a vehicle. And if we hold the vehicular theory of consciousness, or think about consciouensss on its terms, then we are led to deny that the self-deceiver is ever conscious of the truth under normal circumstances. According to the vehicular theory, if X is conscious that P, he must either be perceiving that P through the senses, or entertaining memory images depicting that P, or expressing that P linguistically to himself or another, or have some other similar vehicle for his consciousness. For example, Jones may be conscious that a child is running in front of his car, when he sees the child in front of it. Later, images of the child running in front of his car may pass through his mind, and then we can say that he is conscious that a child ran in front of his car. Or, he may simply say, either to 1himself or another person, that a child ran in front of his car, 122 and again we can say that X is conscious that a child ran in front of his car. Freud held such a vehicular theory of consciousness. Freud recognized that consciousness is episodic and that to be conscious of something is to have it on one's mind or present to consciousness. In 'A Note on the Unconscious in Psychoanalysis' he writes: A conception--or any other mental element--which is now present to my consciousness may become absent the next moment,and may become present again, after an interval, unchanged, and as we say, from memory, not as a result of a fresh perception of our senses. It is this fact which we are accustomed to account for by the supposition that during the interval the conception has been present in our mind, although latent in consciousness.14 However, Freud tended to take the notion of 'present to consciousness' quite literally. In The Interpretation 9£_Dreams he likens consciousness to "a sense organ for the apprehension of psychical qualities."15 Initially consciousness "can receive excitations from the periphery of the whole apparatus, the perceptual system; and in addition to this, it can receive excitations of pleasure and unpleasure".15 But excitations other than those from the perceptual system, which here includes the systems of memory, can only be objects of consciousness insofar as they carry with them .pleasure or unpleasure. So, ...in Order to make more delicately adjusted performances possible, it later became necessary to make the course of ideas less dependent upon the presence or absence of unpleasure. For this purpose the Pcs. system needed to have qualities of its own which could attract conscious- ness; and it seems highly probable that it obtained them by linking the preconscious processes with the mnemic system of linguistic symbols, a system which was not without 123 quality. By means of the qualities of that system, consciousness, which had hitherto been a sense organ for perceptions alone, also became a sense organ for a portion of our thought processes.15 In his later works Freud does not mention the suggestion that consciousness be viewed as a sense organ for the detection of psychic qualities. However, the contention that conscious thought must have a vehicle is reaffirmed. In "The Ego and the Id' Freud appeals to this distinction in distinguishing between Ug§_ideas and Pcs or Cs ideas. ...the real difference between a Egg and a Pg§_idea (thought) consists in this: that the former is carried out upon some sort of material which remains unrecognized, whereas the latter (the Egg) is in addition brought into connection with word presentations. This is the first attempt to indicate distinguishing marks for the two systems, the Pg§_and Egg, other than their relation to consciousness. The question, "How does a thing become conscious?" would thus be more advantageously stated: "How does a thing become preconscious?" And the answer would be: "Through becoming connected with the word presentations corresponding to it."16 This last passage suggests an even more stringent version of the vehicular theory of consciousness than that held in The Interpretation 9: Dreams: X is conscious that P only if the thought or idea that P has become "connected with the word presentations corresponding to it." This later view sounds quite close to Fingarette's view that to become explicitly conscious of something is to spell it out. However, Fingarette realized, as Freud did not, that the vehicular theory so narrowly construed is false, for "one often becomes explicitly conscious of something...without émny evident utterance, even to oneself, or with only allusive or (Zryptic ones."17 124 Moreover, not only is this narrow version of the vehicular theory false, all versions, wide or narrow, are false. To see this, let us suppose that M is home alone sitting in front of his fireplace watching the fire. As he sits there, he stares deeply into the flames. He says nothing to himself or anyone else. No images, neither auditory nor mnemic images, nor images of any other kind pass through his mind. Yet it is not inconsistent, odd, or nonsensical to say that M is brooding about his wife's infidelity during this time. One way in which we might find out that M has been brooding about his wife‘s infidelity is through what he says. We see him staring morosely into the flames and we ask him what he is thinking about. He replies that his 'loving' (sarcastic tone) wife is out again for the third time that week, probably shacking up in some motel with her boyfriend, that he was thinking about this and feeling lonely and bitter. Providing we do not question the sincerity of his reply, we shall accept at least the part about his thinking without hesitation. Moreover, if we found out that he had said nothing to himself or to another person during this time, and that no images had passed through his mind, this would certainly provide no good reason to doubt his sincerity. The priviledged status of M's reply to our inquiry is indicative of the special authority which is possessed by what a ;person says about his own thinking and consciousness. This aauthority provides, I believe, the main impetus to vehicular theories <3f'consciousness, for they are all primarily aimed at explaining how 125 a person know§_what he is thinking about or what he is conscious of. On their view, he knows what he is thinking about or what he is conscious of because of the connection between these things and his images and internal speech. The latter provides the grounds upon which his knowledge of the former are based. Thus Freud was inclined to view consciousness as a kind of sense organ for the detection of psychic qualities, in particular the auditory images of internal speech, and it was only through the use of this 'sense organ' that the individual himself learned what he is thinking about. If thoughts were not connected with these auditory images, then the individual would not know what he is thinking about, since thoughts are pg£_§g_without 'psychic quality'. What these theories all fail to take into account is that if there were a problemxvith how an individual knows what he is thinking about and what he is conscious of, then there would also be a problem with the individual's knowledge about his own images and internal speech. A person exercises the same kind of authority with regard to his images and internal speech as he does with respect to his thinking and consciousness. He may lie about his images and internal speech, but he cannot be mistaken about them, and what he sincerely says about them is true. Once this is realized the vehicular theory loses much of its persuasiveness, since the 'problem' - if there is one - has not been solved but merely moved to a different level. I am not maintaining here that the above example concerning M's lDrooding about his wife's infidelity fits in very well with our 126 earlier supposition that he is deceiving himself about her infidelity. I have introduced the example only for the purpose of showing that vehicular theories of consciousness are false, and not for the purpose of showing that self-deceivers are at times conscious of the truth. On the other hand, it is not difficult to come up with an example which is at once a counter-example to vehicular theories of consciousness and also a counter-example to the claim that self—deceivers are never conscious of the truth except under very special circumstances (drugs, drink, hypnosis, psychoanalysis). Suppose, for example, that contrary to his usual habit, M is on his way home from work early in the afternoon. As he drives up to his house, he sees a gold '74 Buick parked a few yards down the street from his house. His reaction to this sight is immediate. With the first glimpse of the car, a flush of heat passes over his body, beginning with his scalp and face, radiating downwards through his limbs, and outwards, covering his flesh with a rush of prickliness. Simultaneously, his body grows numb and heavy, he feels paralyzed, and he cannot bring himself to look at his house - it seems alien, hostile, and he feels as though there were a force pushing his face away from his house. His stomach churns, sinks, and a wave of nausea rises up from his bowels through his stomach into his throat. All of these feelings seem.to merge and float outwards from him, swirling around the gold Buick. It is as if he had no body, as 127 if he were a pinpoint of feelings, sights, and sounds. The flush of heat, the prickliness, the heaviness, the sinking sensation, the nausea, the pressure of the seat against his back and legs, all mingle with the dense afternoon neighborhood, with the thick, viscuous sunlight, with the repellent brilliance of the green grass and the blue sky, with the shade and suffocating heat of the inside of the car, with the smell of exhaust fumes, with the remote sound of honking horns, with the backyard voices and cries of playing children, with the chimes of a far away ice—cream vendor. Every- thing bends and merges towards the gold Buick, forming a whirling tunnel around it. The car has now become solid, dense, immovable, indestructible - a monument which draws everything to it but is touched by nothing. Time stops around it. As the spell subsides, as the universe extricates itself from its swirl around the gold Buick, a cool breeze flickers past M's face. The thought enters his head of driving down to a nearby lake and relaxing within the dark confines of a bar on its shore. M drives off, the whole monstrous experience fading behind him, attached to the gold '74 Buick. M recognized the Buick as belonging to his wife's lover, and when he saw it, he was struck by the thought that his wife and her lover were using his house for a rendezvous. Thus when he saw the lover's car M was conscious of his wife's infidelity, and his experience was a reaction to seeing the-car-of-his-wife's-lover- Parked-near-his-house rather than simply to seeing a gold '74 Buick Pamked near his house. Yet throughout the whole experience described above, no ii and he said to the vehi We mus to the clai except in c is in a rat with the ci infidelity Of his Wift with the ( is becaum theory of “maple, and her 1 Slut! NOW the £5me deceiVing This Phi-age, , to take : 128 above, no images, no internal speech passed through M's mind and he said nothing aloud. Thus we again have a counter-example to the vehicular theory of consciousness. We must now decide whether we also have a counter-example to the claim that the self-deceiver is never conscious of the truth except in quite special circumstances. The example as so far stated is in a rather neutral status. It is not clearly inconsistent with the claim that M is deceiving himself about his wife's infidelity, but neither does it clearly show that M is conscious of his wife's infidelity while he is deceiving himself about it. What we must do now in order to get a counter-example to the claim that self-deceivers are not conscious of the truth is to sharpen the example by adding further details to it. We might begin by noting that one reason the example does not clearly conflict with the claim_that M is deceiving himself about his wife's infidelity is because it does provide a counter-example to the vehicular theory of consciousness. If it did not provide such a counter- example, if we supposed, for instance, that M imagined his wife and her lover coupling in his bed or that he said to himself, "The slut! Now she's even using my_house for her dirty affairl", then the example would sharply conflict with the supposition that M is deceiving himself about his wife's infidelity. This brings us to the second way of construing Fingarette's phrase, "explicitly conscious'. The first way of construing it was .to take it as equivalent to 'conscious', and, as we have seen, in connection with Fingarette's analysis of self-deception this leads to 129 the second major paradox of self—deception. The second way of construing 'explicitly conscious' would be to take it in a much more limited way in which it is not co-extensive with 'conscious'. Fingarette's model of explicit consciousness - spelling-out in the colloquial sense - suggests that we can take explicit consciousness to be consciousness which is accompanied by spelling-out in the colloquial sense, and, consistently with Fingarette's own directions, the notion can be expected to include consciousness of the truth which is accompanied by cryptic or allusive reference to the truth. We could go on extending the notion of explicit consciousness in this way, listing kinds of instances of explicit consciousness. We might, for example, further extend the notion by adding that ‘explicit consciousness is to include consciousness which is accompanied by some form of pictorial representation of the truth, whether that representation be given in mental imagery or in some external form, e.g., a drawing. But no such listing could ever be complete. For example, suppose that, after learning of his wife's infidelity, M refuses to sleep with his wife, offering no explana- tions for this to anyone, including his wife. Providing that his refusal is a reaction to what he has learned, i.e., that his wife has been unfaithful to him, we shall want to say that he is explicitly conscious of her infidelity when,e.g., he comes home, grabs his pillows, blankets, and belongings, and moves them into the guest room. Yet he may neither spell-out her infidelity, nor make Cryptic or allusive references to it, nor picture it in mental images or in any other way. 130 Such examples can be multiplied indefinitely, and thus any listing of kinds of instances of explicit consciousness must necessarily be incomplete, and, hence, vague. Vagueness is not necessarily a bad thing, but for our purposes, the particular vagueness of the notion of explicit consciousness which would result from such a listing would be intolerable; moreover, this vagueness is not necessary. What all of these instances of explicit conscious- ness have in common is that they contain an acknowledgment of the truth. To spell-out the truth, to refer to it cryptically or allusively, to picture it in mental imagery or a drawing is normally to acknowledge it. Likewise, M's refusal to sleep with his wife amounts to an acknowledgment of her infidelity. Hence, we can (define explicit consciousness as consciousness which is accompanied Iby an acknowledgment of the truth. Now, in order to make the above example concerning M a clear counter-example to the claim that self-deceivers are not conscious <3f the truth except in very special circumstances, we must suppose that M, while conscious of his wife's infidelity when seeing the gold '74 Buick, is ngt_explicitly conscious of it. And, to make clear what this supposition involves, several points need to be made . First, the definition of explicit consciousness as conscioun- Jness which is accompanied by an acknowledgment of the truth is Inisleading, for explicit consciousness is not merely consciousness Vflhich is concommitant with an acknowledgment of the truth. A 131 necessary condition of acknowledging the truth is that one can be conscious of the truth while one is acknowledging it. This means that if, for example, M were to say that his wife was being unfaithful to him (perhaps as a lie), or if he were to (jokingly) allude to