AN INVESTIGATION OF COMMUNICATION , EFFECTS IN COGNITIVE SPACE ' - Disser’rafion for +he Degree of Ph.‘ D. MICHIGAN STATE UNIVERSITY ” ROBERT T, CRAIG I976 This is to certify that the thesis entitled An Investigation of Communication Effects in Cognitive Space presented by Robert T. Craig has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for Ph. D. degree in Communication new 7/4 ( ) 'Major 10er r Date 4'7’7/(7/ 20,) ’7 7L 0—7639 \ lllllWHIHHIIHIIWHIHIlllllllllllllllllllllllllll 3 1293 10382 4706 \ E34? ABSTRACT AN INVESTIGATION OF COMMUNICATION EFFECTS IN COGNITIVE SPACE By Robert T. Craig The working assumption of this study was that models of cognitive structure may fruitfully be elaborated into general models of information which describe the structure of messages and constrain theories of the cognitive effects of communication. Because of its intuitive appeal and mathematical convenience, and because of its prominence in several disci— plines, the spacial model of cognitive structure was selected for study. The spacial model views the mind as a multidimensional space in which concepts are defined by their locations. Several variations of the spacial model were discussed. The model tested in this study assumed that cognitive space is Euclidean and that cognitive change is representable as motion of concepts in cognitive space. A theory of linear motion was mathematically derived. The theory posits that the effect of information inputs about a pair of concepts is to induce change in the distance between those concepts along the line connecting them. Whenever the cognitive space comprises three or more concepts the theory makes non—trivial predictions of "indirect" change in distance between each "manipulated" concept (those which are the sub- jects of information inputs) and all other concepts. Several lines of research bearing on the theory of linear motion were reviewed. Studies using the semantic differential (Osgood), non— metric multidimensional scaling (Shepard and others), and metric Robert T. Craig multidimensional scaling (Woelfel and associates) have all demonstrated that conceptual structures can be meaningfully represented by spacial models. There is less decisive but still suggestive evidence that motion of concepts in cognitive space is meaningful and that the effects of in- formation may be linear. Thus the theory of linear motion has some plausibility based on previous research. A study was performed to test the theory of linear motion. A pretest-manipulation-posttest, within-subjects experimental design was used. Subjects were 64 graduate and undergraduate students in com- munication classes at a large university. Fifteen concepts were scaled. The concepts were Nations. The Nations were selected by a procedure that combined random and judgmental features. The procedure for measuring psychological distance was a direct, ratio judgment procedure suggested by Torgerson and developed by Woelfel. The scaling procedure used was also developed by Woelfel and his associ— ates, and is based on the classical metric model of Torgerson: essentially an orthogonal decomposition of the variance-covariance matrix. Three messages were constructed. Each message argued that a pair of nations was either ”very similar" or "very different." The messages were of comparable length and structure. In the pretest the fifteen nations were scaled. The subjects made direct, ratio judgments of the distances between all one hundred five pairs of concepts. The subjects then read the messages, which were in- tended to induce motion in six concepts, leaving nine concepts unmoved. The two sets of concepts (manipulated and not) provided experimental Robert T. Craig control. Theory predicts that specific changes should have occurred in 69 out of the 105 distances among the fifteen concepts, while the remaining 36 distances should not change. The subjects also made estimates of the distances between manipulated concepts ”in the message," those estimates to be used as estimates of the content of the messages. In the posttest (one week later) the subjects again read the three messages, then again estimated the 105 inter-concept distances, which distances were to be compared with those predicted by theory. Pretest and posttest distances were aggregated across subjects and the mean distance matrices were subjected to metric multidimensional scaling, the second space rotated to comparability with the first by two procedures based on different assumptions. Reliability and validity of measurement were assessed. It was con— cluded that the measurements and other procedures of the study were of acceptable quality. The fundamental hypothesis test was a correlation coefficient be- tween predicted and observed posttest distances among concepts. There are many bases upon which the correlation can be computed; all of them were computed. Zero order correlations between predicted and observed distances were all in the .8 to .9 range. These high correlations reflect the overall stability of the cognitive space over time. First order partial correlations controlling the pretest distances and computed for the sixty—six indirectly changed distances only, how- ever, were generally small and non-significant. These results were judged not to support the theory. Robert T. Craig Seven alternative explanations of the results were discussed: (1) the experimental manipulations may have been too weak; (2) the ex— perimental messages may have had unintended effects; (3) "noise"—— uncontrolled information from the environment——may have caused unin— tended changes; (4) insufficient time may have been allowed for cogni— tive equilibrium to be established; (5) the concepts may have been in motion prior to the experiment; (6) the concepts scaled may not have composed a domain in the functional sense; (7) the spacial model may be radically false; the mind may be, instead, a network of concepts. In connection with (6), motion among a subset comprising the six manipu— lated concepts only was found to be substantially better predicted by the theory than was motion of all fifteen concepts. The six manipu— lated concepts might reasonably be thought to compose a domain. No support was found for the network interpretation. AN INVESTIGATION OF COMMUNICATION EFFECTS IN COGNITIVE SPACE By ‘ "L. J u‘ I ‘0 Robert T. Craig A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Communication 1976 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am happy to acknowledge the contributions of others without whose support and advice this work could not have been done. Dr. Joseph Woelfel, friend and Advisor, stimulated the idea for this research and contributed valuable support and criticism. Dr. Donald P. Cushman, friend and Teacher, has been the dominant intellectual influence on me for over ten years. I cannot overstate my indebtedness to this man, whose enormous dedication, creativity, critical intelligence and personal forcefulness have captured the imaginations and have raised and helped to realize the aspirations of so many young scholars. He challenged and criticized my work at every step. Dr. Gerald R. Miller and Dr. James L. Phillips, who rounded out my doctoral committee, also deserve thanks. Dr. Miller contributed to my intellectual development throughout my years at Michigan State. Dr. Phillips was generous enough to spend hours with me on several occasions during which I learned much about cognitive theory and formed many of the ideas contained in this dissertation. My friend Cynthia Goldstein, besides tolerating my ups and downs and generally seeing to it that the ups predominate, has been my most highly valued English composition teacher throughout this and other recent writing. Walter Gantz, friend and office mate at Michigan State, gave me valuable advice on all subjects from theory to phraseology. ii The students who served as subjects in this research must remain anonymous, but their contribution is most appreciated. Many others, teachers, colleagues and friends, have made important contributions to my general intellectual growth. I should mention es— pecially Dr. Lloyd Bitzer, who taught me the meaning of scholarship and the value of philosophy, and (now) Dr. Thomas Farrell, my good friend and companion through eight years of school and beyond, who taught me about things generally. My parents, Robert and June Craig, also had something to do with all of this. TABLE OF CONTENTS ITEM LIST OF TABLES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . LIST OF FIGURES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . CHAPTER I. THE SPACIAL MODEL AND A THEORY OF LINEAR MOTION Introduction: A Working Assumption . . . . . . . . . Spacial Models of Cognition . . . . . . . . . . . . . Assumptions of Spacial Models . . . . . . . . . . . . Spacial Models of Messages . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Spacial Theories of Communication Effects . Theory: Communication Effects as Linear Motions in Cognitive Space . . . . . . . . . . Scope Conditions . . . . . . . . . . . . Derivation of the General Structural Equation . Summary of Empirical Assumptions Inherent in the Theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . CHAPTER II. PREVIOUS RESEARCH BEARING ON THE THEORY . Spacial Cognitive Structures . . . . . . . The Meaningfulness of Motion in Cognitive Space . . . Linear Force Aggregation Theory . . . . . . . . . . . Cognitive Consistency Without Awareness . . . . . Summary . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . CHAPTER III. METHODS . . . . . . . . . . . . . Design and Procedures . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Subjects . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Cognitive Domain . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Experimental Messages . . . . . . . . . . . . Measurement of Variables . . . . . . . . Loading of the Theory . . . . . . . . . . Data Analysis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Preparation of Data . . . . . . . . . . . Program GALILEO . . . . . . . . . . . . . Program TESTLAW . . . . . . . . . . Statistical Analyses . . . . . . . . . . Assessment of Measurement and Procedures . Hypothesis Tests . . . . . . . . . . iii vii NH (DJ-\OONH 23 24 27 29 29 34 41 48 50 53 53 53 54 55 56 59 65 66 66 66 69 72 72 74 iv ITEM CHAPTER IV. RESULTS . Multidimensional Scaling Analysis . Assessment of Measurement and Procedures . Reliability . Validity Procedures Hypothesis Tests . . . . . . . Test One: Mean Changes . . . . Test Two: Inter-concept Distances Test Three: Coordinates . . CHAPTER V. DISCUSSION . . . . . . . . . . . Evaluation of Measurement and Procedures . Evaluation of Results Alternative Explanations . Summary and Conclusion . REFERENCES . APPENDIX A: PRETEST QUESTIONNAIRE AND POSTTEST COVER LETTER . APPENDIX B: PROGRAM TESTLAW . APPENDIX C: COORDINATE MATRICES FROM GALILEO Page 79 79 89 89 105 109 111 111 112 121 127 127 129 130 146 149 156 167 173 LIST OF TABLES TABLE 1. 2. 10. ll. 12. Assumptions of Selected Spacial Models . . . . . . . . . Possible Distributions of Changes of Distance in a Domain of 15 Concepts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Effects of Deletion of Extreme Values on the Posttest Mean Inter-concept Distances . . . . . . . . . . Effect of Rotation Procedure Upon Distances Moved by Concepts Between Pretest and Posttest . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Means and Standard Deviations of Pretest Distances, Posttest Distances and Pretest—Posttest Changes in Distance; Pearson Correlations of Pretest with Posttest Distances; and t—Tests for Correlated Means . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Means and Standard Deviations of Pretest Masses, Posttest Masses and Pretest—Posttest Changes in Mass; Pearson Corre— lations of Pretest with Posttest Mass, and t—Tests for Correlated Means . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Means and Standard Deviations of Pretest Message Content Estimates, Posttest Message Content Estimates and Pretest— Posttest Changes in Message Content Estimates; Pearson Correlations of Pretest with Posttest Message Values; and t—Tests for Correlated Means . . . . . . . . . Pearson Correlations of Mean Pretest Inter—Concept Distances (Sij) with Mean Posttest Inter—concept Distances (s'ij) Pretest—Posttest Pearson Correlations of MDS Coordinates . . Pearson Correlations of 3'1, with §mi. and Si., Broken Down by Number of Dimensions Included in Computations, by Method of Obtaining s'ij and by Subsets of Cases . . . . . . First Order Partial Correlations (Controlling Si.) of s' with §mi and Si, , Broken Down by Number of Dimensions Included in Computations, by Method of Obtaining s' ij and by Subsets of Cases . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11 Pearson Correlations of A5,. with A§m_. and Ag ., Broken Down by Number of Dimensions Included in Computations, by Method of Obtaining s'ij and by Subsets of Cases . . 57 68 81 90 101 102 106 117 119 119 vi TABLE Page 13. Pearson Correlations of A31. with A§mi, and A§i., Asij Computed from Actually Observed S'i" and Smi, and gij Computed from Fifteen Dimensions, Broken Down by Subsets of Cases . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 121 14. Pearson Correlations of f', with fmi and fik for Two Rotations, Cases Broken Down by Cumulative Dimensions and Experimental Groups . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 122 15. First Order Partial Correlations (Controlling fik) of f'ik with fmik and fik for Two Rotations, Cases Broken Down by Cumulative Dimensions and Experimental Groups . . . . . . . 124 16. Pearson Correlations of Af. with Afm. and Afik for Two Rotations, Cases Broken Down by Cumulative Dimensions and Experimental Groups . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 125 17. First Order Partial Correlations (Controlling Si.) of s'ij with gm, and §., for Indirectly Changed Distances Among Manipuleed Conddpts Only . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139 18. Pearson Correlations of Distance From Each Concept With Absolute Change of Distance From That Concept . . . . . . . 145 19. Pretest Coordinate Matrix . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 173 20. Unrotated Posttest Coordinate Matrix . . . . . . . . . . . . 175 21. Rotated Posttest Coordinate Matrix, No Stable Concepts Rotation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 177 22. Pretest Coordinate Matrix Translated to Stable Concepts Centroid . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 178 23. Unrotated Posttest Coordinate Matrix Translated to Stable Concepts Centroid . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180 24. Rotated, Translated Posttest Coordinate Matrix, Stable Concepts Rotation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 182 FIGURE 1. No 2. No 3. No 4. 5. 6. LIST OF FIGURES Stable Concepts Rotation, X—Y Plane . . . . . . Stable Concepts Rotation, X—Z Plane . . . . . . Stable Concepts Rotation, First Three Dimensions Stable Concepts Rotation, X—Y Plane . . . . . . Stable Concepts Rotation, X—Z Plane . . . . . . . Stable Concepts Rotation, First Three Dimensions . vii 85 86 87 88 CHAPTER I THE SPACIAL MODEL AND A THEORY OF LINEAR MOTION Introduction: A Working Assumption It is perhaps unnecessary to remark that we would understand a great deal more about human communication if we understood the human mind. That in itself, however, is not sufficient justification for communication theory to embrace cognitive theory. The working as- sumption of this study is that there is potentially a more specific kinship between the two fields: that formal models of structure can be applied equally well to cognitions and messages, and that constraints on process inherent in those structural models can shape theories of the cognitive effects of communication. This implies that theoretical borrowing between the fields ought to be worthwhile. The borrowing process is illustrated and the validity of the working assumption is put to the test in the present study. Beginning with a general ”spacial” model of information, this Study develops a model of message content and derives and tests a specific hypothesis about the cognitive effects of messages. Thus the purpose of this study is to test the general hypothesis that cognitive change brought about by messages is spacial in character, by testing a specific hypothesis derived from spacial assumptions. This chapter outlines the theoretical background of the general hypothesis, and derives the specific hypothe- sis of this study from general assumptions. Chapter II reviews the re- search literature bearing on the theory presented in Chapter 1. Chapter III describes the design and procedures of an experiment intended to test the theory. Chapter IV presents the results of that study. Chapter V, finally, discusses the findings in relation to the theory and to the adequacy of the study as a test of the theory, and draws impli- cations for further research. Spacial Models of Cognition Several theorists have developed more or less elaborate models of the mind as a multidimensional space in which concepts are defined by their locations. In order to place in context the model used in the present study, some of the more important of these models will now be reviewed, and their assumptions compared and contrasted. Scott (1969) conceives of cognitive structure as a multidimensional space spanned by attributes, in reference to which cognitive elements are ”phenomenal objects located. The term "domain" refers to any set of which the person treats as functionally equivalent, and the attributes by which he comprehends those objects” (p. 262). That a "primitive” at— tribute such as evaluation (like—dislike) may be well—nigh universal among domains notwithstanding, the concept of domain is introduced pre- cisely because it is assumed that the set of attributes differs from domain to domain. Not all cognitive objects are comparable. Moreover, not all objects even within a domain are necessarily directly comparable. Objects are compared by reference to attributes: An attribute is represented in the model as a line in multidi— mensional space, divided into segments corresponding to charac— teristics (categories of the attribute) that the person recognizes (p. 262). Scott does not appear to assign any particular significance to a set of reference axes of the cognitive space, except insofar as the number of "dimensions worth” of attributes in the space is a type of cognitive com— plexity. He apparently does not assume that attributes pass through the origin of the space, or that the origin is in any way meaningful. He does not assume that attributes are continuous. Quite to the contrary, he assumes that in the most common case, attributes are made up of gross segments within which the person makes no discriminations. Finally, Scott makes no mention of any concept of cognitive change. The most interesting aspect of Scott's model is that not all objects within a domain are necessarily comparable. For the geometry of cogni- tive space, this implies that not all points in the space have projections; on all attributes—-a peculiar geometry! "Image comparability," the judgment of all objects in a domain on a common set of attributes, is a variable in this model, and is only one of several possible styles of cognitive integration. This View is well-suited to Scott's interest in cognitive complexity, a context in which to model the mind in the Appol— lonian idiom of Euclidian geometry might appear to beg the essential questions. Yet one wonders whether Scott, who sacrifices the continuous, homogeneous properties of Euclidian space without replacing them with a similarly coherent system, has not thereby denuded the spacial model of much of its suggestiveness. His model has no unambiguous entailments. Several other cognitive theorists have worked with models which, like Scott's, might be characterized as ”quasi-spacial." Zajonc (1960) and Runkel (1963) are further examples of theorists who view cognition as projection of a stimulus on a set of psychological dimensions, with— out making any further assumptions about the nature of this cognitive space. Kelly (1963, p. 146) also makes reference to a "psychological space” whose axes are dimensions (his term is ”constructs"), but he develops the idea no further. Schroder, Driver and Streufert (1967) define the properties of information processing structures in dimensional terms: differentiation is the number of psychological dimensions in a structure, discrimination is the fineness of categorization along the dimensions, and integration is the manner in which the dimensions are interrelated in information processing. The issue of integration is crucial for a spacial model. Whether a "set of dimensions" constitutes a true space depends upon what one assumes about how the psychological dimensions are integrated. Schroder gt .21- define integration in terms of the non-spacial concept of "schemata” or "rules." Certainly the most notorious spacial model of cognition is the "semantic space" of Osgood and his associates (Osgood, Suci and Tannen- baum, 1957).* More than do any of the models previously reviewed, this one employs the full resources of the spacial paradigm in both conceptu- alization and operationalization of cognitive structure. The essentials of the semantic space are succinctly stated in The Measurement of Meaning: 1. Semantic judgement can be completely represented in a [Euclidian] space defined by a set of elemental semantic factors . . . 2. Any axis or dimension placed through the origin of the semantic space represents a potential semantic scale or attribute of judgment . . . 3. The semantic nature of any such attribute is given by its relations [cosines of the angles between it and] the elemental factors . . . * I should stress that it is the semantic space concept only with which we are here concerned, and not the "representational mediation" theory of meaning (which Osgood nevertheless sees as the more fundamental ex- planatory principle). The representational mediation theory, in any case, seems not to have generated much interest among communication researchers, while the semantic space and its associated measurement and analysis techniques have become staples of the field. 4. Every concept in semantic space may be said to be "contained" by its characteristic attribute [the axis passing through the concept and the origin] . . . a. Another concept is different from this concept by virtue of having a characteristic attribute which is independent (not co-linear with) the concept; b. Another concept is different by virtue of having more or less of the same characteristic attribute. 5. Two concepts may interact [e.g. may be compared] to the extent that they are contained by the same attribute . . . (pp. 116- 117). The "elemental factors” are obtained by factorization of a matrix of correlations among a representative set of seven—point bipolar adjec- tive scales (the "semantic differential") on which subjects judge the meanings of concepts. Research suggests that three such orthogonal factors are EvaIuation, Potency and Activity. The meaning of a concept can be represented as the concept's projections on these factors (the origin being the point of neutral meaning), and the "semantic distance” or difference in meaning between concepts is given by _ Z 2 D11 ‘ j dil ’ where D11 is the linear distance between concepts_i and_l, and dil is the difference between the projections of_i and_1 on factor 1, This equation also serves as a definition of cognitive change. While not all kinds of belief or knowledge structures covered by the term "cognition" are representable in terms of the semantic space, the idea of "conceptual structure" is, nevertheless, defined within the model as a spacial configuration: Conceptual structure . . . The distance [D] between each concept and every other concept can be calculated and entered into an mixim_matrix. This matrix represents the semantic structure of of the set of m_concepts, giving the distance or similarity relations among all concepts. The set of distances repre- senting the semantic structure are "plotable" in a space having the same (or fewer) dimensions as the number of dimensions represented in the measuring instrument (pp. 93-94). The final model to be reviewed here is quite different from the others. This model has been developed by Woelfel and his associates (references under Woelfel, Saltiel, Gillham, Barnett, Serota, Taylor, \ Danes). If the majority of cognitive theorists cited have foregone the benefits of powerful mathematical assumptions for the sake of substantive assumptions about the cognitive attribute space, Woelfel represents an entirely contrary orientation. He argues for ”the restructuring of existing theory or the creation of new theory itself designed to fit the most powerful measurement and research models currently available”* (Woelfel, 1974a). He argues, that is, that we should begin with the most mathematically powerful analysis techniques available, and construct measures and theories to fit their requirements. For cognitive theory, this implies a spacial model. Woelfel (1974a) postulates that cognition is ”a process of relating objects of thought to each other. Fundamentally, this involves taking note of similarities and differences between objects . . ." The phrase "similarities and differences" suggests the notion of attribute, and, indeed, this is what Woelfel has in mind. Attributes are important in his model, however, only insofar as the aggregation of respects in which two objects of thought differ is taken to underlie an overall *Woelfel makes this statement in the context of a discussion of sociological theories, but he applies its implications to cognitive theory as well. dissimilarity or distance between the two objects. Thus dissimi— larity, rather than attribute, is the generating concept of Woelfel's model. Dissimilarities among cognitive objects may be represented by a continuous numbering system such that two objects con- sidered to be completely identical are assigned a paired dis- similarity score or distance score of zero (0), and objects of increasing dissimilarity are represented by numbers of increasing value . . . The definition of any set of [n] con— cepts or objects may therefore be represented in terms of the [n x n] matrix D . . . where any entry dij represents the dissimilarity or distance between i and j (Woelfel & Saltiel, 1974). The distance matrix is analyzed by subjecting it to a metric multidimensional scaling routine (Torgerson, 1958; Serota, 1974) which yields a coordinate space of n—l or fewer dimensions in which the concepts are "plotable." This definition of conceptual structure is obviously similar to Osgood's, but in both its derivation and its applications it is quite different. For Osgood, the conceptual structure is derived from distances between concepts on a set of funda- mental semantic factors, which are Obtained, in turn, from analysis of the semantic differential. For Woelfel, the conceptual structure is directly derived from an instrument which requires the subject to pro- vide direct, metric, pairwise distance estimates. While attributional differences are assumed to underlie these distances, there is no as— sumption of an attribute space spanned by fundamental factors. The dimensions of the cognitive space, that is, are not assumed to have any psychological significance, although they may have such signifi— cance. Whatever overall interpretability the space may exhibit is a function of the extent to which the pairwise attributional differences between concepts fall into interpretable patterns. These patterns might be clusters, dimensions or other forms, depending upon the particular set of concepts scaled-—or the patterns may not be at all interpretable. In any case, the configuration "is" just what it "is”: it's validity is not considered to be dependent upon its interpretability. What is of key importance for Woelfel is not the interpretability of cognitive space, but its dynamics. "Change in the definition of any object may be represented as movement of the object in the space relative to other objects" (Woelfel & Saltiel, 1974). Movement is measured by obtaining the matrix D and its spacial representation at several points in time, rotating the coordinate spaces to a criterion which is assumed to make them comparable to each other, and computing changes in location. Velocities can be calculated from locations at two points in time, ac— celerations from locations at three points in time, and so forth. The crucial test of Woelfel's model is whether "laws of motion" can be found to parsimoniously account for the changes observed in the cognitive space. If such laws cannot be found, or if more parsimonious laws can be found in another paradigm, then the model fails. Assumptions of Spacial Models The examples of the spacial model reviewed above encompass a con- siderable range of assumptions. Table 1 summarizes these assumptions roughly. The table makes it obvious that most of the models are quite crude. In the majority of cases it is impossible to determine whether or not a given model implies a given assumption. Why I have applied the term ”quasi-space" to all of the models except Osgood's and Woelfel's should also be clear: The models so designated have few unambiguously spacial properties. Table 1. Assumptions of Selected Spacial Models. Scott Zajonc Runkel Kelly Schroder Osgood Woelfel 3—111; e_ta_l- Dimensional Attributes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No Continuous Attributes No ? ? ? No Yes No All Objects Comparable No ? ? ? ? Yes Yes Interpretable Reference Axes No ? ? ? ? Yes No Interpretable Origin No ? ? ? ? Yes No Change = Motion In Space ? ? ? ? ? Yes Yes Continuous Space ? ? ? ? ? Yes Yes Unbounded Space ? ? ? ? ? No Yes Homogeneous Space ? ? ? ? ? No Yes Isotropic Space ? ? ? ? ? No Yes The most interesting contrast in the table is that between the Osgood and Woelfel models, for these two are both unambiguous and very different from each other. The differences might be summed up by saying that, while Osgood makes strong assumptions about cognitive structure, 10 Woelfel makes strong assumptions about cognitive change. It also appears that Woelfel's is the more general, and the more testable, of the two models. I have already pointed out the differences between Osgood and Woelfel with respect to the nature of attributes and the "interpret- ability" of the structure of cognitive space. I might add that these differences are evidence for the greater generality of Woelfel's model. Were Osgood's assumptions true, Woelfel's model would be no less viable; but were Woelfel's assumptions true, Osgood's model would lose its soul. The five assumptions at the bottom of the table are more relevant to change than to structure. The assumption that cognitive change is equivalent to motion in cognitive space is fairly trivial in the Osgood model, but is a very strong assumption in the Woelfel model. The as— sumption implies that cognitive objects can be observed to "move” in a geometrically reasonable fashion. In general, this means that the motion of a cognitive object does not disturb the overall structure of the space, or the locations of other objects. This is trivial in Osgood's model because a change in the meaning of a concept on the semantic dif— ferential would not generally be expected to change the factor structure of the scales or the meanings of other concepts. In Woelfel's model the motion of an object requires that definite changes occur in the directly measured distances between that concept and every other object in the space, an implication which allows for rigorous tests of "laws of motion" as in the present study. Both models assume a continuous space, but Osgood's space is bounded whereas Woelfel's is not. The boundedness of Osgood's space is 11 an artifact of (l) the semantic differential, which is made up of seven— point scales, and (2) factor analysis, which normalizes (to a range of 1.1.0) the projections of concepts on the reference axes of the space. Woelfel's is a metric model in which boundedness is a strictly empirical question. Both models pretty much beg the question of continuity. A homogeneous space, in contrast to a heterogeneous space, is one whose density, or resistance to motion, is equal at all points. An iso— tropic space, in contrast to ananisotropicspace, is one in which objects have no "natural resting place" or natural direction of movement (Gillham, 1972). Woelfel's model assumes a homogeneous, isotropic space (Woelfel, 1971, Chap. 1). These assumptions are a pragmatic, if not a strictly logical requirement of the assumption that the coordinate system of cogni- tive space is entirely arbitrary. If cognitive space is heterogeneous or anisotropiq then Woelfel's model may fail due to a failure to find ”nice” laws of motion, because "dense regions" or "natural resting places,” if they exist, cannot be located_a priori with respect to an arbitrary co- ordinate system. In this case the model can be saved only by finding some other set of antecedents which can incorporate the peculiarities of cog- nitive space into the laws of motion. Osgood's model appears to assume a heterogeneous, anisotropic space. I say "appears" because, although Osgood and his associates do not comment directly on the issue, there is considerable circumstantial evidence to justify my inference. The evidence comes mainly from the congruity model of cognitive consistency (Osgood & Tannenbaum, 1955). Three aspects of the congruity model have implications for the semantic space. First, the congruity model assumes a tendency toward "polarization” of meanings—- 12 that is, a tendency for objects to be valued 1‘3 on the semantic differ- ential scales. Thus there appears to be a "natural resting place" at the boundary of semantic space. (Note that this would be expected as an artifact, were cognitive space "really” unbounded.) Second, the model assumes that the more polarized is a concept, the more difficult it is to change the concept (in any direction)--in effect, semantic space be- comes "denser" as the boundary is approached. Third, there is evidence that the congruity model applies variously to the several dimensions of semantic space. Tannenbaum (1968) states: . . . It is worth noting that the congruity predictions in cogni— tive interaction studies are generally supported least (i.e., there is a greater discrepency between predicted and obtained scores) on the evaluative, as opposed to the activity and potency factors . . . One suggestion (and it is only a tentative suggestion) is that Egg same rules d2 up; apply £9 all dimensions (p. 62). One ought to point out that any evidence for the uniqueness of evaluative judgments not only suggests that Osgood's semantic space is heterogeneous, but is evidence £23 that assumption as opposed to the assumption of homogeneity in Woelfel's model. Whether Woelfel's model will encounter empirical difficulty along these lines remains to be seen. Woelfel's model has some shortcomings, the most severe of which arise from the problems of measurement. The model handles measurement very well 13 principle, but in practice it is just measurement which most seriously limits the model's applicability. The model requires ratio level measurements of psychological distance which, quite simply, cannot be reliably provided by individual human subjects, at least under pro- cedures so far devised. Thus the model, which one would like to describe individual as well as aggregate phenomena, can be tested only on aggre— gate data-—which, it has been pointed out, can be made as reliable as l3 necessary by means of the sample size (Barnett, 1972; Woelfel, 1974b; Danes and Woelfel, 1975). One could also attack Woelfel's model by citing cognitive structures which it seems unable to describe—-my knowledge of how to tie my shoes, for example. But this sort of criticism ignores the large range of phenomena which the model dggs seem to describe, and avoids rather than attacks the central issues raised by the model, which are both empirical and interesting. No claim of universal synthesis can be made for the model. The literature of cognitive theory is a cornucopia of spaces, networks, schemata, groups, implicational structures, psychologics, algorithms and other paradigms (cf. Zajonc, 1968; Deese, 1969; Weick, 1968). To attempt to subsume all of those models under one model at the present stage would be folly. It would be better, as in the present study, to tackle the issues raised by a specific, well-formulated model, attempting thereby to determine the range of phenomena to which it applies. Despite its possible shortcomings, Woelfel's model seems to be the best\gxtantkapproximation to a general spacial model of cognition. This is because (1) the model is very general--genera1 enough to subsume many of its rivals; (2) the model is fully spacial——it incorporates a full set of geometric assumptions and implications, and thus epitomizes the spacial paradigm; and (3) the model is more empirically testable (begs fewer questions) than the Osgood model, its closest competitor. Never— theless, Osgood's model should be kept in mind as a viable alternative. The model employed in this study is essentially Woelfel's. It assumes that cognitions are representable as locations in multidimensional 14 space, that cognitive change is representable as motion in space, and that cognitive space is continuous, unbounded, homogeneous and isotropic. The model makes no assumption as to the psychological interpretability of the spacial coordinate system_pg£_§e, but assumes that the coordinate system is a stable manifold for which concepts like location, distance and motion, and the full range of geometric implications of those con— cepts, are valid. This model has been selected because it is operation— alizable and permits a full and fair test of spacial assumptions. Spacial Models of Messages A spacial model of messages assumes that the content of a message is a "scaling" or "plotting" of concepts in a message space having the same sorts of structural properties as the cognitive space which it reflects. Woelfel has proposed a definition of the message in the spacial paradigm: Any message, whether verbal or otherwise, may be defined as a statement of the location of some object relative to some other object(s). To the extent that this definition differs from the location (definition) already assigned to that object by the in- dividual, the message may be said to contain information. Any message, therefore, may be concisely and exactly defined as a vector from the point in the self at which the individual himself locates the object to the point in space at which the message locates the same object. When the message defines the location of the object to be the same as the individual's own definition, the information content, and consequently the force, of the in- coming message is zero. . . .When the individual is in receipt of several messages at once (as is frequently the case) the vector sum of all the messages will constitute a resultant vector which describes the aggregate message at an instant in time (Woelfel, 1971, Chapter 6, pp. 11-12). There are three directions in which I would like to extend Woelfel's definition. First, at least one aspect of the definition can be construed 15 as ambiguous. The message is defined both as a statement of the location of an object, and as a vector from the receiver's location of an object to the location proposed in the message. But these are not the same—— one can be thought of as a quality of the message itself, and the other is a relationship between the message and the receiver. While there is some justification in communication theory for a refusal to define the message except in relation to some receiver, that consideration must be weighed against the pragmatic need to study messages in their own right (as in content analysis). The two parts of the definition ought to be distinguished. Second, the definition ought to more explicitly recognize that a message usually refers to several cognitive objects. This is logically required by the assumption that an object is defined by its location with respect to other objects (or with respect to attributes in Osgood's model). Since it is theoretically likely that the message will, to some extent, exert forces upon all of the objects to which it refers, the message should be expected to create more than one vector of change in the re— ceiver. Third, the definition fails to recognize that messages usually have some internal structure. A verbal message usually includes a set of sentences organized in some fashion. The theory of argumentation views the message as a proposition supported by arguments,which are, in turn, comprised of evidence, warrants, etc. We often want to manipulate or measure the internal structure of messages, and the definition of message should allow for this. In view of these arguments I propose the following set of defini— tions. l6 Assertion: The coded representation of a psychological distance between two objects. Message (coded form): A set of assertions. Argument: A function defined on that subset of a message which includes all assertions referring to either or both members of a given pair of concepts. Proposition : The output of an argument; the "distance in the message" between two concepts. Message (cannonical form): An n x n matrix of propositions, where n is the number of objects referred to by assertions in the coded form of the message. Message (reduced form): An n x m matrix of coordinate values, where n is the size, and m is the rank, of the cannonical form of the message; a "plotting" in m—dimensional space of the set of n objects referred to by a message. Message (assimilated form): A transformation of the message as a function of the corresponding cognitive structure in the receiver. Information in a messag : The difference between the assimilated message and the corresponding cognitive structure of a receiver, assuming a "best fit" rotation of the two coordinate systems; a set of vectors from the location of an object in the cognitive structure of a receiver to the locations of corresponding Objects in the assimilated message. These definitions are designed to suggest a spacial model of the message, and to extend Woelfel's definition in the directions indicated above. The definitions are, nevertheless, admittedly crude. There is the problem of operationalization——I discuss this below, but obviously the problem is formidable. There are further problems at the conceptual level. Do the definitions of assertion, argument and proposition fully specify the internal structure of messages? The definition says that an argument is a function which operates upon the assertions in a message, but what sort of function? This is not so much a conceptualization as a category of conceptualizations which need to be developed. The definition 17 is general because it cannot presently be further specified. What the definition does propose is that the assertions in a message are combined in some manner, and that the nature of that combination is a subject for investigation. What I have in mind is that the distance between concepts can be derived indirectly from assertions relating each of the concepts to "third” concepts, but this is only a hint. Similar comments could be made about the definition of the assimilated form of the message, which likewise is not so much a conceptualization as a subject for further thought and research. In order to operationalize the concept of assertion, "the coded ' we must identify rules of representation of a psychological distancefl transformation between linguistic and other codes, and spacial cognitive structures. This is, at best, a far off goal. Furthermore, one wonders whether such an enormous task is worth undertaking before we have good evidence as to the relative usefulness of the spacial model. But how are we to gather data for the model if we cannot operationalize it? The answer, of course, is that when we cannot directly measure variables, we look for indirect indices of them. There appear to be some promising routes toward this more modest objective. Osgood (1959) discusses two methods, one of which is closely re- lated to the semantic space model, but the other of which is more directly applicable to the general spacial model. "Evaluative Assertion Analysis" is a method of measuring the evalu- ation of concepts in a message. It does not provide an index of psycho— logical distance, but it is an approach which could be extended to pro— vide such an index. The method proceeds in several steps from 18 identification of the attitude objects in the message, to "translation" of the message into a series of evaluative assertions, to assignment of directionsenuiweights to each assertion, and finally, to averaging of the evaluations. The result is a scaling of the concepts in the message on an (assumed) unidimensional attitude scale. This method could be extended by performing a similar series of steps for other semantic di— mensions, such as Potency and Activity, and deriving a distance matrix from the multidimensional differences between objects. This procedure would, of course, be extremely laborious. Still worse, it would be practically impossible to computerize. Nevertheless, the method would yield an index of psychological distance which would have a good pre— sumption of validity in terms of both the semantic space model and the set of definitions given above. "Contingency Analysis" might yield a cruder but more direct index of psychological distance. Osgood sees this method as giving an index of the association structure of a source, but whether one interprets the data in terms of association or psychological distance is, at present, purely a function of the model one prefers. Contingency analysis proceeds by (1) dividing the message into units, (2) noting the presence or absence of reference to each concept or category in each unit, and (3) computing the contingencies or co—occurences among concepts. Osgood suggests that the contingencies be tested for statistical significance (in effect, treating the results dichotomously), but from the standpoint of the spacial model, it would be better to treat contingency directly as an index of proximity. The selection of units is a problem: the general criterion is to select units which are neither so small as to preclude co-occurence of concepts, nor so large as to insure universal l9 co-occurence. Another potential source of problems is that a rather large "message" may be necessary in order to obtain a complete, reliable distance matrix. The advantages of this method (and they are strong ad- vantages) are that (l) the whole process, from division of the message into units to multidimensional scaling of the distance matrix, can be made explicit enough for a computer program; and (2) the output from the procedure has face validity as an index of psychological distance (see Osgood, 1959, pp. 66-73, for examples). The face validity of contigency analysis might be questioned on the grounds that, for example, ”commu— nism" and "democracy" co-occur frequently in Western propaganda, despite their great psychological distance. How does the method account for the linguistic difference between comparison and contrast, both of which are co—occurences? The answer is that is doesn't directly, and this might indeed be a problem. One only hopes that experience will show that con— trasts and explicit dissociations are not so frequent as to distort the inferred cognitive space. One might find, for example, that communism” "politicalness," but and "democracy" are quite close on a dimension of quite far apart on a dimension of evaluation. Such an interpretation would be possible if the concepts co—occur only in the presence of other "political" terms. Smith (1974) has developed a set of computer programs, based on principles similar to Contingency Analysis, which yield "computer gener- ated analogues of mental structures from language data." The programs generate multidimensional spacial representations of message content and permit observation of changes over time. The existence of this software opens up new possibilities for exploration of spacial models of messages. 20 Unfortunately, none of the above techniques are applicable in situations (such as the present study) in which short messages are to be presented to subjects as part of an experimental procedure. Two approaches to operationalizing the spacial model of message content remain. One ap- proach would be to infer message content from its effects on receivers. In a study like the present one, however, such a method would beg the essential question, since what is at issue is just what effect messages do have on cognitions spacially conceived. The final method is to have a sample of subjects directly estimate the distances between pairs of concepts "in the message." This, too, has its shortcomings, insofar as message "content" is likely to be as much a function of the judges as of the message reflecting, in short, the "assimilated" message. However, the use of the receivers' judgments of message content is a defensible and practicable, if less than ideal, method of estimating message content in an experimental situation. (One might argue that the subjects who judge message content should be other than the experimental subjects. One might as easily retort, however, that the judgments of "outside” judges would be simply a less accurate estimate of the message as as— similated by the experimental subjects.) Thus a spacial model of messages appears to be operationalizable in all types of situations in which it is likely to be applied, indicating that the project of coordinating formal models of cognitive and message structure is practical as well as theoretically interesting. Spacial Theories of Communication Effects Woelfel (1971; Woelfel and Saltiel, 1974; Saltiel and Woelfel, 1975) has proposed two hypotheses regarding communication effects in terms of the spacial model. 21 The first hypothesis, which we may call the cognitive Law of Motion, holds that cognitive objects have constant resistance to acceler— ation in a cognitive space which is continuous, unbounded, linear, homo— geneous and isotropic. Formally, this reduces to the classical, me— chanical equation, F=ma. In principle, this hypothesis can be tested by experiments analogous to experiments which confirm the mechanical law. For example, the assumption of constant inertial mass is confirmed if the ratios among accelerations induced in concepts by identical forces (e.g. identical messages) are constant across experiments. A further implica— tion of the law is that motion (velocity), once induced, remains constant unless it is opposed by some force. In the case of human cognition, the influence of a message would result in constant change until the force of the message is countered by some opposing force——other messages either internally or externally generated. The law assumes that the cognitive space itself has no viscosity, or resistance to motion within it, but we could be forced by data to amend this assumption and complicate the law accordingly. Woelfel's second hypothesis, known as the Theory of Linear Force Aggregation (FAT), proposes that a cognition is equal to the arithmetic mean of all information accumulated by a person. Communication effects are thus equivalent to a change in the mean given additional values. In this theory, the number of messages which have formed a concept may be identified with the constant inertial mass referred to in the cognitive law of motion. From the standpoint of FAT, the effect of communication is to establish equilibrium points toward which concepts will tend to move; while, from the standpoint of the Law of Motion, the effect of a 22 message is to generate force as a function of the discrepancy between the message content and the cognitive space of the receiver. The two theories are not entirely integrated with each other, although Woelfel and Saltiel (forthcoming) have taken a step in that direction. The assumption which naturally arises from FAT is that the force generated by a message is directly proportional to its discrepency from the belief of a receiver. Woelfel and Saltiel show, however, that this assumption can run into problems when one attempts to explain certain attitude change findings——boomerang effects, for example. Woelfel and Saltiel suggest the possibility that the broadest range of findings in the literature can be explained by supposing that the theory predicts an equilibrium point to which the belief will converge over time, but that the instantaneous force generated by a message is inverse to its dis— crepancy from the receiver's position. The present study sidesteps most of these issues, which are left for later investigation. The study of "motion" in the strict sense can be pursued after it has been determined that cognitive change is de- scribable generally in spacial terms. Thus The Linear Force Aggregation Theory is the basis for the present study for two reasons. First, FAT is the more closely tied of the two theories to the spacial model of message content, in that it explicitly includes messages as the key explanatory variable. Second, FAT is testable without necessitating the measurement of the acceler— ation of concepts in cognitive space——a tricky procedure better not attempted at this early stage of experimental investigation. Roloff (1974) measured acceleration in an experimental setting; however, that 23 was acceleration of a unidimensional attitude rather than of concepts in a multidimensional space. Gillham (1972) computed accelerations in a multidimensional space; however, he used the accelerations only as an index of inertial mass, and could not test any hypotheses regarding ac- celeration, because he lacked the necessary experimental and statistical controls. One point concerning spacial theories of communication effects should be made clear: the test of any particular theory is not equiva— lent to a test of the general spacial model. Many spacial theories are possible-—some more complicated than others. The theory to be presented here, for example, assumes linear motion in a stable, Euclidian space. Complications such as nonlinear motion and warpage of space could be in— troduced later if the simpler theory fails to explain data. The general strategy should be to test simpler theories first, and to complicate theories only when forced to by data. It should be recognized, however, that there is a point at which the repeated failure of ever—more-complex theories to account for the observed phenomena would force us to con— clude that Umegeneral spacial paradigm is unfruitful. So while no study can provide a "crucial" test of the general spacial model (or even, for that matter, of the specific theory under investigation), a study such as the present one can contribute to the ultimate evaluation of the general spacial model. Theory: Communication Effects as Linear Motions in Cognitive Space Scope Conditions The theory predicts the time 5' distances among a set of concepts (s'ij) given the following: 24 (i) The following quantities are known: the set of distances between each pair of concepts 1 and j_at time E (Sij)’ the projection of each concept on each dimension of cognitive space at £(fi the k), inertial mass of each concept (ni), the number of messages received in the interval £_—.£' (p), and the set of assertions contained in messages received during the interval £_- 3} (Eij). (ii) The interval_£ —_E' is sufficient for equilibrium to be established in the cognitive space following receipt of messages. (iii) No change occurs during the interva1_£ — 3} except that induced by known messages. Derivation of the General Structural Equation Woelfel's Linear Force Aggregation Theory states that a belief is equal to the mean value of all messages received. Translated into terms of the spacial model, (1) n )3 = k=l Sijk , ij n Where: sij = the psychological distance between concepts i and j, s. = the distance proposed by message k, 1jk n = the total number of messages which have located 1 and j—— the 'inertial mass' of Sij' A direct implication is that the effect of "new" messages on an already established belief is equivalent to a change in a mean given additional values. (2) ns.. +ps.. p 25 l ij p = the number of new messages Where: 5 = the new belief sij = the mean distance proposed by the new messages In view of the conclusions of Woelfel and Saltiel (forthcoming), we Cu; to regard s'ij as an equilibrium value that will be approached over tir as the messages are processed. In short, we are dealing here with whaI "comparative statics" rather than dynamics. strictly might be called Assume that n, the total number of messages which have located 1 and j, can be expressed as a sum of two quantities, = + (3) n ni n , where n. and n3. are the number of messages which have located 1 and j, 1 respectively. This assumption allows us to partition the expression or the right in equation (2) so as to reflect the relationship between in- ertial mass and message effects. (4) n. p ~ _ n. p ~ _ , 1 . . (sij Sij) + ._1 . . (sij Sij) n n + p n n + p .1 where the left bracketed expression is the change brought about in j ar the right bracketed expression is the change brought about in i. The change brought about, that is, is inversely proportional to the number of messages which has located a concept. In still other words, the ch: brought about by new messages is "apportioned" between i and j in inveI proportion to their inertial masses. Now assume that i and j are located in a multidimensional space, and our problem is to determine the change in location of a "moved" C0] cept i with respect to all other concepts in the space. The first ste 26 in doing this is to note that sij can be expressed in terms of the pro— jections of i and j on a set of orthogonal reference axes of the space. (5) = r _ 2 ij kil (fik fjk) ’ where f. 1 k and fjk are the projections of i and j, respectively, on axis f, and r is the dimensionality of the space. Eij and s'ij can, of course, be expressed similarly. The general structural equation for post-message pairwise distances among concepts in the space can now be derived in three steps. First, we need an expression for f the projection of concept 1 on axis f as ik’ proposed by new messages. Second, we need an expression for f'ik’ the new equilibrium for the projection of i on f brought about by the new messages. Third, we can write the general structural equation. The expression for fik assumes that one—half of the change proposed by Eij is directed toward concept 1, and that the change proposed is ap— portioned among the dimensions of the space proportionate to the distance between the projections of i and j on the dimensions. 2 (6) ~ = (f. — f. ) 1 ~ _ f. — f, fik fik + __3JL___igi__ -____ - (Sij Sij) . 1k jk (Sij) 2 lfik ' fjkl The last factor in expression (5) is needed to determine the sign of the changes proposed in fi The expression for f’ the post— k' ik’ message equilibrium value of the projection of concept 1 on axis f, can now be adapted from the appropriate parts of equation (4). (7) f' — + zni . P (E ) ik " fik ' ik ' fik n n + p 27 In equation (7),;1 is multiplied by 2 to take account of the fact that the derivation of Eif has already divided the proposed change, and allo- cated the change to concepts i and j separately. Note that if either p=0 or §1j=sij, then equations (6) and (7) result in f'ik=fik' These equations, that is, can be applied to any concept in the space, regard— less of whether any messages have affected that concept. Substitution into equation (5) now gives the general structural equation. (8) . = r . _. 2 Sij 1:1 (f 1k fjk) ’ where i and j are any two concepts in the space. Equation (8) is a general structural equation in the sense that it gives the post-message distances between all pairs of concepts, including pairs in which neither, one or both concepts have been affected by messages. Summary of Empirical Assumptions Inherent in the Theory (i) The theory assumes that the variables such as ni and Eij are stable phenomena, quantities that can be measured, and quantities which in fact age measured by the instruments employed. (ii) The theory assumes that all relevant messages are known, im- plying both that messages received before time 5 have no effects during the interval t — t' and that all information received during the interval is included in the calculations. This assumption could be especially dangerous if Woelfel's hypothesis that cognitive objects have constant resistance to acceleration (but not velocity) is valid. (iii) The theory assumes the spacial model of message content—- that a message is composed of a set of assertions which propose distances 28 between pairs of concepts, thus setting up forces along the lines con- necting these concepts. The theory further assumes that the force of an assertion is divided equally between a pair of concepts, and that a con— cept's resistance to that force is a function of the number of messages which have located the concept. (iv) The theory assumes that complex cognitive processes occur out of the awareness of subjects. It seems rather unlikely, that is, that subjects consciously make indirect changes in cognitive distances so as to conform to the spacial model. If these processes go on, they do so implicitly and unconsciously. (v) Finally, the theory assumes that the pairwise distances among cognitive objects are constrained by the stable, Euclidian charac— ter of cognitive space, so that the pairwise distances are not indepen- dent of each other: the motion of a concept implies precisely calculable changes in its distance from every other concept in the space. CHAPTER II PREVIOUS RESEARCH BEARING ON THE THEORY This chapter surveys research literature bearing upon the theory of linear motion at several points. The issues discussed include (1) the existence of cognitive structures conforming to the spacial model; (2) the meaningfulness of motion in cognitive space; (3) Woelfel's Theory of Linear Force Aggregation; and (4) the occurrence of complex cognitive processes out of the awareness of subjects. Following the review of these issues, we consider the overall status of the theory in light of previous research. Spacial Cognitive Structures Evidence that cognitive structures exist which can be represented in terms of a spacial model has come mainly from (1) studies of Osgood's ' and (2) studies employing nonmetric multidimensional "semantic space] scaling methods. Both of these lines of research tend to support the spacial model, although the MDS studies are perhaps the more credible. Osgood and his associates have found that at least some dimensions of semantic space are remarkably stable and invariant across cognitive domains. Osgood, Suci and Tannenbaum (1957) state: The same three major factors of evaluation, otency and activity (which were empirically rather than theoretically derived) have reappeared in a wide variety of judgmental situations, particu- larly where the sampling of concepts has been broad. The rela— tive weights of these factors have been fairly consistent: evaluation accounting for approximately double the amount of variance due to either potency or activity, these two in turn being approximately double the weight of any subsequent factors. (p. 325) This central finding has held up quite well in subsequent studies in many cultures. Seventeen years after publication of The Measurement 29 3O pf Meaning, Osgood (1974) is able to assert that the accumulated research "is rather convincing evidence for the universality of the affective meaning system" (pp. 33—34). There are, however, several problems associated with the semantic space research. First, and most significantly, Osgood's research methods are such as to make it difficult to falsify his central assumptions. The relative success of those methods in a massive accumulation of studies is certainly evidence of the merit of the assumptions. On the other hand, the question of whether cognitive space is_pgsp thought of as an attri— bute space cannot very directly be answered by a method which involves measuring meaning on interval attribute scales and factoring those scales. The method begs the question. Second, there is evidence that the sort of bipolar scales used in the semantic differential do not actually repre— sent psychological poles. Wishner (1960) found indications that "gram— matical antonyms do not necessarily correspond to psychological opposites" (p. 110). Danes and Woelfel (1975) performed a multidimensional scaling study including adjectives frequently used in the semantic differential, and found that supposed polar opposites (l) were at substantially dif- ferent distances from the origin and (2) were at angles to each other through the origin substantially different from 180 degrees. Third, as noted in Chapter I, the semantic space is bounded as a result of both the seven step scales and the factor analysis procedure used to generate the semantic space. Such a set of procedures must lead to ceiling ef— fects in measurement. Thus not only the apparent boundedness of semantic space but its apparentaniSotropimnand heterogeneity are methodological artifacts. 31 These three difficulties are sufficiently serious to cast some doubt on Osgood's findings, although it must be admitted that the con— sistency of those findings and the consequent wide and successful appli— cation of the methods of the semantic space in social science research provide at least some support for the utility of a spacial view of cog— nition. Thus the semantic space research is one source of evidence for the existence of stable, spacial cognitive structures. The basic logic of multidimensional scaling as applied in psycho- logical research has been expressed by Helm, Messick and Tucker (1959): . . . The fundamental concept in multidimensional scaling is psychological distance, which is usually estimated in terms of judgments of similarity among stimuli; i.e., two stimuli judged to be very similar are considered to be psychologically closer together than two stimuli judged to be very different. Given judgments of similarity among all the stimuli in a set, mathe— matical models exist which provide an interpretation of this psychological distance in terms of Euclidian space, and analytical techniques are available to obtain the dimensionality of the space as well as stimulus scale values determined within a rotation and translation. (p. 111) Serota (1974) has outlined the background and history of MDS in some detail. Within the category of MDS we can distinguish between metric and nonmetric techniques. Metric or classical MDS was developed as a psychological measurement technique largely by Torgerson (1958). Metric MDS requires the input of interval or ratio level paired compari— sons data among a set of concepts, and operates upon the data to scale the concepts in an orthogonal vector space which retains all of the in— formation in the original data (i.e., the distance matrix can be exactly reproduced from the coordinate matrix by application of the Pythagorean Theorem). 