infidelity on her part, or if he were to image her and another man having sexual intercourse (perhaps in a voyeuristic phantasy), then the saying or alluding or imaging would not count as an acknowledgment of the truth if he were not at the same time conscious of the truth. It is consciousness of the truth which constitutes such sayings, allusions, and imagings as acknowledg- ments of the truth. And it is only consciousness of the truth, which does constitute an acknowledgment of the truth as an acknowledg- ment of the truth which counts as explicit consciousness. So, when we suppose that M is conscious of his wife's infidelity upon seeing the car but it not explicitly conscious of her infidelity, we are supposing that he does nothing which is constituted by his consciousness of her infidelity as an acknowledgment of her infidelity. And this means that the example is automatically a counter-example to the vehicular theory of consciousness, for it entails that he does not spell-out, image, or picture his wife's infidelity, though it precludes as well other forms of acknowledgment which are not incorporated into the vehicular theory of consciousness. Secondly, Fingarette is correct — in a sense - in treating becoming explicitly conscious as something one does, for acknowledging Nthe truth is something one does. However, this only means that the <:onsciousness is already given and that making it explicit is 132 something one does. One imparts a quality to an already existing consciousness. It does 22t_mean that becoming conscious is something one does. Consciousness, whether it be the kind which constitutes an acknowledgment or the kind which does not, is something that befalls one. When M became conscious of his wife's infidelity upon seeing the gold Buick parked near his house, he did not make himself conscious of her infidelity. His becoming conscious of her infidelity was a reaction to what he saw over which he had no control. This does not mean that in general one never has control in any form over one's consciousness. One can, for example, avoid becoming conscious of the truth by avoiding situations in which one is likely to be reminded of it or by preoccupying one's mind in some form of distraction, just as one can avoid automobile accidents by being careful and taking certain precautions. And one can arrange things so that one will become conscious of something at such and such a time or under certain circumstances. A person may, e.g., ask someone to remind him of something at a particular time. But this sort of control does not justify saying that becoming conscious is something one does. Indeed, if, per impossible, anything were to count as "purposely Jbecoming conscious of the truth for some reason" or as "making coneself conscious of the truth for some reason", these descriptions ‘would presuppose that one was already conscious of the truth, and so it would be incorrect to apply them. Thirdly, in the definition of explicit consciousness as «consciousness which is accompanied by an acknowledgment of the truth - 133 which definition might now be better rendered by saying that explicit consciousness is consciousness which constitutes an acknowledgment of the truth as an acknowledgment of the truth - we are using the term 'acknowledgment' in a way which stretches its sense in two different directions. First, we are stretching it in a way that covers not only straight-forward verbal acknoeledgments of the truth given in reply to inquiries or challenges, but also in a way in which it covers 'in effect', figurative acknowledgments of the truth to others, e.g., M's refusal to sleep with his wife in response to her infidelity. Secondly, we are using the term 'acknowledgment' to cover acknowledgments tg_oneself, where the term is being used in a secondary way, with the straight-forward and figurative acknowledgments to others providing the primary uses. Thus if, upon seeing the gold Buick parked near his house, M were to exclaim to himself, "The slut! Now she's even meeting him in my housel", or if he were to image his wife and her lover coupling in his bed, then this would under normal circumstances count as an acknowledgment to himself of his wife's infidelity. There is no need to apologize for this stretched use of the ‘term 'acknowledgment'. It is an established use, one with which we Eire familiar, and this is even true of 'acknowledgments to oneself'. TPhe latter use is as familiar as 'saying to oneself', 'telling one- sself', 'admitting to oneself'. Thus its occurrence in the definition (bf 'explicit consciousness' provides a basis for applying the term "exp1icit consciousness', for talking about explicit consciousness :in a general way or for deciding in a given case whether or not 134 someone is explicitly conscious, and so on. Granted, the use of the term 'acknowledgment' in the definition still allows for some vagueness in the term 'explicit consciousness', but this is not the pervasive vagueness which results when the term is defined through a list of instances. The fourth point I wish to make about explicit consciousness connects the avoidance of explicit consciousness in a particularly close way with feigning or pretending to be ignorant of the truth.18 It is often the case that one is conscious of the truth and that one does something such that special steps are necessary if what one does is ggt_to be constituted by one's consciousness of the truth as an acknowledgment of the truth. What one must do is feign or pretend ignorance of the truth. In still other cases where one is conscious of the truth, if one fails to indicate in some way that one does not accept what is in fact the truth, then one's conscious- ness of the truth constitutes one's failure as an acknowledgment of the truth. I shall divide examples to illustrate this point according to whether feigning or pretending ignorance of the truth is necessary in order to avoid acknowledgment of the truth to others or in order to avoid acknowledgment of the truth to oneself. Thus, to begin xwith the former, M's refusal to sleep with his wife would normally involve an acknowledgment of her infidelity, and so would involve explicit consciousness of her infidelity. M cannot avoid this acknowledgment by allowing that his wife has been unfaithful but Iby denying that he is refusing to sleep with her in response to 135 her infidelity, for even though this would prevent his refusal to sleep with her from being constituted as an acknowledgment of his wife's infidelity, it would only do so at the expense of making another acknowledgment of her infidelity. The only way that he can prevent his consciousness of her infidelity from constituting something or other as an acknowledgment of her infidelity is by feigning ignorance of her infidelity. Thus, he may, for example, avoid acknowledging her infidelity to others by becoming terribly 'annoyed' at his wife's frequent tossing and turning at night, and by explaining to others that he does not sleep with her because his tossing and turning keeps him awake, when really his 'annoyance' is disguised anger at her for her infidelity, and his refusal to sleep with her is both punishment of her for her transgressions and an effort to disassociate himself from her and her behavior. Or, for another example, M may confide to a friend that he does not believe that his wife could be sexually "satisfied by any man." Normally the friend could take this as a rather facile and self-serving attempt by M to explain his wife's infidelity, and thus as an acknowledgment to him (the friend) of her infidelity. JBut if M adds, "None the less, she has remained completely faithful ‘to mel", while the friend may still treat M's remark as an attempt ‘to explain his wife's infidelity, the friend can no longer treat 'the remark as an acknowledgment of the wife's infidelity. M's éadditional assertion, which marks him as pretending ignorance of his -\vife's infidelity, has removed the remark from the status of an acknowledgment of his wife's infidelity. 136 To turn now to our second set of examples, Pugmire's incompetent official provides an excellent example of a person who is pretending tg_himself to be ignorant of the truth in order to avoid acknowledging the truth to himself. Even while he is telling himself that on the jobs from which he was dismissed there were unfair adversities and mitigating circumstances, the official as Pugmire describes him is conscious that he performed incompetently on these jobs. Pugmire describes him as having the "thought" or "awareness" that the charge of incompetence is correct, and his consciousness that he did perform incompetently is further revealed through the sinking feeling or sensation which he experiences while giving himself these excuses. The official's telling himself that there were unfair adversities and mitigating circumstances amounts to a denial to himself that he had performed incompetently on the jobs from which he was dismissed. Pugmire does not give us enough in the way of details to say why the official feels it is necessary to deny his incompetent performances, but we can supply these details ourselves. We might suppose that the official has just been fired a few hours earlier on grounds of incompetence, that he is still severely :smarting from this, and that the charge of incompetency is still, 615 it were, ringing in his ears. He cannot get the dismissal nor ‘the charge of incompetence off of his mind. He feels compelled to (Swell on it, and in the course of doing so, memories of earlier -<3ismissals are revived, adding to his despair and misery. 137 His position here parallels one in which someone else has leveled the charge of incompetence against the official. If the official were to allow the charge to stand, if he did not deny it, this would be to acknowledge the truth of the charge to the person. Similarly, when it is the official himself who has the charge on his mind, and who is conscious of its truth, if the official were to allow the charge to stand without denying it, this would be to acknowledge the truth of the charge to himself, and thus it would be to make his consciousness of the truth of the charge explicit. His denial is a defense against explicit consciousness of the truth. The denial is not the only element in this defenSe. The official probably despairs - the sinking sensation - of ever being able to perform competently. He may turn this into 'despair of ever being treated fairly'. Indeed, the particular form which his denial takes suggests that something like this is at work. They - "those bastards" - put unfair obstacles in his way. They got rid of him because he is not a 'Yes-man', and was not afraid to tell them the truth. Perhaps, just because of his competence, his hard work, and his integrity, they felt he was a threat to their own jobs, and fired him before he could show them up. He tells himself things like ‘this, and as he does so, he chokes up with 'anger' at the unfairness <3f it all. He resolves to go the following day and speak to the superior of the official who fired him. He will not let this pass ‘Vwithout a fight - no more Mr. Nice Guy. The next day his 'anger' 138 has subsided. He decides that it would do no good to fight his dismissal. He does not go. One cannot help notice the strength which is mustered for the defense against explicit consciousness of the truth. One wonders why in such a case it would not be sufficient for the official simply to refuse to accept the charge of incompetence, to tell him- self, for example, that while the charge may be true, it is not clear that it is true — there were these unfair adversities and mitigating circumstances, and so on. Wouldn't that be enough to defend against an acknowledgment of his incompetence, and, thus, against making his consciousness of the charge explicit? If so, then why does the official go to such extremes? Why does he dggy_ to himself that he was incompetent, and concoct this elaborate explanation of his dismissals? . In answer to these questions, first, it is true that the official could avoid an acknowledgment of his incompetence — and thus avoid explicit consciousness of his incompetence - simply by refusing to accept the charge leaving the question of his incompetence open. He need not go so far as to deny the charge and provide himself with this elaborate rationalization. However, ileaving the question open in this way itself poses a threat, one Vvhich can be appreciated by again turning to a parallel case. If :someone else were to charge the official with incompetence to his :face, the official could avoid an acknowledgment to this person of -t:he truth of the charge by indicating to the person that while the 139 charge may be true, he did not accept it, and here is why: there were these mitigating circumstances, unfair adversities, etc. However, by avoiding the acknowledgment in this way, the official leaves himself open to further efforts on the part of the person who has levied the charge to get him (the official) to acknowledge his own incompetence. By leaving the question open, the official does acknowledge that the question is not settled, that further evidence concerning his own behavior, his job performance, and his circumstances can be advanced to settle the question. Moreover, in making this acknowledgment, he commits himself to a fair consideration of the evidence and to abiding by its decision. This leaves him open to efforts by the other person to advance evidence and arguments to show that he had performed incompetently. His position is now a very anxious one. As he knows, the evidence is overwhelmingly strong in favor of the charge that he had performed incompetently. If he allows it to be advanced, then, particularly if the other person is articulate and forceful, he risks being compelled into an acknowledgment of his incompetence. First, it will be difficult, if not impossible, for him to deny the force of the evidence. Unless lie is particularly clever and quick, and in good control of all of liis faculties, he may be backed into a corner where it would seem liopeless to him to do anything else but acknowledge his incompetence. 