32 Serota (1974) describes the concerns about metric MDS that led to the development of nonmetric techniques by psychometricians: First, the notion that subjects could make reliable interval of ratio judgments was not readily accepted. It is axiomatic that the reliability of the judgment is inversely proportional to the difficulty of the judgment task. Since the model was attempting to describe individual differences in cognitive arrangement, or psychological distance, it was believed that the technique should be adapted to function with ordinal judgment data which simplify the subject's task and increase the reliability of the findings reported. Second, the use of the "additive constant" approach was con— sidered suspect since its use with ratio scaling violates the assumption of absolute magnitude and its use with interval sealing required separation of systematic and random error to get the data to fit a Eculidian real space. Richardson (1938) made the as-, sumption, which Torgerson defends, that the data was fallible and represented a foreshortening of the differences which when strictly interpreted would yield triangle inequalities and add unnecessary dimensions. The nonmetric approach (Shepard, 1962a, 1962b; Kruskal, 1964a, 1964b) avoided the problem rather than attempting to deal with it by (1) eliminating the distance component from the procedure, (2) artificially generating a configuration in a Euclidian real space of m dimensions (m is less than n and is de- termined from the data) which could be adjusted to fit the dis— similarities relationship and (3) reporting the degree of mono— tonicity between the scale distances and the reported dimensionality (stress). Third, the process of determining dimensionality was itself challenged as contradictory to the goal of simplicity. Shepard (1962a, 1972) states that the purpose of multidimensionality in scaling should be to produce an expression of interrelationship which is readily interpretable. Techniques built upon this view- point tended to emphasize rank reduction at the price of iso- morphism of the solution to the raw data . . . (pp. 48-49). Because of its emphasis upon producing an interpretable space of small dimensionality, nonmetric MDS can be and has been used to determine the utility of a spacial concept of cognitive structure. A representa- tive, indeed almost comprehensive source for the current theory and ap- plications of nonmetric MDS in the behavioral sciences is the two volume collection by Shepard, Romney and Nerlove (1972). A review of the papers in those volumes tends both to further evidence the utility of the 33 spacial model of cognition and to justify our suspicion of Osgood's methods of operationalizing that model. Many MDS studies, that is, have found interpretable spacial configurations, but many of those studies also suggest that not all interpretable multidimensional spacial repre— sentations of cognitive structures also have interpretable dimensional structures. Spacial structures may appear as interpretable clusters, circumplexes or other nondimensional forms. The set of possible forms has been somewhat systematized by Degerman (1972). In a study that exemplifies the flexibility of MDS, Rapoport and Fillenbaum demonstrated that color terms in American English scale as a two dimensional circumplex corresponding quite closely to the theoretical color circle, and that "Have" words in American English (return, steal, take, etc.) scale as a set of clusters in space. Regarding the "Have" words, the authors conclude (p. 121): "The two dimensions are difficult to interpret, and as the tight clusters appearing on the plot suggest, any attempt at a dimensional representation imposes structure on the data that is not there . . ." Indeed, Rapoport and Fillenbaum argue that MDS analysis is inappropriate in such a case, but their argument rests en— tirely on the assumption that a spacial representation must yield inter— pretable dimensions——a doubtful assumption in view of the clearly inter— pretable clusters present in the plot of their data. When MDS studies have found interpretable dimensions, the dimensions are sometimes similar to the Evaluation, Potency and Activity dimensions of the semantic space and sometimes not. The study of Nations reported by Wish, Deutsch and Biener (1972) found the evaluation-like dimension of Political Alignment and the potency-like dimension of Economic Development, 34 but also found dimensions of Geography—Population and Culture—Race which have no correspondence with semantic space findings. Rosenberg and Sedlak (1972) found, for personality terms, clear dimensions of good—bad and dominance—submission. Burton (1972) found that occupation names fall long dimensions of dependency, prestige and skill, D'Andrade, ep._al. (1972) found that disease terms scale by seriousness and contagion. These studies all give evidence both of the validity of the general spacial model of cognition and the utility of MDS as a way of operation- alizing the spacial model. Perhaps more compelling evidence, however, comes from those studies which have related spacial representations to human behavior assumed to depend upon the cognitive similarity of objects. That such relations hold has been demonstrated for the substitutability of consumer products (Stefflre, 1972) and of political candidates (Mauser, 1972): products or candidates found by MDS to be closer together are more likely to be substituted for one another (switched among) in the market or the electoral arena. Jones and Young (1972) found that fre— quency of social communication could be predicted from distances among people in a spacial representation of a social structure. In sum, both semantic space and nonmetric MDS research tends to confirm the utility of a spacial model of cognition, in that those studies have shown that the spacial representation is stable, valid on its face, and reliably related to other human behavior. The Meaningfulness of Motion in Cognitive Space If nonmetric MDS has a strength it is in the reduction of data to interpretable spacial representations. If we take seriously Woelfel's theoretical argument as presented in Chapter I, however, the existence 35 of such interpretable configurations is neither necessary nor sufficient to support the spacial model. Interpretability is unnecessary in that a cognitive structure might be spacial and yet display no "interpretable" dimensions or other structures. Nor is interpretability sufficient to support the spacial model, for the concept of space implies motion, in terms of which the space may be described as homogeneous or hetero- geneous and so forth. Because the relationships it displays can be assumed, even in principle, to be merely ordinal, nonmetric MDS may be considered unsuit— able for the investigation of motion in cognitive space. Thus their interest in the study of change has motivated the renewed interest of Woelfel and his associates in metric techniques. This revived interest has led to the development of the Galileo system——a set of measurement and design techniques and a package of computer programs——which adapts classical MDS to Woelfel's interest in the study of cultural processes." The Galileo system has been described in detail by Serota (1974), but a succinct overview of the technique is provided by Taylor, Barnett and Serota (1975): The subjects are given a complete (n(n—l)/2) list of pair com— parisons for the set of concepts being scaled. They are asked to make ratio judgments of the dissimilarity between concepts using the form: Iflx and y are_u units apart, how far apart are concept a and concept p2 Such an item wording requests a distance judgment from a respondent (" . . . how far apart are a and p?”). However, it requests that this judgment be made as a proportion of a standard distance provided by the researcher ("if x and y are u units apart . . ."). This format allows the respondent to report any positive value; the scale is thus unbounded at the high end, con- tinuous, and grounded with a true zero (identity — two concepts are perceived to be the same). 36 Since the data for an individual case is highly unreliable (reliability being inversely proportional to the difficulty of the judgment' task), and since our goal here is a measure of social or cultural conceptions (Serota pp, 31,, 1975), we may use aggregation techniques to improve our measurements. By applying the Central Limits Theorem and Law of Large Numbers we find that the arithmatic average of all responses for any cell in the matrix will converge on the true mean for the population as the sample grows large. . . The mean distance matrix is further transformed to a scalar— products matrix which has been double—centered (Torgerson, 1958) to establish the origin at the centroid of the distribution. This matrix is subsequently factored (using a direct iterative, unstandardized procedure) to achieve a coordinate matrix whose columns are orthogonal axes and whose rows are the projections of the concept location on each of the axes . . . This space has the property of representing the average distance judgments for all possible pairs simultaneously. Additionally, the multi— dimensional space is constructed from the unstandardized dis— tance vectors between all possible pairs, and all variance in the sample population is thus accounted for by the n—dimensional space. Finally, this procedure is repeated at each point in time and the spaces are rotated about the centroid to a least-squares best fit to provide approximations of the concept motions over time. From these resultant cross-time coordinate matrices we can fit curves (trajectories) of motion which describe the relational change from the set. (PP- 4—5) A more recent addition to the system is an alternative rotation pro— cedure which takes account of theoretical assumptions about which con— cepts havernuihave not ”moved" during the interval between observations (Woelfel, et a1., 1975). Woelfel's mathematical theories and the (in principle) precision of the Galileo system as an operationalization of cognitive space not- withstanding, the evidence thus far produced to support the inference *Studies by Barnett (1972) and by Danes and Woelfel (1975) have achieved adequate levels of reliability with samples of well under one hundred people. 37 of meaningful motion in cognitive space is both sparse and rather impre— cise. An examination of four studies bearing on the question finds that the inference of meaningful motion rests largely on the_pg§£_hgg "inter— pretability" of observed changes in location of concepts. Even so, the obtained results are sufficiently interesting to warrant further investi— gation. Gillham (1972) found that motion over two intervals (encompassing several months) in the aggregate cognitive space of members of a soci- ology department was "lawful” according to several criteria, including interpretability in terms of_pg§£_hgg explanations, general stability of the configuration over time and predictability of magnitudes of changes of concepts from gross differences and changes in volume of information flow about the concepts. Gillham made no specific prediction of forms of motion; nor did he measure or control the content of information. The study incorporated only rough indices of the amount of information communicated about each concept. Gillham's pgsp_hgg interpretations of motions were aided by interviews in which respondents to the study were asked to explain specific changes in their responses. The resulting flavor of Gillham's interpretations is given by a brief quotation: Once again the dimensions that are used vary considerably across respondents. The professor who has the largest changes from time two to time three is said to be ' . . . a nicer guy than I had thought' and 'more of an outcast' in relation to another professor who once had much power in the department. It is clear from personal observation that this professor whose posi— tion changed so much has recently spent much more time talking with graduate students than he once did. Two respondents who were later interviewed mentioned meeting him in the graduate lounge . . . (pp. 53-54) In a five wave panel study of the 1972 U. S. Presidential Election, conducted in Champaign County, Illinois, Barnett, Serota and Taylor 38 (1974) tested several qualitative hypotheses about motion of candidates and issues in the aggregate space. These were: (1) that candidates would converge over time with issues with which they were publicly as— sociated; (2) that the candidates would diverge from each other over time; (3) that the candidate whose aggregate distance from ”Me" (one of the concepts scaled) was minimal at the time of the election would be elected; and (4) that the overall magnitude of the space would shrink as the election approached. The study suffered from methodological problems --in particular, a very high rate of subject attrition. And again, as in Gillham's study, the hypotheses could be tested only by post hoc inter— pretations of observed changes in light of what the authors informally knew about the events of the election campaign. By that weak criterion the data were claimed to provide some support to the hypotheses. The authors conclude: These findings clearly lack the rigor necessary to test the primary hypothesis that movement in the vector space is a function of the amount of information the subjects receive. We can only infer this from the results reported above. It is, however, possible to ob— serve regular motion in the space reported here which maintains a high level of face validity with both current political polling practices and actual voting behavior for the population. To use— fully apply these techniques and test our main hypothesis it will be necessary to control the information concerning the scaled con- cepts and/or perform a content analysis about those topics, while utilizing the metric multidimensional scaling instrument at a level of rigor consistent with the precision which it is able to achieve. (p. 30) Taylor, Barnett and Serota (1975) have since completed a trend study of a congressional election near Detroit, Michigan. The trend study, by observation of independent samples at several points in time, avoids the problems of subject attrition and sensitization. Hypotheses one, three and four of this study'were identical to those of the previous 39 study, while hypothesis two was replaced. The new hypothesis two was that "identification of a candidate with the issues clustering closest to the average position for the respondents (Me) will cause that candi- date to converge with the average position for 'Me'." The method of analysis employed—fipgsg hgg, qualitative interpre— tation of motions in light of informal knowledge about the campaign—— was similar to that of the previous study. This time, however, the authors appear to have had much more direct and intimate knowledge of the Democratic candidate's campaign strategies, and, indeed, seem to have influenced those strategies to a degree. This greater knowledge permitted the authors to make several qualitative predictions, which generally were confirmed. The Democratic candidate attempted to identify himself with crime prevention and subsequently converged with that concept in the space. The candidate's distances from two concepts on which he did not comment, however, remained relatively stable. This was considered to support Hypothesis One. The new Hypothesis Two is still more interesting be— cause it introduces a question of indirect change——whether identifying a candidate with an issue that is ”close" to the aggregate Me will move the candidate closer to Me. Significantly, a qualitative analysis of the Democratic candidate's motion with respect to Bussing, Crime Preven— tion and Me was judged to support the hypothesis. Since the prediction of the election outcome by a formula based on the distance of the candi— dates from Me was accurate within two percent, and was more accurate than a prediction based on customary polling methods, Hypothesis Three was also considered supported. Hypothesis Four, however, was not supported. 40 Although the study discussed above is in many ways quite impressive, its limitations are also obvious (and readily admitted by the authors). The most general and serious problem is that lack of control (statistical or experimental) over information flow prevented before—the-fact pre— diction of motion based on explicit mathematical assumptions. A second problem is that the analysis tended to focus upon certain motions and ignore others. In particular there was no attempt to systematically ex- plain all observed changes, to seek out evidence contrary to theory, or even to account for apparent anomalies (like the great motion of the Republican Party, presumably a relatively massive concept). A fourth study which has attempted to assess the meaningfulness of motion in cognitive space is reported in Woelfel, gt .al. (1975). This study was conducted in a controlled setting. Data were collected at four points in time. Between measurements subjects received messages, attri— buted to two sources, advocating a behavior, the CTP, the meaning of which was left vague. As predicted, the two message sources and CTP were observed to converge in space. This motion was especially evident when a rotation procedure was employed which attempted to leave only those three concepts free to vary, a result which suggests the possibility that the results of previous studies would have been more clear—cut had they been able to use the new rotation procedure. Just because this study was so much more controlled than the pre— vious three its weakness as a test of theory, rather than as a piece of research pg£_§g, become prominent. Once again, despite the mathematical precision of Woelfel's theories and the presumed precision of the scaling technique employed, only a qualitative prediction was made. Furthermore, 41 only some of the spacial information available was used in making and testing the predictions. Specifically the prediction that the two sources and CTP would converge says nothing about how those concepts would move with respect to other concepts in the space. If the notion of "Laws of Motion in Cognitive Space" is to have any nontrivial meaning then that additional information must be taken into account and the corresponding phenomena explained. Linear Force Aggregation Theory The hypothesis that a cognition is equal to the mean of all the information to which a person has been exposed has been somewhat success— fully tested from several standpoints in studies carried out by Woelfel and his associates. One line of research has considered whether a belief or attitude can be predicted from estimates of the information to which the person has been exposed. In the earliest of these studies, which predated the theory itself, Woelfel and Haller (1971) accounted for 64 percent of the variance in high school students' educational aspirations, and 57 per— cent of occupational aspirations, with linear regression models which included as predictors the means of the educational and occupational ex— pectations for the student held by the student's designated significant others.‘ Mettlin (1970) successfully replicated those results with a different sample of students. Using linear regression models, Woelfel and Hernandez (1974) accounted for about 55 percent of the variance in college students' self—conceptions as marijuana users, and Woelfel, g; 31, (1974) accounted for about 62 percent of the variance in French— Canadian separatism. 42 The impressive coefficients of determination reported in these studies should be interpreted with a great deal of caution. First, as a practical matter we will seldom be able to measure 311 messages to which an individual has been exposed, and we certainly will not be able to do so in field settings and for substantially interesting cognitions. Thus FAT cannot be, and in fact has not been, strictly tested in field studies such as those cited above. Second, the linear models tested in studies incorporated many variables, which are only interpretable £9 varying degrees as indices of ”information." In Woelfel and Haller (1971), for example, Educational Aspirations were about as strongly predicted by Occupational Aspirations and Academic Performance as by Significant Other Expectations, and all three of these variables contributed to the re— ported R2 of .64. Academic Performance can be considered as self- reflexive behavior and therefore as information, but to similarly inter- pret Occupational Aspirations would be questionable. The results of Woelfel and Hernandez (1974) and Woelfel, g; 31. (1974) are even more dubious from this standpoint. Information exposure in these studies was measured by subjective reports, which over twenty years of cognitive consistency research (Abelson, et al., 1968) suggests may correlate with attitude quite independently of actual communication content. Further— more each study included over thirty variables in the multiple regression models, and in each case demographic ("structural") and "related atti- tude” variables independently explained significant proportions of vari— ance. Again, demographic variables may incorporate location in the societal communication network, but "related attitudes” seem entirely indefensible as information measures. Third, these studies actually 43 contradict the simple mathematical formulation of the theory insofar as they have found indications that not all sources ”count" equally in attitude formation. This is evident to some extent from the varying regression weights of the exposure variables. More directly, Woelfel and Hernandez (1974) estimated the "inertial masses" of various sources and found them to vary considerably. Woelfel, however, has always regarded the theory as oversimplified in this respect (see, for example, Saltiel and Woelfel, 1975); and the necessity, under some circumstances, of differentially weighting messages from different sources does not seriously compromise the principle of a linear force aggregation theory. Nor is the above critique intended to assert that the available evidence denies the predictive utility of FAT. It asserts only that the available evidence, while suggestive, falls far short of ”proof." A second line of research into FAT comprises two studies which test the implication that the more information upon which a cognition is based the more resistant to change is that cognition. First, Gillham (1972) examined the hypothesis that motion of a concept in multidimensional cognitive space is inversely proportional to the amount of information composing it. The concepts in his study were members of a sociology faculty, and the amount of information was indexed by such variables as the number of graduate assistants working with the professor and the mean number of hours respondents reported talking with the professor. All correlations between these indices and the ”inertial mass" (relative stability) of the concepts were in the predicted direction, although most of the correlations were quite low. Second, Saltiel and Woelfel 44 (1975) found that attitude change in a sample of high school students over a six month interval inversely correlated (r=.l9, p<.05) with an index of "number of messages." The index was computed for each respon— dent by multiplying the number of people with whom the respondent re— ported (specifically named) having talked about the attitude issues by the average amount of communication the respondent reported having with these "significant others." Thus two very different studies have both found absolutely low but directionally consistent correlations supporting the FAT implication that information accumulates as the inertial mass of concepts. Saltiel and Woelfel (1975) report additional results bearing on the theory. Most interesting among these are the negative findings that attitude change was BEE related to heterogeneity of significant other opinions (as measured by the variance of attitude responses directly ob— tained from respondents' nominated significant others), nor to an index of psychological stress, nor to self-reported strength or certainty of opinion. These negative findings tend to rule out possible competing explanations of attitude stability. A third and final line of research into FAT includes studies which directly attempt to assess the theory's utility for predicting the cog— nitive effects of information inputs. The study reported in this dis— sertation is in this line, which may be said to have begun with Roloff (1974). Roloff tested the basic implication of the theory for cognitive change: the proposition that attitude change is directly and linearly related to the number of incoming messages and the discrepancy of those 45 messages from the old attitude, and that attitude change is inversely related to inertial mass (accumulated information). In a multiple— message experiment Roloff found significant correlations between dis— crepancy and attitude change at different times, for two of three topics. For the third topic discrepancy and attitude change were correlated at one time but not at the other time. The deviant issue was later iden— tified as having the highest inertial mass of the three. Roloff also found that the maximum attitude change on each topic occurred with the delivery of the first message. Subsequent messages induced significantly smaller change increments. Again, this is consistent with the idea that information accumulates as inertial mass. Although these are not precise tests of the mathematical theory, they do lend the theory some support. The political study by Taylor, Barnett and Serota (1975) also at— tempted to test the cognitive change implications of FAT. The authors grant at the outset that in . . . field studies such as the research described here, however, lack of experimental controls prevents adequate empirical exami— nation of these [FAT] equations. Attitude change, then, is treated as a simple quantitative function of the number of mes- sages an individual has received about a given attitude object. Thus, the greater the information history about an attitude ob— ject the more difficult it becomes to foster attitude change. (p. 2) By this weaker test findings such as that the less known Democratic challenger moved more in cognitive space than did the more known Repub— lican incombant, and that the Democratic candidate moved more with respect to issues on which he campaigned than issues which he didn't mention, may provide some support for the theory. On the other hand, how are we to explain the fact that among the concepts that underwent the greatest change were the Republican Party, the Democratic Party and 46 Me—-presumably highly massive concepts? The support given FAT by this study is weak at best. Finally, Woelfel 3;, 31., (1975) report a laboratory experiment in which three low mass concepts associated with each other by means of messages converged toward each other in cognitive space. These results conform generally to the theory; although again no direct test is made of the mathematical theory, and the relative motions are not entirely consistent with what one might reasonably suppose to be the relative masses of the concepts. Considered together these three studies are rather weak evidence for the utility of FAT for predicting the cognitive effects of messages. In fact, the present study is the first to attempt a direct test of FAT as a mathematical theory of the cognitive effects of communication. Two very substantial lines of research in addition to the three sets of studies discussed above might be interpreted as bearing on FAT. These are studies of the relation between advocated and obtained atti— tude change and studies of information integration. FAT quite unambiguously predicts a positive linear relation be— tween attitude change advocated and obtained. A summary of the research literature by Greenberg and Roloff (1975), however, makes clear that non— linear and even negative relations frequently have been found. Ulti- mately either the conflicting studies will have to be reinterpreted to fit the theory or the theory itself will have to be changed or restricted in scope. The last choice is taken by Greenberg and Roloff, who suggest that the relation is linear and positive (thus FAT may apply) only for low mass concepts. Greenberg and Roloff report data showing a linear 47 relation between attitude change advocated and obtained on a set of topics relatively unknown to the experimental subjects. This is consistent with their interpretation, but does not, of course, demonstrate the proposition, fatal to FAT as a general theory, that the relation is nonlinear for high mass topics. The main event in the information integration literature has been a bout between models which assume that information inputs are added to form an overall impression and models which assume that information inputs are averaged. Considered as an information integration model, FAT is quite definitely an averaging model. Reviewing the literature on "summative" versus averaging models of information integration, Wyer (1974) concludes: It is undoubtedly clear by now that 'critical' tests of summative and averaging models, and the identification of the psychological processes to which they pertain, are very difficult to construct. The data usually interpreted as evidence for a summative process (e.g., the 'set size' effect) can be accounted for by an averaging model such as Anderson's. On the other hand, the 'averaging—like' effects when moderately polarized information is added to highly polarized information could in principle be predicted by a summa— tive model, suchzfi;Fishbein's, which takes into account the influ— ence of attributes other than those specified in the information presented. (p. 300) Wyer goes on to present further data which he argues support a summative over an averaging model. However, he goes still further to suggest that both models may be false or may apply only in limited circumstances. All considered, the research evidence bearing on FAT must be re— garded as equivocal. Clearly there are many issues to be resolved. As is frequently the case in the behavioral sciences, resolution of these issues is made more difficult by the fact that competing theories are applied in different research paradigms which are not always easily com— parable. How do we relate Gillham's results to the information inte— gration literature, for example? Still unless a theory succeeds pp its 48 pyp ground it is not at all worthy of consideration. In the present case the "home ground" of FAT is the set of studies by Woelfel and his associ— ates which seem generally consistent with the theory, although the sup— port is weak and the studies unrigorous. Research is called for to test the theory more rigorously. Cognitive Consistency Without Awareness At least one aspect of the theory of linear motion presented in Chapter I may be quite counter—intuitive. As we previously have noted, the theory assumes a total integration of cognitive structure in terms of a "consistency" principle which is representable as the stable, Euclidian character of cognitive space. Thus motion of a concept with respect to_§py other concept implies motion of that concept with respect to_gll other concepts in accordance with a straightforward application of the Pythagorean Theorem. Not only does such a consistency principle imply exceedingly complex cognitive processes, but those processes must operate entirely outside of the subject's awareness. Does psychological research lend any plausibility to such a hypothesis? Brock (1968) has considered this issue from the standpoint of con— sistency theories in social psychology. Brock cites several examples of studies in which dissonance reduction (or a corresponding consistency process in terms of some other theory) has apparently taken place with— out the conscious awareness of subjects. Lack of awareness is assumed on diverse grounds, including young age of subjects (three—year—olds, Brock, 1963), assessment of awareness of response-reinforcement con— tingency in a verbal conditioning setting (Cohen, Greenbaum and Mansson, 1963), and use of hypnosis (Brock and Grant, 1963; Blum, 1961; Rosenberg, 1960). 49 Perhaps the most impressive evidence, however, comes from studies of consistency models which are both complex and unfamiliar to subjects but to which subjects' behavior nevertheless conforms, thus presumably unconsciously. Brock cites one such study in which McGuire (1960) found, among a sample of below average achievement high school students, in— direct attitude change as required by the multiplicative probability rule on propositions syllogistically related to propositions which were the targets of persuasive messages. McGuire comments: In the present study several procedures were employed in an at— tempt to minimize the degree of conscious awareness. (For example, no mention was made to the 35 that their consistency was being assessed; the related propositions were widely separated from one another in the questionnaire; a quantitative expression of opinion was required and the assessment of inconsistency involved a mathe- matical model unfamiliar to the Ss.) (p. 352) McGuire's main finding was replicated in two experiments reported by Dillehay, Insko and Smith (1966), who conclude that ”it is unlikely that a conscious effort toward logical consistency is operating: the properties of the model are far too complex to be understood and applied by even the most astute subjects” (pp. 653-654). A somewhat similar line of reserach has been pursued using the congruity model (Osgood and Tannenbaum, 1955) as the criterion of con— sistency. Tannenbaum and Gengel (1966) established three source—concept linkages, and, in a separate message, made the concept attitude positive or negative. Congruity predictions of subsequent attitude changes toward the sources (which were not mentioned in connection with the per— suasive messages) were generally supported, although there were some con- trary findings. The subjects were college students. Tannenbaum (1966) extended the logic of the first study to a situation in which linkages 50 were established between a single source and two concepts, and attitude toward one of the concepts was then changed by a persuasive message. The congruity model prediction that change in the first concept would influ— ence the source attitude, and that this source change would, in turn, produce appropriate changes in the second concept, was strongly supported in the results. The subjects were high school males. Although it is not mentioned in the original report, Tannenbaum (1968) adds: When subjects were queried for their reasons for showing fairly substantial attitude change toward one concept as a result of reading a 300 word message on another concept, a considerable number first indicated surprise and doubt that they had changed. When their pre— and post—test scores were made available and they were convinced that they had indeed changed their beliefs, they voiced considerable resentment and were clearly upset with them— selves. (p. 434) The accumulated evidence impressively supports the proposition that complex consistency processes can occur without the conscious awareness of subjects. None of this, of course, directly bears on the theory tested in the present study, except that it generally lends plausibility to theories of a certain type; i.e., theories which postulate complex, unconscious cognitive processes. Whether the maintenance of relation— ships as required by the theory of linear motion is a process that actually goes on is an unanswered empirical question. The point is that the evidence suggests the question is worthy of serious study: it is not on its face absurd. Summary This chapter has reviewed research literature bearing upon (1) the utility of a spacial representation of cognitive structure; (2) the meaningfulness of motion in cognitive space; (3) Woelfel's Theory of Linear Force Aggregation; and (4) the occurrence of complex and 51 unconscious consistency processes in the human mind. What, in general, is the status of the theory of linear motion in light of the literature? First the literature strongly supports the inference that spacial models can be meaningful and useful representations of cognitive structures. This is not to say that all cognitive structures can be represented spac— ially, but is to say that a broad range of structures can be so repre- sented, and that such representations have won an important place in behavioral research. Second, however, the evidence for the meaningfulness of motion in cognitive space, while suggestive, is far from conclusive. The research so far has not been very rigorous; and in fact the accumulated evidence largely consists of pg§5.hgg interpretations of selected features of the observed changes in spacial locations of concepts. The theoretical work in this area is rather highly developed. Needed is research of com— parable quality, research that will test g priori hypotheses derived from explicit assumptions. Third, the evidence bearing on FAT is quite equivocal. Despite its conceptual simplicity the theory is very difficult to operational— ize. All evidence, both positive and negative, can be attacked, for example, on the ground that it fails to take account of all information to which the subject has been exposed. While studies by Woelfel and his associates have generally been interpreted as at least consistent with the theory, little effort has been made to explain the apparently contradictory findings of research on message—attitude discrepency and information integration. There is a presumption that the theory is over— simple and will ultimately have to be complicated. Here the need is for 52 research of precision sufficient to suggest the necessary complications. Attention must be directed particularly to operationalizing the con— cepts in the theory and testing numerical predictions. Fourth, plenty of evidence points to the occurrence of complex, unconscious consistency processes. Thus our theory of linear motion cannot be rejected out of hand merely because it assumes that such pro— cesses occur. Of course the theory may well be rejected because the specific processes it posits happen not to occur——but that is a matter to be settled by empirical investigation. This dissertation was conceived in View of the above. Building upon the secure foundation of spacial models of cognitive structure, the theory of linear motion extends those models into less—explored territory: the explanation of cognitive change. The particular as- sumptions made permit numerical predictions, which, in turn, permit a more rigorous test of both the spacial model and FAT. The study re— ported in the following chapters is an attempt at such rigorous theory— testing. CHAPTER III METHODS This chapter describes the methods——design, procedures and analysis ——of an empirical study intended to test the theory of linear motion pre— sented in Chapter I in view of the research background presented in Chapter II. The study is described under the two main headings of Design and Procedures, and Data Analysis. Design and Procedures Overview A pretest-manipulation-posttest, within—subjects experimental de— sign was employed. The study was conducted at Michigan State University on two successive Mondays, June 23 and 30, 1975. In the pretest a cognitive domain of 15 concepts was scaled using the Woelfel technique of direct, ratio judgments of inter—concept dis— tances (see below "Measurement of Variables"). Subjects then read three messages, each intended to change the distance between a pair of concepts. Thus motion should have been induced in six concepts, leaving nine con— cepts which were not manipulated. The two sets of concepts (manipulated nad not) provided experimental control. As a result of this procedure, theory predicts that specific changes should have occurred in 69 of the 105 pairwise distances among the 15 concepts, while the remaining 36 distances should not have changed. In the posttest the actual post-message inter—concept distances were measured, these to be compared with those predicted by theory. Pre— test and posttest were separated by one week. Messages were presented pgph immediately following the pretest and immediately before the post— test. The purpose of this procedure was to allow for a period of time 53 54 sufficient for complex cognitive changes to occur, while also taking account of the tendency for the effects of messages to "wear off” over time. In sum, the pretest consisted of a printed packet containing the following: (1) a cover letter explaining the purpose of the experiment, (2) an instrument for obtaining estimates of the inertial masses of the 15 concepts, (3) the 105 distance estimates, (4) the three messages, and (5) questions following each message for obtaining estimates of the dis— tance proposed by the message. The posttest, administered one week later, consisted of a printed packet containing the following: (1) a cover letter, (2) the three messages, (3) questions following each message for obtaining estimates of the distance proposed by the message (in order to assess reliability of those items), (4) the measures of inertial mass (in order to assess reliability and validity of those items and provide a filler following the message), and (5) the 105 distance estimates. Subjects The participants in the study were students in communication classes at Michigan State University. The questionnaires were admin- istered during classes, and the students were informed that participa— tion was strictly voluntary. A total of 93 students participated. Of those, 64 provided usable data. Fourteen subjects were present at the pretest but not at the post— test, while ten subjects were present at the posttest but not at the pre— test. Four subjects, although they were present at both administrations, failed to complete one or both questionnaires. Thus 28 subjects had to be excluded from the data analysis because they provided insufficient data. 55 The data of one additional subject were excluded. The posttest data of this subject displayed a pattern which the experimenter inter— preted as intentional non—cooperation with the experiment. 102 of the 105 distance estimates of this subject were identical (all were 100). The remaining three estimates were sharply changed from the pretest in the direction opposite to that suggested by the experimental messages. Whatever may explain the behavior of this subject it is not the hypothe— sis under investigation. Thus 64 subjects were included in the data analysis. Of these, 36 were students in one graduate course and 28 were students in two under— graduate courses. 38 of the subjects were males and 26 were females. The mean age of the subjects was 26 and the median age was 24. In general, then, the subjects tended to be advanced college students, people who are capable of performing complex cognitive tasks. Cognitive Domain ”nations" was selected for study. The The cognitive domain of domain seemed suitable for spacial modelling because it consists mainly of a set of discrete entities (nations) to which we attribute various characteristics. The domain also has previously been studied——for example, by Wish, Deutsch and Biener (1972). The spacial representation of the domain should, therefore, be somewhat predictable. Fifteen nations were studied. The number 15 was considered to be the approxi~ mate upper limit possible for the subjects and setting of the study. The specific nations to be included in the study were selected by a three-stage procedure that combined random and judgmental features. First, a set of six nations judged to be diverse and relatively familiar to most people was selected from the list used by Wish, Deutsch and 56 Biener. The six are U.S.A., U.S.S.R., China, Brazil, West Germany and India. The purpose of this procedure was to provide a stable framework for the cognitive space and to make the structure of the space somewhat predictable (Wish, Deutsch and Bierner found clear dimensions of Poli— tical Alignment and Economic Development). Second, a pool of 18 countries was selected by means of a table of random numbers from the roster of the United Nations (Office of Public Information, 1972). Third, 9 of the 18 countries were discarded based on three criteria: (1) eliminate countries duplicated in the six chosen from the Wish, Deutsch and Bierner study, (2) retain pairs of countries which seem promising for message construction, and (3) retain countries so as to maintain a roughly even spacial dis— tribution in terms of the expected dimensional structure. The nine coun— tries chosen by this procedure were: Singapore, Mexico, Portugal, Poland, Fiji, Central African Republic, Congo, Greece and Guyana. The 15 countries to be included in the study were assigned numbers from a table of random numbers. These numbers determined the order of appearance of the countries on the questionnaires and were used as iden— tification numbers in the data analysis. Thus the final list of nations was: (1) China, (2) Singapore, (3) Mexico, (4) U.S.A., (5) Portugal, (6) Poland, (7) India, (8) Fiji, (9) West Germany, (10) Brazil, (11) Central African Republic (C.A.R.), (12) Greece, (13) U.S.S.R., (14) Congo and (15) Guyana. Experimental Messages The decision to use three messages was constrained by several con— siderations. A "message" is conceived of as a set of arguments bearing upon the distance between a single pair of concepts. With respect to a 57 message the whole set of distances among concepts in a cognitive domain can be divided into three subsets: (l) the single distance ”directly" changed by the message, (2) the set of distances "indirectly" changed by the message, and (3) the set of distances not at all changed by the mes— sage. "Direct" change in distance means simply that the manipulated con— cepts move either toward or away from each other. ”Indirect" change in distance means that the manipulated concepts, as they move toward or away from each other, each also move with respect to all of the remaining con— cepts in cognitive space. Distances neither directly nor indirectly af— fected by a message are assumed not to change at all. In a domain of 15 concepts there are 105 distances. If one message is processed the spacial theory predicts one directly changed distance, 26 indirectly changed dis— tances and 78 unchanged distances. Table 2 gives the whole set of pos- sible distributions of types of changes in a 15-concept cognitive domain. Table 2. Possible Distributions of Changes of Distance in a Domain of 15 Concepts. No. of No. of Distances No. of Distances No. of Distances Messages Directly Changed Indirectly Changed Unchanged 0 0 O 105 l l 26 78 2 2 48 55 3 3 66 36 4 4 80 21 5 5 90 10 6 6 96 3 7 7 98 O All three types are theoretically important in that the theory pur— ports to exactly predict them. A failure with respect to any type would 58 constitute a failure of the theory. The "indirect" changes, however, are particularly crucial because they alone are a unique consequence of the spacial model. The "direct" and "no change" types are predicted by many other possible theories and thus do not distinguish among theories. In light of this the number of messages should be selected so as to provide for some of each type of change, but should emphasize the theoretically crucial "indirect" changes. Another general consideration is the practical limitations imposed by the subjects and the experimental setting. Both of these factors sug- gest that the smallest possible number of messages be used, as each mes- sage exacts a price in time and in the information processing capacities and the good will of subjects. Three messages seemed to be an optimal number, all of the above considered. Three pairs of concepts were selected for inclusion in messages. The selection was based on both theoretical and practical grounds. The theoretical grounds were that the nations be Of no greater than moderate inertial mass and that the members of each pair be at a moderate dis- tance from each other. The former criterion was established to facili- tate manipulation of the concepts with a single message, while the latter criterion was established to maximize flexibility in message construction and minimize the possibility of regression artifacts in the results. Nations were measured against these criteria by the judgment of the ex- perimenter. The practical ground for selecting pairs of nations was that the mere presentation of factual information by a moderately high credi- bility source could be expected to imply a substantial change in the 59 distances between the concepts. This test also was applied by the judg— ment of the experimenter. The pairs of countries selected were (1) Singapore and Fiji, (2) Congo and Guyana, and (3) Portugal and Brazil. Information about the six countries was obtained from the Encyclo— paedia Britannica (1974: "Brazil, History of”; Fu—kiau kia Bunseki—L.; "Guyana"; Ho; Honeybone; Perez de Amaral). Information was selected based on its judged interest and relevance to a consistent theme of similarity or difference between the pairs. The information was used in composing three messages. The first message developed the theme that "Fiji and Singapore are remarkably similar"; the second message argued that "Congo and Guyana are very different”; and the third message pro— posed that "Portugal and Brazil are closely related.” The messages are included with the questionnaire in Appendix A. The messages are of similar length. The Fiji—Singapore message is 204 words long, the Congo—Guyana message is 204 words and the Portugal— Brazil message is 178 words. The structure of the first and third mes- sages differs somewhat from that of the second. In the former cases the countries are compared point by point; whereas in the latter case the countries are discussed in separate but parallel parts of the message. This structural difference was intended to reinforce the content em— phases of the messages by associating the similar countries and dis— sociating the dissimilar countries. Measurement of Variables The measurement of variables in this study was throughout based on the principle of direct, ratio estimation advocated by Woelfel (see 60 Woelfel, 1974; Danes and Woelfel, 1975). In brief, the rationale for this method holds that the measurement of any cognitive variable can be thought of as the measurement of conceptual separations, or distances between entities. Given this assumption the problem of measurement be- comes just a practical one of establishing a unit of measurement in terms of which all values of the variable may be expressed as ratios. Danes and Woelfel (1975) reason: Let's suppose for a moment that no standardized metric existed for the measurement of distance, a problem that our ancestors were faced with years ago. Then could the distance between A and B be measured? Yes. But a metric and a rule for doing so must initially be created before measurement could proceed. That is, some arbitrary distance, say the distance between x and y, must first be generated, and the distance between A and B could then be given in relation to that arbitrary distance . . With respect to the measurement of conceptual separations, the identical logic could be used, and measurement of the conceptual domain could then be given by a two-staged procedure: the speci- fication of a metric and a request to use ratios of that metric for the measurement of the separations among other conceptions. As an example, the following kind of question could be asked: If NIXON and AGNEW are one hundred (100) units apart, then in relation to NIXON and AGNEW how far apart are NIXON and McGOVERN? From the experience of the authors, most persons would report a number considerably larger than one hundred. (p. 3) The technique proposed by Danes and Woelfel is not entirely new. The technique was recommended by Torgerson (1958), who suggested: "The subject might be told to assume that on some scale the distance (amount of difference) between stimuli A and B is ten units. His task would then be to report the distance (amount of difference) between stimuli A and C on the same scale" (p. 293). Torgerson also warned, however, " . . . the task may ordinarily be too difficult for the subject, since it involves judgments of a fairly high level of complexity" (p. 293). The difficulty of the task would be expected to produce unreliability of measurement. Anyone who proposes to use the technique, then, must confront and deal with the problem of unreliability. 61 Woelfel (1974, p. 12) accepts that unreliability seriously limits the technique's utility for measuring individual subjects (though he suggests, without much basis, that the diffusion of the technique through the scientific community and the general culture would improve precision in the task because of practice and familiarity).* Woelfel argues, how— ever, that the reliability problem disappears when attention is focused upon measurement of aggregate variables rather than individual variables. In the aggregate case one can use large samples of people, taking advan— tage of the statistical principle that the sample mean converges toward the true population mean as sample size increases. Thus the problem of unreliability becomes essentially one of cost. Given unlimited resources and a large population from which to sample, the reliability of aggre- gate measurement (the sample mean) can be made as high as one might wish. Two papers have systematically investigated the reliability of Woelfel's technique of aggregate measurement. Barnett (1972) reports two studies which tested the reliability of a metric multidimensional scale for which direct ratio judgments were used to obtain the distance matrices. In the first study he tested re- liability by correlating time 1 with time 2 projections of 17 concepts on the first three dimensions of the space. Before calculation of the correlations, the time 2 coordinate matrix was rotated to least squares best fit with the time 1 matrix. The analysis was performed separately upon random subsamples of sizes 25, 50, 75 and 100 subjects. Findings *Woelfel (personal communication) has proposed the additional argument that the apparent unreliability of the technique in many situations may result not from the faultiness of the technique but from the true instability of the phenomena supposedly measured. This argument, how- ever, only redefines the problem as one of invalidity-—trying to measure something that doesn't actually exist. 62 were that the larger the sample the greater the reliability, that the first dimension was more reliable than the second and the second more reliable than the third, and that reliability ranged from a low of .23 for the third dimension and 25 cases to a high of .80 for the first dimension and 100 cases. In a second study Barnett examined 15 concepts at three points in time (four weeks and then three weeks apart) for sub— samples of 25, 50 and 61 subjects. Here again the reliability increased "size" of the dimension, but the corre- with both size of the sample and lations in this case were somewhat higher, ranging from .13 to .86 with 25 cases, from .44 to .97 with 50 cases and from .45 to .95 with 67 cases. Barnett attributes the greater reliability of the second scale to several factors, including greater homogeneity of the subject popula- tion, better data preparation, shorter time interval between administra— tions, fewer concepts and a more homogeneous conceptual domain. Barnett conducted a third analysis with random data and found correlations of .21, .01 and .38 for the first three dimensions. These numbers suggest the order of magnitude at or below which one should question whether the data reflect real phenomena. Danes and Woelfel (1975) obtained judgments of separation among 17 concepts from 50 respondents at two administrations with an interval of five weeks between measurements. The researchers evaluated reliability by three methods. First the test—retest correlation computed over the 136 cells of the inter-concept distance matrix was .86, indicating good reliability of the aggregate separations. Second the technique of cor— relating test-retest coordinates in the multidimensional space generated by a metric MDS procedure with rotation of the second space to least 63 squares best fit with the first space——the technique used previously by Barnett-—yielded correlations of .97, .81 and .87 for the first three coordinates. Thus this study found slightly better reliability than did Barnett's. Third the absolute amount of reliable variance was computed by multiplying the total variance for all items on each coordinate by the reliability of that coordinate. This was compared by several procedures to the reliable variance of a set of seven—step Likert-type items that correlated highly with the first (evaluative) dimension of the multidi— mensional scale. The procedures involved transformation of the Likert items to make them comparable in range to the MDS coordinates. All com— parisons were said to indicate that the multidimensional scale had greater reliable variance than the set of Likert—type items. In sum, research on the reliability of aggregate, direct, ratio judgments of separation indicates that adequate reliability 2gp be achieved with a relatively homogeneous sample of about 50 people and a relatively homogeneous set of 17 or less concepts. Although it must still be regarded as experimental, the technique is not without basis. Three sorts of variables were measured in the present study: con- cept inertial masses, inter—concept distances and message contents. The questionnaire referred to in the following text is included as Appendix A. The inertial mass of a concept is defined by Woelfel as the con— cept's resistance to acceleration, which is theoretically a function of the total information about the concept accumulated by a subject or aggre— gate. A set of items was devised based on this conceptualization and the technique of direct, ratio estimation. The subject was asked to estimate "how much information you have——how much you know—~about each 64 of fifteen countries. Consider all that you know about each country, from whatever source." The unit for the scale was established by anchor— ing zero as "the complete absence of knowledge" and 100 as ”an average amount of information.” Thus the mass of each nation was estimated as a ratio of an ”average” amount of information. Inter—concept distance is conceptualized in the spacial model as psychological distance or total attributional difference. Accordingly, the inter—concept distances were measured by direct, ratio estimation of "how different (or in other words 'far apart') you perceive the countries to be." The unit was established by stipulating that "Italy and England are 100 units apart.” The value of zero was said to mean that the pair of countries was "exactly the same." Each subject estimated all 105 inter-concept distances in this fashion. The items were listed system- atically in order of concept numbers (1—2, 1—3, . . . , 2—3, 2—4, . . .). The items were grouped in clusters of eight on the page in order to en— hance readibility. Message content is conceptualized in the spacial model as an as— sertion about the distance between a pair of concepts. Its theoretical function necessitates that message content be measured on the same scale as the inter—concept distances. Thus the subjects were asked to estimate, for each message and the corresponding pair of nations, "how different the two countries are according to the message." The unit of measurement was again established by stipulating that "Italy and England are 100 units apart." The instructions for the items were placed on a separate page preceding the messages. Each message was placed on a separate page, with the items measuring message content at the bottom of the page. 65 Loading of the Theory The theory of linear motion requires that the following quantities be estimated: 5,, S',. f, f', s,, n, and for all conce ts i 13’ 13’ 1k’ 1k’ 1], 1 p p -—’ pairs of concepts i,‘j and spacial coordinates_k. sij and S'ij’ the pretest and posttest inter—concept distances, were taken from the means (across subjects) of the direct, ratio judgments of inter-concept separations. fik and f' the pretest and posttest ik’ spacial coordinates, were obtained by metric multidimensional scaling analysis of the mean distance matrices S and S', with rotation of the posttest coordinate space to congruence with the pretest space. This procedure is described below (see "Program Galileo"). The Eij, the inter— concept distances as proposed by messages, were assumed equal to the corresponding sij’ except for the three distances intended to be mani— pulated by the messages. These three Eij were taken from the three items for measuring message content. The grand means of the pretest and post— test sample means were used as the most stable estimates available. The ni were estimated by the grand means of the pretest and posttest sample means of the inertial mass items discussed above. Finally, p was assumed equal to unity for each of the six concepts directly affected by the three messages and zero for all other concepts. Hypothesis The hypothesis tested in this study was that the observed, post— test, mean inter-concept distances and the observed, posttest spacial coordinates would correlate highly with those predicted by theory. The preceding sections describe the design and procedures upon which a test of the hypothesis was based. The following sections describe the data analysis procedures by which the hypothesis was tested. 66 Data Analysis Preparation of Data Data were keypunched by the author directly from the (pre—coded) questionnaires. The data deck was cleaned by visual inspection of a list and by tabulation and inspection of variables having restricted "legal" values. After those procedures ten cards were selected randomly, in- spected and found to be error—free. Program GALILEO GALILEO is a package of computer programs, developed by Woelfel and his associates, which accepts as input sets of inter—concept distance estimates, computes descriptive statistics, performs a metric multidi— mensional scaling analysis on aggregate inter—concept distance matrices, performs rotations to make spaces from different samples or different time periods comparable, and outputs printed statistics, printed and punched distance and coordinate matrices, and two—and three—dimensional, static and dynamic plots. The inner workings of the GALILEO package have been described in detail by Serota (1974, pp. 52-8L-87-99). GALILEO was used in the present study in two stages. In the first stage the raw inter—concept distance data were subjected to the "Dis— tance Means Matrices" option, which computes descriptive statistics and outputs printed and punched aggregate inter-concept distance matrices. The program allows the user to specify a "maximum value” for the inter- concept distances. Values larger than the maximum are ignored in com— puting the aggregate matrices. One disadvantage of unbounded scale items is that subjects who use relatively large numbers have disproportionate influence on the 67 aggregate results. With vary large samples this problem is negligible, but with smaller samples it can lead to serious distortions when, for example, one subject uses extraordinarily large numbers. Gillham (1972, pp. 40-42) encountered this problem and solved it by discarding the data of the deviant subject. The ”maximum value" feature has been incorporated into GALILEO to facilitate the solution of similar problems. The raw distance data were run with the Distance Means Matrices option twice: once with no maximum value and once with a maximum of 1000. Punched mean distance matrices were obtained from both runs. Only the means matrices with a maximum value of 1000 were used in subsequent runs. This involved deletion of 10 data points from the calculation of the posttest means matrix. Eight of these were from one subject and two were from a second subject. The effects of these values on the corres- ponding mean distances are given in Table 3. It is evident that these values would have had a greatly disproportionate influence on the results of the study. The second stage use of GALILEO involved processing of the mean distance matrices (maximum value of 1000) by means of the ”Comparison of Spaces" option. This option performed multidimensional scaling analyses on both pretest and posttest mean distance matrices, rotated the posttest coordinate system to congruence with the pretest coordinate system, out— put printed and punched, rotated and unrotated coordinate matrices, and prepared dynamic plots of the pretest and posttest data in a common co— ordinate system of both two and three dimensions. The Comparison of Spaces option of GALILEO allows the user to in- corporate assumptions about which of a set of concepts have remained 68 Table 3. Effect of Deletion of Extreme Values on the Posttest Mean Inter—Concept Distances. Extreme Subject Mean Including Mean ExCluding Concept Pair Value ID Extreme Value Extreme Value Mexico-USSR 2184 08 211.406 180.095 Poland-Guyana 1084 08 178.203 163.825 China-Guyana 7000 62 277.141 170.429 Singapore-Mexico 7000 62 231.078 123.635 Singapore—Brazil 9000 62 288.812 150.540 Mexico—Fiji 5000 62 227.000 151.238 Mexico-W. Germany 4000 62 209.125 148.952 Mexico-Brazil 2000 62 117.891 88.016 Mexico-C.A.R. 4000 62 207.078 146.873 Brazil—Greece 9000 62 270.687 132.127 stable over time. The default assumption is that all concepts are stable. Thus the posttest coordinates are rotated to least squares best fit with the pretest coordinates. The main advantage of this procedure is that it is based on the simplest possible assumptions. The main disadvantage of the procedure is that it tends to distort and obscure "real" motion of concepts by minimizing that motion and distributing it among all of the concepts scaled. Alternatively time user may specify a set of concepts which may be assumed to be stable. The rotation then proceeds in such a way as to minimize the change of those concepts while allowing the others to change. This procedure is described in detail by Woelfel,_gg .gl. (1975). Briefly, the procedure involves translation of the coordinate 69 systems to the centroid of the specified stable concepts and rotation to the criterion of least squares best fit of those concepts with themselves. The main advantage of the stable concepts option is that it can yield more accurate description of motion by taking advantage of information about stable concepts. The main disadvantage is that it can distort and obscure real motion if the assumptions about stable concepts happen to be false. It also leaves the researcher open to the charge of question-begging. The Comparison of Spaces option was run twice: once specifying no stable concepts (the default option), and once specifying the nine unmani- pulated nations (those not mentioned in messages) as stable. The later procedure took advantage of what was known about the experimental pro— cedures and their intended effects; while the former procedure allowed for the possibility that the experimental procedures might have had un- intended effects. All further analyses were conducted in parallel fashion on the output of both options. Thus the researcher hedged his bets. Program TESTLAW TESTLAW is a FORTRAN IV program written by the author to perform calculations necessary to the analysis of this experiment. The program is included as Appendix B. The general functions of the program are to accept as data the output from GALILEO, to compute theoretical predic- tions, and to output predicted and observed inter-concept distances and concept coordinates. The output may then be subjected to further sta- tistical analysis. Although TESTLAW was written especially for the present study, it is sufficiently general to be applicable to a range of studies testing the same or a highly similar hypothesis. By some further effort the program could have been made still more general (certainly more elegant!), but those are matters for the future. 