'Phis would be a situation in which his anxiety would be so great, éand the effort of defending himself against the evidence so difficult ~£ind painful, that the burden of defending himself would seem to him ‘to outweigh the suffering which would result from acknowledging the 140 truth - better to acknowledge the truth than to go through this hell any longer. Yet from the very outset, the official would be anxious, tense, and not in good control of his faculties. Hence, the risk of being forced into an acknowledgment of his incompetence is great if he allows the other person to advance the evidence which favors the charge. Secondly, even if he does not collapse under the burden of defending himself against the evidence, he still risks, in his anxious and tense state, the possibility of inadvertently acknowledging the truth, of allowing such an acknowledg- ment to slip from him. His position would not be very different from that of someone who, in his very anxiety to avoid making a certain error, makes the error in spite of all of his efforts to prevent it. Third, there may be other reasons why the official would feel that he might acknowledge the truth. For example, he may have a desire to be punished for something, or a self-destructive desire, and he may feel that he will succomb to such an urge once he gets drawn into a discussion of the evidence in favor of the charge of incompetence. Of course, the official may refuse to honor the commitment which he made when he left the question open. He may, for example, simply refuse to discuss the matter with the other person, or he may ‘walk off. But any such effort, disguised or not, to evade honoring the commitment to consider the evidence, will almost certainly be interpreted as a flight from a discussion of the evidence: why did he refuse to discuss the matter (walk off, change the subject, say that he was late for an appointment)? Because he knew that the 141 charge is correct, he knew that the evidence is overwhelmingly strong in its favor, and that he would not be able to deny it. Such an effort to evade a consideration of the evidence would be tantamount to - and would be treated by the other person as — an acknowledgment of the truth. In the broad sense of 'acknowledgement' that we are using, it would be an acknowledgment of the truth. By vigorously denying the charge of incompetence, the official avoids the risk of acknowledging the truth, and he avoids the painful anxiety and hardship which would be involved in defending himself against the evidence in favor of the charge of incompetence. By denying the charge he implies that the matter is settled, that it is not open to further discussion. There is nothing left to be said - or listened to. To return now to Pugmire's example, a similar threat is posed to the official if he does not deny to himself the charge of incompetence. If he leaves the question open, but then does not go on to consider the evidence, this evasion would be an acknowledg- ment of the truth of the charge of incompetence tg_himself. On the other hand, if he does consider the evidence, if he allows himself, that is, to become explicitly conscious of it, he may back himself into a corner where it would seem hopeless to do anything else but acknowledge his incompetence to himself. The burden of defending himself against the evidence may simply become so great, that it no longer seems worthwhile to maintain the defense. Moreover, even if 'he does not collapse under such a burden, he still risks inadvertently acknowledging the truth to himself. Finally, he may have a desire 142 to punish himself, or to destroy himself, and he may feel that he will succomb to this urge once he begins to make the evidence explicit. The official denies the truth of the charge of incompetence to himself in order to avoid putting himself in this position, and thus to avoid the risk of acknowledgment, the anxiety which this risk would produce, and the painful difficulties of trying to defend himself against the evidence. By denying the charge he settles the matter in his own mind. He does not need to consider the evidence in favor of the charge, and, as Pugmire tells us, he shrinks "from reminiscence about the wrong things", he omits "to recall the particulars of the history of painful episodes - tardiness, misplaced documents, grievously mistaken briefs submitted, warnings, the dismissals - which lurk, half obscure, in his memory." In Chapter Two I distinguished between the self-deceiver's feigning or pretending ignorance of the truth, and his pretending to believe a falsehood. The latter corresponds to the sort of 'strong defense' against explicit consciousness which we have taken Pugmire's official to be making. The former may include either only a 'weak' defense, or a 'weak' and 'strong' defense together. However, in speaking of 'pretending' we must be careful, for we are treading again close to the edge of paradox. The aim of pretending is not always to deceive, to prevent someone from knowing the truth. In play, a child may pretend to be a 'mommy, she may 143 to do the things that mommies do, to say the words that mommies say, and she may even pretend to think the thoughts that mommies think. But the aim of this is not to take anyone in, to keep them from knowing that she is not a mommy or to get them to believe that she is a mommy. Similarly in self-deception. The primary reason the self- deceiver pretends not to know or believe the truth, whether he is pretending to others or only to himself, has nothing to do with concealing his knowledge of the truth or the truth from others or from himself. Rather, the primary reason the self-deceiver pretends not to know or believe the truth is to avoid acknowledging the truth to himself and to others. And the reason he wants to avoid acknowledg- ing the truth to himself and to others is because he fears that were he to acknowledge the truth, whether to himself or to others, this would cause him great mental suffering; he would be crushed by despair, grief, guilt, shame, remorse, or sorrow. That acknowledgment of the truth or, what comes to the same thing, explicit consciousness of the truth is dreaded by the self-deceiver because he believes that it would cause him great mental suffering is part of our concept of self-deception. If someone avoided acknowledging the truth but did so for reasons other than this, then he would not be deceiving himself. I shall try to show that this is so in Chapter Five. What we need to note at present is that this is the self-deceiver's primary reason and that it , explains his pretending without the slightest recourse to the concepts of deception or concealment. 144 That the self—deceiver's primary reason for feigning or pretending ignorance of the truth has nothing to do with concealing either the truth or his knowledge of the truth is often vividly illustrated in examples of self-deception. Thus, when M refuses to sleep with his wife out of anger at her for her infidelity, then even though he does not acknowledge her infidelity, does not become explicitly conscious of it, he may still want her to know that he knows that she has been unfaithful, and that his refusal to sleep with her is a response to her infidelity. He may want her to know that he is angry at her for her infidelity to make her smart with shame and guilt at the realization, and he may choose this particular way of expressing his anger to her - refusing to sleep in the same bed - in order to express to her how loathsome he considers her - so loathsome, in fact, that he cannot stand to be near her, particularly not in such intimate contact - and thereby increase her feelings of loneliness, guilt, and isolation. If this is in fact the case, then he may be strongly depending on the fact that his wife does not want to bring their conflict out in the open, that for reasons of her own she strongly prefers to keep it submerged. By the same token, M risks bringing the conflict out in the open by these tactics, both because his particular wayof expressing his anger may force his wife closer to her lover in order to diminish her isolation, and because she may not want strongly enough to avoid open conflict that she is willing to endure such .punishment. 145 Similarly, when M confides to his friend that his wife cannot be sexually satisfied by any man but disavows any infidelity on her part, thus avoiding an acknowledgment of her infidelity, M may know that his friend knows of his wife's infidelity and of his (M's) knowledge of her infidelity, and M may make this remark concerning his wife in order to get his friend to believe that he bears no responsibility for her infidelity. In effect, M is saying, "Don't blame me. I had nothing to do with it. She is over-sexed. She could not remain faithful to any man, no matter how virile he is or how good a husband he is." But he manages to communicate this without acknowledging his wife's infidelity. And here M may be depending on his friend's tact and kindness to keep the issue submerged, to keep it from coming out in the open. An even more striking group of examples of this sort is provided in Eugene O'Neill's play, The Iceman Cometh. The characters in the play are crowded together at Harry Hope's, a combination of cheap gin-mill and sleazy hotel. Each of the nineteen characters is deceiving himself about something which is central in the way he lives his life, and each person maintains a facade of pretenses. Yet these pretenses cannot be aimed at taking the others in, for each character knows that the other characters are aware of his self-deception, and is constantly teased by the others about it. For the most part, this teasing is accepted in a good-humoured . way, or is met with mock 'anger', and it is only when a character is pressed too closely to acknowledge the truth that he begins to 146 show real anger and resentment. Episodes of the latter sort are few and are not vigorously pressed until Hickey, a salesman who periodically stops by the bar, returns. Hickey stubbornly tries to get each of the characters to acknowledge the truth, He does so by challenging their pretenses, by pointing out to each one of them how inconsistent their lives are with their facade of pretenses. Rather than acknowledge the truth, each of them attempts to live up to the facade he has created, a fact which causes much unhappiness, dissention, and bitter resentment towards Hickey . It is only when Hickey inadvertently reveals that he too is deceiving himself about a painful truth, and thus reveals a similar weakness that the others can exploit, that Hickey drops his efforts to get the others to acknowledge the truth. Hickey becomes one of them, tied to them by indissoluble bonds of kinship. This new realization of the role of feigning ignorance in self-deception must force us to revise somewhat our earlier account of the self-deceiver's feigning. Earlier we said that a necessary condition of someone's deceiving himself is that he feigns ignorance of the truth. Now, however, we shall have to drop this claim and say instead that a necessary condition of anyone's deceiving himself is that he feigns ignorance of the truth whgg this is necessary or is perceived by him to be necessary in order to avoid acknowledging the truth. This means that it is possible - though I suspect that such cases are quite rare - for someone to deceive himself without .ever feigning ignorance of the truth. Such a case will exist when someone is deceiving himself and never finds it necessary to feign 147 ignorance in order to avoid acknowledging the truth and has no other reason as well to feign ignorance. We need not, however, revise everything we said earlier about the self—deceiver's feigning. Even though the self-deceiver's primary reason for feigning ignorance is to avoid acknowledging the truth, this is not his 921y_reason in most cases. Here we can divide these further reasons into two categories. First, there are reasons which relate to the purpose of avoiding consciousness of the truth in any form, whether explicit or non-explicit. Some self-deceivers wish not only to avoid explicit consciousness of the truth but all consciousness of the truth, and most self-deceivers at least part of the time try to avoid consciousness of the truth other than explicit consciousness. These wishes give rise to reasons for the self-deceiver to conceal his knowledge of the truth from others. Given that the self-deceiver wants to avoid conscious- ness of the truth, he will not want to be reminded by others of the truth, and by concealing his knowledge of the truth from people who do not know that he knows, he manages to reduce the likelihood that they will remind him of it. Many people, especially if they realize that making him aware of the truth is likely to be quite painful for him, will not want to be the person who informs him of it, and thus will refrain from trying to get him to recognize the truth. Other people, even though they are not deterred by the knowledge that they are likely to cause him pain, are likely to give up trying to get him to realize the truth if he is persistent enough and his ignorance appears intractable enough. 148 Moreover, the self-deceiver who wishes to avoid more than just explicit consciousness of the truth has reason to feign ignorance even in the presence of persons who know that he knows the truth. Some of these people, when they see the self-deceiver feigning ignorance, will realize that he does not want to be reminded of the truth, that consciousness of it is painful to him, and then, whether out of motives of kindness, pity, fear, or a wish to remain in the self-deceiver's good graces, will carefully refrain from mentioning it to him. Even those persons who are not disposed to leave him unreminded may, if he is persistent and intractable enough, eventually give up trying to remind him of the truth. Moreover, in dealing with both kinds of people, the self- deceiver will have behaved in a way which does not conflict with his concealing his knowledge from people who do not know that he knows the truth. He will not, for example, have acknowledged the truth and asked or begged not to be reminded of it, thus risking the chance that word of his acknowledgment will get back to people from whom he is trying to conceal his knowledge of the truth. The first category of reasons apply to self-deceivers only in so far as they are trying to avoid consciousness of the truth other than just explicit consciousness. The following reasons, all in the second category, may apply to any self-deceiver, even one 'who wishes to avoid only explicit consciousness of the truth. First, the self-deceiver may feign ignorance of the truth in order to . conceal his knowledge of the truth from others who do not know that 149 he knows the truth. And he may want to conceal his knowledge of it from them because he fears that if they knew that he knew the truth, then they would press him to acknowledge it, as, e.g., Hickey tries to force the residents of Harry Hope's to acknowledge the truth, thus at the very least unpleasantly complicating his life and making it more anxious, and at the worst, forcing him into the unhappy and depressing position of trying to live up to his pretenses or even trapping him or tricking him into acknowledging the truth. Secondly, he may feign ignorance of the truth in order to deal with the people who know that he knows the truth. By doing so, they will see that he does not want to acknowledge the truth, and so may either refrain from doing anything which draws him close to acknowledging it, or, providing he is persistent enough, will eventually tire of trying to get him to acknowledge the truth. Certain other frequent, though non-essential components of self-deception dove—tail very closely with the self-deceiver's efforts to avoid explicit consciousness, to avoid (sometimes and in some cases) consciousness of the truth, and his feigning ignorance. of the truth, so it is just as well that we mention them here. First, as we have already noted, self-deceivers frequently try to avoid learning new evidence which points to the truth or new details which contribute to their knowledge of the truth. One reason that the self-deceiver does this is because the more evidence he has at his disposal, the more difficult it is for him to convincingly feign ignorance of the truth, and hence the more difficult it is for him 150 to avoid acknowledging the truth and to conceal his knowledge of the truth from others. In addition, each time the self-deceiver becomes aware of a fresh piece of evidence or a fresh detail, the self-deceiver becomes conscious of the truth, often painfully so, and this provides another reason for avoiding the acquisition of new details and evidence. Finally, the more evidence and details the self—deceiver acquires, the more difficult it is for him to avoid consciousness and explicit consciousness of the truth in the future. For example, even though he knows his wife's lover and the lover's car on sight, M may try to avoid learning the name of his wife's lover because, if he learns the name, then each time he hears it, he will be reminded of his wife's infidelity. The second frequent, though non-essential component of self- deception is the device of distraction. By preoccupying his mind in some activity or group of activities, the self-deceiver lessens the chance that he will be reminded of the truth, and so lessens the chance that a painful consciousness of the truth will be thrust on him or that he will be tempted, tricked, trapped, or compelled to become explicitly conscious of the truth. When he is painfully reminded of the truth or threatened with explicit consciousness of it, the self-deceiver will often throw himself into some activity in order to occupy his mind and so crowd out consciousness of the truth. In order for any activity to be useful for these purposes, it must be absorbing, exciting, and interesting enough, or dulling enough, that the self-deceiver can engage himself in it without pause 151 or rest, and in spite of fatigue, and so that it leaves him no room to think of anything else. Drinking, sex, eating, drugs, smoking, work, certain forms of entertainment and play, and