70 The punched output from GALILEO-—mean distance matrices and rotated coordinate matrices-—may be input into TESTLAW. Additional required in- puts include a run name, a set of parameters (number of concepts, number of dimensions, number of real dimensions—time one, number of real dimen— sions-time two), message content values and concept masses. The punched output from TESTLAW consists of three decks. The first is a deck of Coordinate Values. This deck comprises one "case'' for each coordinate value—jg x m cases, where p = the number of concepts and m = the number of dimensions. Each case includes, in addition to the concept and dimension identification numbers, four variables: the pretest co— ordinate (fik)’ the posttest coordinate (f'i ), the coordinate predicted k by theory including inertial mass in the computation (fmi and the co— k), ordinate predicted by theory excluding inertial mass from the computation A A (fik). fmik is computed from the theoretical equations given in Chapter I (expressions 6 and 7); while fi is computed from the same equations k only excluding hi, the concept mass, from the computation. The predic- tions are computed both ways in order to permit a check of the usefulness of the variable mass. The second output deck from TESTLAW is a deck of Pairwise Distances. This deck comprises one case for each inter-concept distance—5p x 3 cases. Each case consists of l.+ 1 cards, where l = (m/3) + 2, m is the number of dimensions and m/3 is rounded down to the lower whole number. The di- mensions included are the first three and every third thereafter (1, 2, 3, 6, 9, . . .). Each card begins with the two concept numbers, and each of the first 1 cards follows those by a dimension number. The_l + 1th card indicated 99 for the dimension number. Each of the first 1 cards 71 includes four variables. The four variables on the kth card (5.5.1) have been computed based upon the first g coordinates. The variables are pre— test distance (sij posttest distance (S'ijk)’ distance predicted by k), theory including inertial mass in the computation (§mij ), and distance k ). predicted by theory excluding inertial mass from the computation (gijk Again, §mij is computed from the theoretical equations given in Chapter I (expressions 6, 7 and 8); while gij is computed from the same equations only excluding ni from the computation. The purpose of computing_l ver— sions of the four variables is to allow the user to check whether, for example, predictions based on the first few dimensions are superior to predictions based on more dimensions which presumably include more ran— dom error. The 1_+ 1th card includes, in addition to the two concept numbers and the number 99, three variables. These are the two concept inertial masses (ni, nj) and the actually observed mean posttest dis— tance (S'i')' This last variable will differ from (s'ijm)’ the posttest distance as computed from all m coordinates, because of distortions intro- duced when GALILEO rotates the imaginary dimensions of the posttest co— ordinate system. See Danes (1975, pp. 34-37) for a discussion of this problem. The third output deck from TESTLAW is a deck of concept variables. This deck comprises one case for each concept—jg cases. Each case in— cludes the following: the concept number, m values for ”the change in concept 3F (Aik), each computed on the basis of the first g dimensions (5 = 1, m), the pretest distance ofyi from each manipulated concept, the change in distance of_i from each manipulated concept, the pretest dis— tance of ;_from each unmanipulated concept, the change in distance of i 72 from each unmanipulated concept, the total of the pretest distances 0f.£ from all manipulated concepts, the total of the changes in distance of_i from all manipulated concepts, the total of the pretest distances of.l from all unmanipulated concepts, the total of the changes in distance of g from all unmanipulated concepts, and the mass of i. All of the changes in distance referred to above are absolute changes. In the present study TESTLAW was run once with each of two sets of GALILEO outputs: the set deriving from the stable concepts rotation pro— cedure and the set deriving from the no stable concepts rotation procedure. Statistical Analyses All statistical analyses were performed using Statistical Package for the Social Sciences (SPSS) programs (Nie, pg ‘gl., 1975). "Statis— tical significance" of a result is taken to mean a probability of .05 or less, as determined by the SPSS program. AssessmentcfifMeasurement and Procedures Several analyses were conducted to assess the measurement and pro— cedures of the study. These include tests of reliability and validity, and procedural and manipulation checks. Reliability of measurement was assessed in three, distinct ways. The first involved analysis of the raw data——the data of the 64 subjects. Test-retest Pearson correlations were computed across subjects for each variable——the 105 inter—concept distances, the 15 concept masses and the three message content estimates. The second way of assessing reliability involved analysis of ag— gregate data. Here the reliability of the aggregate inter—concept dis— tances was assessed by correlating pretest with posttest means across the 105 distances. This correlation was computed in 60 different ways. First, three different versions of s'ij could be used: that derived from the no stable concepts rotation procedure, that derived from the stable concepts rotation procedure, and that derived from the raw data. Second, the correlation could be computed for four important subsets of the 105 inter—concept distances: the whole set of 105, the 36 unmanipulated dis— tances, the 69 manipulated distances and the 66 indirectly manipulated distances. Finally, for each of the two rotation procedures, s'l could be based on 1, 2, 3, 6, 9, 12, or 15 coordinates (these are the_l = 7 values of s'ij computed by TESTLAW for these data). Thus there were k ((2 x 7) + l) x 4 = 60 possible ways of computing the reliability of the aggregate inter-concept distances. All of these were computed. The third way of assessing reliability was to use the methods of such studies as Gillham (1972), Barnett (1974) and Danes and Woelfel (1975). This involved correlating the pretest coordinates with the post— test coordinates for each dimension of the multidimensional scale to determine the stability of each dimension. This method assesses the reliability of the structure of the multidimensional space, rather than the reliability of the individual or aggregate inter—concept distances. All three methods of assessing reliability, of course, confounded unreliability and real change, although these could be sorted out some— what at the individual level by comparing the reliabilities of manipu— lated distances to those of unmanipulated distances. Measurement validity was assessed by two kinds of procedures. The first involved inspection of the data and judgment of face validity based on such questions as whether very "close” and "distant" countries are 74 those that one would expect, and whether more prominent countries have larger measured masses than less prominent countries. A second kind of procedure involved comparison of the reliabilities of manipulated versus unmanipulated variables. For the reliabilities of manipulated variables to be lower than those of unmanipulated variables would be consistent with the assumption of greater real change of the manipulated variables. Taken together, these procedures could yield some, albeit imperfect indications of the validity of measurement. The procedural assessment of the study included three checks. The first check was to determine whether the pairs of nations selected for in- clusion in messages met the stated criteria of low to moderate inertial mass and moderate distance. This was determined by comparing the masses and distances to the means of those variables. The second check was whether the messages, as measured by the message content estimates, actually advocated changes in distance as intended by the experimenter. The third check was whether the experimental manipulation worked. One would expect to find that t-tests for correlated means performed on the pretest-posttest changes would be significant for the three directly manipulated distances, and for many of the 66 indirectly manipulated dis- tances as well; while the 36 unmanipulated distances should not have changed significantly. Hypothesis Tests The general hypothesis test was a comparison of predicted with ob- served posttest inter-concept distances and concept coordinates. Such a test, however, may be conducted in many different ways, each of which contributes information from a unique point of view. Three general types of tests were employed in this study. 75 The first type of test involved inspection of changes in the inter- concept mean distances, and of the plotted results of the multidimensional scaling analysis, to determine whether the pattern of changes from pre- test to posttest was consistent with the hypothesis. This type of analy- sis, admittedly, can produce no clear decision as to the merits of the hypothesis. It can, however, at once make an overall impression and yield up a wealth of details that might help in interpreting findings derived from more structured procedures. The second type of test was a correlation of predicted with observed posttest inter-concept distances. This correlation can be and was com- puted on 384 distinct bases. First, two different rotation procedures were used to make the posttest space comparable to the pretest space (see above "Program GALILEO"). Each procedure (because it involved rotation of some imaginary coordinates) yielded a unique set of "observed" post— test distances as computed from spacial coordinates. The actually ob- served mean posttest distances were, of course, still a third set. Thus at least three correlations might be computed, one for each set of post- test distances. Second, there is some reason to believe that the theo— retical predictions may be more accurate when restricted to the first few dimensions of the space, since the higher (smaller) dimensions may con— tain a larger proportion of error and the imaginary dimensions may repre- sent some sort of cognitive inconsistency. Program TESTLAW gives, in the present case, computations based on seven cumulative Subsets of the dimensions: 1, 1-2, 1-3, 1-6, 1—9, 1—12, 1—15. Thus for each of the three sets of posttest distances, seven correlations may be computed, or 21 correlations in total. Third, TESTLAW gives two sets of predicted 76 post—message inter-concept distances, one set computed from the exact equations presented in Chapter I, and a second set computed from those same equations only excluding inertial mass from the computations. The purpose of computing both sets of predictions was to see whether the in- clusion of masses affects the accuracy of prediction. Thus 42 correla- tions could be computed. Fourth, these 42 correlations could each be computed for four interesting subsets of the inter-concept distances. These include, in addition to the whole set of 105 distances, the 36 un— manipulated distances, the 69 manipulated distances and the 66 indirectly manipulated distances. Thus 168 correlations could be computed. Fifth, the theory predicts that the inter-concept distances will not change except insofar as they are directly or indirectly affected by the input of information. It is of great importance to separate those two compo- nents-—the stability component and the change component-—to determine whether the theory successfully predicts both. If the theoretical pre- dictions are accurate only in predicting stability then the theory is useless as a description of cognitive change. Thus the stability compo— nent should be removed from the analysis. This can be done by statis- tically controlling the pretest distances, which in turn can be done either by computing partial correlations or by correlating predicted with observed changes in distance. Thus 504 correlations in total might be computed: the 168 correlations discussed above and their counterpart first order partials and change score correlations. Some of these cor— relations, however, would not be meaningful. The partials and change score correlations need not be computed for the 36 unmanipulated dis- tances because no change is predicted for those distances. That 77 eliminates 84 potential correlations. Nor would it be meaningful to compute change scores consisting of the difference between pretest dis- tances computed on the basis of less than all of the dimensions and the actually observed posttest distances, which include, as it were, all of the dimensions. The change scores so derived would simply not represent any theoretically meaningful quantity. Thus 36 more potential correla— tions are ruled out. Actually, then, 384 distinct versions of the cor- relation of predicted with observed posttest inter-concept distances were computed. These 384 correlations did not at all constitute an equal number of independent tests of the theory. Quite to the contrary, the correlations are highly interdependent. Each, however, provides a unique point of view of the data. A similar comment could be made regarding the third set of hypothe— sis tests which were performed. These involved correlating predicted with observed posttest coordinate values. Here again a large number of possible variations of the test were all computed. Again the two rota— "Observed" posttest coordinates. tion procedures yielded distinct sets of There were, however, no "actually observed" coordinates aside from those given by the rotation procedures. Nor were there any "indirectly" mani— pulated coordinates—~one could distinguish only between the coordinates of the manipulated concepts and those of the unmanipulated concepts. Nor was it meaningful to compute correlations based on less than two dimen— sions when they would have as few as five degrees of freedom. Thus, in short, the coordinate values yielded a much smaller set of correlations than did the inter-concept distances. In fact 180 correlations were com- puted. 76 of those were zero order correlations between predicted and observed coordinates based on two rotation procedures, two predictors, 78 seven subsets of the dimensions, three subsets of the concepts (all concepts, the manipulated concepts and the unmanipulated concepts), and excluding eight correlations that would have had too few degrees of freedom. 52 first order partials controlling the pretest coordinates were computed. These corresponded to the zero order correlations except for the 24 based on the unmanipulated concepts. Partials in those cases would not have been meaningful. Finally, 52 correlations of predicted with observed changes in coordinates were computed. These corresponded to the partials. CHAPTER IV RESULTS This chapter presents the results of the study under the general headings of Multidimensional Scaling Analysis, Assessment of Measurement and Procedures and Tests of Hypothesis. Multidimensional Scaling Analysis The results of the metric MDS analysis are given in Tables 19 through 24 (Appendix C) and in Figures 1 through 6. Table 19 is the coordinate matrix for the pretest data. Table 20 is the unrotated coordinate matrix for the posttest data. Fifteen roots were extracted from each distance matrix. This result would be theoretically impossible since p points can always be represented in pfl or fewer dimensions. In each case, however, one dimension accounted for approximately none of the variance in the distance matrix. These coor- dinates, as Serota points out (1974, p. 64), " . . . are artificial and represent rounding error in the computer algorithm . .” Three of the 14 valid roots extracted from the pretest matrix were negative, while two of the 14 valid posttest roots were negative. The negative roots accounted for about 6.7 percent of the total pretest inter—concept distances (the total of their eigenvalues was —ll,553 as compared to a trace of 161,713 for the matrix). The negative roots ac— counted for about 2.7 percent of the total posttest inter-concept dis- tances (the total of their eigenvalues was —4397 as compared to a trace of 161,192 for the matrix). Similar shrinkage of the imaginary dimen— sions has been noted in previous studies (e.g., Taylor, Barnett and Serota, 1975). 79 80 Table 21 gives the posttest coordinates matrix rotated (so as to be comparable to the pretest space) by the no stable concepts rotation pro— cedure. Tables 22 and 23 give the unrotated pretest and posttest coordi- nate matrices translated to the centroid of the nine stable (unmanipu— lated) concepts. Table 24, finally, gives the results of the stable con— cepts rotation performed on the translated posttest matrix to make it comparable to the pretest space. An examination of the coordinate matrices indicates that the two rotation procedures give somewhat different results. The data in Table 4 make the effect of the rotation procedures much clearer still. Table 4 gives the amount of change of each concept from pretest to posttest coordinate spaces as determined from the two rotation procedures. The mean changes for the no stable concepts rotation were 65.29 for the un— manipulated concepts and 53.30 for the manipulated concepts, while the mean changes for the stable concepts rotation were 29.99 for the unmani- pulated concepts and 110.37 for the manipulated concepts. Thus the ratio of the mean changes of manipulated to unmanipulated concepts was about .8 for the no stable concepts rotation (the "stable" concepts changed more!), but the ratio was about 3.7 for the stable concepts rotation. Plots of the MDS results are given in Figures 1 through 6. In all figures the pretest and posttest locations are plotted together, connected by lines. The pretest locations are indicated by the concept identifica- tion numbers. Figures 1 through 3 are of the results of the no stable concepts rotation procedure, and Figures 4 through 6 are of the results of the stable concepts rotation procedure. Figures 1 and 4 show the first two dimensions: X (the abscissa) is the first dimension and Y (the 81 Table 4. Effect of Rotation Procedure Upon Distances Moved by Concepts Between Pretest and Posttest. Distance Moved Concept No Stable Concepts Stable Concepts 1. China 86.421 31.025 2. Singapore# 46.534 96.377 3. Mexico 57.143 25.329 4. U.S.A. 69.008 40.956 5. Portugal# 45.951 110.364 6. Poland 68.218 27.125 7. India 38.269 17.480 8. Fiji# 82.820 119.441 9. W. Germany 65.002 46.909 10. Brazil# 40.340 113.628 11. C.A.R. 43.710 17.582 12. Greece 89.591 23.494 13. U.S.S.R. 70.270 39.977 14. Congo# 49.104 103.903 15. Guyana# 55.050 118.527 #Manipulated Concept. 82 ordinate) is the second dimension. Figures 2 and 5 show the first and third dimensions: X (the abscissa) is the first dimension and Z (the ordinate) is the third dimension. Figures 3 and 6 are three dimensional plots: X, the first dimension, runs from left "front" to right "rear”; Y, the second dimension, is vertical; and Z, the third dimension, runs from right "front" to left "rear." Regardless of rotation or point in time, the X and Y dimensions are readily interpretable as Economic Development and Political Ide— ology, respectively. The first dimension runs from U.S.A. and West Germany at the high end through moderately developed European and Latin American countries to the least developed African and Asian countries to the low end. The second dimension runs from China and U.S.S.R. at one end through various Asian and European countries to the American nations at the low end-—a general, although not entirely consistent trend from most radical to most conservative countries. These two di— mensions are similar to the first two dimensions found in the nonmetric MDS analysis of nations by Wish, Deutsch and Biener (1972). The third dimension is not so readily interpretable (nor was it in the Wish, g£_gl. study). Regional clustering, however, is evident on the X—Z plane (Figures 2 and 5), with each quadrant corresponding roughly to a continental zone. The single important exception--the location of Guyana in the ”African” quadrant—~is discussed below. Figure 1. No 83 l Stable Concepts Rotation, X—Y Plane Figure 2. No 84 9.10 ‘9 5 15 f :2“ 0’ 0c. 13 1411 6"- Stable Concepts Rotation, X-Z Plane 85 [q \n \ 0.8 / 14 \Alo/ \4 B... ’ 15 '3 N‘S‘FCLC "N Figure 3. No Stable Concepts Rotation, First Three Dimensions 14 86 1K. ‘./).13 60'. 2 7 f! 9 a 5 12 I 511 .310 \4 Figure 4. Stable Concepts Rotation, X—Y Plane 14 87 Ifi 3 1. 1 7 F 1iFl: 1,9 1', I f} \. Figure 5. Stable Concepts Rotation, X-Z Plane 88 147:”. . ._,.v {-I MN" Jung.” Figure 6. Stable Concepts Rotation, First Three Dimensions 89 Assessment of Measurement and Procedures Reliability Reliability was assessed in three ways, the first being test— retest comparisons of the raw (unaggregated) data. Tables 5, 6 and 7 contain the information relevant to this assessment. Table 5 gives, for the 105 inter-concept distances, the pretest and posttest means and standard deviations, the means of the pretest—to—posttest changes, the standard deviations of those changes, Pearson correlations of pretest with posttest scores, and t-tests for correlated means. Table 6 gives the same information for the 15 concept inertial mass estimates and Table 7 gives the same information for the three message content estimates. The reliabilities of the inter—concept distances, as indicated by the Pearson correlations, were quite poor. Of the 105 correlations only 32 were statistically significant and only 7 were greater than .5. No correlation was negative. The concept mass reliabilities were higher but by no means absolutely high. Fourteen of the 15 correla- tions were significant; 11 were over .5; the highest was .64. The three message content estimates were quite unreliable. Only two of the three correlations were significant and none was as great as .4. The second way of assessing reliability is by pretest—posttest comparison of the aggregate inter—concept distances——a correlation computed over the sample means. As was noted in Chapter III, we are interested in 60 different versions of this correlation. The results are given in Table 8. sN.I oNs.«g« Aoe.emav Ams.aeav Aww.esav sa.o- ae.owa ma.ewa eHaNmHmImaaao om.- sme.««r AqN.N~aV Aoo.Nmav Aos.mmav we.mu wm.wsa ow.mwa smashes .sumeaeo AN.H ONN.F AHG.HAHV Aew.ssav Ass.owv om.sN mm.ema ma.w~a eamamIaeaao as.a smm.««« nem.maav Aam.mmav Awe.msv mm.mm mm.sma ON.NHH maeaHImeaeo em. awe.«F« Awo.soav Ama.moav Asa.aoav ae.s mo.ama sm.osa ecmaomlmeaeo we. smm.«% Aaa.osav Asa.sqav Ase.mwv ma.aa sm.eea wN.sma eamwsuuomlmeaau HG.HI Nmm.*«« Aos.ssav Ams.wmav Ass.aowv % mm.mm- om.saa as.mmw .<.m.plmaaao as. sea. Aem.maav Amm.meav Asm.amav am.wa mm.NwH Na.mea coaxmzumaaeo mm.m««« st.«1 flee.aav Aok.qu Aam.~sv ss.os ma.aaa mm.as amuoaawaHmImeaeo I. I, A.m.mv use: A.o.mv A.m.mv u H as ha ha ha meoaumz mo name A mI .mv new: .m cam: m .mcmoz pmumeHuou How mummuLW can mmwocmumflm umwuumom nuHB umwuwum mo maOflumHmuuou comumwm ”museumflo ma mowamso uwwuumom Inmpuwsm pom wwoamumfln amouumom .mmuamumam umououm mo mOOHOMH>Om vumvamum new memo: .m wanna 91 me.u amo. Asa.smav Aeo.woav Ase.mmv mm.eu me.mm No.Noa ashamuemuoamwaam NN.H mms.««¥ Ama.omav Amq.asv Ase.msv me.aa sm.a~a aw.saa «HecHIemuoamwaam ma. mma. Ame.seav Ams.amav Asm.awv wa.ma sa.osa wa.ema eamaomuemuoamweam mm. sow. Ace.mmav ANN.ANHV Amm.msv om.e ma.oqa ae.ama eammsuuomIemuoamwaam as.- was. Aom.aeav Aaa.amv Aas.amav ma.man sm.mma ms.ssa .<.m.enemuoamweHm om.a- wwo. Aes.aqav Awe.sev Ams.omav e~.mm- me.mma sw.esa ooaxmzlemuoamMEam 04.- oam.« AHN.NwHV Amo.esav Amm.meav am.s- ew.sea sa.msa sowaooumaaao aw.a Nss.«ww Aww.asv Awe.soav Aoa.moav sa.ea mm.e~a em.aoa .m.m.m.:ImcHao ow.- me.F« Asa.seav Awm.ksav Asm.smav oh.eau o~.sea as.awa mommeeumaanu AN. anm.« Amm.wsav Awm.osav Ase.asav sa.m OA.NAH ms.eea .m.<.oumaaeu u p A.mhmvnwmmz A.Q.ww A.Q.ww wcowumz mo Hfimm Aoomlco-mv ammz o. .m cm0250m Aemsaauaouv .m magma i. 92 Na. oea. Aoa.©mav Amm.saav Aaa.emav am.~ sa.aaa ms.woa eamwsunomuooaxmz es.a mom.w«« Awo.qu Asm.mwv Aao.mmv om.ma ms.moa we.ma .a.m.pIooaxmz so. ems. Asm.seav Aoa.qsav Aem.eoav mm.ma s¢.~ma sa.mma emamssuuemuoamweam we. ska. Ams.mwav Ams.aeav Amw.saav sm.sa mo.aea o~.ama somaooIamuoammaam se.- amm.«« Amm.ssav AmH.NaV Aao.mmav ae.wu Ne.mma aa.wea .m.m.m.snemuoamwaam ms. moN. Amm.msav Amm.amav Aes.amv om.ma mo.aoa mm.ssa mommueIemuoamwcam mm. sem.a Amm.seav Awm.maav Aom.maav oo.~a mm.mea mm.mma .m.<.ouemuoamweam as.- ago. Ama.mwav Amw.mmav Asa.emav mm.a- sm.oma Na.ama eHHNmumIemuoammaam sm.I HAN. Asa.smav Ama.esav Amo.oaav mm.s- mo.oma mm.eoa samaumo .zuemuoammaam [I I o o Gmm o o o o u u A mamvna z A a NW A a MW meoaumz mo name A mI .mv :mmz .m new: m AvwsaHuGOOV m manna 93 HN. Nae. Ase.mwav Ame.NmHV AoN.mNNV ww.q Ns.osN sw.asa emnmsselooaxmz me. omo. Aaa.eaav Asm.amav Aom.mmav ao.ea wo.moa wa.wqa eowaou-oowa2 No.I amo. Amm.sONv Aoa.mmav Asw.mmav aw.a- oa.owa om.awa .e.m.m.sIooNxmz Nm. mmo. Amw.NNHv Aam.mNHv ANN.NNHV MN.NH ma.msa aw.Nma muwwueIouaxmz Ha. Nma. Amm.sNHV AeN.NNHV Ame.wmav os.N Nm.eqa wa.asa .m.<.oIOUNxmz NH.N« HON. Aos.mmv AeN.NsV ANN.msv «N.ea No.ww mN.HN eNNNaENIooNxmz 40.- HNo. Aoa.swav xNa.mNHv Aoa.smav Nm.I ma.msa NN.aqH Anagram .2Iooaxmz wN.I mos. Ams.amav Aoe.smav Aeo.esav ms.o- 4N.Hma NG.NmH eNmamlooaxmz ea. oqa. Asa.sNav Ame.amav Amm.mmav ma.N ma.wma qa.mma maeaHlooNxez mN.- «we. Aaa.wsav Aom.mmav AHN.NNHV NN.mI sw.mma oo.ama eawaomuooaxez I .I . . new . . . . A ml .mv sows .m one: m Avmsawudoov m OHQNH 94 Ns.I amm.«« Awa.maav Ams.NAHV ANN.oAHv Hm.oaI ee.eaa AN.GON someooI.<.m.s Aq.HI Aas.F«« Aam.mmav Ams.awv Asw.Nmav em.sNI aa.wma AG.N©H .m.m.m.eu.<.m.s As.I NAm.*« AAs.msaV Aom.AoaV ANN.mqav om.wI Aa.ama As.osa momwuoI.<.m.e os.I wwo. ANq.ONNv AAm.AoAV Amo.mmav GH.AHI ma.omH AA.NNH .m.<.OI.<.m.: ms.I ANA. AAe.ooAv ANm.oAv AwA.smv ms.eI wN.MNH mw.mNH eaaumumI.<.m.p so.I Nam.11 Awm.omav ANH.AAV AwN.mmHv am.- NA.ooa Hm.aoa Acmeumu .3-.<.m.: MA.I was. AmA.mONV Aoe.Nmav Ams.HAav sw.wa- Ns.moa AN.NwA eHmHmI.<.m.e as.I Amm.*« ANA.oeHV Amw.mNav Amm.smAV mA.NI Na.eAa sm.mwa «NeeHI.<.m.p «N.AI NAH. Aoa.qAAv AHm.ONHV Aqm.asav sw.eNI sa.mma WA.owa eemaomI.<.m.p ma.- mes. Amm.aoav AON.HsHv ANs.mOAV mm.NI Ns.AmH oo.oea eammsuuomI.<.m.: I. I. A.m.mv new: A.o.mv A.m.mv u u T.” 3 .3 ms mCOflumz mo Hfimm A m.. .mv new: .m game m Aew=ENueoov m magma 95 ma. wma. Aaa.MAav Awm.ssav Awo.wNav wa.m em.Nea mm.mma somaOOIaammsaaoa mo. NaN. Ams.eaav Asa.mav Awm.aaV ma.a se.mma Nm.sma .m.m.m.eIAammaaaom No.I Awa. Ame.aAv Ame.amv Amm.AeV mN.I ma.moa NA.moa mommaoIAammsuaoa ee.I oNa. AmA.amav AaA.eNav Aos.omav mN.maI om.Ama ww.Nma .m.<.OIAamwsaaoa ow.a- coo. Amm.amav AmN.asV Aem.ANav ae.mNI Aa.oA wA.moa eaammamneamweaaom am.I Nam. Aao.awv Asa.aev AGA.NAV Aa.mI wa.maa ee.sNa Aamaame .zueamwsaaom eo.I sea. Aaw.mmav ANo.mNaV AAw.aaav aa.aI mm.Asa mA.waa eaaaAIAamwaaaoa as. AoN. Aam.amav Amo.mNav Ase.NaV mA.A Aa.oma Ne.Nsa maeeaIeamwsaaoa Aa.a emm.aa Aam.wAV Aaw.eAv Aam.mmv wN.aa aa.NNa ma.moa ecmaomIAammsaaoa ma.a- oAa. Amw.saav Aso.osav Aos.aeav se.ANI NA.aea mm.awa Amemssz.a.m.p l | A.Q.mv one: A.m.mv A.a.mv a a ha ha ha ha meoaamz No Name A ml .3 Ewe: .m :wmz m Aemseauaoov m magma 96 so. Nam.a AmN.smav Aaa.ANav AmN.maV Ne.aa mm.mea aN.Nma Awemssu-eamaoa eo.- wsa. Amm.mAav Aes.NmaV Awa.omav sm.a- ea.oea om.aea eowcoo-ecmaoa mm.m« Hom.xx« Acm.amv Am©.mmv Amm.mmv oo.ma No.oa ma.sA .m.m.m.p-eemaoa ma. Aeo. Awm.Naav Asm.oav Ama.mAv oe.N mm.oNa Ae.Aaa Queens-enmaom ma. maa. ANA.wmav Ama.Nmav ANa.omav aa.a ee.wAa Nm.aAa .m.<.o-eemaoa Na. Amo. Ace.eAav Aom.mNaV Aoa.sNav oN.a ON.Ama oo.wqa eaaamam-esmaom ON.a aoN. Ass.mwv Amm.eev AON.on mw.Na sm.Aaa Nm.eoa sameamu .3-eemaoa mm. waa. Aoa.mmav ANo.Amav Ama.Nmav ow.Na om.oAa ao.mea eamam-eamaom om. aea. Ame.meav Aom.asav Aoa.moav mm.oa Ae.eAa ao.aea maeaa-eemaoa Na. mmo. Amw.aAav Aam.amav Aom.wwv ow.ma me.aea mw.aqa Amamsso-Aammsaaoa m. m. A.m.mv new: A.Q.mv A.Q.mv waOfiumz mo mem .a ha ha ha A ml .mv ammz .m smoz m Apmdaauaoov m OHQOH 97 0a.- N00. ANO.A0a0 A0a.sNav A00.mqa0 s0.aa- 00.nsa mA.0ma eaaNmam-eamaa 00.- 0Aa. AmA.swa0 Aam.sma0 AaA.Nma0 00.ma- 0a.00a 00.4Aa Asmaamo .3-aaaaa ma.a- Asm.aa Amw.0Na0 AAa.mA0 AAO.mma0 Aa.0a- AN.ANa ss.maa emcmssu-maeaa m0. 0mm.«« Ama.m00 A00.N00 Aes.N00 0m. Nm.mma m0.Nma sowaoo-maeaa 00.- smN.* A00.Nma0 AA0.A0a0 AaA.0ma0 04.aa- MN.ama NA.m0a .N.m.m.0-maeea mm. mmm.a*« A00.0A0 AON.NAO Amm.NA0 mm.m mA.0ma Na.mma mommao-maeaa ma. 0aa. Aom.Ama0 ANm.Naa0 Aos.MNa0 N0.N 00.0aa m0.msa .m.<.o-maeea 0a. 000. AAm.mAa0 Awa.ama0 Ae0.0Na0 AN.N m0.mma 00.0ma eaawmam-maeaa 0m. ANa. ANa.m0a0 Aes.mma0 A00.maa0 mm.aa am.00a 0A.Ama Aemaame .3-ma0ea NN.- m0a. AN0.N00 A00.000 Awm.0A0 0m.N- As.NNa 00.mNa eanaa-maeaa I. -. A.a.mv amwz A.o.mv A.o.mv u .a 3 .3 ma 3 maoauwz mo Hanna A mI .3 5mm: .. .m cmwz m Aemscaueoov m maame 98 ms.- 00a. AsA.a0a0 AaA.sma0 AmA.mma0 00.0a- ma.mAa aa.0ma eommoo-agmagme .3 00. mmN.m Amg.0Na0 ANN.Aaa0 A00.A00 0m.0a sw.ema mm.eNa .m.m.m.3-aemaame .3 0a.- a00. Ams.Ama0 ANO.N0a0 A00.00a0 AN.m- mm.ANa 00.0ma mmmmge-Ammagmm .3 m0.- «MN. A00.0Aa0 Amm.mma0 A00.0sa0 aa.aN- Nm.00a m0.A0a .m.<.O-aemsamw .3 mN.- 000. Asm.mAa0 A40.NNa0 ANA.0ma0 0m.m- 0N.0sa mm.msa Aaammag-agmagmm .3 N0.- m00. A00.a0a0 Ams.a00 AAO.Asa0 00.0a- AA.sNa ma.mqa Ammmame-Aaaaa A0.- mNN.m Asm.A0a0 A00.a0a0 Aam.mma0 mm.a- N0.mma a0.00a aomgoo-eaaaa m0.a- 00m.mm Ama.00a0 A0m.mma0 A00.00a0 AN.MN- N0.m0a 0N.00N .m.m.m.0-Aaaaa as. 0aN. AOA.mma0 ANa.0mav AA0.N0a0 s0.A AN.00a mm.0ma mmmmgu-Aaaaa am. 0m0. AmN.m0av AON.mma0 AmA.ema0 aa.A 0m.mma 0a.0sa .m.<.0-Aaaaa I. I. . . gmm . . . . A ml . 3 new: . m ammz m Ammmgaggomv m magma 99 00.Nm a00. A00.ama0 AsA.0aa0 A0A.smv mm.0m NA.Nma 0N.am Ammmam0-.m.m.0 ma.Nm Asa. AAm.0ma0 A0m.mma0 A00.aA0 mm.0a 00.0aa sm.0A eomm00-.m.<.0 0N. ama. AmN.00a0 Am0.Ama0 A00.Asa0 m0.m a0.mAa 00.0Aa .m.m.m.0-.m.<.0 30. 0Aa. Amm.AAa0 AA0.00a0 A0a.A00 mm.0a 03.0Aa a0.aaa mmmmg0-.m.m.0 0a.- mmo. A00.00a0 A0N.mma0 A00.mqa0 0A aa- 00.0ma 0A.Asa Amgmamm-Aaammgg 0N. 000. Aa0.a0a0 Ass.gqa0 ANA.0ma0 AN.0 0a.ama 00.40a Aomgoo-Aaammgg am.- N00. Aam.m0a0 AAN.0ma0 A00.mma0 NN.A- Nm.N0a mA.00a .m.m.m.g-Aaammag as.- NaN. AmN.Ama0 Aaa.NA0 Aa0.Nma0 aA A- Na.Nma 00.0ma mmmmgm-Aaammgg 0A. NN0. Aam.00a0 AAN.0ma0 AmN.mma0 00.0a 0a.0ma 0a.Ama .m.<.0-Aaammgg 0a.- m00. Am0.00N0 AaN.A0a0 Amm.mma0 00.0a- 00.00a 00.a0a Amgmamm-Agmaamm .3 I. -. . . mmm . . . . A ml .mv cme .m cmoz m Apmncaucoov m manna 100 mgu.a.m .gmmg mmaamg-osm .a00.v0 «mm mgu.g.m .mmmg mmaamm-osg .a0.v0 mm mgn.a.m .ammg mmaama-oza .m0.vm m ammoaoo wmumasaasmza mw.a 0aa. AON.AAa0 AON.mma0 AAm.ama0 am.aa mm.0sa 0N.00 Ammmamu-Aomgoo mm.- 0A0. A30.amN0 Ama.sma0 AOA.00a0 Na.sa- N0.00a sm.moN Amemamo-.m.m.m.g AA.- aA0. A00.0mN0 AON.aga0 Am0.Ama0 0N.mN- 0m.AAa 30.00N sommoo-.m.m.m.0 0N. maa. AmN.mAa0 A00.0sa0 A03.00a0 0m.s NA.00a mm.N0a Amgmamo-mmmmmo 0N.- me. Aaa.0Na0 AmA.A00 AmN.00a0 00.0- AN.mma m0.Ama aomgoo-mmmmgm 0m.- Nma. Amm.mma0 A00.000 A00.0Na0 ma.0- mm.mma 00.0ma .m.m.m.g-mmmmm0 I. I. A.g.mv emmz A.n.mv A.o.mv u .a ma mun 3 ma mdoaumz m0 .323 A ml .3 new: .m new: m Ammmeaggouv m magma 101 00.a 0am.mmm AN0.0sv Aam.am0 AmN.0m0 mm.aa AA.NHH AH.HOH .m.m.m.D 00.nmmm 000.mmm Amm.0sv A0A.000 Asa.0mv «H.HN AN.Nm ma.am mommau om.N« emm.««« Aom.wmv Amo.mmv Aqa.mqv mm.aa mA.mm ow.c¢ .m.<.o om.m«« wom.«e« Amo.mqv Amq.mqV Amq.mqv mo.wa qm.mm Hm.qm *aawmam Hw.N«« wmq.««« Aqm.mqv Auo.qu Aoo.mmV wo.oa N¢.Noa qm.ow NAcame-ammo .3 mq.m««« omq.««« Aqm.qu Aqm.oqv Aqm.wmv mm.mH om.No mm.q¢ *anam 00.- a0m.mmm Aa0.m00 Ama.mev Amm.40av qq.l AN.Hm om.Hm manna 0a.smmm 000.mmm Aam.0m0 Amm.000 A00.0mv NN.HN Hq.ow ma.mm pamaom m0.smmm amm.mmm Aaa.0av Aam.Nev Aaa.000 om.qm Hm.mw om.mo *Hmwnuaom 0a.a www.mmm Am0.qma0 ANN.aaN0 A00.m0a0 qm.Am om.mmm Nm.wma .¢.m.D mm.m««a mam.e«« Aow.mqv Amm.qu Awq.mmV cm.wa Hm.maa mm.om coaxoz Aw. mmo. AHA.cNHV AAm.mmv Amw.AHHV 00.ma A0.AA Aa.sm ammommmmam Am.a wmq.««« Aqq.wmv Aqm.qu Aqm.cov cm.qa mm.woa mm.qm measo Im- IM. Ammomv A.Q.mv A.Qomv GOHUQZ a a a a saw: A.cl..cv new: .. cmoz .c .mcmmz wmumamaaoo aom wuwmuhw mew ”mew: ummuumom nuas ummumam mo mcoaomamaaoo cowamwm ”mum: ca mmwemno ammuumom lummumam new mmmmmz ammuumom .mmmwmz ammumam mo meoauwa>mm pampcmum can memos .o magma 102 m0u.a.0 .gmmg emaamg-osg .a0.vg mm m0u.a.0 .gmma emaamg-osm .00.vm m 0A. Nma. A00.mma0 AN0.0Na0 Aa0.N00 00.Na 00.0A 00.A0 aammgg-ammsgaoa AN. amm.mm A00.0ma0 A00.msa0 A00.000 a0.0 N0.00a am.00a mmmamm-omgoo 0N.- 0am.m Asa.000 Amm.a00 A00.N00 0N.N- Ne.ms 00.00 aaaa-maogmwgam a a. A000 mmmz A000 A000 mmmmmmz aa aa aa aa Ml .M flmwz AM Gwmz m .wcwmz vmumeaaoo How mummulw.pcm mmmsam> owmmmmz_ummuumom SuHB ammumam mo mdoaumawaaoo comamwm “moumaaumm pamucoo owmwmmz CH mmwcmso ummuumomlummumam mam .moumefiumm uamuaoo owmmmmz ummuumom .moumaauwm uaousoo wwmwmmz ummumam mo maoauma>mm unaccepm mam mammz .m mHQwH 00-.a.0 .gmma emaamg-oaa .a00.vm «mm m0u.a.m .gmmg emaamg-osm .a0.v0 mm m0n.0.0 .gmmg emaamg-osg .00.v0 « uaoocoo pmumasaacmz * a0.0mmm 0m0.mmm A00.000 AAN.000 Amm.000 0N.Nm 00.A0 00.00 Amgmamo 00.0mm 000.mmm A00.000 A00.m00 A00.000 NA.0a 00.00 0A.a0 aommoe m. m. A.g.00 A.g.mv A.g.00 goaumz H H H H awe: A.ml..:v dmmz ..c cme .c Ammmgaggomv .0 magma 103 Table 8. Pearson Correlations* of Mean Pretest Inter-concept Distances (Sij) with Mean Posttest Inter-concept Distances (S'ij)' Indirectly Unmanipulated Manipulated Changed Method of Dimensions All Distances Distances Distances Deriving Included in Distances Only Only Only S'ij Calculations (N=105) (N=36) (N=69) (N=66) No Stable 1 .964 .949 .973 .972 Concepts Rotation 1-2 .954 .933 .964 .963 1—3 .921 .918 .925 .919 1-6 .877 .880 .891 .875 1—9 .837 .845 .842 .836 1—12 .863 .887 .858 .860 1-15 .835 .862 .823 .825 Stable 1 .973 .968 .976 .975 Concepts Rotation 1-2 .903 .945 .880 .876 1—3 .918 .955 .904 .905 1-6 .838 .922 .808 .788 1-9 .811 .912 .779 .770 1-12 .824 .901 .800 .795 1-15 .804 .929 .759 .752 Observed -— .865 .914 .835 .848 V S ij * All correlations are significant (p<.001, one—tailed test). 