sleep often fit this bill admirably so that self-deceivers frequently get hung up on these things, often to the point of obsession. The more he dreads consciousness of the truth, and the more difficult it is to prevent consciousness of the truth, the more desperately and energetically he will throw himself into distracting activities until he seems totally obsessed, driven by forces beyond his control. But the 'driving force' of the obsession is the self- deceiver's fear of consciousness of the truth. In connection with the counter-example we are building, we do not need to suppose that M feigns ignorance of his wife's infidelity in order to avoid acknowledging the truth to another person, though we do need to suppose that he would have feigned ignorance of the truth h3§_circumstances developed in such a way that he believed it to be necessary in order to avoid acknowledging the truth to another person. On the other hand, we gg_need to suppose that M pretends not to know or believe that his wife has been unfaithful to him in order to avoid acknowledging her infidelity tg_himself, for under the circumstances, a failure on his part to make this pretense would constitute, I think, an acknowledg- ment of the truth. Thus we might suppose, for example, that when - upon seeing his wife's lover's car - M suffers feelings of suffocating warmth, heaviness, nausea, and all the rest, he exclaims to himself, "My God! What's happening to me?", as though he were being stricken down by some physical affliction and did not know what was happening to him. At the same time he 'plays' at being afraid in the way he would be afraid if his experience were caused by some physical affliction beyond his ken. He opens his eyes wide in 'horror', his mouth drops in 'shock' and 'surprise', his hands and arms stiffen at the wheel until his knuckles are white, as though he were desperately trying to 'hold on' until the spell subsides. The whole time this exaggeration is helped along by the fact that he is somewhat shocked and surprised at seeing his wife's lover's car parked near his house and it feeds on the sensations which he is experiencing and which are a reaction to what he sees. As the spell subsides, M gasps in 'relief', he tells himself that he has been working too hard and is exhausted, and it is then that the thought strikes him to go to the bar on the lake. As he leaves for the bar, he maintains the posture of a man who has been stricken by an 'attack', who is reacting in fear and shock, and who is seeking out a drink and a quiet place in order to settle his nerves and compose himself. This additional supposition requires that we amend the earlier statement of our example. We can no longer suppose that no images, no internal speech passes through M's mind, and that M says nothing to himself, for we have supposed above that he does say something to himself. But clearly this additional supposition in no way commits us to conceding that M has a vehicle for his consciousness of his wife's infidelity, and so it does not threaten the status of 153 the example as a counter-example to the vehicular theory of consciousness. With this, our task of building a counter-example to the claim that self-deceivers are never conscious of the truth except in quite special circumstances (drink, drugs, hypnotism, psychoanalysis) is finished. When M has this experience he is conscious of his wife's infidelity, though non-explicitly so, and the example is clearly consistent with the supposition that M is deceiving himself about his wife's infidelity. Moreover, not only do we have this counter- example to the above claim, in the course of building our counter- example we have uncovered a number of other such counter-examples. Pugmire's incompetent official is conscious of his incompetent performances, yet he may very well be deceiving himself about his imcompetence, and Pugmire supposes that he is. M is non-explicitly conscious of his wife's infidelity when he refuses to sleep with her in reaction to her infidelity, pretending 'annoyance' at her tossing and turning and an inability to get sleep with her, yet clearly we may also suppose that he is deceiving himself about her infidelity. Likewise when M confides to a friend that his wife is 'over-sexed', but disavows infidelity on her part, he is non- explicitly conscious of her infidelity, yet he may very well be deceiving himself about it. The patrons of Harry Hope's bar are often non-explicitly conscious of some central feature in their lives, yet they are also deceiving themselves about their lives. The claim that the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth 154 except in quite special circumstances is not only false, it misses the mark widely. For not only are self-deceivers sometimes conscious of the truth in ordinary circumstances, they are frequently conscious of the truth in all sorts of everyday, non-special circumstances. 155 Section 4. The self-deceiver is essentially a person who is not explicitly conscious of the truth during the period of his self- deception; who has over-riding reasons for not becoming explicitly conscious of the truth during this period of time; who, when he is conscious of the truth, does whatever he deems necessary to prevent his consciousness from becoming explicit in accordance with these over-riding reasons; and who, when he is not conscious of the truth, wogld, in accordance with his over-riding reasons, do what he deemed necessary to avoid explicit consciousness of the truth wgrg he to become conscious of the truth. It is possible to be a self-deceiver and never be conscious of the truth or feign or pretend ignorance of the truth. On the other hand, such cases can never be detected with any certainty, for it is the occasion on which the self—deceiver is conscious of the truth and is feigning ignorance of it which provides the most telling grounds for attributing self-deception to him. Without the evidence provided by his consciousness of the truth and his feigning ignorance, the best one could do is to accumulate evidence tending to show that he knows the truth and has strong reasons to avoid becoming explicitly conscious of it, and this would tend to supply some support for the speculation that if he were to become conscious of the truth, then he would avoid making his consciousness explicit in accordance with those reasons. However, the only way to confirm such a speculative hypothesis with any degree of certainty - or reliability would be if he did become conscious of the truth and avoided making his consciousness explicit in accordance with those 156 reasons, and one determined that he did this. Thus the cases of self—deception which we detect, and thus, on which our attention focuses, are those in which the self-deceiver is conscious of the truth, feigns or pretends ignorance of it, and, to a lesser extent, avoids learning new evidence and details, and attempts to distract himself in some absorbing activity. The second major paradox of self-deception does not arise in the above account of self-deception, nor, hopefully, does any paradox. We recognize that the self-deceiver is often conscious of the truth, and also that our description of him as purposely avoiding making his consciousness of the truth explicit entails that he is conscious of the truth. But because being conscious of the truth is not the same thing as being explicitly conscious of it, we do not land in the contradiction that the self-deceiver is and is not conscious of the truth. He may often be conscious of the truth, but he never willingly makes his consciousness of the truth explicit. Moreover, this account recognizes that self-deception is essentially purposive, thus according with our intuitions. Accounts such as Freud's, which construe self-deception as essentially independent of the self-deceiver's purposes and as being imposed on him by forces beyond his control, receive their primary support from the vehicular theory of consciousness, according to which all consciousness necessarily requires a vehicle, and thus is explicit consciousness. Since the self-deceiver is not explicitly conscious of the truth, they conclude that he is not conscious of the truth at all, and then, in order to avoid the second major paradox of 157 self-deception, they conclude that it is false that he is not conscious of the truth because he has an over-riding reason for not becoming conscious of the truth. Instead, they explain his not being conscious as due to forces operating beyond the self-deceiver's control. The development of this view in Freud's work is interesting and deserves special comment. Even when stating his mature views, Freud hints at counter—examples both to the vehicular theory of consciousness and to the claim that the self-deceiver never becomes conscious of the truth except in special circumstances. Thus, w for example, in speaking of patients who were showing resistance as they approached closer to the truth, Freud says, "We then tell him that he is dominated by a resistance; but he is quite unaware of the fact, and, even if he guesses from his unpleasurable feeling that a resistance is now at work in him, he does not know what it is nor how to describe it."19 One is tempted to explain such feelings of discomfort as due to the fact that the patient is conscious that he is being drawn closer and closer to acknowledging the truth, that he has grown fearful, and that his feelings of discomfort are a part of his fear. But though Freud might have tried such an explanation at the time of 3 Studien fiber Hysteria (where, as we have seen, he treats repression as intentional on the patient's part), in his later works he was prevented from doing so by his recognition that his patients were not explicitly conscious of repressing the truth. Holding as he did a 158 vehicular theory of consciousness, he concluded that his patients were not conscious of repressing the truth. But, if the patient were himself purposely repressing the truth and purposely putting up a resistance, then he would be conscious of doing so. Freud takes the patient to be not conscious of doing this, and so he treats the patient as though he were not purposely repressing the truth. r; This leads him directly to the view that the repression emanates i from forces beyond the patient's control. This leaves the purposes i for the resistance and the repression hanging up in the air, without an agent. In Freud's works this difficulty is obscured by Freud's Pel- frequent personifications of parts of the mind which seem to give an agent to which these purposes can be attributed. The role of the vehicular theory of consciousness in this deve10pment is very clear and very important. Had Freud rejected this theory, he would have seen that the fact that the patient is not explicitly conscious of repressing the truth does not mean that he is not conscious of repressing the truth, and thus he could have retained an explanation in terms of the patient's purposes. This would, of course, have bfought him face to face with the second inajor paradox of self-deception. But, with the vehicular theory (of consciousness out of the way, this paradox would have dissolved, for without the vehicular theory of consciousness, there would have lbeen no bar to recognizing that patients are conscious of the truth, 'though non-explicitly so, and without the claim that the self- .«ieceiver is not conscious of the truth except in special <1irtumstances,there is no paradox. 159 The course of development of Freud's views suggest that what he regarded as the dynamic unconscious, the ch, could more appropriate- ly and correctly be considered the mass of ideas which can become conscious but which cannot become explicitly conscious because of the patient's over—riding reasons for preventing them from becoming explicitly conscious. Rather than speaking of these ideas as belonging to the Unconscious, it would then be better to describe F them as belonging to the Repressed. The Repressed, in turn, would 3 be part of the Egg, the Preconscious, though it would have to be sharply distinguished from another part of the Pcs, the Pecs, Pre— . Explicitly Conscious, which would include those ideas in the Egg_ which can become explicitly conscious. The gg_in turn would have to be divided into the Eggg, Non-Explicitly Conscious, and the Egg, Explicitly Conscious. How well this suggestion fares will depend, of course, on the extent to which Freud fashioned his categories in order to accomodate self—deception. This is a question whose answer at the present time is not clear to me, though clearly some revision of these categories is necessary if the foregoing arguments are correct.20 While we are on the topic of Freud, it is worthwhile noting that Fingarette develops a reinterpretation of Freud, based on his (Fingarette's) own analysis of self-deception, in order to resolve a problem which arises through Freud's recognition that resistance, repression, and other defensive manoeuvres are 'unconscious', i.e., in our terms, 'non-explicitly conscious‘. Fingarette states the problem thus: 160 If it is the ego which regulates defense, which, fer example, represses an id derivative, gg!_does it keep itself unconscious of what it is doing? Is its defensive activity gynamically_unconscious, i.e., itself the object of defencs? But then how shall we account for this latter defensive manoeuvre, i.e., the 'second-level' manoeuvre of keeping from consciousness the initial defensive manoeuvre? Is this 'second-level' defensive manoeuvre available to consciousness, or is it in turn dynamically unconscious because, for example, repressed by still a third level of repressive defence? Then somewhere, finally, we must come to grips with the problem of the last term in this hierarchy. Is the last defence in the hierarchy conscious (or readily available to consciousness)? The only alternative to an infinite regress would seem to be to suppose that the defence-- or at least the last defence in such a hierarchy--is ESE. dynamically unconscious. How, then, shall we account for that resistance to the uncovering of defence which is actually found in therapy?21 Fingarette notes that: ...there is no theoretical problem about how the repressed impulse is kept from consciousness. According to standard doctrine, the ego withholds a hypercathexis (i.e., the specific attention-cathexis which establishes a mental content as explicitly conscious), In addition, the ego directs a counter-cathexis onto the ideational derivatives of the impulse, thus removing them from status as preconscious (i.e., from the status of being available for attention hypercathexis). The impulse is now dynamically unconscious.22 But the problem at hand is not how an impulse is kept unconscious, but how the defensive activity is itself kept unconscious. To resolve this problem, Fingarette offers a reinterpretation of Freud's theory which assimilates the theory to his own. The answer to this question lies in turning our question upside down. Instead of asking how the defensive activity is kept unconscious, we need to ask how it-- or any mental content--ever is made to be conscious. Psychoanalysts have tended to overlook the significance of the fact that mere absence of counter-cathexis is not enough to make something explicitly conscious, 161 though it allows it to be preconscious. The ego has a further task if it is to make an ego activity (or indeed any mental activity) explicitly conscious. As we have already noted, psychoanalytic theory postulates an additional cathexis, an 'attention hypercathexis', if anything is to be made explicitly conscious. To say a mental element is pggconscious is to say, among other things, that it satisfies all the conditions for being conscious except one--it is not hypercathected. ...whatever the other changes in his views over the years, Freud always was convinced that language was the essence, r- or very intimately related to the essence of preconscious- ness and consciousness. This strongly suggests, though .Freud never put it in this way, that the 'mental act' denoted by 'hypercathexis' is essentially a kind of linguistic or paralinguistic act. It is, I suggest, much the same as what I have called 'spelling-out'. I think it is reasonable to say that preconsciousness is the state I of being available for spelling-out on particular appropriate l occasions, and that Freud means by 'conscious' what I have called 'explicit consciousness'. The ego does not hypercathect at random or in some automatic way; it hypercathects when there is reason to do so--and of course it will not hypercathect when (a) there is no teason not to do so, or (b) there is overeriding reason not to do so. The latter consideration is relevant in the case of defence. For a defensive counter-cathexis (which corresponds, as we shall see, with what I shall disavowal) amounts to a removal, as a matter of 'policy', of some mental content from the status of being available to hypercathexis, i.e., spelling-out. Fingarette's sympathetic reinterpretation of Freud is, I believe, too generous.) It does not take into account the fact of Freud's allegiance to a vehicular theory of consciousness, and the consequent treatment of self-deceivers as though they were prevented from becoming conscious of the truth by forces beyond their control. Fingarette's suggestion that Freud was using the term 'conscious' as equivalent to his own term 'explicitly conscious' is false. While it is true that Freud tended to apply the term 'conscious' only to explicit consciousness, this was not because he used the term with the 162 same meaning, but rather because he held a vehicular theory of consciousness. There is another respect, too, in which we differ from Fingarette. Fingarette feels that it is necessary to introduce the notion of a 'policy' of not becoming explicitly conscious in order to account for the self-deceiver's not becoming explicitly conscious of the truth or, what comes to the same thing, for the r- non-availability of a mental content to explicit consciousness. I can see no justification for the introduction of this notion. -.