104 All of the correlation coefficients were positive and statistically significant (they were, of course, highly interdependent); and the corre- lations were, in absolute terms, quite within the range of reliability usually considered acceptable. No computation yielded a correlation below .75; 27 of the 60 correlations were greater than .9 and 54 were greater than .8. The correlations tended to decline as more dimensions were included in the analysis, a result which indicates that measurement errors were concentrated in the smaller, ”residual” dimensions. The effect of rotation procedures on the results is also evident in Table 8. For the no stable concepts rotation there was no noticable difference between the reliabilities of unmanipulated and manipulated distances. For the stable concepts rotation, however, the unmanipulated distances were consistently more reliable-—an intended outcome of the rotation procedure. Particularly important are the coefficients for the directly observed posttest distances, for these were undistorted by rotation of the coordinate system. Here the reliability of unmanipu- lated distances was .914 while that of the manipulated distances was .835. Thus the stable concepts rotation gives results more in line with those of the actually observed distances than does the no stable con- cepts rotation. The third way of assessing reliability is by examination of the stability of the coordinate system. This is done by correlating the pretest coordinates with the posttest coordinates for each dimension. These correlations are given in Table 9. 105 Although complete correlation matrices were computed only the correlation of each dimension with itself over time is given in the table. In principle all other correlations should have equalled either unity or zero. The correlation of each coordinate with itself within a given time period is necessarily perfect. The correlation of each co- ordinate with each other coordinate in the same time period should be null as a consequence of the orthogonality of the MDS solution. This was true for the pretest coordinates. Slight correlations were observed among the posttest coordinates and among non—corresponding pretest and posttest coordinates, however. The correlations among the posttest coordinates presumably resulted from rounding errors during rotation, while those among non-corresponding pretest and posttest coordinates presumably resulted both from rounding errors and from change in the coordinates over time. With a few, isolated exceptions, these corre— lations were less than .1-—too low to be of any concern. Turning now to the correlations in Table 9, one can conclude, in general, that all but the smallest dimensions were quite stable. The outstanding exception was the fourth coordinate for the no stable con- cepts rotation, whose correlation was essentially zero. The correla— tions for the first three dimensions compare favorably with those re— ported in previous studies (Cf. Gillham, 1972; Barnett, n.d.; Danes and Woelfel, 1975). Validity Validity of measurement was assessed in two ways. The first 'method was to observe the pattern of t-tests for correlated means computed on the raw (unaggregated) data (see Tables 5, 6 and 7). 1 06 Table 9. Pretest-Posttest Pearson Correlations of MDS Coordinates. No Stable Stable Concepts Dimension Concepts Rotation Rotation l ***.987 ***.990 2 ***.978 ***.925 3 ***.946 ***.942 4 -.O7O **.697 5 ***.944 **.619 6 ***.951 *.469 7 **.631 *.541 8 *.554 .101 9 ***.745 **.699 10 ***.790 .327 11 .406 *.445 12 -.011 .263 13 **.638 ***.786 14 **.597 *.524 15 ***.895 ***.777 * p<.05, two-tailed test, d.f. = 14 ** p<.Ol, two-tailed test, d.f. = 14 *** p<.01, two-tailed test, d.f. = 14 107 Only five of the changes in the 105 inter-concept distances were significantly different from zero. Of the five significant changes, four Tame manipulated distances. The fact that only one change occurred among the unmanipulated distances is consistent with the assumptions of the experiment, but the fact that only four of the 69 manipulated distances changed is not. The very high variances of the changes seem to preclude statistically significant t-ratios in most cases. There was a general tendency for the concept mass estimates to increase from pretest to posttest——10 of the 15 underwent statistically significant changes, all positive. 5 of the 10 significant changes were of those among the 6 manipulated concepts. That is consistent with the fact that information (mass) about the manipulated concepts was given in the experiment. None of the changed masses had a pretest value greater than 90; while only one concept with a pretest mass of less than 90 (Singapore—-a manipulated concept) failed to change. This is gener- ally (except for the failure of Singapore to change) consistent with the concept of inertial mass: lower masses should be more susceptable to change by the addition of information over a short period of time. The general increase in masses is also consistent with the idea of mass, Which is supposed to accumulate. In the present case, however, it may be as reasonable to attribute the changes to some undetermined feature 0f the experimental situation. None of the three message content estimates changed significantly, nor was there any recognizable pattern in the observed changes. This is as expected if message content is a stable quantity. 108 The second way of assessing validity was to observe the pattern of means to determine whether the aggregate measurements correspond with what one would expect intuitively, based on general knowledge. The inter—concept distances are most conveniently examined in the form of plots of the multidimensional scaling results (Figures 1 through 6). Figures 1 through 3 are plots of the results of the no stable con- cepts rotation procedure, and Figures 4 through 6 are plots of the re— sults of the stable concepts rotation procedure. Examination of the plots, or of the data in Table 5, confirms that the observed distances are generally reasonable. One apparent exception is the greater close- ness of Guyana to the African nations of Congo and Central African Republic than to the Latin American nations of Mexico and Brazil. That apparent misplacement, however, is consistent with what the author has informally observed: that uninformed people frequently assume that Guyana is in Africa because its name "sounds" African (four students informally interviewed prior to the study all located Guyana in Africa). Among the largest distances at both pretest and posttest measurements were those of China-U.S.A., Congo-U.S.A., Fiji-U.S.S.R., Congo—U.S.S.R. and Guyana—U.S.S.R. None of these would be expected to be a small dis— tance. Among the smallest distances at both times are Mexico-Brazil, Poland-U.S.S.R. and U.S.A.-West Germany. These, too, are reasonable. .Another indication of the validity of the measurements of inter-concept distances is the overall similarity of the present results to those <flbtained by Wish, Deutsch and Biener (1972) in another study of nations. Turning now to the inertial mass data, the question is whether thezlneans appear to correspond in general to the prominence of the 109 nations. The four greatest masses at both points in time are those of U.S.A., Mexico, U.S.S.R. and China; while smallest masses are those of Fiji, Central African Republic and Guyana. The higher mass countries are all ones about which Americans would be expected to know something because of their physical proximity or international importance; while the lower mass countries seem relatively unimportant or at least un- publicized. Finally the three message content estimates indicate, as expected, that the message arguing that Congo and Guyana are "very different" was thought to place those countries at greater distance than average, and at about three times the distances at which Singapore—Fiji and Portugal— Brazil were placed by their messages. Procedures Three checks were made of the experimental procedures. The first was whether the manipulated concepts were, as intended, of low to moderate mass and at moderate distances from each other within the mani— pulated pairs. The mean mass of all concepts at both points in time was 88.2 and the standard deviation 39.0. The mean of the six manipulated concept masses was 67.6. The highest mean mass among the manipulated concepts was Brazil's 83.3. Thus the six manipulated concepts were of low to moderate inertial mass. The grand mean of the 105 pretest inter-concept distances was 148.9 and the standard deviation 30.8. The grand posttest mean was 149.8 and the standard deviation 24.3. The pretest distances of the three mani— pulated pairs were: 102.0 (Singapore-Fiji), 105.8 (Portugal—Brazil), 110 and 99.2 (Congo—Guyana). Thus the three manipulated mean distances were all quite similar, but were all nearly two standard deviations below the grand mean. A regression artifact would tend to increase these distances. Two of the three experimental messages, however, argued for a decrease in distance. A second precedural check was whether the messages, as measured by the message content estimates, actually advocated the intended changes in distance. Comparing the means in Table 7 to the corresponding pretest means in Table 5, it is evident that the messages did advocate the in- tended changes. The first message argued (45.7) that Singapore and Fiji (102.0) are similar. The second message argued (165.3) that Congo and Guyana (99.2) are different. The third message argued (57.9) that Brazil and Portugal (105.8) are similar. The third procedural check was whether the experimental messages had the intended direct effects-—whether, that is, the three manipulated distances actually changed in the intended directions. All three of the observed mean changes (as given in Table 5) were in the advocated di- rections. The distance of Singapore from Fiji changed from 102.0 to 95.6 for a decrease of -6.39. The distance of Congo from Guyana changed from 99.2 to 140.5 for an increase of 41.3. The distance of Portugal from Brazil changed from 105.8 to 76.2 for a decrease of 29.6. None of these changes was statistically significant, although the latter two approached significance (p<.08 for Portugal—Brazil; p<.07 for Congo-Guyana). At the individual level of analysis, then, the manipulations cannot be claimed to have succeeded. At the aggregate level it is perhaps of more importance that the mean of the three manipulated absolute changes was 25.8 as com- pared to a mean absolute change of 12.2 for all 105 inter—concept distances. 111 Hypothesis Tests The main hypothesis of the study was tested by three sets of pro- cedures. First, the mean changes were directly examined. Second, the correlations of predicted with observed inter-concept distances were examined. Third, the correlations of predicted with Observed coordinates were examined. Test One: Mean Changes The questions to be answered by a direct examination of the mean distances are whether the three kinds of changes (direct, indirect and no change) occurred as predicted and whether the overall pattern of changes (as visible in the plots of the MDS analysis) is interpretable in a way consistent with the hypothesis. The mean of the absolute changes of the three directly changed dis- tances was 25.8. The mean of the absolute changes of the 66 indirectly changed distances was 12.3. The mean of the absolute changes of the 36 -pg_change distances was 10.8. This pattern is consistent with the hypo- thesis. Turn now to the plots and coordinate matrices of the MDS analysis. Examine the motions of the manipulated concepts pair by pair, considering all views and rotations. While the BEE Change in each case was as pre- dicted, the motion was not, as assumed by the theory, directly along the lines connecting the pairs. The slight net convergence of Singapore and Fiji resulted mostly from changes along dimensions not plotted. The two countries actually diverged on the first and third dimensions (in the latter case bypassing one another) and converged on the second dimension only because of Singapore's greater velocity: Fiji moved in the direction opposite to that predicted. Again, Congo and Guyana's net divergence 112 resulted from movements at large angles to the directions predicted. Regardless of rotation procedure one of the most prominent changes was Congo's movement, contrary to prediction, along the second dimension. The divergence of the two nations on the third dimension was about as expected, but their lock—step motion on the first dimension was quite opposite to that predicted. Finally, Portugal and Brazil's net con- vergence occurred despite Brazil's movements Opposite to predictions on the first and third dimensions and Portugal's opposite movement on the first and second dimensions. Net convergence on the second and third dimensions occurred only because the country moving in the "right" di- rection tended to overtake the other country. There are evident in the plots other changes that are not inter- pretable in terms of the hypothesis. Even in Rotation #2, which was designed to minimize their change, several unmanipulated nations exhibited apparently substantial movements. One noticeable tendency was for the more extreme countries to move inwards in the general direction of the origin——a pattern suggestive of the phenomonon of regression toward the mean. The specific observed changes are not interpretable in terms of facts known to the investigator. Test Two: Inter-concept Distances The second hypothesis test was by means of a correlation between predicted and observed inter-concept distances. As discussed in Chapter III, the study provided many distinct bases upon which such a correlation may be computed. The results are presented in Tables 10 through 13. In Table 10 are the zero order Pearson correlations between the posttest inter-concept distances (S'ij) and those predicted by the theory, 113 either including concept masses in the computations (gmij) or excluding concept masses from the computations (§ij). All of the correlations (which, of course, were highly interdependent) were statistically highly significant. Most were greater than .8. Several general patterns in these correlations may be noted. First, there was a tendency for the correlations for the "computed" posttest distances to increase in magni— tude as less dimensions were included in the computations. This would be expected since the larger (lower) dimensions are more stable. The cor— relations for the actually observed posttest distances, however, fit an opposite pattern, yielding higher correlations for predictions based on more dimensions. This also would be expected, however, since the pre— dictions based on only a few dimensions are not truly comparable to the actually observed posttest distances, which are, as it were, based on all dimensions. Second, different patterns resulted from the different rotation procedures. The stable concepts rotation displayed a pattern, for all but computations based on only the first dimension, of higher correlations for unmanipulated distances than for manipulated distances. The no stable concepts rotation produced no such pattern. The pattern of correlations for the actually observed posttest distances was more similar to the stable concepts than to the no stable concepts rotation --a fact which may suggest the greater validity of the stable concepts procedure. Finally, there was no clear pattern of differences between correlations involving predictions taking account or not taking account of the concept masses. Thus inertial mass, as measured in the present study, did not clearly contribute to the theory's predictive power. 114 Table 10. Pearson Correlations* of S'ij with Smij and Sij, Broken Down by Number of Dimensions Included in Computations, by Method of Obtaining S'ij’ and by Subsets of Cases. Distances S',. Comp. S',, Comp. 13 13 Included Dimensions Predictor From No From Stable Actually in the Included in A=Smij Stable Con— Concepts Observed Analysis Computations B=Sij cepts Rotation Rotation S'ij All 1—15 A .836 .804 .866 (N=105) B .858 .815 .885 l-12 A .864 .825 .867 B .878 .831 .885 1-9 A .838 .812 .866 B .854 .822 .882 1-6 A .888 .838 .841 B .883 .838 .858 1-3 A .921 .917 .821 B .922 .922 .828 1-2 A .954 .903 .757 B .953 .904 .763 l A .964 .973 .619 B .964 .973 .619 Unmani— 1-15 A .862 .929 .914 pulated B .862 .929 .914 $i§auces 1—12 A . 887 . 901 .889 (N=36) B .887 .901 .889 1-9 A .845 .912 .881 B .845 .912 .881 1—6 A .878 .922 .857 B .878 .922 .857 1-3 A .918 .955 .806 B .918 .955 .806 1-2 A .933 .945 .814 B .933 .945 .814 1 A .949 .968 .594 B .949 .968 .594 115 Table 10. (continued) Distances S'ij Comp. S'ij Comp. Included Dimensions Predictor From No From Stable Actually in the Included in A=Smij Stable Con- Concepts Observed Analysis Computations B=Sij cepts Rotation Rotation S'ij All 1-15 A .824 .759 .836 Manipu- B .862 .773 .867 gizignces 1—12 A .859 .801 .858 (N=69) B .885 .810 .887 1—9 A .843 .780 .864 B .870 .796 .890 1-6 A .891 .808 .847 B .898 .807 .872 1-3 A .925 .904 .831 B .928 .912 .843 1—2 A .964 .880 .736 B .963 .881 .746 l A .973 .976 .631 B .973 .975 .631 Indirectly 1-15 A .826 .752 .849 Changed B .837 .747 .851 p;:22?ces 1-12 A .860 .795 .870 B .861 .788 .869 1—9 A .836 .770 .874 B .844 .768 .873 1-6 A .876 .788 .855 B .877 .785 .860 1-3 A .919 .905 .856 B .919 .910 .856 1-2 A .963 .876 .765 B .960 .876 .762 l A .972 .975 .616 B .972 .975 .616 * A11 correlations in this table are significant, p<.OOl, one—tailed test. 116 In Table 11 are the first order partial correlations controlling for the pretest interconcept distances (sij). These correlations were substantially lower than the zero order correlations, demonstrating that much of the accuracy of prediction displayed in Table 10 was due simply to the stability over time of the aggregate cognitive space, a stability rightly assumed by the theory. Three additional facts about this table are worth noting. First, several of the partials were large enough to be statistically significant (the meaning of this, however, is complicated by the interdependence of the correlations). Second, the correlations were lowest when restricted to the 66 indirect changes, although a few (including, however, none of those for the actually observed posttest distances) were still large enough to be significant. Third, negative partials were observed for correlations based on the first dimension only, and those correlations are among the largest in the table in absolute magnitude. The negative correlations are clearly contrary to the theory. In Tables 12 and 13 are the zero order correlations of predicted with observed changes in distance. The use of change scores is a second way of controlling for the pretest distances. The pattern of these cor- relatiOns was much like that of the partial correlations: they were sub- stantially lower than the correlations in Table 9; many of them were large enough to be statistically significant; the correlations for the indirect changes were substantially smaller than those for all manipu- lated distances; and negative correlations were Observed for computations based on the first dimension only. Overall the correlations between predicted and observed inter- concept distances were not strongly supportive of the theory. 117 Table 11. First Order Partial Correlations (Controlling Sij) of S'ij with Smij and Si., Broken Down by Number of Dimensions Included in Computations, by Method of Obtaining S'ij’ and by Subsets of Cases. Distances S',. Comp. S',, Comp. 13 1 Included Dimensions Predictor From No From Stable Actually in the Included in A=Smij Stable Con— Concepts Observed Analysis Computations B=Sij cepts Rotation Rotation S'ij All l—15 A *** .346 * .209 *** .336 (N=105) B *** .358 ** .230 *** .370 1—12 A *** .317 * .212 *** .331 B *** .330 * .225 *** .360 1-9 A ** .294 ** .228 *** .315 B *** .311 ** .237 *** .341 1—6 A * .186 .057 *** .334 B * .200 .091 *** .356 1—3 A .142 ** .280 ** .275 B .137 ** .260 ** .256 1-2 A .017 .078 * .194 B .051 .120 * .180 l A —.120 ***—.346 .060 B —.144 ***-.317 .032 All l—15 A *** .444 * .224 *** .385 Manipu- B *** .455 * .244 *** .425 gigiinces 1-12 A We .41:- =2 .239 w: .412 *t* A *** (N=69) B = .425 .249 .444 1-9 A *** .388 * .262 *** .402 B *** .405 * .264 *** .430 1—6 A * .238 .059 *** .420 B * .253 .094 *** .450 1—3 A * .207 ** .357 *** .373 B .196 ** .325 ** .347 1-2 A .006 .072 * .261 B .050 .116 * .234 1 A —.l7l ***—.436 .074 B *—.204 ***-.402 .040 118 Table 11. (continued) Distances S'ij Comp. S'ij Comp. Included Dimensions Predictor From No From Stable Actually in the Included in A=Smij Stable Con- Concepts Observed Analysis Computations B=Sij cepts Rotation Rotation S'ij Indirectly 1-15 A * .242 .062 .150 Changed B * .249 .079 .183 p;:22?ces 1-12 A .171 .066 .149 B .179 .074 .173 1-9 A .204 .094 .137 B * .216 .093 .155 1—6 A .112 -.021 .165 B .126 .024 .187 1—3 A .114 * .255 .082 B .105 * .227 .052 1—2 A —.054 .026 .006 B -.004 .080 —.033 l A —.153 ***—.424 -.035 B -.l9O ***-.386 —.066 * p<.05, one-tailed test ** p<.Ol, one-tailed test *** p<.001, one-tailed test 119 Table 12. Pearson Correlations of Asij with ASmij and ASij, Broken Down by Number of Dimensions Included in Computations, by Method of Obtaining S'ij’ and by Subsets of Cases. Distances Dimensions Predictor A913 Computed Sij Comp. From Included in Included in A=ASmij From No Stable Stable Con- the Analysis Computations B=ASij Concepts Rotation cepts Rotation All l—15 A ** .297 * .198 (N=105) B ** .301 * .213 1—12 A ** .258 * .199 B ** .260 * .206 1-9 A ** .254 * .210 B ** .262 * .212 1-6 A * .206 .095 B * .219 .125 1-3 A .112 * .224 B .126 * .225 1-2 A .017 .071 B .081 .138 l A —.099 **-.291 B -.139 **—.287 All 1-15 A ** .374 * .219 Manipu- B ** .373 * .234 fiigignces 1—12 A ** .329 A .233 7H: 9‘: (N=69) B .323 .236 l-9 A ** .328 * .247 B ** .329 * .241 1-6 A * .257 .104 B * .270 .136 l-3 A .171 .290 B .184 ** .286 1—2 A .033 .084 B .115 .157 l A -.124 **—.357 B -.178 **—.356 120 Table 12. (continued) Distances Dimensions Predictor Agij Computed ng Comp. From Included in Included in A=ASmij From No Stable Stable Con- the Analysis Computations B=ASij Concepts Rotation cepts Rotation Indirectly 1-15 A * .219 .072 Changed B * .220 .086 €§:22§Ces 1-12 A .147 .071 B .144 .075 1-9 A .186 .101 B .188 .096 1—6 A .190 .064 B * .216 .115 1-3 A .138 * .251 B .162 * .259 1—2 A .042 .081 B .135 .166 l A -.090 **-.335 B —.152 **-.333 * p<.05, one-tailed test ** p<.01, one-tailed test 121 Table 13. Pearson Correlations of A3,. with A§m.. and A§.., As.. 13 13 13 13 Computed from Actually Observed S'ij’ and §mij and gij Computed from Fifteen Dimensions, Broken-down by Subsets of Cases. Distances Predictor Included in the A= §mij Analy51s B= g.. r 13 All (N=105) A **.267 B **.286 All Manipulated Distances A **.314 B **.334 Indirectly Changed A .139 Distances B .159 Test Three: Coordinates The third hypothesis test was by means of a correlation between predicted and observed spacial coordinates. The several versions of this correlation as a function of predictor, rotation procedure, di- mensions considered, concepts considered and statistical control of the pretest coordinates are given in Tables 14 through 16. In Table 14 are the zero order Pearson correlations between the posttest coordinates (f'ik) and those predicted by the theory, either including concept masses in the computations (fm ) or excluding concept ik masses from the computations (fi ). All of the correlations were sta- k tistically highly significant (recall that they are statistically inter- dependent). The pattern of these correlations was much like that of the inter-concept distance correlations. The magnitudes of the correlations were greater when fewer dimensions were considered in the computations, Table 14. Pearson Correlations* of F', 122 1k With Fmik and Fik for Two Rotations, Cases Broken Down by Cumulative Dimensions and Experimental Groups. Concepts Included in the Analysis Dimensions Included in Predictor A=Fm . _ ik the Ana1y31s N B-Fik No Stable Conc. Stable Conc. Rotation Rotation A11 1-15 225 A .834 .784 B .839 .789 1—12 180 A .846 .793 B .851 .797 1-9 135 A .812 .814 B .877 .817 1—6 90 A .909 .861 B .911 .859 1—3 45 A .973 .957 B .973 .959 1-2 30 A .983 .962 B .983 .962 1 15 A .987 .990 B .987 .990 Unmanipu- 1—15 135 A .821 .960 lated B .821 .960 SEECEPtS 1-12 108 A .832 .967 y B .832 .967 1-9 81 A .861 .978 B .861 .978 1—6 54 A .893 .980 B .893 .980 1—3 27 A .975 .982 B .975 .982 1—2 18 A .982 .986 B .982 .986 123 Table 14. (continued) Concepts Dimensions Predictor Included in Included in A=Fm,k No Stable Stable Conc. the Analysis the Analysis N B=FiR Conc. Rotation Rotation Manipu— 1-15 90 A .855 .559 lated B .867 .568 3°???“ 1—12 72 A .868 .578 n y B .880 .587 1-9 54 A .889 .617 B .905 .623 1-6 36 A .943 .695 B .947 .688 1-3 18 A .973 .911 B .975 .915 1-2 12 A .977 .860 B .975 .858 * All correlations in this table are significant, p<.001, one—tailed test. 124 Table 15. First Order Partial Correlations (Controlling Fik) of F', 1k with Fmik and Fik for Two Rotations, Cases Broken Down by Cumulative Dimensions and Experimental Groups. Concepts Dimensions Predictor Included in Included in A=Fmik No Stable Stable Conc. the Analysis the Analysis N B=Fik Conc. Rotation Rotation All 1-15 225 A * .152 .113 B * .151 .135 1-12 180 A ** .168 .111 B ** .166 .135 1-9 135 A .206 .102 B .205 .124 1—6 90 A .137 -.061 B .119 -.039 1-3 45 A .166 .207 B .150 .201 1-2 30 A .066 .088 B .072 .101 1 15 A -.174 -.372 B -.l99 -.348 Manipu- 1-15 90 A *8 .273 .113 lated B ** .275 .131 gzicepts 1—12 72 A *8 .299 .111 y B - 8* .300 .130 1-9 54 A ** .368 .104 B ** .370 .119 1-6 36 A * .292 -.069 B .259 -.050 1-3 18 A .336 .234 B .320 .224 1-2 12 A .092 .001 B .103 .008 125 Table 16. Pearson Correlations of AFi with AFmi and AFik for Two k k Rotations, Cases Broken Down by Cumulative Dimensions and Experimental Groups. Concepts Dimensions Predictor Included in Included in A=AFmik No Stable Stable Conc. the Analysis the Analysis N B=AFik Conc. Rotation Rotation A11 1-15 225 A ** .157 * .121 B ** .162 * .147 1-12 180 A * .172 .119 B ** .176 * .146 1-9 135 A ** .204 .109 B ** .209 .133 1-6 90 A .129 -.052 B .120 -.026 1-3 45 A .204 .237 B .191 .233 1-2 30 A .147 .152 B .157 .167 1 15 A -.070 -.218 B -.113 -.245 Manipu— 1-15 90 A ** .284 .134 lated B ** .291 .158 goicepts 1-12 72 A 88 .308 .130 n Y B 88 .314 .155 1-9 54 A ** .371 .121 B ** .378 .140 1-6 36 A * .289 -.053 B .264 -.027 1-3 18 A .370 .283 B .357 .278 1-2 12 A .277 .179 B .300 .198 * p<.05, one—tailed test ** p<.01, one~tailed test 126 reflecting again the greater stability of the larger dimensions. Again, the stable concepts rotation produced higher correlations for the unmani— pulated concepts' coordinates than for those of the manipulated concepts; while the no stable concepts rotation produced no such difference. And again, there was no clear difference between predictions including or ex— cluding the concept masses from the computations. If anything the pre- dictor excluding concept masses produced slightly better predictions. Table 15 gives the first order partial correlations controlling the pretest coordinates (fi ). The partials were substantially lower than the k zero order correlations, demonstrating again that the theory's accuracy of prediction rested mainly upon the stability of the coordinate system. Once again several of the partials for the manipulated concepts were large enough to be statistically significant, but only for the no stable concepts rotation. Unlike the inter—concept distances, the coordinates cannot be partitioned into direct and indirect changes. Consequently the effect noted for the inter-concept distances—-lower partials for the indirect changes—-cannot be observed here. No consistent differences emerged be— tween predictions including or excluding concept masses in the computations. Finally, there were small, observed negative partials for the first and the first six coordinates. Thus the theoretical predictions were in the wrong direction for some dimensions. Table 16 presents the zero order correlations between predicted and observed changes in coordinates. The pattern of these correlations was very similar to that of the partials, except that these correlations were slightly higher. Overall, then, one may conclude that the correlations between predicted and observed coordinates , like those between predicted and observed inter- concept distances,1«uxanot strongly supportive of the hypothesis. CHAPTER V DISCUSSION This chapter discusses the findings of the study in relation to the theory of linear motion and to the adequacy of the study as a test of that theory, and draws implications for further research. The chapter begins by evaluating the measurement and procedures of the study, then evaluates the overall degree of support which the study gives to the theory of linear motion, and then closely examines several alternative explanations of the results. The chapter closes with a summary and conclusion of the dissertation. Evaluation of Measurement and Procedures Measurement reliability in this study was at least adequate at the aggregate level of analysis, but was poor at the individual level of analysis. Since the hypothesis tests were conducted with aggregated data, the adequate degree of reliability achieved at the aggregate level is of primary importance. Measured reliability of the aggregated data was somewhat higher than the best results achieved by Barnett in his study of the reliability of metric MDS techniques. Since the size and homogeneity of the subject sample and the number and homogeneity of the concepts scaled in this study were similar to Barnett's studies, the higher measured reliabilities in this study may be attributed to its shorter (one week) interval between measurements. Thus the reliabilities reported by Barnett may still be regarded as typical for the conditions. Questions of measurement validity and the success of experimental procedures are less straightforwardly answerable than is the question of 127 128 reliability. Our data were tested against severa1_a priori criteria. Again, the criteria were quite well satisfied whenever the test involved aggregated data, but were not so well satisfied when the tests involved individual-level data. One can view this finding in several ways. The finding is perfectly reasonable given the findings concerning reliability, and given the theoretical principle that reliability is a necessary con- dition for validity. And again, since the hypothesis tests were conducted with aggregated data, the positive results for the aggregated data may be of prime importance. On the other hand, the criteria for the aggre- gated data were generally less formal, more intuitive. One cannot, in these circumstances, rule out the possibility that wishful thinking by the experimenter might influence his interpretations. Furthermore, the assessment of validity of measurement and procedures becomes involved in a delicate balance between theory and data. If one strongly believes one's theory, then the failure of theory-testing studies may, in the absence of external criteria of construct validity, be attributed to in- valid measurement and procedures. After repeated use over a period of time, of course, such an argument must begin to wear thin. In any case, there seems no strong and self-evident reason to reject this study on the ground of invalidity alone. As an aside to the discussion of measurement we should mention the interesting tendency for the inertial mass estimates to increase between pretest and posttest. The explanation that the subjects' information about the experimental concepts actually increased during the study seems too facile; yet no other explanation comes readily to mind. The further fact that measured inertial mass did not relate to cognitive change in 129 the theoretically expected manner suggests that we must search further for a valid explanation of its behavior. Evaluation of Results The results of this study do not appear to support the hypothesis. The first test, the inspection of mean changes in distance, disclosed several anomalies. The second and third tests, the correlations of pre- dicted with observed inter-concept distances and coordinates, showed that the theory predicts very well, but only because it predicts the general stability of the cognitive structure. When the change component is iso— lated by statistically controlling the pretest scores or by correlating predicted with observed changes, the predictive power of the theory is quite poor in absolute terms: seldom does it account for as much as five percent of the variance in the dependent variable. Isolated correlations might appear promising, but the overall pattern does not. Certain results are strongly negative in their implications. Were the theory correct, one would expect better results for the stable con- cepts rotation than for the no stable concepts rotation, since the former assumes the success of the experiment. The reliability tests found that the stable concepts rotation gave results which were more like those for the actually observed distances than did the no stable concepts rotation. Yet the no stable concepts rotation, in the hypothesis tests, gave results which were, if anything, slightly more supportive of the hypothesis than did the presumably more valid stable concepts rotation. This suggests that whatever apparent success the theory may have had in some instances was accidental. Even more disturbing are the negative results on the first dimension. Some of the strongest partial correlations are negative 130 correlations for computations based on the first dimension only. These correlations are contrary to the theory. It is clear from inspection of the plots hgw_this result occurred, but it is not at all clear why it occurred. Perhaps the most rigorous single test of the hypothesis is in the correlations at the bottom of Table 13, the correlations for indirect changes in the inter—concept distances based on the actually observed posttest distances. These correlations are unaffected by the uncertain meanings of rotation procedures and computed "observations." The corre- lations are .139 for the predictor including inertial mass and .159 for the predictor excluding mass. Neither of these correlations is statis— tically significant. Some indication of the insubstantial nature of these correlations is given by comparing them to those immediately above them, which differ only in including the three direct changes. The correlations including the three direct changes are almost .2 higher than those not including the direct changes. The addition of only three cases (which are trivially consistent with the theory) doubles the magnitude of the correlations. One cannot consider the correlations as indications of a reliable trend in the data. Alternative Explanations If the results of this study are not explicable by the hypothesis, then how may they be explained? This chapter suggests and evaluates seven possible responses to that question. In considering each of seven alternative explanations of the results we will both present whatever facts in the present study might fall under the explanation, and discuss features that might be incorporated in future studies to test the explafi. nations. 131 The first three alternative explanations all have in common the implication that this study failed to support the theory only because it failed adequately to control the information to which the subjects were exposed. The first alternative hypothesis is that the experiment failed, not because the theory is false, but because of a failure of the experimental manipulations to work. This hypothesis holds that the experimental mes- sages simply had no systematic effect on the aggregate cognitive structure. If the messages had been "stronger"—-if more, or more credible information had been provided, or if more powerful techniques of persuasion had been employed-—then the resulting cognitive change might have conformed to the theory of linear motion. This hypothesis cannot strictly be ruled out, because none of the direct changes in distance supposedly induced by the messages were statistically significant; although we have argued that the overall pattern of mean changes suggests that the manipulations did work. A future study designed to rule out the hypothesis would have to have three features. First, the messages would be strengthened, perhaps by adding information or by adding redundancy, as in a multi-media presen- tation. Second, the messages would be more thoroughly pretested to ensure their effectiveness prior to the main study. Third, a separate control group of subjects would be used so that treatment—control comparisons could be made of the same inter-concept distances (rather than only be— tween manipulated and unmanipulated distances as in the present study). A second alternative explanation is that the messages were powerful enough to bring about cognitive change, but the contents of the messages were not those which the experimenter intended. The messages, in other 132 words, were noisy; they contained "unintended" information, and so moved the concepts in unintended directions. Here we confront a serious dilemma which no future experiment of this sort can ignore. A realistic and credible message concerning a particular pair of concepts must, it would seem, make references to many "third" concepts by way of introducing points of comparison or contrast between the experimental concepts. In comparing Fiji and Singapore, for example, we said that both were small, tropical, former British colonies, recently independent, and parliamentary democracies. Perhaps the weakest aspect of this study, in retrospect, was its assumption that the infor- mation incorporated in the messages would exert force only along the line directly connecting the pairs of manipulated concepts. In retrospect it would havelmxuljust as reasonable, and perhaps more reasonable to assume, for example, that saying that Singapore and Fiji are both parliamentary democracies not only would move Singapore and Fiji toward each other but also would move bg£h_8ingapore and Fiji toward the concept of "parlia- mentary democracies." This, then, is the dilemma: on the one hand, we want realistic, credible messages; on the other hand, we can only include a limited number of concepts in the multidimensional scaling analysis. It seems that we must choose either ineffective or invalid manipulations. The dilemma might be avoided if we had a truly adequate spacial model of message content. More immediately, the dilemma might be avoided by thorough pretesting of the messages in several pilot studies which would incorporate, in overlapping parts, all of the concepts referred to in the messages. The meaning of the message would then not be measured, as it was in this study, by a single item referring to the single pair 133 of experimental concepts. Rather the meaning would be measured by a set of items referring to a set of reference concepts common to all of the pretest studies and the main study. And the movement of the manipulated concepts would not be predicted to occur along the lines connecting the pairs; nor would the force of the message be assumed divided equally be- tween the two experimental concepts. Rather, the movement of each con- cept would be predicted as a linear function of its predicted movements with respect to the whole set of reference concepts. The theoretical prediction of "indirect" changes would then be based on a set of concepts included in the main study but not in any of the pilot studies. By comparison to this ideal set of procedures the messages used in this study were little better than shots in the dark. Can the apparently chaotic movements apparently induced by the experimental messages be ex- plained by assuming that the messages were noisy? The answer, in general, is trivially ”yes." Less trivially and more concretely, certain unpre— dicted changes do seem directly attributable to certain unintended mes- sage contents. The example of Singapore and Fiji is a case in point. Both countries, which were said to be parliamentary democracies having capitalist economies, moved toward the "conservative" end of the second dimension, which seemed to represent political ideology. Another case concerns Congo. It was mentioned earlier that Congo's movement toward the "radical" end of the second dimension was one of the most prominent changes in the study. This movement, which was not at all predicted, is not at all surprising in view of the assertions, in the message about Congo and Guyana, that Congo has a socialist economy and a one-party government, and is a self-proclaimed "communist" state. Perhaps we could 134 even explain Brazil's movement toward the African cluster as a consequence of the reference in the message to Brazil as a former colony. Perhaps we could explain Guyana's movement in a general "European" direction as a result of references to it as a parliamentary democracy or as a member of the British Commonwealth of Nations. These post hog explanations must be viewed with appropriate skepti— cism. They do, however, support the general contention that the noisiness of the experimental messages cannot be ruled out as an alternative ex— planation which preserves the basic character of the theory of linear motion. A third alternative hypothesis is that the observed movements of concepts were affected by messages other than the experimental messages, such as news reported in the mass media during the interval between pre— test and posttest measurements. This hypothesis, like the previous two, holds that the theory is correct but that the experiment failed to con- trol adequately the information inputs to the subjects. Information such as mass media news was treated as environmental noise in the design of this study-~uncontrolled and assumed to be randomly distributed among the 105 inter—concept distances. If a separate control group of subjects had been included in this study, then the environmental noise might have been controlled statistically. Wisely or not, the experimenter decided not to allocate scarce subjects in that fashion. A future study might do so and might achieve superior results. On the other hand, an unsys- tematic review of mass media references to the fifteen nations during the week of the study failed to identify any apparent relationships with the movements of concepts. 135 The fourth and fifth alternative explanations both raise the issue of control of time. Both explanations could more easily be ruled out by a study which took measurements at three or more points in time. The fourth explanation holds that the theory may be correct but not enough time was allowed for equilibrium to be establishedin cogni- tive space following the messages. This explanation might have been ruled out had a second posttest been administered. If the results failed to improve from first to second posttest, then the hypothesis would be false. Even the presently available data, however, rule out this hypo- thesis as a sufficient explanation. The hypothesis seems to require, even in the short run, that all changes would be in the predicted dif rection; but that clearly was not the case in this study. The fifth explanation is Woelfel's proposed cognitive Law of Motion, or something like it: the idea that concepts have resistance not to velocity but to acceleration in cognitive space, and that, consequently, one cannot predict the effect of a message without knowing the velocity of the affected concepts prior to the message. The posttest distances would be a result of the prior velocities and the message inputs. Under this hypothesis, failure to take account of prior velocities could lead to just the sort of apparently chaotic results found in this study. Statistical control of velocities prior to the messages would require that a second pretest be administered. Prior velocity would be measured by change occurring between the two pretests. A thorough consideration of the fourth and fifth alternative ex- planations, in short, would require that observations be made at at least four points in time, including two pretests and two posttests. 136 The last two alternative explanations raise even more complex issues than did the first five, for they raise the specter of a hetero— geneous cognitive space. The sixth explanation is that not all concepts or sets of concepts in cognitive space behave lawfully, and that the concepts in this study failed to behave lawfully because there were too many of them, or be- cause they, or some of them, were not meaningful. Two factors are in- volved in this explanation. First is the notion of information proces- sing capacity. People can handle only a limited amount of information in a given period of time. If the environment presents information beyond this limit, then excess information is simply not processed sys- tematically. By rough analogy with experiments on short term memory we might suppose that in an experiment such as ours the maximum number of concepts that would behave lawfully would be about seven (Miller, 1960). The second possible factor is meaningfulness. Perhaps we cannot expect a concept to behave lawfully just because it is included in an MDS in— strument; perhaps we must know, in addition, whether the concept meant anything to the subjects prior to administration of the instrument. How many subjects in our study had ever heard of Guyana or Fiji? Can we claim to have measured the meaning of these concepts, or must we admit to having merely created an apparent meaning by including them along with the rest of the concepts? And can we expect such pseudo-cognitions, if they exist in the study, to behave lawfully? ' a set of con* These two factors point to the concept of "domain,' cepts that behave together as a unit, or are, in Scott's (1969) terms, "functionally equivalent." Under this explanation the laws of motion do 137 not apply to just any set of concepts; the concepts must compose a domain. There may be an upper limit to the size of domains. Spaces including more than that number of concepts would not behave lawfully. If the limit is around seven, then this study, with fifteen concepts, exceeds the limit. Or again, there may be some "critical mass" that a concept must attain before it can function as part of a domain. The theory of linear motion has assumed that mass is important only as resistance to motion: the more mass the more resistance. Now we must wonder whether nearly mass— less concepts are at all capable of lawful motion. The data of this study were examined from several standpoints in an effort to test this alternative hypothesis. Particular attention was focused on subsets of about seven concepts that might, for one or another reason, constitute a domain. Predictions of distances involving the seven highest mass concepts, and predictions of the smallest third of the inter-concept distances, were examined and found to be no better than predictions for the whole set of distances. Thus the present study offers no direct support for the contention that concepts can belong to a domain only if they have a certain critical mass or if they are close to each other in cognitive Space. A third subset of distances, however, was found to conform more closely to the theory than did the data as a whole. These were the dis— tances among the six manipulated concepts: fifteen distances, or if the three directly changed distances are excluded, twelve distances. Table 17 displays the partial correlations (controlling pretest distances) of predicted with observed posttest distances for the twelve indirectly changed distances among the six manipulated concepts. These partials 138 are, on the whole, substantially higher in absolute magnitude than the corresponding partials in Table 11. Few of them are statistically sig— nificant, but then it must be considered that they have only nine degrees of freedom. Had these partials appeared in Table 11 they would have been touted as strong support for the theory, this despite some anomolies among them, most notably the (now even stronger) negative correlations for the first dimension. Three factors seem to favor the theory. The first is the large magnitude of the partials. The second is that the best results are achieved with the stable concepts rotation, which assumes the success of the experiment. The third favorable factor is that the correlations "peak" around the middle of the range of cumulative dimen- sions (2 through 6 dimensions), which presumably include the greatest proportion of reliable information. One must, of course, view_pg§tnhgg_analyses with some skepticism. Still we can ask whether this particular subset of the concepts falls under the alternative explanation. Do they compose a ”domain" in a sense that the whole set of concepts does not? One interpretation is that the six manipulated concepts constitute a domain just in consequence of being manipulated, which entails both being mentioned in connection with each other and being infused with information in the form of experi- mental messages that might create the needed "critical”mass." This in— terpretation is interesting, but it should not be taken too seriously until the finding has been replicated. The sixth alternative explanation might be ruled out by a future study which experimentally varied the number of concepts scaled. 139 Table 17. First Order Partial Correlations (Controlling Sij) of S',, with Sm,, and 8,, for Indirectly Changed Distances 1] 13 13 Among Manipulated Concepts Only. Dimensions Predictor S'ij Computed S'ij Computed Actually Included in A=Smij From No Stable From Stable Observed Computations B=Sij Concepts Rotation Concepts Rotation S'ij 1-15 A .436 .359 .359 B .449 .402 .402 1-12 A .384 .392 .403 B .397 .424 .444 1-9 A .322 .416 .352 B .357 .436 .414 1—6 A .336 * .532 .511 B .321 * .528 * .523 1—3 A .335 .466 .165 B .362 .437 .163 1-2 A .333 ** .775 -.213 B .474 ** .793 —.138 l A —.490 -.512 .004 B *—.553 -.484 -.027 * p<.05, one-tailed test, d.f. = ** p<.01, one-tailed test, d.f. = KOO 140 The seventh and final alternative explanation to be considered here is that the results of this study seem unsystematic because a radically inappropriate model has been applied; the mind is not at all space-like but is instead a network. A network model views the mind as a set of concepts which are or are not connected by various sorts of links. The mathematical model is a set of nodes or points connected by lines which may or may not be di— rectional (asymmetrical) and labeled (Harary, e£_al., 1965). For example, "A likes B” might be represented as A_;:Q.B, or more abstractly as A ___B. The former expression is directed and signed, while the latter expression says only that there is some connection between A and B. A network model focuses attention on the kinds of links and on higher—level phenomena that emerge when links are composed into larger networks. Network models may be fairly simple. Balance theory (Heider, 1958), for example, con- siders only two kinds of links--unit relations and sentiment relations, each of which may only be positive or negative. Network models may, however, be astonishingly complex, as a recent paper by Frederiksen (1975) well shows. Network and spacial models make radically differently assumptions about how the mind is organized. The heart of the matter is that under the strong spacial assumptions of theorists like Osgood and Woelfel (and Craig) all cognitive objects are comparable, for all are scalable in cognitive space. If we regard psychological distance as a kind of relation or connection, then a "network" defined on that relation has highly determined structural properties. First, the network necessarily is completely interconnected, in that any scaled object necessarily is 141 some distance from every other scaled object. Second, the relation necessarily is symmetrical, in that Sij’ the distance from i to j, is necessarily identical to Sji’ the distance from j to i. Third, the re- lation necessarily is intransitive, in that sij and s, puts only a loose jk restriction on Sik (assuming a real, multidimensional space-—in imaginary space there is no restriction at all). In short, the key structural variables of network models, such as continuity, direction, symmetry and transitivity of relations, and connectedness, integration and structural differentiation of networks, are all invariants, and thus essentially meaningless, in spacial models. Spacial models assume that cognitive space exists as a kind of "medium” in which objects are located, regardless of whether or not the subject is aware of the medium as such. Network models, in contrast, focus upon the question of explicit cognitive connections between things, and thus do not assume that such connections exist. In a network model cognitive elements may not be connected. Concepts may be "similar" yet unrelated; or concepts may be quite different or distant, and yet be highly related by an asymmetric relation. Thus the crucial structural assumption of "distance" in the spacial model is meaningless or para- doxical from the standpoint of a network model; unrelated concepts have no distance, and the various kinds of connections seem to have no clear translation into distance. Robert Abelson (1968) has distinguished be- tween "maximalist" and "minimalist" positions on cognitive structure. The spacial model, with its highly restrictive assumptions, necessarily takes a maximalist position; it assumes a great deal of structure. “M ’V \, 141 some distance from every other scaled object. Second, the relation necessarily is symmetrical, in that Sij’ the distance from i to j, is necessarily identical to Sji’ the distance from j to i. Third, the re- lation necessarily is intransitive, in that sij and sjk puts only a loose restriction on Sik (assuming a real, multidimensional space——in imaginary space there is no restriction at all). In short, the key structural variables of network models, such as continuity, direction, symmetry and transitivity of relations, and connectedness, integration and structural differentiation of networks, are all invariants, and thus essentially meaningless, in spacial models. Spacial models assume that cognitive space exists as a kind of "medium” in which objects are located, regardless of whether or not the subject is aware of the medium as such. Network models, in contrast, focus upon the question of explicit cognitive connections between things, and thus do not assume that such connections exist. In a network model cognitive elements may not be connected. Concepts may be "similar" yet unrelated; or concepts may be quite different or distant, and yet be highly related by an asymmetric relation. Thus the crucial structural assumption of ”distance” in the spacial model is meaningless or para— doxical from the standpoint of a network model; unrelated concepts have no distance, and the various kinds of connections seem to have no clear translation into distance. Robert Abelson (1968) has distinguished be— tween "maximalist" and "minimalist" positions on cognitive structure. The spacial model, with its highly restrictive assumptions, necessarily takes a maximalist position; it assumes a great deal of structure. v’v\ 142 Under the assumption that the mind is "really" structured like a network rather than like a space, some apparently unsystematic features of our results become plausible. In a network model change in a single relation is not generally expected to change the relations between the two elements involved and all other elements in the network, if only because it is not generally expected that all such possible relations exist. Nor does a network model require that change in a single rela— tion wouldleaveunchanged relations at more than one step remove from the changed relation. Rather, such implicational change is a function of whatever higher—order structural principles (such as balance) are operative. The spacial model, in contrast, requires both that a change in distance between two concepts changes the distances between each of those concepts and all other concepts scaled and that the distances among the unmanipulated concepts are unaffected. This reasoning would suggest that the present study supports a network model of cognitive structure, since neither of the mentioned requirements of the spacial model is strongly evident in the data. Such reasoning, however, would be spurious, because the "evidence" for the network model is entirely negative; the network hypothesis becomes, in effect, the null hypothesis. Can any feature of our data be used to test the network hypothesis more forthrightly? No direct test can be designed because we have no very good basis for assuming what kinds of connections, if any, are present among the concepts. Two indirect tests, however, were tried. The first test requires that the cognitive network is ruled by the higher—order principle of cognitive balance. Phillips (1967) has shown that a cognitive network can be represented as a matrix of W\ 143 relations, and that the matrix can be factored. Thus it is mathemati— cally possible to represent a network as a multidimensional space, as- suming that the network is completely connected and is composed of con— tinuous (i.e. numerical) relations. Phillips has also shown that a perfectly balanced cognitive network would be unidimensional (i.e. one factor would perfectly account for the relational matrix). Thus a ten— dency toward cognitive balance might appear in our data as a tendency for the cognitive "space" to become unidimensional. A glance at the tables in Appendix C will confirm that no such tendency was present in the data. The dimensions, if anything, become more equal in importance over time as indicated by the relative sizes of their eigenvalues. The second indirect test of the network hypothesis requires that we assume that the spacial concept of psychological distance is identi— cal to the network concept of "relatedness." Then we must further assume that a "balance" tendency operates such that when we change a concept's relation to some other concept (as by transmitting an experimental mes— sage), then concepts highly related to the changed concept will tend to "change along" with it, while unrelated concepts will not be affected by its motion. One might imagine the more tightly connected concepts being "dragged along by their connections” when we "move” a concept. It follows from this that the closer (more related) a concept is to a ”moved" concept the less the change in relatedness of that concept should be to the moved concept. In other words, for distances involving a manipulated concept there should be a strong positive correlation between magnitude of distance and absolute change of distance, while for distances involving 144 an unmanipulated concept, any change in which is assumed to be random, the correlation would not necessarily be strongly positive. Table 18 displays the correlations between distance and absolute Change in distance computed separately for each of the fifteen concepts. Manipulated and unmanipulated concepts are listed in separate columns to facilitate comparison. If the above reasoning is correct, then the net— Work model is false, since the pattern of correlations, if there is a pattern, is just the opposite of that expected. The author has imagined several interpretations of these corre— lations, only one of which is credible enough to mention here. The in— terpretation is that the negative correlations for the manipulated con— cepts indicate that the experimental manipulations had systematic effect only in the regions nearby the manipulated concepts. Thus large absolute changes occurred between the manipulated concepts and nearby concepts but not between the manipulated concepts and far away concepts. This suggests a "domain" interpretation of the study, with domains comprising local regions of cognitive space. Unfortunately, as was noted several paragraphs above, there was no detectable tendency for the theory of linear motion to make more accurate predictions of small distances than of large distances. If, in other words, our interpretation of the corre- lations in Table 18 is correct, we still have not saved the theory of linear motion. We imply instead that some other "law of motion" governs the movement of concepts within regional cognitive domains. The two indirect tests attempted do not, in any case, support a network interpretation of the present study. The author has not devised a means by which a future study might rule out the hypothesis of network 145 Table 18. Pearson Correlations of Distance From Each Concept with Absolute Change of Distance From that Concept. MANIPULATED CONCEPTS UNMANIPULATED CONCEPTS Concept Concept No. r No. r 2 -.417 l —.347 5 —.256 3 —.203 8 .332 4 * .581 10 *-.582 6 —.072 14 *—.576 7 —.l36 15 **—.618 9 * .489 11 ***-.750 12 * .596 13 .173 * p<.05, one—tailed test, d.f. = 12 ** p<.01, one—tailed test, d.f. = 12 *** p<.001, one—tailed test, d.f. = 12 146 structure. Continued failure of spacial models, however, would suggest that we move toward the network model as an alternative. Summary and Conclusion The working assumption of this study was that models of cognitive structure may fruitfully be elaborated into general models of informa- tion which describe the structure of messages and constrain theories of the cognitive effects of communication. Because of its intuitive appeal and mathematical convenience, and because of its prominence in several disciplines, the spacial model of cognitive structure was selected for study. A model of message structure and a theory of linear motion were elaborated from the general spacial model by strict deduction from ex- plicit definitions and assumptions. Previous research bearing on several aspects of the theory of linear motion was discussed. It was concluded that the theory of linear motion was plausible (though not at all proven), and that research on such a theory would be a reasonable next step from several points of view. An empirical study was conducted in an attempt to test the theory of linear motion. The study employed a pretest—manipulation-posttest, within-subjects experimental design. Subjects were presented with in— formation designed to change directly three of the 105 pairwise distances among fifteen concepts. The hypothesis was that the messages would bring about cognitive change as predicted by the theory of linear motion. The results were basically negative; the theory was not supported, except insofar as it correctly assumed the general stability over time Of cognitive space. The observed changes in location of concepts gener— ally were inexplicable from the standpoint of the theory. 147 Several alternative explanations of the results were considered. Several of these "save" the theory by indicting the experiment. Others suggest alternative theories. One general indictment of the experiment is that it may have failed to control adequately the information to which subjects were exposed (used ”weak" messages; included extraneous (or merely unaccounted for) information in the messages; failed to control for information from the environment beyond the experiment). The experi— ment may also have failed to control adequately the variable 0f.E£EE (failed to allow sufficient time for the theoretical effects to occur; failed to take measurements at enough points in time to allow observa— tion of accelerations). The theory may have failed to take adequate account of the concept of cognitive domain——a set of functionally equi- valent concepts. Thus the experiment may have included a number of con- cepts which exceeded the information processing capacities of the subjects, or it may have included meaningless concepts that could not be expected to behave lawfully. Some evidence suggests that the theory might have been successful had predictions been restricted to a domain comprising the manipulated concepts. Finally, the theory may be false because it makes a radically false assumption about cognitive structure. If, for example, the mind is ”really" a network rather than a space, a study such as ours would be expected to produce apparently unsystematic re— sults. No specific evidence was found in these data to support a network interpretation, however. Future research should be directed toward re- solving the issues raised by these alternative explanations. As we pointed out in Chapter I, a test of a particular theory is not equivalent to a test of the general spacial model. If this study 148 has not been entirely decisive regarding the theory of linear motion, much less has it been decisive concerning the general spacial model. If the theory of linear motion is false, some other cognitive "law of motion,” perhaps more complex, may ultimately be found true. The results of this study, all considered, do not vindicate the working assumption; but neither is the failure of a single experiment sufficient to warrant rejecting a general strategy of inquiry. Our investigation must be considered as only a step along the way to an— swering the broad questions which stimulated it. REFERENCES Abelson, R. P. "Discussion: Minimalist vs. Maximalist Positions on Cognitive Structure," in Abelson, R. P., 35.3l. (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. 526-528. Abelson, R. P. "Psychological Implication," in R. P. Abelson, §£_al. (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. 112—139. Abelson, R. P., et_§l. (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. Barnett, G. "Reliability and Metric Multidimensional Scaling." Unpublished paper, Michigan State University, Department of Communication, n.d. Barnett, G., Serota, K. and Taylor, J. "A Method for Political Com— munication Research." Presented at the Annual Conference of the Association for Education in Journalism, San Diego, California, 1974. Blum, G. S. A Model of the Mind. New York, 1961. "Brazil - History offl'inEncyclopaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macropaedia, Vol. 4. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 144-151. Brock, T. C. "Effects of Prior Dishonesty on Postdecision Dissonance," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psycholog , 1963, 66. 325-331. Brock, T. C. "Dissonance Without Awareness," in Abelson, R., 23.21- (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. 408—416. Brock, T. C. and Grant, L. D. ”Dissonance, Awareness and Motivation," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1963, 67. 53-60. Burton, M. "Semantic Dimensions of Occupation Names," in Shepard, R. §£.§1- (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Research in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 55—71. Cohen, A. R., Greenbaum, C. W. and Mansson, H. H. "Commitment to Social Deprivation as a Determinant of Cognitive Dissonance," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 1963, 67. 