|o"l The existence of an over-riding reason for not-spelling out the \ . I truth is sufficient in itself to explain why the self-deceiver does not become conscious of the truth in an explicit way. So long as the self-deceiver has such a r eason, he will not willingly make his consciousness explicit. Thus, if we are going to engage in a reinterpretation of Freud, it would be better to explain the non- availability of a mental content to explicit consciousness in terms of the possession of an over-riding reason for not becoming explicitly conscious of the truth. Moreover, not only is the introduction of a 'policy' not necessary, but it seems to be out of place in a context of self- deception. It would seem that one cannot be said to have a policy unless it is explicitly adopted, and that would require a formula- tion of the policy in words. If this is correct, then self-deceivers could not have a policy of not becoming explicitly conscious of the truth, To have such a policy, he would have to spell it out, and that would require spellingeout the truth. Thus, in the very act of adopting the policy, the self-deceiver would violate it. 163 Having made his reinterpretation of Freud, Fingarette goes on to give his solution to the problem of avoiding an infinite regress of defensive activities. In essence, his solution is that once an impulse, e.g., an aggressive impulse, is counter-cathected, no separate defence is required at all to keep the defence against the impulse 'unconscious'. To hypercathect the defence would entail hypercathecting the impulse, and so a counter-cathexis of the impulse is itself a counter cathexis of the defence. The aim of inhibiting the expression of an aggressive impulse is the kind of think which in general can become conscious. When this is the aim of defence, there is a peculiar difficulty; to hypercathect the aim would be to hypercathect the aggressive impulse as well, for the aggressive impulse is an essential constituent of the context of the aim. But if we assume there is defence, we are assuming the aggressive impulse has been counter-cathected: thus it now is in a status which precludes hypercathexis. Thus, in turn the aim of inhibiting the impulse is perforce excluded from hypercathexis too. Much the same kind of argument holds with regard to the motive of defence [anxiety]; to hypercathect the anxiety gg_§gg.gg_the aggressive impulse is of course to hypercathect the impulse. But this, as already remarked, is excluded. At most the ego may hyper- cathect the anxiety pg£_gg, But of course the anxiety will then be perceived either as free-floating anxiety or as attached (displaced) to some other datum of consciousness. Thus, to summarize, given a counter-cathexis of the impulse, the entire dynamic complex is excluded from consciousness--a theoretical conclusion which exactly con- forms with clinical fact. This conclusion also is parallel to the account I have given of the automatically self-covering aspect of the policy not to spell something out.24 Avoiding an infinite regress of defensive activities is not the only problem which Fingarette finds in Freud's theories and tries to resolve. Fingarette takes it to be a "fundamental problem at the core of psychoanalytic theory" to provide an adequate answer to the question, "why should the ego aim to keep anything at all 164 unconscious, whether it be defence or impulse?"25 He charges psychoanalysts, including Freud, with assuming "some kind of hiding of the impulse from oneself, some kind of ignorance due to successful 'disguise'."26 If this is true, it would mean that Freud's theory was more deeply enmired in the first major paradox of self-deception than I have indicated in my treatment of his views. But the charge is erroneous, at least in Freud's case. ? As we have seen, repression does not in any literal sense aim at concealing the truth. The direct aim of repression is the avoidance of 'unpleasure', or, in Freud's later works, of anxiety “In which would be induced in the ego by the superego. Nowhere can I find the suggestion that the immediate purpose of repression is hiding or concealing something, and that avoiding 'unpleasure' or anxiety is contingent upon such hiding. Keeping oneself ignorant of the truth is not a link in the chain of avoiding unpleasure or anxiety; the avoidance is assumed simply by repressing the idea. It is true that Freud often speaks of ideas being 'disguised' in order to evade the ego's repression, but this is a totally different matter and does not involve the contention that repression is a kind of concealment or disguising. It is also true that while repression is not a form of concealment for Freud and does not aim at ignorance, still Freud's construal of repression seems to have the implication that the effect of repression is a kind of ignorance. Again, however, this is quite different from saying that the aim of repression is to induce or maintain ignorance. Moreover, his view of repression seems to have this implication because of the 165 invalid reasoning set out in argument b(l)"'. Whether or not Freud fell into such reasoning, we would still not be justified in saying that for him the aim of repression is a kind of hiding of the impulse from oneself. Thus Fingarette's charge that "the main outcome of defence was thought to be a form of self-induced ignorance" is false.27 166 Section 5. We have not yet resolved all of the difficulties in Fingarette's analysis. It seems to be Fingarette's view that in philosophical analysis of the concept of self-deception we should not try to answer the question of whether the self-deceiver knows the truth, and for the most part, his analysis of self-deception r‘ in terms of spelling-out characterizes self-deception in a way which avoids this question. Fingarette's reasons for taking this position are not clear. In one place he says: ‘w— |"_.. -'-.I -'l- Paradoxes arise in connection with self-deception when we characterize it primarily in terms of belief and knowledge, or in terms of 'perception' language such as 'appear' and 'see'.28 But it is not clear what he means by this. He may only mean what we noted earlier, namely, that "the deep paradox of self-deception lies...in the element of knowing, intentional ignorance." But if this is so, the remark does not justify him in avoiding altogether the question of whether or not the self-deceiver knows the truth. To the contrary, it points up the urgency of settling this question. It is true, of course, that so long as we do not try to answer this question in our own analysis, that analysis will not fall prey to the paradox. But this is not to resolve the paradox, it is simply to ignore it. Moreover, if Fingarette does hold that we ought not try to answer the question of whether the self-deceiver knows the truth, then he did not scrupulously follow his own dictum. Speaking of the self-deceiver, he tells us that: 167 The purposefulness and the often remarkable ingenuity with which he carries through his engagement lead us to insist that 'He must know what he's doing; he must know the truth.‘29 In everyday speech we use the word 'know' to capture the complex purposefulness of the actual engagement: 'Really', 'at bottom', 'in the last analysis', 'deep in his heart'--he knows.29 He then goes on to characterize this way of speaking as "idiomatic language", and then, on the same page, he delivers his dictum against "persisting in such questions as, 'Does he really know?‘ or 'How can he do all this and not know?'"29 It is hard not to see an inconsistency in all of this, for Fingarette seems to be suggesting that the self-deceiver 'knows' the truth only in an idiomatic sense, and thus, that he does not know the truth in any straight-forward sense of 'know'. Apparently he has answered the forbidden question, though this is not certain since his position on these matters is far from clear. Things become more confused when he tries to explain why we use this 'idiom', as opposed to an idiom such as he has proposed. The reasons are: Because the crux of the affair up to this point lies in the area demarcated by the phrase 'becoming explicitly conscious', and because consciousness has traditionally been characterized in the language and imagery of knowing, believing, and perceiving.3O I do not have the slightest idea of what the first 'reason' given amounts to. As for the second reason, while it is true that consciousness has traditionally been characterized in the language of perceiving, especially vision, it is absolutely false that 168 consciousness has been portrayed in terms of knowledge and belief. Quite the reverse, for knowledge and belief have for centuries been characterized in terms of perception, again especially vision, and in terms of consciousness. Moreover, even the characterization of consciousness in terms of vision has been harmful to the analysis of self-deception primarily because it contributed to the vehicular theory of consciousness. By itself, the characterization need not lead to any paradoxical consequences for self-deception. The earlier parts of Fingarette's argument fair no better. He argues that we want to say that the self-deceiver 'knows' the truth because of "the purposefulness and the often remarkable ingenuity with which he carries through his engagement." But this is wrong on at least two counts. First, people deceive themselves about things other than their own engagements, i.e., their own purposeful doings, acts, actions, and activities. M, for example, deceives himself about his wife's infidelity, and yet we still want to say that he knows the truth. We can, of course, speak of his wife's infidelity as a purposeful engagement, but they are his wife's purposes, not his, and they do not point to his knowledge in the way they point to his wife's knowledge. Secondly, and more importantly, even if we restrict consideration to those cases in which someone deceives himself about (his own purposeful doings, acts, actions, and activities, Fingarette's contention is still wrong. For it is not only or even primarily the purposefulness of his engagement which provides the impetus to 169 saying that he knows the truth. A number of things contribute to this, e.g., the slips discussed in Chapter Two, but of equal or greater importance is a feature of self-deception which Fingarette builds into his own analysis of self-deception, and which we have not yet discussed in this connection. I am referring to the purposefulness with which the self-deceiver avoids becoming explicitly conscious of the truth. It is Fingarette's view that the self-deceiver persistently avoids spelling-out his engagement, i.e., that he persistently avoids becoming explicitly conscious of his engagement. But this avoidance is not accidental or coincidental, it is purposive: he does not become explicitly conscious of the truth because he has an over-riding reason not to do so. I shall show that it follows from this that the self-deceiver Egggg_the truth. First, it is clear that a necessary condition of someone's being conscious that S is that he knows that S. Just as one cannot be conscious that S if it is not true that S, so one cannot be conscious that S if one only believes that S - though, instead, «one can be thinking that S. Nor is it an objection to this claim 'that, for example, one can be conscious that one is in pain, but «one cannot know that one is in pain. One can be conscious g£.a ‘pain, e.g., in one's arm, But this is not to say that one is conscious t_ha_t'; one is in pain. And if it is true that one cannot know that one is in pain, then it is also true that one cannot be conscious that one is in pain, even though it may be true that one feels pain in one's arm, and so is conscious of it. 170 So, someone who does not know that S cannot become conscious that S. Moreover, since a necessary condition of being explicitly conscious that S is that one is conscious that S, if someone does not know that S, then it is impossible for him to become explicitly conscious that S. Suppose now that someone does not know that S, and so cannot become explicitly conscious that S. Then it would be fglgg_to say of this person that "he does not become explicitly conscious that S because he has an over-riding for not doing so." The fact that such a person does not become explicitly conscious that S would have to be explained in terms of his not knowing that S. So long as it is impossible for him to become explicitly conscious that S, an explanation in terms of his reasons simply cannot be applied. Notice that this issue turns solely on the force of the 'because' in such explanations. Someone might not know that S, and thus could not become explicitly conscious that 8, even when he had a strong reason for not becoming explicitly conscious that S, and even knew that he had such a reason. However, so long as he does not know that S, that reason cannot be invoked to explain the fact that he has not become explicitly conscious that S. The reason is, so to speak, 'inoperative'. Suppose, for example, that Brown does not know that S. He may know that if he did know that S and were to become explicitly conscious that S, then he would be weighed down with shame and :remorse. Clearly, Brown has a strong reason for not becoming explicitly conscious that S, and he knows that he has this reason. 171 But his having this reason does not explain, and cannot be appealed to in order to explain, the fact that he is not conscious that S. In order to explain this, we would have to refer to his lack of knowledge that S. It is Fingarette's view that the self-deceiver does not become explicitly conscious that S because he has an over-riding reason for not becoming explicitly conscious. His position entails that the self-deceiver Egggg the truth, and thus he is committed by his own account to saying that the self-deceiver knows the truth. While in our own account (cf. pages 155-156, above) we have allowed that in some cases of self-deception it is not true that the self-deceiver is not explicitly conscious of the truth because he has an over-riding reason for not becoming explicitly conscious of the truth, still we have maintained that in those cases which we detect with any certainty, it is true that the self-deceiver is not explicitly conscious of the truth because he has an over-riding reason for not becoming so. But in order to establish the latter with any certainty, and doing so is our best proof that he is deceiving himself, we must first establish with certainty that he knows the truth, since knowledge of the truth is a necessary condition for such an explanation to hold. To show this we may draw on many aspects of the self-deceiver's circumstances, speech, and behavior. Where the truth concerns the self-deceiver's own engagement, then the apparent purposefulness and ingenuity of it will be one, but only one, factor in our determination. 172 The foregoing argument does not show that all self-deceivers know the truth. But it is a telling argument. First, it under- mines Fingarette's arguments to show that the self-deceiver only knows the truth in an idiomatic sense - if that was the aim of those arguments. Secondly, again providing that Fingarette held, as he seems to have done, that self-deceivers know the truth only in an idiomatic sense, the argument shows that he was being inconsistent. Third, the argument can be expanded to show that all self-deceivers know the truth. It leaves only one kind of case in doubt; those cases in which the self-deceiver is not conscious of the truth during the period of his self-deception. We cannot explain the fact that such self-deceivers are not explicitly conscious of the truth in terms of over-riding reasons, because not only is knowledge of the truth necessary for such an explanation to hold, but consciousness of the truth is also. Since such self-deceivers are not conscious of the truth, it is the latter which explains their not being explicitly cons cious -of the truth, and not their over-riding reasons. Suppose that X is a person who does ggg_know the truth, but who has over-riding reasons for not making his consciousness of the truth explicit if he were to become conscious of the truth. If he knew the truth and were to become conscious of it, then he would avoid making his consciousness explicit in accordance with his over-riding reasons. One must admit, I think, that even if X knew the truth, but were not conscious of it, etc., his case would be a border-line one. The expression 'is deceiving himself' is 173 a metaphorical one, based on a likening of the self-deceiver to two persons, one of whom knows the truth and who in some way prevents the other, who does not know the truth, from learning it. In paradigm cases of self-deception there is something which corresponds to the other-deceiver's preventing the deceived from learning the truth, namely the self-deceiver's purposeful avoidance of explicit consciousness of the truth. But in X's case, even if he knew the truth, there would not be this important point of similarity since X is not conscious of the truth, and so never purposely avoids making his consciousness explicit. Saying that X is a self-deceiver in such circumstances may strive one as being the same as saying that Y has deceived Z, where Y has done nothing to prevent Z from learning the truth, but would try to do so if Z seemed to be on the verge of learning the truth and Y had the opportunity to interfere. It would be incorrect to say that Y had deceived or is deceiving Z in such circumstances. Similarly, if X never avoids making his consciousness of the truth explicit, there would seem to be no 'deception', and so it would seem to be incorrect to say that he is deceiving himself. This argument is, I believe, correct, and its acceptance will entail a modification of our earlier statement of self- deception. It is false that someone is deceiving himself if he Iggygg, throughout the period of his self-deception, conscious of the truth, and so never avoids making his consciousness explicit. What misled us is that self-deception is continuous.~ A person may 174 be said to be deceiving himself throughout a stretch of time, perhaps a very long stretch of time, during which he is not conscious of the truth, and so, during which he does not purposely avoid making his consciousness explicit. This may lead us to think that self-deception is a state or a disposition, and we may then look at conscious on which the self-deceiver is conscious of the truth and does avoid making his consciousness explicit as simply actualizations of that state or disposition. This is, in fact, precisely how we treated the matter earlier, on pages 155-156. However, this view is not entirely correct. While self- deception is continuous, and does involve a state such as we have described - such a state is essential to it - it does not coincide with this state. What marks the beginning of a period of self-deception is an occasion on which the self-deceiver, for the first time, is conscious of the truth and purposely avoids making his consciousness explicit. Usually, though perhaps not always, this will be the occasion on which the self-deceiver first learns the truth, when he realizes it for the first time, or, so to speak, it dawns on him for the first time. Thereafter, he continues to deceive himself until he becomes explicitly conscious of the truth willingly; he does not, e.g., slip or is not tricked into becoming explicitly conscious of the truth. Throughout the intervening period he need not be conscious of the truth, he need simply have the disposition we have described. But possession of this disposition is not by itself sufficient for him to be deceiving himself. 175 Here there is an exact analogy with other-deception. The other—deceiver must know the truth, and he must be disposed to prevent someone from learning the truth. But this is not sufficient for us to say that he is deceiving the other person. In order for that to be the case, there must be at least one occasion on which he does prevent the other person from learning the truth. Then, there is a sense of 'deceive', what we might call the continuous sense in which we can say that he is deceiving this other person from this first occasion on which he prevents the other person from learning the truth and for so long as he has the disposition to prevent him from learning it. Given such a first occasion, if the other person learns the truth and also realizes that he has been taken in, then he might say to the deceiver, "You have been deceiving me all this time", i.e., continuously. The expression 'is deceiving himself' is used in an analogous way. Thus there cannot be a case of self-deception in which the self-deceiver does not know the truth. For X to be deceiving himself, he must from the start know the truth because his self- deception does not begin until he is conscious of the truth and purposely avoids making his consciousness explicit. X is not a self-deceiver. In one way, this alteration in our account brings it closer to Fingarette's analysis. He was right in suggesting that the self-deceiver is someone who purposely avoids becoming explicitly 176 conscious. On the other hand, this contention entails that the self-deceiver knows the truth. If he held, as he appears to have done, that self—deceivers do not know the truth, then he was wrong, and the latter contention contradicts a central and correct feature of his own analysis of self-deception. 177 CHAPTER FIVE. Over-Riding Reasons. Section 1. We have characterized the self-deceiver as someone who avoids making his consciousness of the truth explicit for reasons which 'over-ride' any he may have for making his consciousness explicit. We have further stated that foremost among these over-riding reasons is the desire to avoid psychic 'pain'. In this chapter we shall consider the self-deceiver's desire to avoid psychic 'pain' in a more specific and less vague manner. This part of our investigation still lies within the province of an analysis of self-deception, and it is not primarily an empirical psychological investigation. Self-deceivers necessarily avoid explicit consciousness of the truth for a reason of a particular kind. If someone were to persistently avoid explicit consciousness of something which he knew, but did not do so for such a reason, then he would not be deceiving himself. This does not mean, however, that our investigation is not a psychological one. Imbedded, as it were, within the concept of self-deception is a psychological explanatory structure. So long as we do not construe the term 'theory' too narrowly, we can say that the expression, 'is deceiving himself (herself)' is a 'theory-laden' one, and our task in this chapter will be to uncover the general ourline of that theory. However, in spite of the fact that our investigation is primarily analytical, in practice it is very difficult to separate 178 this analytical task from the empirical one of determining that people do avoid explicit consciousness of the truth in order to avoid psychic 'pain' of the relevant sort. This is because with the exception of the rarified atmosphere of mathematics and some of the more highly developed sciences, our concepts do not come ready-made prior to any possible application of them. In a sense, they owe their existance to the fact that they are applied, that they are part of an interdependent structure of concepts in terms of which we perceive and explain our world even at the most basic and 'empirical' level. This does not mean that we cannot deny, e.g., that people avoid explicit consciousness of the truth in order to avoid psychic 'pain' or that when they do avoid explicit conscious- ness, they do in fact prevent 'psychic pain'. It does mean, on the other hand, that we cannot deny these things without abandoning a large part of the structure by means of which we explain human behavior. So far I have characterized the self-deceiver's reason as simply "the avoidance of psychic 'pain'". This phrase is quite vague, however, and our first task shall be to flesh it out in a way which makes it clear. To accomplish this, let us return to Pugmire's official and ask, "What would happen if he were to acknowledge the truth to himself? What would this do to him?" We have expressions which would cover the probable outcome of such an acknowledgment. Thus we might say, "He would be crushed" or "He would be destroyed". But these ways of speaking, along with 179 Fingarette's more artificial, "The acknowledgment would be destructive of his self", while perhaps more meaningful in a human way, are still not clear. What would it be for him to be crushed? What must happen to him in order for us to say that the acknowledgment crushed or destroyed him? In answer to this latter pair of questions we can first note that to be crushed in this sense is always to be overwhelmed in a certain way by any of a number of emotions. Thus one can be crushed by grief, crushed by despair, crushed by remorse, crushed by guilt, crushed by shame, crushed by sorrow. On the other hand, not all emotions can be overwhelming in this way. It makes no sense to speak of someone being crushed by joy, crushed by anger, crushed by compassion, crushed by envy, crushed by jealousy, even if the person is overwhelmed by one of these emotions. Secondly, we should note that to be crushed by grief, despair, remorse,guilt, shame, or sorrow is not the same thing as having or feeling grief, despair, remorse, guilt, shame, or sorrow. One can, for example, feel ashamed for something one has done or felt or thought without being crushed by shame. Similarly, one can grieve over the loss of someone without being crushed by grief. Third, the difference between, say, feeling grief and being crushed by grief is not simply a matter of intensity or degree. To say that a person has been crushed by grief is to say, among other things, that his life has ceased to have any significance, any meaning for him. It is to say that there is no longer any- thing which makes his life worth living, that he no longer has any 180 reason to live. Usually when we think of "The Meaning of Life" we think of those large and enduring projects, goals, and activities which occupy the center of a person's life and which tie the various parts of his life together. However, to really appreciate what it means for someone's life to have lost its meaning, and thus to appreciate what it means to be crushed, it is better to focus on those little details of life which we all take for granted. Consider the simple act of eating. Where before a man who is now crushed by guilt (or grief, shame, etc.) could look forward to eating, could engage in it eagerly and with enjoyment, eating is now of no interest to man. It is not that food has lost its taste. The man has not lost his ability to see, to hear, to feel warmth and cold, textures, hardness, etc., nor has he lost his ability to feel pain or bodily sensations or to taste things, to tell the difference between flavors, and so on. But in his mouth these tastes have become dead, lifeless things. They have lost altogether their power to interest him, to delight and entice, to spark his desires. It is not simply eating which has lost its significance for this man. Eating and its pleasures may have been relatively unimportant to him. His life has lost its meaning because virtually everything which before would have interested him, which would have delighted him or would have been the source of joy or pleasure, which would have been an object of his desires, is now a matter of indifference to him. To say that his life has lost its meaning 181 means, among other things, that he has no reason to go on living because of his indifference to the things which used to fill his life or which could fill his life. The man's indifference is not, however, total. Often, rather than being merely indifferent to something, he will take a kind of negative interest in it, and be repulsed by the thing in question. Thus if the taste of food moves him at all, it does so only in a negative way, b ecoming downright repugnant, clinging to his mouth like a bad odor clinging to his nostrils. This repulsion extends to people, even people whom he has deeply loved, and he will often find their presence distressing and yearn to be left along. Because of this negative interest which he often takes in things, this man will most likely be irritable and quick to anger. Even this lack of positive interest and the frequent negative interest is not enough, however, to mark a person as having no reason to go on living, nor, therefore, as having been crushed. Essential to both of these things is a certain pessimistic attitude. A person may, for example, grieve deeply over the death of a loved one, refuse to eat, with to be alone, and so on, without it's being the case that the meaning has gone out of this person's life or that the person has been crushed by grief. What marks the difference here is that the person in question knows or believes that the lack of positive interest and the frequent negative interest associated with his or her grief is temporary, that these things will pass, and that sooner or later a renewed interest in life will 182 be possible. After a period of time such a person will make an effort to once again take an active interest in life. But a person who is crushed by grief takes the opposite attitude: he or she believes that the condition will not pass, that it will never again be possible to have positive interests, and that he or she will continue to take only a negative interest in things. Thus having no reason to go on living and being crushed always and necessarily contains an element of despair. In despair one views it is inevitable that one will lost something whose loss one dreads or that one will continue to be plagued by the presence of something which one dreads. The person who has been crushed by some emotion and whose life has ceased to have meaning always and necessarily despairs of ever again taking a positive interest in life or of being free of the repulsion which constitutes his negative interest in life. This essential component of despair in turn tends to make the person's condition a self-perpetuating one, whether he has been crushed by grief, despair, remorse, guilt, shame, or sorrow. The reason for this is that despair over anything involves a reaction of the sort described above, it involves, that is, losing a positive interest in life and taking on a negative interest in it. And so long as a person believes that he will never again be able to take a positive interest in life and that he is doomed to take only a negative interest in it, the despair which rests on this belief will continue to generate this reaction long after the emotion which originally generated the reaction has passed. What happens here is 183 that the person in question mistakenly attributes the continuance of this reaction to the original emotion, and thus while his belief is mistaken, the despair which the belief supports continues to generate the effort which confirms and reinforces the belief. On the other hand, were the person to realize that his belief were mistaken, his despair would cease, and his belief would cease to be confirmed. And had he had a more realistic attitude from this very beginning, had he realized, that is, that his emotion would pass, he would never have been crushed by it in the first place. We implicitly recognize this, I believe, in our dealings with people who seem to be taking things "too hard". One of the first things we do in such a case is try to reassure the person that his grief, despair, sorrow, shame, etc., will pass. Moreover, we often speak of someone who has been crushed by some emotion and who despairs of ever picking up his life again as "feeling sorry for himself". This is, I take it, a reference to the despair which is perpetuating his pain. What I have said above should not be taken to imply, however, that whenever someone is crushed by a certain emotion, say grief, then his despair over picking up his life again necessarily endures beyond his grief and perpetuates his lack of positive interest in life and his negative interest in life after his grief has passed. What I am saying is that when a person is crushed by an emotion like grief, despair necessarily contributes to this crushing effect, and sometimes the despair outlives the original emotion and perpetuates his condition long after the original emotion has passed. 184 In the latter sort of case, a mistaken belief is involved. However, it is not necessarily true that in all cases of someone's being crushed by an emotion the person mistakenly attributes his continued lack of interest in life and his repulsion to his emotion. He might be right. To return to Pugmire's official, then, were he to acknowledge the truth to himself, we would expect him to be crushed by certain emotions: for example, shame over having been dismissed for incompetence, grief over the loss of his position and the loss of the respect of other people - acquaintances, friends, family - and despair over ever being able to perform competently, have security, and to have the respect of others. And we may surmise that Pugmire's official avoids acknowledging the truth ip'ggggg to avoid being crushed by shame, grief and despair. In refusing to acknowledge the truth and doing what is necessary to avoid an acknowledgment of the truth, the official gipg_at saving himself from being crushed by shame, grief, and despair, and thus at insuring that he will have reason to go on living and that his life will not become a dark and empty pit. Notice now that even if the official is successful in avoiding an acknowledgment of the truth and this in turn prevents him from being crushed by shame, grief, and despair over the above mentioned things, this does not.mean that he never feels shame, grief, or despair over these things. Indeed, the latter is quite unlikely and when we meet with the official in Pugmire's example these feelings are apparently already welling up in him. Moreover, it is quite 185 possible that the official has these feelings quite frequently, and that intermittently he loses his positive interests in life or finds them diminished, and that similarly he finds himself repulsed by many things which otherwise would attract him. But this is not to say that he has been crushed by shame, grief, and despair. First, even though these things happen freguently or intermittently, this is not the same as his continuously feeling despair, grief and shame, continuously lacking positive interests, and continually taking a negative interest in life. But the latter is what would have to occur for us to say that he had been crushed. Secondly, there is a question of intensity. Even though he feels despair, shame, and grief, it does not follow that he feels these things as intensely as he would if he were crushed by them. Similarly, to say that his positive interests in life have diminished is not the same as saying that he takes no positive interest in life whatsoever, and the latter is what would occur if he were to be crushed. Finally, there is the qualitative difference mentioned earlier. For him to be crushed, not only would he have to believe that at present he had no positive interests and only negative ones, but he would have to believe that never again would it be possible for him to have positive interests and that he was doomed to having only strong negative interests in life. And in addition, this would have to cause him despair. But it does not follow that he has this belief or the despair which rests upon it, even though it does follow from what was said above that he believes that Eg£g_he to acknowledge the truth, then it would never again be possible for him 186 to take a positive interest in life or to be free of strong negative interests. The latter follows, of course, from the supposition that his aim in not acknowledging the truth is to prevent himself from being crushed. The foregoing makes it plausible, I hope, that at least in some cases of self-deception, the self-deceiver avoids acknowledg- ing the truth in order to avoid being crushed by grief, despair, guilt, shame, remorse or sorrow. But it is, I believe, a necessary condition of self-deception that one avoid explicit consciousness of the truth in order to avoid being crushed by such emotions, and thus, that if someone were to avoid explicit consciousness of the truth for reasons other than this, he would not be deceiving himself. I have no knock-down arguments to prove this contention, but a number of considerations can be brought to bear which strongly support it. First, there is our reaction to someone whom we know to be deceiving himself. We tend to view the self-deceiver with a mixture of pity and scorn. I suggest that the reason we do pity the self-deceiver is because we realize that his desperate flight from the truth is an attempt to avoid being crushed. Having been tormented by such feelings ourselves, we sympathize with his position. At the same time we view his flight from the truth as due to a flaw in his character, as due to a lack of courage, and we feel that he would better eeal with the truth were he to face his grief, despair, etc., openly and overcome it. 187 Secondly, most of those cases which we would regard as typical examples of self-deception display this feature. The mother who refuses to acknowledge her son's wrong—doing - why does she do so? We are quite prepared to think that she does so in order to avoid being crushed with sorrow for her son, and with guilt and remorse over not having done a better job of raising him. And we tend to view in a similar way, the husband who refuses to acknow- ledge that his wife has been unfaithful, the homosexual who refuses to acknowledge his desires, the excessively 'mild' person who refuses to acknowledge his anger and aggressive activities, the aggressive person who refuses to acknowledge his tender feelings and kindly activities, Robinson Crusoe on his island who refuses to acknowledge that there is no hope for rescue, the man who refuses to acknowledge that he hates his job, his family, and his way of life, Hickey who refuses to acknowledge that he killed his wife out of hatred and bitter resentment. In so far as we view any of these as cases of self-deception, we tend to view the aim in each case as preventing being crushed by grief, despair, shame, guilt, remorse, or sorrow. Third, when we entertain examples which are ambiguous with respect to this feature, which neither clearly display it or exclude it, we do not know whether to attribute self-deception or not, even though all of the other features of self-deception are clearly present. On the other hand, we can turn such examples into clear- cut cases of self-deception by supposing them to have this feature. claim: 188 One example - from Sartre - should suffice to illustrate this Take the example of a woman who has consented to go out with a particular man for the first time. She knows very well the intentions which the who who is speaking to her cherishes regarding her. She knows also that it will be necessary for her to make a decision.‘ But she does not want to realize the urgency; she concerns her- self only with what is respectful and discrete in the attitude of her companion. She does not apprehend this conduct as an attempt to achieve what we call "the first approach;" that is, she does not want to see possibilities of temporal development which his conduct presents. She restricts this behavior to what it is in the present; she does not wish to read in the phrases which he addresses to her anything other than their explicit meaning. If he says to her, "I find you so attractive!" she disarms this phrase of its sexual background; the man who is speaking to her appears to her sincere and respectful as the table is round or square, as the wall coloring is blue or gray.....This is because she does not quite know what she wants. She is profoundly aware of the desire which she inspires, but the desire cruel and naked would humiliate and terrify her. Yet she would find no charm in a respect which would be only respect. In order to satisfy her, there must be a feeling which is addressed wholly to her personality--i.e., to her full freedom--and which would be a recognition of her freedom. But at the same time this feeling must be wholly desire; that is, it must address itself to her body as object. This time then she refuses to apprehend the desire for what it is; she does not even give it a name; she recognizes it only to the extent that it transcends itself toward admiration, esteem, respect and that it is wholly absorbed in the more refined forms which it produces, to the extent of no longer figuring any more as a sort of warmth and density. But then suppose he takes her hand. This act of her companion risks changing the situation by calling for an immediate decision. To leave the hand there is to consent in herself to flirt, to engage herself. To withdraw it is to break the troubled and unstable harmony which gives the hour its charm. The aim is to postpone the moment of decision as long as possible. We know what happens next; the young woman leaves her hand there, but she does not notice that she is leaving it. She does not notice it because it happens by chance that she is at this moment all intellect. She draws her companion up to the most lofty regions of sentimental speculation; she speaks of Life, of her life, she shows herself in her 189 essential aspect-~a personality, a consciousness. And during this time the divorce of the body from the soul is accomplished, the hand rests inert between the warm hands of her companion--neither consenting nor resist- ing--a thing.1 Sartre's example is a highly complicated one as we shall see. The point I wish to make at present is that even if we discount the possibility that the young woman is simply being coy, and we agree that she is refusing to acknowledge her companion's sexual desire even to herself because - as Sartre seems to suggest - "the desire cruel and naked would humiliate and horrify her," it is still not clear that the young woman is deceiving herself. It is entirely consistent with the example as Sartre describes it to suppose that eventually she gives up trying "to postpone the moment of decision as long as possible", that she clearly though perhaps discretely acknowledges her companion's desire for her, and that she even enthusisatically engages in love making with him. If this were to happen, then we should reject, I think, the claim that the young woman was deceiving herself, and the reason we should do so, I submit, is that it would show that she was not refusing to acknowledge her companion's desire because doing so would cause her to be crushed with grief or despair. 0n the other hand, by bringing out explicitly certain things which Sartre's description suggests, and by adding further details to the example, it is possible to turn it into a case of self- deception. Sartre focuses on the young woman's refusal to acknowledge her companion's desire. But if he intended the example to be taken 190 as an example of self-deception, this is misleading. There is much in much in the example which suggests that she is herself sexually aroused, and it is on her own aroused sexual desire which we should concentrate if we are to plausibly construe the example as an example of self-deception. The primary reason for inferring from Sartre's description that the young woman is herself sexually aroused is that it is her consciousness of her companion's aroused sexual desire for her which gives the evening its charm for her. To see why this is a reason for holding that she is sexually aroused, it is important to concentrate on certain features of aroused sexual desire. First, when one person, X, is in an initial stage of aroused sexual desire for another person, Y, X desires physical contact of some sort with Y, usually including sexual intercourse in heterosexual relationships. But this desire is by no means the whole of X's aroused state. In order to characterize X's desire for Y as sexual desire in the erotic sense of 'sexual', it is necessary that X also desire that Y has a certain desire, namely, the desire for physical contact of the same sort with X. If X becomes aware that Y does have this desire, then typically this will have the effect that X becomes further aroused sexually, not only because X thereby knows that one of his desires has been satisfied, and this satisfaction, pleasurably experienced, sparks his desire for more, but also because it increases X's expectations that his other components desires will be satisfied. 0n the other hand, if x becomes conscious that Y does not have aroused sexual 191 desire dor him/herself, X, then this will tend to dampen X's own desire, and especially so, if X takes this as an indication that Y will not in the future become sexually aroused with desire for X. The second feature about aroused sexual desire we need to notice is this. The initial stage of sexual arousal is marked by certain physiological characteristics - dilation of the pupils, drooping of the eyelids, slightly labored breathing, increase in the beating of the heart and pulse, slight perspiration, tumescence and erection of the nipples, penis, elitoris, and secretion of fluids from the penis and the vagina, muscular contractions in the anus, vagina, and around the penis. Moreover, and more importantly for our purposes, there are subjective changes which correspond to these physical ones; slight haziness of vision, a feeling of heaviness in the eyelids, palpitations in one's chest, a feeling of slight tightness in one's chest, stirrings in one's stomach and bowels, stirring and itching in one's loins, and a greatly increased sensitivity to touch, to pressure, to colors and bright- ness, to smells and tastes, and to sounds. This increased sensitivity extends over the whole body and encompasses all of the sense organs, but it is perhaps most marked on the surface of the skin and in ‘particular areas of the body: the tongue and mouth, the breasts and.nipples, the buttocks, the anus and genitals, the hands and feet. Now, what we need to note about these subjective changes is that when one is sexually aroused, this increased sensitivity 192 contributes to a modification of one's perception of the world, including one's own body. The world takes on what might be called 'an erotic structure.‘ Along with this modified sensibility, one's interests in the world changes, and it is now seen in terms of the sensuous possibilities which it offers. Thus, a slight touch against the penis or clitoris is intensely felt and perceived pleasurably; colors, sights, sounds, tastes, smells take on a new meaning. The low, yellow flame of a candle burning between two sexually aroused people, which earlier was casually ignored, an appointment of a familiar and expected kind, like the silverware, the chairs, the rug, the table-cloth, is now a thing of indescribable beauty for both people. The smell of the melting wax, which earlier went unnoticed or was annoying, might now become deliciously pungent. The brush of the aroused person's clothing against his body, so familiar and uninteresting, now becomes for him a caress, sending a thrill down his back. Even the defects in the other person, which earlier were regarded as repugnant, may now become attractive. Pores which were earlier regarded as too large may now become fascinating and attractive. The nasal whine in the other's voice, annoying before, may now become seductive. Indeed, it is a common experience among both men and women to awake on the morning after making love with someone, and finding the other's naked body next to one, to become disgusted and to wonder how one could ever had come into such intimate contact with them. .193 Let us now return to Sartre's young woman. A plausible explanation of the "charm" which she finds in the evening and its dependence on her awareness of her companion's desire and intentions is that the young woman herself is sexually aroused, that her awareness of his desire has intensified her own, and that in consequence, she is perceiving the world erotically, the world has taken on an erotic structure for her. If we suppose that this explanation is correct, and explicitly add it to the description of the example, then it is possible to' turn the example into a clear case of self-deception. In addition, we must suppose that the young woman cannot acknowledge her own aroused sexual desire, not even to herself, for fear that if she does so, she will be crushed by guilt and remorse. I might note here that such a supposition is by no means implausible. Since her companion is trying to make "the first approach", this is apparently their first social contact, and obviously they are not married to one another, nor do they have any serious interest in one another as prospective spouses or as lovers. Thus the young woman's desire for her companion is entirely casual - it is, if you will, lust. Most of us have known people for whom such a casual sexual desire is a hideous and obnoxious thing, one which they cannot acknowledge even to themselves for fear of being overwhelmed by guilt and re- morse. Hence, there is nothing surprising or awkward about the supposition that Sartre's young woman avoids acknowledging her own 194 sexual desire out of fear that were she to acknowledge it, she would be crushed by guilt and remorse. Once we have made this supposition, it then becomes clear that she is deceiving herself, and, moreover, we can still readily account for other features of the example. First, it is clear that the young woman cannot respond to her companion's overtures in any way which could be construed as an acknowledgment of her own aroused desire. Thus, when he says, "I find you so attractive,” she cannot respond with, "I find you very attractive too," since this would be to acknowledge her desire for him. Similarly, when he takes her hand, she cannot respond by squeezing his hand warmly, since this would again be to acknowledge her own desire. On the other hand, if she were to respond to his expression of desire with the words, "I am sorry, but I am not attracted to you in the same way", or the like, or if, when he takes her hand, she were to quickly withdraw it, then this would risk extinguishing his desire, and indirectly destroying the erotic atmosphere which she finds in his presence. The latter would result not only because the intensity of her own desire is dependent on her perception of his desire, but also because if his desire were extinguished, then for her this would remove any Egg$_possibility of her own desire being satisfied. And while it is logically possible, I suppose, for her to remain sexually aroused even after she realizes that there is no real possibility of her desire being satisfied, 195 this is not very likely. Normally when one realizes that one's sexual desire cannot be satisfied, this realization has the effect of killing one's desire. It should be noted here that the above implies that the young woman is aware that there is a real possibility of her and her companion's desires being satisfied. And this awareness forms the kernel for a second self-deception. She could no more acknowledge this real possibility than she could acknowledge her desire, for to acknowledge this possibility would be to acknowledge that she Egy_engage in sexual intercourse with her companion, and this acknowledgment is quite as likely to have a crushing effect on her as the first. This is why, I suspect, Sartre says, "she does not want to see possibilities of temporal development which his conduct presents." For these possibilities are her possibilities, and can exist only with her consent. The young woman is therefore in a dilemma. She finds a way out of this dilemma by not acknowledging Eifi.’ her companion's - desire. When he says, ”I find you so attractive," she treats this as if it were an expression of his admiration and respect, and not as an expression of his desire, calculated to elicit a positive or negative response from her. Similarly, when he takes her hand, she 'doesn't notice' that he has done so, because "it happens by chance that she is at this moment all intellect." By behaving in this way, she avoids acknowledging her own desire while at the same time doing nothing which her companion can interpret as a rejection. 196 Hence she avoids being crushed with guilt and remorse through an acknowledgment of her desire (or an acknowledgment of the possibility that she will satisfy her desire and her companion's), and at the same time she preserves the erotically charming structure of her evening. We expect, of course, that eventually the young woman will have to make a decision, for it is likely that sooner or later her companion will manoeuvre her into a position where she will have no practical alternatives between either acknowledging her own desire or rejecting his overtures. It does not automatically follow, however, that she will choose to reject her companion. Her companion may "get" her drunk and "take advantage" of her, or he may "convince" her that he loves her and wants to marry her while she at the same time "falls in love" with him, or he may use some similar ruse calculated to provide her with some excuse. I want to conclude this chapter with some comments about the place of anxiety in self-deception. Anxiety may play quite a prominent role in self-deception, though Freud himself misunderstood this role. It is not primarily to avoid the 'pain' or 'unpleasure' of anxiety that the self-deceiver avoids explicit consciousness of the truth. Rather, as Fingarette correctly sees, anxiety is often the motive for avoiding explicit consciousness of the truth. When the self-deceiver is conscious of the truth and he feels threatened with an acknowledgment of the truth, and thus with the crushing despair, grief, etc., that such an acknowledgment would bring, and acting pp; g£_anxiety, he does what is necessary to reduce the threat and to avoid acknowledging the truth. Here his primary aim is to avoid being crushed. Granted, anxiety may itself be in 197 some sense painful, and he may also act to avoid anxiety, but the latter can only be a secondary aim. Unless there were some- thing else which he dreaded and desperately wanted to avoid - being crushed - there would be no reason to speak of him as being anxious. 198 NOTES Chapter One. 1. This train of argument owes a great deal to Fingarette's criticism of Demos' analysis. 2. Demos' 'Lying to Oneself', Journal ngPhilosophy, Vol. 57 (1960). p. 588. 3. Ibid., p. 588. 4. Ibid. 5. Ibid. 6. Ibid., p. 591. 7. Ibid., my emphasis. 8. Ibid. 9. Ibid., p. 592. 10. Ibid., p. 593. 11. Ibid., p. 594. 12. Frederick Siegler, 'Self-Deception'. Australasian Journal p§_Philosqphy, Vol. 41, (1963). PP. 29-43. Cf. esp. pp. 36-39. 13. Herbert Fingarette, Self-Deception (London, 1969), p. 14. 14. Demos implicitly recognized, that is, that self-deception gg_pg construed £E_could only occur if the self-deceiver does not appreciate the incompatibility in his beliefs. 15. David Pugmire, 'Strong Self-Deception', Inguiry, Vol. 12, (1969). pp. 339-361. 16. Ibid., p. 344. 17. Cf., ibid., p. 344. 18 0 Ibid. I PP. 344-345 0 19. 199 Conflict theories are also espoused in the following: Canfield and McNally, 'Paradoxes of Self-Deception', Analysis, Vol. 21, (1960) Pp. 140—144. A. O. Rorty, 'Belief & Self-Deception', Inguigy, Vol. 15 (1972) pp. 387-410. D. W. Hamlyn, 'Self-Deception', Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, No. 45 (1971), pp. 45-72. Jean-Paul Sartre, Being_and Nothingness, trans. by Hazel Barnes (New York, 1966), paper. Cf. esp. Ch. Two, 'Bad Faith'. Chapter Two. 10. 11. 12. S. Freud and J. Breuer, Studies ngHysteria, pp. 116-117 of Vol. II, The Standard Edition g£_The Cogplgte Psychological works g£_Sigmund Freud (hereafter 'SE'), translated from the German under the general editorship of James Starchey in collaboration with Anna Freud, assisted by Alix Starchey and Alan Tyson (London, 1966). Ibid., p. 117. Ibid., p. 268. Ibid., p. 269. Ibid., p. 270. Ibid., p. 269. Ibid., p. 116. Cf. above, p. 45. Cf. above, p. 45. The central parts of Freud's views concerning the conversion of a quantity of affect into hysterical symptoms ’is sketched in Parts I and IV of Studies gp_Hysteria. Ibid., p. 122. Ibid., p. 270. John King-Farlow, 'Self-Deceivers and Sartrian Seducers', Speer, Inside The Third Reich, trans. by Richard and Clara Winston (New York, 1970, paper.), 99- 480-481. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 200 Jean-Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, trans. by Hazel Barnes (New York, 1966, paper.). PP. 101-102. Ibid., p. 89. Ibid., p. 287. The part played by the censor is extensively marked out in The Interpretation pf Dreams, trans. by James Starchey New York, 1965, paper.). Freud, The Ego and The IQ, SE, Vol. XIX, p. 17. Ibid., p. 17. Ibid., p. 18. I owe much of this point to Fingarette. Cf. Self-Deception, Chapter Three, esp. pp. 47-48. Chapter Three. 1. 10. 11. Frederich C. Siegler, 'Demos on Lying to Oneself', Journal g£_Philosophy, Vol. S9,(1962),pp. 469-475. Siegler, 'Self-Deception', Australasian Journal g§_Philosophy, V61. 42 (1963). PP. 29-43. Cf. DLO, p. 470. DID, p. 473. Cf. DLO, p. 474; SD, p. 33. OLD, p. 474; SD, p. 33. DLO, p. 473; SD, p. 32. OLD, p. 474; Cf. SD, p. 33. John V. Canfield and Don F. Gustavson, 'Self-Deception', Analysis, Vol. 23 (1962), pp. 32-36. Ibid., p. 34. Ibid., pp. 35-36. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 201 Terence Penelham, 'Pleasure and Falsity', American Philosophical anrterly, Vol. 1 (1964). Reprinted in Stuart Hampshire, ed., Philosophy pf Mind (New York, 1966), pp. 242-266. All page references are to Philosophy g£_Mind. Ibid., p. 258. Ibid.: PP. 258-259. Ibid., p. 259. Cf. ibid., pp. 259-260. Cf. Stanley Paluch, 'Self-Deception', Inguigy, Vol. 10 (1967), pp. 268—278, Paluch also suggests an argument to show that the self-deceiver does not know the truth except in a "non- standard" sense of 'know', and again this conclusion is based upon the self-deceiver's 'inability'. The same i reply works against this argument that was made against ;, Canfield and Gustavson. Other authors who have introduced "weak" or "idiomatic" or "non-standard" uses of 'know' into the analysis are H. O. Mounce ('Self-Deception', Arist. Soc., Supp. Vol. 45 (1971), pp. 61-72) and Fingarette. Chapter Four. 10. 11. Herbert Fingarette, Self-Deception, London, 1969. Ibid., p. 29, my emphasis. Ibid., p. 38. Ibid., p. 35. Ibid., p. 37. Ibid., pp. 38-40. Ibid., p. 40. Ibid., p. 41. Ibid., p. 43. Ibid., p. 43. Ibid., p. 43. 12. 13. 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. 30. 202 Ibid., p. 48. Ibid., p. 28. Freud, SE, Vol. XII, p. 260. Freud, SE, Vol. V, p. 574. Freud, SE, Vol. XIX, p. 20. Cf. p. 131 above. I believe this observation lies behind Fingarette's claim that "A self-covering policy of this kind [a policy of not spelling-out the truth] tends to generate a more or less elaborate 'cover story'. For a natural consequence is the protective attempt on the part of the person to use elements of the skill he has developed in spelling-out as inventively as possible in order to fill in plausibly the gaps created by his self-covering policy." Ibid., p. 50. Cf. above, p. 80. Fingarette draws a similar conclusion about Freud. Cf. Ibid., p. 121. Ibid., p. 114. Ibid., pp. 119-120. In Freudian terminology, a 'cathexis' is a 'charge of psychic energy' attaching to an ideational content. The notion is obscure at best, and, as we shall see, Fingarette reinterprets both 'hypercathexis' and 'counter-cathexis' in an effort to clarify these notions. For Freud's own treatment of these notions consult his essay, 'Repression', SE, V01. XIV. Ibid., pp. 120-121. Ibid., p. 124. Ibid., p. 115. Ibid., pp. 115-116. Ibid., p. 116. Ibid., p. 34. Ibid., p. 63. Ibid., p. 64. BIBLIOGRAPHY BIBLIOGRAPHY Canfield, J. & McNally, P., 'Paradoxes of Self-Deception.' Analysis, Vol. 21 (1960). pp. 140-144. , & Gustavson, D., 'Self-Deception,‘ Analysis, Vol. 23 (1962). PP. 32-36. Demos, Raphael, 'Lying to Oneself,‘ Journal g£_Philosophy, Vol. 57 (1960). PP. 588—595. de Sousa, R., 'Review of Self-Deception,' Ingpigy, Vol. 13 (1970), pp. 308-321. Dilman, I., a Phillips, D. 2., Sense and Delusion, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1971. Fingarette, Herbert, Self-Deception, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1969. Freud, Sigmund & Breuer, J., Studies pp Hysteria, Vol. II, The Standard Edition 2:; the Complete Psychological Works pg Siggpnd Freud (hereafter 'SE'). trans. from.the German under the general editorship of James Starchey in collaboration with Anna Freud, assisted by Alix Starcyey and Alan Tyson, The Hogarth Press, London, 1953-1966. , The Interpretation pg Dreams, SE, Vol. V. , The Ego and The IQ, SE, V61. XIX. , 'A Note on the Unconscious in Psychoanalysis,‘ SE, Vol. XII. , 'Repression,‘ SE, V61. XIV. Gardiner, P., 'Error, Faith, and Self-Deception,‘ Proceedings g_f_ the Aristotelian Society, Vol. 70 (1970), pp. 221-243. Gustavson, D. & Canfield, J., 'Self-Deception,' Analysis, V61. 23 Hamlyn, D. W., & Mounce, H. 0., 'Self-Deception,‘ Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 45 (1971), pp. 45-72. Part I is by Hamlyn, Part II by Mounce. King-Farlow, J., 'Self-Deceivers and Sartrian Seducers,‘ Analysis, Vol. 23 (1962), pp. 131-136. MacIntyre, A. C., The Unconscious, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1958. McNally, P., & Canfield, J., 'Paradoxes of Self-Deception,‘ Analysis, Mounce, H. O., & Hamlyn, D. W., 'Self-Deception,‘ Aristotelian Society, Supp. Vol. 45 (1971), pp. 45-72. Part I is by [L Hamlyn, Part II by Mounce. ’ Paluch, S., 'Self-Deception,‘ Ingpigy, Vol. 10 (1967), pp. 268-278. Penelhum, T., 'Pleasure and Falsity,‘ Amer. Phil. Quarterly, Vol. 1 . (1964). Reprinted in Philosophy g£_Mind, ed. by Stuart F Hampshire, Harper & Row, New York, 1966. i Phillips, D. 2., & Dilman, 1., Sense and Delusion, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1971. Pugmire, D., '"Strong" Self-Deception,‘ ngpiry, Vol. 12 (1969), pp. 339-361. Rorty, A. 0., 'Belief and Self-Deception,’ Inguigy, Vol. 15 (1972), Sartre, Jean-Paul, Being and Nothingness, trans. and with an introduction by Hazel E. Barnes, washington Square Press (Pocket Books), New York, 1966. Siegler, F. A., 'Demos on Lying to Oneself,‘ Journal pg Philosophy, Vol. 59 (1962), pp. 469-475. , 'Self-Deception,‘ Australasian Journal pg Philosqppy, Vol. 41 (1963), pp. 29-43. , 'An Analysis of Self-Deception,‘ Nous, Vol. 2 (1968), pp. 147-164. Trilling, L., Sincerity and Authenticity, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1971.