410-421. 149 150 D'Andrade, R., E£.§1° "Categories of Disease in American—English and Mexican-Spanish," in Shepard, R.,_g£.§l. (eds.), Multidimensional Scaligg} Theory and Research in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 9-54. Danes, J. "Multidimensional Scaling Models for Communication: Methods and Applications," Unpublished paper, Michigan State University, De- partment of Communications, July, 1975. Danes, J. and Woelfel, J. "An Alternative to the 'Traditionalm Scaling Paradigm in Mass Communication Research: Multidimensional Reduction of Ratio Judgments of Separation.” Presented at International Com- munication Association Annual Meeting, Chicago, Illinois, 1975. Deese, J. "Conceptual Categories in The Study of Content." In Abelson, R., _g£_§l. (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. 504—511. Degerman, R. "The Geometric Representation of Some Simple Structures," in Shepard, R.,_g£_§l. (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. I. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 193-211. Dillehay, R., C. Insko and M. Smith, ”Logical Consistency and Attitude Change," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1966, 3. 646—654. Frederiksen, Carl H. "Representing Logical and Semantic Structures of Knowledge Acquired From Discourse," Cognitive Psychology, 1957, 7. 371-458. Fu-kiau kia Bunseki-L., Andre. "Congo (Brazzaville)," in Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macropaedia, Vol. 4. Chicago: Encyclo- paedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 1113—1118. Gillham, J. "The Aggregation of Shared Information in a Sociology Depart— ment." Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Illinois, 1972. Greenberg, B. and Roloff, M. "Attitude Change Advocated and Obtained on Low Information Topics." Paper presented to the International Com- munication Association Annual Meetings, Chicago, Illinois, 1975. "Guyana," in Engyclopaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macropaedia, Vol. 8. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 506-512. Harary, F., Norman, R. & Cartwright, D. Structural Models. New York: Wiley, 1965. Heider, F. The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations. New York, 1958. Helm, C. E., Messick, S. and Tucker, L. Psychophysical Law and Scaling Models. Princeton: Educational Testing Service, 1959. Ho, Robert. "Singapore," in Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macro- paedia, Vol. 16. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 784-790. 151 Honeybone, Reginald Crawshaw. "Fiji," in Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macropaedia, Vol. 7. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 295-298. Jones, L. and Young, F. "Structure of a Social Environment: Longitudinal Individual Difference Scaling for an Intact Group," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1972, 24. 108—121. Kelly, G. A Theory of Personality: The Psychology of Personal Con— structs. New York: Norton, 1963. Krippendorff, K. ”Models of Messages: Three Prototypes,‘ in Gerbner, G.,_g£_gl. (eds.), The Analysis of Communication Content. New York: Wiley, 1969. 69—106. Kruskal, J. B. "Multidimensional Scaling By Optimizing Goodness of Fit to a Nonmetric Hypothesis," Psychometrika, 1964a, 29, 1—27. Kruskal, J. B. "Nonmetric Multidimensional Scaling: A Numerical Method,” Psychometrika, 1964b, 29, 115~129. Mauser, G. "A Structural Approach to Predicting Patterns of Electoral Substitution," in Shepard, R. .33 E1: (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 245—287. McGuire, W. "Cognitive Consistency and Change,” Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 1960, 60. 345-353. Mettlin, C. J. "Assessing the Effects of Interpersonal Influence in the Attitude Formation Process." Unpublished doctoral disser- tation, University of Illinois, 1970. Miller, G. A. ”The Magical Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two: Some Limits on Our Capacity for Processing Information.” Psychological Review, 1956, 63. 81—97. Nie, N. H., g£_§l. SPSS: Statistical Package for the Social Sciences, Second Edition. New York: McGraw Hill, 1975. Office of Public Information, United Nations. United Nations Yearbook, 1972. Appendix I, ”Roster of the United Nations (as at 31 December 1972). Vol. 25. New York, 1975. 823—824. Osgood, C. "The Representation Model and Relevant Research Methods," in Pool, I. (ed.), Trends in Content Analysis. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1959. 33—88. Osgood, C. ”Probing Subjective Culture," Journal of Communication, 1974, 21. 21-35, 82-100. 152 Osgood, C., Suci, G. and Tannenbaum, P. The Measurement of Meaning. Urbana: The University of Illinois Press, 1957. Osgood, C. & Tannenbaum, P. "The Principle of Congruity in the Pre— diction of Attitude Change," Psychological Review, 1955, 62. 42-55. Perez de Amaral, Ilé dio Melo and Jose Shercliff. "Portugal," in Encyclopaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macropaedia, Vol. 14. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 855—864. Phillips, J. ”A Model for Cognitive Balance,” Psychological Review, 1967, 74. 481—495. Pool, 1. (ed.), Trends in Content Analysis. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1959. Poppino, Rollie E. "Brazil,” in Encyclgpaedia Britannica, 15th Edition. Macropaedia, Vol. 3. Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1974. 123—144. Rapoport, A., and Fillenbaum, S. "An Experimental Study of Semantic Structures," in Shepard, R., g£_gl. (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 93—131. Richardson, M. W. "Multidimensional Psychophysics," Psychological Bulletin, 1938, 35. 659-660. Roloff, M. E. ”An Application of Linear Force Aggregation Theory to the Relationship Between the Amount of Change Advocated in a Message and the Amount of Attitude Change Obtained.” Unpublished Master's thesis, Department of Communication, Michigan State University, 1974. Rosenberg, M. "Cognitive Reorganization in Response to the Hypnotic Reversal of Attitudinal Affect," Journal of Personalily, 1960, 28. 39-63. Rosenberg, 8., and Sedlak, A. "Structural Representations of Perceived Personality Trait Relationships," in Shepard, R., §E_§l, (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 133-162. Runkel, P. "Dimensionality, Map Matching and Anxiety," Psychological Reports, 1963, 13. 335—350. Saltiel, J. and Woelfel, J. "Inertia in Cognitive Processes: The Role of Accumulated Information in Attitude Changes," Human Communica— tion Research, 1975, 1, 333—344. 153 Schroder, H., Driver, M. & Streufert, S. Human Information Processigg. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston, 1967. Scott, W. "The Structure of Natural Cognitions," Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1969, 12. 261—278. Serota, Kim Blaine Metric Multidimensional Scaling and Communication: Theory and Implementation. Unpublished Master's thesis, Michigan State University, Department of Communication, 1974. Shepard, R. "The Analysis of Proxemities: Multidimensional Scaling with an Unknown Distance Function, I," Psychometrika, 1962a, 27. 125—140. Shepard, R. ”The Analysis of Proxemities: Multidimensional Scaling with an Unknown Distance Function, II," Psychometrika, 1962b, 27, 219-246. Shepard, R. "A Taxonomy of Some Principal Types of Data and of Multi- dimensional Methods for Their Analysis," in Shepard, R. gg_al. (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. I. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 561-592. Shepard, R., Romney, A. and Nerlove, S. (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vols. 1, II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. Smith, J. "Computer Generated Analogues of Mental Structures from Language Data," in Information Processing 74. North—Holland Publishing Company, 1974. 842—845. Stefflre, V. "Some Applications of Multidimensional Scaling to Social Science Problems," in Shepard, R-’.E£,§1- (eds.), Multidimensional Scaling: Theory and Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 211—243. Tannenbaum, P. "Mediated Generalization of Attitude Change Via the Principle of Congruity," Journal of Personaligy and Social Psychology, 1966, 2. 493—499. Tannenbaum, P. "The Congruity Principle: Retrospective Reflections and Recent Research," in Abelson, R., §£_gl. (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. pp. 52-72. Tannenbaum, P. and Gengel, R. "Generalization of Attitude Change Through Congruity," Journal of Personalily and Social Psychology, 1966, 3. 299-304. 154 Taylor, J., G. Barnett and K. Serota. "A Multidimensional Examination of Political Attitude Change." Presented at International Com— munication Association Annual Meeting, Chicago, Illinois, 1975. Torgerson, Warren S. Theory and Methods of Scaling. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1958. Weick, K. "Processes of Ramification Among Cognitive Links," in Abelson, R.,_g£_§l. (eds.), Theories of Cognitive Consistency: A Sourcebook. Chicago: Rand McNally, 1968. 512—519. Wish, M., Deutsch, M. and Biener, L., "Differences in Perceived Similarity of Nations,” in Shepard, R., gg_gl. (eds.), Multi— dimensional Scaling: Theogyyand Applications in the Behavioral Sciences. Vol. II. New York: Seminar Press, 1972. 289-313. Wishner, J. ”Reanalysis of'Impressions of Personality,'" Psychological Review, 1960, 67. 96-112. Woelfel, J. Sociology and Science. Unpublished ms., Michigan State University, 1971. Woelfel, J. "Procedures for the Precise Measurement of Cultural Pro- cesses." Unpublished paper, Michigan State University, 1974 (a). Woelfel, J. "Metric Measurement of Cultural Processes," presented to the Speech Communication Association Annual Meetings, Chicago, Illinois, December, 1974 (b). Woelfel, J. "A Theory of Occupational Choice," in Picou, J. and R. Campbell (eds.), Career Patterns of Minority Youth, forth‘ coming. Woelfel, J. and Haller, A., "Significant Others, the Self Reflexive Act and the Attitude Formation Process," American Sociological Review, 1971, 36. 74—87. Woelfel, J. and Hernandez, B. "Media and Interpersonal Effects on Attitude Formation and Behavior," Unpublished manuscript, Department of Communication, Michigan State University, 1974. Woelfel, J. and Saltiel J. "Cognitive Processes as Motions in a Multidimensional Space." Unpublished manuscript, Department of Communications, Michigan State University, 1974. Woelfel, J.,_§£_gl. "Political Radicalization as a Communication Process." Communication Research, 1974, 1, 243—263. 155 Woelfel, J., §p_§l. "Orthogonal Rotation to Theoretical Criteria: Comparison of Multidimensional Spaces." Paper presented at the Annual Convention of the Mathematical Psychology Association, Purdue, Indiana, August, 1975. Wyer, R. S. Cognitive Organization and Change: An Information Pro— cessing Approach. Potomac, Maryland: Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc— iates, 1974. Zajonc, R. "The Process of Cognitive Tuning in Communication," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 1960, 61, 159-167. Zajonc, R. "Cognitive Theories in Social Psychology,” in Lindsey, G. & Aronson, E. (eds.). The Handbook of Social Psycholo y, 2nd Edition. Vol. 1. Reading Mass.: Addison—Wesley, 1968. 320-411. APPENDICES APPENDIX A PRETEST QUESTIONNAIRE AND POSTTEST COVER LETTER Dear Participant, This is a study of human information processing. We hope to learn more about how people understand and structure information. A second part of the experiment will be administered in a few days. At that time we will more fully explain the purpose of the study. Please follow the instructions carefully. Answer_§ll questions. Leaving blanks unfilled may make your questionnaire unusable. Always put down an answer, even if you have to guess. Complete each page before going on to the next. If for any reason you do not wish to participate in this study, just do not fill out the questionnaire. Thank you very much for your cooperation. Sincerely yours, Robert T. Craig What is your date_p£ birth? .___ PLEASE DO NOT Month Day Year WRITE IN THIS SPACE What is your ESE? Male (Card 1) 0 No. _________ Female 1 2 3 l Gp.__ Wv__1_ 4 5 6 Card Jl__l_ 7 8 Yr, Sx_________ 9 l 1 156 157 The following set of questions asks you to guess how much infor— formation you have-—how much you know-—about each of fifteen countries. Consider all that you know about each country, from whatever source. If zero (0) represents the complete absence pf knowledge, and 100 each country? Remember, if you feel that you have less than an average amount of information about a country, write a number less than 100. If you have more than average information about a country, write a number larger than 100. You may write any number you want. COUNTRY AMOUNT OF INFORMATION China (12—15) (Card 01) Singapore (16—19) Mexico (20—23) U.S.A. (24~27) Portugal ______1 (28-31) Poland (32-35) India (36—39) Fiji (40-43) West Germany (44-47) Brazil (48-51) Central African Republic (52—55) Greece (56—59) U.S.S.R. (60-63) Congo (64—67) Guyana (68—71) 158 The following set of questions asks you Egg different (or in other words "far apart") you perceive the countries to be. Differences in concepts are measured in units, so that the mppg different two con— cepts are, the more units apart they are from each other. To help you know how big a unit is, assume that Italy 229 England g£g_lgg_pplp§ apart. If you think that two countries are mppg different from each other than Italy and England, write a number larger than 100. If you think that two countries are lpgg different from each other than Italy and England, write a number lggg than 100. If you think that two countries are exactly phg.§§mg, that you see no difference at all be- tween them, write a zero (0). Remember, the mppg different the coun— tries are from each other, the higher the number you should write. You may write any number you want. Please answer all questions. Even if you feel unsure of your answer, 5235.3 guess. Work as quickly as you comfortably can. Once you "get going" each answer will take only a few seconds. How far apart are each of the following? COUNTRIES UNITS APART (Card 01) 72-80 0102 China (Card 02) 9—17 0103 China Dup 1-6 18-26 0104 China U.S.A. . . . . . 02 7—8 27-35 0105 China Portugal . . . . & Singapore . . . . . & & & . . . . . 36-44 0106 China & Poland . . . . . . . . . . & & & & Mexico . . . . . . . . . . . 45—53 0107 China India . . . . . . 54-62 0108 China Fiji . . . . . . . . . . 63-71 0109 China West Germany . . . . 72-80 0110 China Brazil . . . . . . . . . 159 How far apart are each of the following? (Card 03) Dup 1-6 03 7-8 (Card 04) Dup 1-6 04 7-8 (Card 05) Dup 1—6 05 7-8 (Card 06) Dup 1—6 06 7—8 9-17 18—26 27—35 36-44 45-53 54-62 63—71 72—80 9—17 18—26 27—35 36-44 45—53 54-62 63—71 72-80 9-17 18—26 27—35 36-44 45-53 54-62 63-71 72—80 9-17 18—26 27—35 36—44 45-53 54-62 63-71 72-80 0111 0112 0113 0114 0115 0203 0204 0205 0206 0207 0208 0209 0210 0211 0212 0213 0214 0215 0304 0305 0306 0307 0308 0309 0310 0311 0312 0313 0314 0315 0405 0406 COUNTRIES China & C China & G China & U China & C China & G Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Singapore Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & Mexico & U.S.A. & U.S.A. & UNITS APART entral African Republic reece .S.S.R. ongo . uyana & Mexico & U.S.A. & Portugal Poland India . . Fiji.... West German Brazil . . . . . . . . Central African Republic Greece . . . U.S.S.R. Q‘QQ‘QQQ’QWQ" & Congo . & Guyana U.S.A. Portugal . Poland . India Fiji . . . . . West Germany . Brazil . . . . . . . . . . Central African Republic . Greece . U.S.S.R. Congo Guyana . Portugal . Poland . 160 Remember: ITALY and ENGLAND are 100 UNITS apart How far apart are each of the following? COUNTRIES UNITS APART (Card 07) 9—17 0407 U.S.A. & India Dup 1—6 18-26 0408 U.S.A. & Fiji . . . . . 07 7-8 27—35 0409 U.S.A. & West Germany . 36—44 0410 U.S.A. & Brazil . . . . . . . . 45-53 0411 U.S.A. & Central African Republic . 54—62 0412 U.S.A. & Greece . 63-71 0413 U.S.A. & U.S.S.R. 72—80 0414 U.S.A. & Congo (Card 08) 9-17 0415 U.S.A. & Guyana . Dup 1-6 18-26 0506 Portugal & Poland . 08 7—8 27—35 0507 Portugal & India 36-44 0508 Portugal & Fiji . . . 45-53 0509 Portugal & West Germany . 54—62 0510 Portugal & Brazil . . . . . . . 63—71 0511 Portugal & Central African Republic . 72—80 0512 Portugal & Greece . (Card 09) 9—17 0513 Portugal & U.S.S.R. Dup 1—6 18—26 0514 Portugal & Congo 09 7-8 27—35 0515 Portugal & Guyana . 36-44 0607 Poland & India 45—53 0608 Poland & Fiji . 54-62 0609 Poland & West Germany . 63—71 0610 Poland & Brazil . . . . . . . 72—80 0611 Poland & Central African Republic . (Card 10) 9-17 0612 Poland & Greece . Dup 1—6 18—26 0613 Poland & U.S.S.R. 10 7-8 27-35 0614 Poland & Congo 36—44 0615 Poland & Guyana . 45-53 0708 India & Fiji . . 54-62 0709 India & West Germany 63-71 0710 India & Brazil . . . . . . . . 72—80 0711 India & Central African Republic (Card 11) Dup 1—6 11 7—8 (Card 12) Dup 1-6 12 7—8 (Card 13) Dup 1—6 13 7-8 (Card 14) Dup 1-6 14 7—8 161 far apart are each of the following? 9-17 18—26 27-35 36—44 45—53 54-62 63-71 72-80 9~17 18-26 27-35 36-44 45—53 54—62 63-71 72-80 9-17 18-26 27-35 36—44 45-53 54-62 63-71 72—80 9-17 18-26 27—35 36-44 45-53 54—62 63—71 72—80 0712 0713 0714 0715 0809 0810 0811 0812 0813 0814 0815 0910 0911 0912 0913 0914 0915 1011 1012 1013 1014 1015 1112 1113 1114 1115 1213 1214 1215 1314 1315 1415 COUNTRIES UNITS APART India & Greece . . . . . . India & U.S.S.R. . . India & Congo . . . . . . . . . India & Guyana . . . . . . Fiji & West Germany . . . . Fiji & Brazil . . . . . Fiji & Central African Republic . Fiji & Greece . . . . . . . . . Fiji & U.S.S.R. . . . . . . . . . . Fiji & Congo . . . . . . . Fiji & Guyana . . . . . . . . West Germany & Brazil . . . W. Germany & Central African Republic West Germany & Greece . . . . . . West Germany & U.S.S.R. . . . . . . West Germany & Congo . . . . . . . West Germany & Guyana . . Brazil & Central African Republic . Brazil & Greece . . . . . . Brazil & U.S.S.R. Brazil & Congo . . . . . . . . . Brazil & Guyana . . . . . . . . . Central African Republic & Greece . Central African Republic & U.S.S.R. Central African Republic & Congo . Central African Republic & Guyana . Greece & U.S.S.R. Greece & Congo Greece & Guyana . . . . . . . . U.S.S.R. & Congo . . . . . . . U.S.S.R. & Guyana . . . . . . . Congo & Guyana . . . . . . . 162 Please read carefully the short messages on the following three pages. Each message is about a pair of countries and consists of a set of facts taken from the Encyclopedia Britannica. After you have read each message, you will be asked to estimate ppy different the two countries are according lp_ppg_message. Differences between concepts are measured in units, so that the mppg different two concepts are, the more units apart they are from each other. To help you know how big a unit is, assume that Italy £29 England 332.199 units gpgpp. If you think that according £p_ppg message two countries are mppg different from each other than Italy and England, write a number larger than 100. If you think that according £p_ppg message two countries are _lg§§ different from each other than Italy and England, write a number lgpg than 100. If you think that according £p_ppg message the countries are exactly EES.§§EE’ write a zero (0). Remember, the mpg; different the message says two countries are from each other, the higher the number you should write. You may write any number you want. 163 FACTS ABOUT SINGAPORE AND FIJI Fiji and Singapore are remarkably similar countries. Both Singapore and Fiji are small, tropical island countries in the Eastern Hemisphere (Singapore at the tip of the Malay Peninsula, and Fiji in the South Pacific north of New Zealand). Both countries have tropical climates——hot, humid and quite uniform in temperature. Fiji and Singapore are both former British colonies which have attained independence within the past decade. Both countries are relatively stable parliamentary democracies, with multiple political parties and legal systems rooted in the British tradition. Fiji and Singapore are both members of the British Commonwealth of Nations. In each of the two countries the majority of citizens are non— European, but are not racially native to the country. This is due to migration during the colonial period. The majority of Singapore is Chinese, although the native population of the islands is Malay. In Fiji the descendants of emmigrants from India outnumber the native Fijians. So both countries have non—native majorities. Another unusual feature is that both Singapore and Fiji can claim an achievement that is the envy of many other developing coun— tries: successful family planning programs have substantially reduced birth rate in both countries. That should facilitate improved standards of living in the future. (Card 15) Remember: ITALY and ENGLAND are 100 UNITS apart. Dup 1—6 15 7—8 How far apart are Singapore and Fiji according pp the message? 9-12 UNITS APART 164 FACTS ABOUT CONGO AND GUYANA Guyana and Congo are two very different countries. Congo is a former French colony located in Central Africa. France continues to control much of the economy of Congo, and French is the official language of the country. The governments of Congo since 1960 have become increasingly militaristic and authoritarian. The country is ruled by a single political party, and there is no national assembly or parliament. Congo, in addition, is a self—proclaimed Communist state which intends to develop a socialist economy. The citizens of Congo are predominantly the same black peoples who inhabited the region before the arrival of the French. Immigration from abroad during the colonial period was relatively low. Guyana, located in Northeastern South America, is a former British colony, and is a member of the British Commonwealth of Nations. The economy and culture of Guyana are still strongly influenced by the British. English is the official language of the country. Guyana is a parliamentary democracy, with several political parties and a British—based legal system. Guyana has a private enter— prise economy, such that there is only minimal government participation and control. The largest racial group in Guyana is East Indian. The native American Indians are a small minority of the population. (Card 15) Remember: ITALY and ENGLAND are 100 UNITS apart. How far apart are Congo and Guyana according pp the message? 13-16 UNITS APART 165 FACTS ABOUT PORTUGAL AND BRAZIL Portugal and Brazil are closely related nations. Brazil is made up of the former Portuguese colonies in South America. Alone among the nations of South America, Brazil has adopted Portuguese as the official language. Along with the Portuguese language, Brazil has imported much of the culture of Portuga1-—for example, the tradition of a patriarchal family structure. Both countries are over- whelmingly Roman Catholic. Over the years, the bulk of immigrants to Brazil have been from Portugal. During the colonial period the ties between Portugal and Brazil were remarkably strong. In fact, Brazil became the seat of the Por— tuguese monarchy and government for a period of fourteen years during and shortly after the Napoleonic wars. Soon after, Brazil became independent, but the two countries have retained close ties and many similar traits. The two countries have become urbanized and industrialized in roughly parallel fashion; while agriculture in both countries has remained highly traditional and inefficient. At the present moment, as has rather frequently been true in their modern histories, both Brazil and Portugal are ruled by military— dominated governments. (Card 15) Remember: ITALY and ENGLAND are 100 UNITS apart. How far apart are Brazil and Portugal according pp the message? 17-20 UNITS APART 166 Dear Participant, This is the second part of a study of human information processing. The purpose of the study will be explained more fully after the question- naires have been collected. Please follow the instructions carefully. Answer all qpestions. Leaving blanks unfilled may make your questionnaire unusable. Always put down an answer, even if you have to guess. Complete each page before going on to the next. If for any reason you do not wish to participate in this study, just do not fill out the questionnaire. Thank you very much for your cooperation. Sincerely, Robert T. Craig What is your date of birth? PLEASE DO NOT Month Day Year WRITE IN THIS SPACE What is your sex? Male (Card 1) 0 No._________ Female 1 2 3 1 Gp. ______ WV LL 4 5 6 Card Jl_ll_ 7 8 Yr, Sx APPENDIX B PROGRAM TESTLAW 167 08/25/75 6508 FIN V3.0-P300 DPI=1 333 SILAN IE V a) ,0 S V 0 SN IN V JE U S O 0 I 5 IO P0 0 U I IV I D . 0 I E o S V P E I E V0 DD H U A o I S J N I EJ CJ I V I OH I H! nu D ‘0 o In A A o o o.) .2 c N N R N 3 a I.” D. «JI N NoAV. N N N N V. V PD) VOA V N N) 300 3 V 0 V J 5 VJ 3 E AR J AI AS PN A N 3 0 R DJN 3: I 0 3V 3NN R I V 3 J V 3 EI P ..J v V C A .I I o .0 R In DK 0 R CA AA 3 3 I 0 A N 3 A N A 9 SPNSO FU L KS S EOF PI DI VF N E F A 3 N 3 ON 0 SN I EIJEI FN N L V N .VNV (I EIV V 3 VI EID 5 V N V A I 3 VA I 3 1 D U CUICI N > NHE E DOII J1 KKO 0 ) E E I A I R A A FX P NUINP DR I >GN N L IS NNI II EF NF! 8 0 I I N I I N IOI I . ARV LJ IJI I 0.2.5.4 ISI IS I 1.. H3 I05 0 5 ..r I P .2 I D F. I 3‘ U IVVIJ CH H 3) D NVVG P:D LLN I3 I .1 S I V N I E E I :. E NNI 0 5:21.53 ”1.. o F. R? OIII ...D... E I D 3 ...5 33A oI I I P C N I: 3 N DIUA .. IIJI.) .L N HV V GIIH CJ: 5‘" 3 EA 3" VI. I N L SICIS :F C .E NSJ 3N5 .ESORSOOHNCNCEOOO V 00 V R NHIo o IAEE 6 N I V ROE E FOOFEESBFOEOYEIRKNRA PA RIONONCHN .L AoLC L A L0 AI 9 I PNCISA A E .S SEJIJIFD ORCEVJCNRBR P 0:35 35F LDSOVV EDA NDA EA 4 A5 V DD. U SINCEI V r7J IJAOAJ RR VGJ P 35 VI NE N 5A3 33JNVJI.CJI)NI.3.IV I vVVJ P 333.11.... I a . HJI 2‘ 2.....D.VAAVSF3 U VEJI... 90H 90...; J 3 IIIOS:I3:.IDS: D03 I 0 2:1 V «.9263... I IS.) .VJD 3 D3 DI.._33::..I3 .SOV..:.:..I4.IAHJIIJIJV23. ...r. VJIVIIDVIVIIIDIV ISM... I A0 EAS L :0!RVZN=L=LEBHHBESSEA IHSHIISII S: SIAEOVODI:=0=oJ0:0::PJI=N I AAIB 1| 34.1.1 ..1. I 0).)N73,.JIDBNJJHBI...H.¢I~J‘.I3I .. VJ..J‘IJ‘.)H.J 1:. ...JIIIIAJ)... levdu”.... OVIJ J “.)..IJ‘ NCIPRS A JANEDZCJCJCNJNNU DNI:IO=P:IDEPDNEKNESCNRNRV:JJEICIEI JICIOI P IEN N A I AI I No HCR 01. IUN: ..NS: ..D:CI0DAKHHKAH AHA:AENE0D( tVINIVIO oINIHIJ N u: I A RIHSV a "NSP P I I N .. HP... ADYDIDNKRK ’10 Q IJ IHDHBUBVJNIOHOHUHNIJOUNUN I ...NJJ a. 3) I I A A.)I....PJIJ(J: NJVGVJSJ‘I 9P 0Du oozoo «mm: wowwmu ma «ud o Juwdmm zatawu 3 ufiuu caOZu ozaaoa adoahxou am: ouwa: donauzum «Zara ocnooo momooh h¢0.ao noaomm ‘ «ocean Quack aubZDOOO¢ MUZ¢hmuo a>¢¢zwu¢xn 02‘ aqua. atho» no mmwdkzwoaua m>~hdaaxao nomooo oNnonb awn-mo mQJoum choQN Damon omhzaouoc muzuhdaarau umNoh maooo whoomu cab-NN mau.o~ OOUUHow> 4HOZH >0 can ouhZDouod mozahmuo no wodhzmoawa ha ~« 5 . a Na Ithaca wt» w>~mwo Oh mZOukdawhu mo Mumzaz oanoasmwu «smoob.nn ficwonsonw mnwodnnon mNoo:sc@4 lenuhat «ab0w>zuuum no amboomy mw34¢>zmumu sakes! NmNo: monoonl unnon40 msmomoc nag-NNI mm:o:c ~no.mml humane- mocowno akaomo usao::> «sm.~:o hwsomo mwoomw owned. musoom LocomAI 0::oo noooun snmosdu snooswo mwaou:n owoon40 ~m0.:00 onaoo: 3ooowuo som.n Oumoooo accomw NONomso uucowu n-on nmo.o« ”Noomo ome- deoJa anuoos omoom :aoomml snooann‘ :sooa nnhomN ammonN msmoN33 ~m~o~u «amoow -oo~m0 ouNoam mucoN: Nnoonm mwooow s~n.~«n «mood mm:oo~ «wooonu maoooMI o-.c: ocoonoa n«:.~o Nooou: ONauono oumoo~ :owowol wmsonw Nuoomc mcaosc a:o.~m mososn, maco::u ~¢coo~ :owoonl «m~.- mnwoov ~m«.¢mo m t n N a Zeubnaom 4 mu no mwhdzHomooo omauqau .xwuumz mumafivuooo ummumum .ma manna dNM-IU‘OKQO 174 non-ac“ ~nnumm «:5.:I ca nawonuNQI nuconwhuwu wo~hq43xou n~a.m¢ osw.mo aoa.a°« aoa.oad om~.oo -m.om .-zou omgzaouuq mozqhwuo 44mm uo mmo<»zuuamu m>apa43x=o oa¢.«- «~a.. aoc.c no~.~ 4ao.« m:¢.~ . --mobu:> 4¢=DH>Hoz~ >m «on ouhzaouca muzqkmuo no mucpzwoaua an : 4 . h 2 ...00¢ mx» m>~mmo ch mzoah«uu»~ no ammxaz a4~.n°nn- o~«.¢n- nn~.- moo.mo«~ ace.»:«m ~m~.¢n~4 --x~«.¢: mogum>zmo~u no .mhoom. wmzqq>zuuHu ndo.:«- Noo. ::«.- mc°.~« «no.4 no~.«n- «z«»:u mu ukm.n~- o~w.«- kmfl.. ¢-.~H- mno. odo.dn ouzou 4a ono.m«- ~om.- m:a. mn~.4 n:w.~o mmn.n- «mm: nu «“m.o«- 4~:.« can. flec.a sam.o ou~.m uomumo Nu oe~.:~ smh. 93“.- Noo.ou ~c=.o- ;«:.~u ma yuq u «a «$0.0- ego.“ :mo. muo.fi~ on~.o«- m«~..« Ju~aam a" mam.“ «on.m we“. ~n«.oua ~5m.:n “sw. zqzumo x m aoo.~«- oo~.«- -H.- ~wo.:- «ma.o «mc.o Hana » o~¢.;fi Noo.«- ~mo.: nwm.o« no:.m -c.n~u «~o2~ s ¢n~.m~ m~m.«- «no. mmw.a. Esp.m« w-.4« ozqdoa w ~:n.~- :Nw.«- «ma. mkm.m«- o~o.m~- «ao.a~- Jauayxoa m 4«~.o- aan.~- au~. ~a~.¢ Non.- a-.nc «m3 4 ono.n« «mm. «ma. amo.««- asc.an 030.- couxmx n ~m~.~« mm». ~oo.- muo.m noo.:~- emo.a~ «enquzum ~ coo.n«- o~:.« ~««.- nko.mu owo.a« em~.«u mu no muh<2uomooo ou4u4quuu«zu a2. 4HP¢4::=u °o«.m~ na~.sa m~:.am aom.n: , .:-.4~ o-aou aupzaouoa muz«pm~o Jana no muoqkzuoaua w>~».4::=u ~54.” :n~.o moc.4a owm.o« a-.a~ qunhum‘. 4<3c~>HQZH >m «on owhzaoood mqurmHa ho woqumuawm «« o . s o Na ..Iwoou m1... u>~¢mo o.— mzcuhaaMhM mo «mmxaz oo~.n~n~« noaooomfl ammome¢~ a~0.coa~m ooh-Nana: chHwqu mahow>zmu~w kc ”whooo. mm3J<>zuuuu m:o.m~ can um}. “swan“! agouno @~:.0m! 12d>30 n-2wu c~o.on mawéol nnmoau ~c0.omo ouzou ”alga! cum-nun mkant nmn .ms o-.mo «mm: m~a.~m «do-kn . ammuomn th‘mJ so an: wowuau s«:.«mo mmwooao och-om- woo 4va Juarwmu mu 0.: u wha. N10.~n ma~3l 0.;ch cur/om." Jdemm «...wJHH Jaclwno mun-N omcouao waowo Zqzmmo x snmumn mo3.~o mks-am onuf—«a 5,3300 :Inu mumom: mm~ .N mmcun omafim «2. com- «we: «woca unnowdo ~:~.~nl ~::o41 aaofiw oxadon «7%.... me .mo nmo.e«I ncwoo~l www.mn uuoa -oon1 s-osmo nsuéa Nm:.«ma chofio «w: mason»: on:.n~ NNNSN wa.:I’ om4 .o 0”:me cooooau Nnooma oueéo «o:.n« 33.9.: conqoz~m nnaowno 0:05“ «Bu-m» «3.3. «mm AK: «:55 m 1 n N a 20 uh: law 445 oz N hum m.— kc mmhuzuozuou ow4~41~h<43230 namaho wn¢.:m .auou omhzaouud Muzawmuo uqux no wmo~p Jmoz~ >m «on omkzzouoq mmzatho uc woqhzwummn cm:.«u« nub-Ned Qwsawud :mo.~au "$5.00 cac.ao« cocoanu :NM'OO no~.do . coo. cum. on».« c o a nu a6~¢¢mo«o omN- ownaadau mNNonJG m~0.n mount on:.«« sow-no mowoqa one. ~4oou «ado- msmo:| wuwo mNmoo onuuuv m:~.mt sno. mwo. unncwwc mno.e«u mmo.l o»m.~v $04.5uo o«m.a~u n~«.n mum's! nwmowl «No.5: Nnc. ::«ov aws.¢n wwn.n Mna.o o::.a«0 nm4.n«I noo.nl 35o. onNon- omeoww «00.nl «Nu. ua¢onl Ascend mmo.m~ omens aeooa mgr-m mom.~« 64“.: :nm.:0 o-.««t o:«.«o mmaon ~u0.m0 wam.:« ”no.0: «ma. oo«.a~ mm~.«l non.c awn. :cn.n~l :Joowl :a nu Na «d zouhbaom dezoz dom moqam 4<20umzmrnouh432 Quupm: q 2H wwqmawm<> ma mmmxaz h a« Ithaca wzk w>umuo ch monhqamhu no N www.c«n4 ch.nm¢m I|x-h¢z «Chom>2uoum no .mhooa. mw34<>2moww cow-Au csocwal 54°omo ~on.o~ mom-«No omooaa Numuau hfio.ono mom.~l smmccwo c~4.~« am~.on mom-cw sco.¢ omn.o~n mum-ma Jamawl c:n.mo hohouwu mmm.~«l «mm. . anm.n a~:.ni on:.~ :oncuan hmo.c~I Nsmoo aNa.~I hmwo«n ho:.«l 9a 0 no muh42~omoou Omanqno Awwacfiuaoov ¢Z¢>Du mu oozoo :« «mm: M« wuuumu Nd mm muq u uu 4H~3u mu oozou cu «mm: ma uomumo Na my and u «« JHqum ca zaxqmu : o ufimu m «HDZN n ozagoa w Jacobean m «m: : onuxm: m aoaU:<42t30 QJN.«¢ «mnouc omo.oo mnuuns ska-mo . mum-mm o«m.um .blmou app—7.30004 mozvnkwma 1.4mm &0 mqumeomma m>KFuJDLDU mmm.m mmn.o na-~ semis ~u«.m« mm .mu mum..,m . Il,uo»um> JHOZH >m won «MpZDoooq MozihmHD um. w0q5.wo.nun_ mam.cm«h monoo-au Numimomna mwr.moar~ mm~.:n«:~ m:m.mm~«: mmm.mum@m I XHth; mohow>2mcum no .m»com. mw34u>2mun moo.:l Paw-'5! Nona: mmmonu :Nn.o~| Nw¢.1ml .ow.~rl 42q>3u mun nmoosNI 4NN.m m4...m«l cavia «yam-RI «n~.mwl ouzou J“ N4n¢mu :Amom maeoa m««.rm| mn:.v.n Tile: uwm: n.“ nuk.mm oeu.u: «mo-m «ms.,.m mo~.a«l marlin momumo Nu ownimm c3u.ml me.u«o aunt—NI nqm.’nl mrm..mci mu w”; o .: unn.MNI MmmJ. mmaém «awful «:m.m~| «1m... JH~qnm on an.gnl mom.c~| norémn amo.:~ come Na .mo Zqzw~o 2 o 551.: mrm.mno «N...~ :ca.om M.N:.3I :mmeNI Hfiuk m wags»: ~n4.mm ~4r.4~| Ant-ma www.ma arm.mol «:3; n au~.a«u mmmomal nanvu :~«.mm meal; m¢m.aw ardaoa w N¢«.ual Moo.«u sNoAfu www.mm ”52;: mwn.u ..qunhuom m 4.3.9 wand-nun. mam.o~u mmo.amn Humiynn. mos-on ...Mfi 0. mNJ.JI waniw @m¢.m: owuooal mchnl 1N4.” oumet n ”Nutnu «amoral New. moment ns....mm www.mcl uOAqmsz N amine: Amuoul nmw.- «mnammn awaié Ncm.:nl <2qu « h o m 3 M N a cept—2mm“ whawuzou meqpm o» nw»<4m:qu» onpaqom « hum uhaqfirnu «v2.nm oko.co nun-mo." Una-mo umo.mo - mmN.mm v.3.mm ..Iyou cwpznoou’u moqumHé qum ma nuqunfiouwa Asquqfirbu mom-:0 «mm-«I :Nn. :m«.« «mm.a wmn.~ uI~.o_rum> 4HQZH >m men nupzaoouu. uuzafiwuo no wadhrfioowm cum.:macl NAOomenl :9“sz now. Nm:.mo~N :om.mncn mwm.n:.: IGXHMFSL makom>zuomm no .wwoomv mm34q>zmumw wan.mul «Levmdl nanoma um«.~l nmm.omu <2<>3o ma muu.ma ...m.«~l «cr.uul www.ml «mm.mn 00200 in @nm.m4| NJu-mal Mmu.a oc:.T. $3.4: mam: Ma umu.e Nam.4«| nnm.m «bx.» 05w.“ “Ummmu Nu NNNJ. urn-om :mc.c| ..n ..QI «:«..nu mm mu: 0 «a .Q/J 4m... nonfual Jaw.mw nsu.m~1 «$11; Jqumm o« l omo.N.—o m¢4.Nt 0.35;! minimal «mm.m zqzmmo x 0 nm:.-n umofwal ~59...- mwu.m 4.‘ .0 :4“. o Nrn.o«0 NNJ'oa Nam-«a xn:.m| mmm.«ml mu no mm.:.2mowcoo 0.3:qu Awmsafluaouv .NN manmy 180 mmo.owma~« uuth coronm chcwn , mam-mm mam.sn Jeu.cn nao.uo Nmm.m: ‘ m£m.o~ Ilwou nm~znouu< muqumuo .>N<2Hoqxu oz< Jammy tho» no mmchZMQNMA m>wpa43rau nw4ouw NNN.~c oa4.an on:.mh 4an.mm anumm www.mJ msn.mN tomou owhzaooofl mQthwHo 44mm ma mmoxhzmuwma m>upq43t3u muwp: ~«m.m mn0.m sau.s N:o.m . amn.4« m:m.~« mum.mu namornm> JqDoH>HozH >0 mom nwpzaouod muzdhmHo no mozwomm mo Amhoomv m4344>zmoum wmwanI mmmohm ens-N st.a~ nmJ.nJu ¢:~.uul nmm.«:o rwm.nsu <24>30 ~mm.k: o:o. nm4o@«v mun.nl mecca- Nam-mun mmmcu www.mnl oozou h:n.r~| «mm-«I mum.aau oo«.~«I omu.~3 amm.« ~r@.«@ gum.¢: umm: maw.c« unwoaul :o¢.ml unromm nmauy: «n«.mml «wu.~ mow-u wumwuu Mc~.cml Nan.om| 01c.mm maa.oal Mooool hum.umt «mn.«w| wmm.:~l mm qu o Ammumal No«.n~ umo.:«l ohfl.n nnm.:1 www.mt :mn..~| amm.fia JHNqnm Lao.am sn:.~NI L u.m: na‘.o« nmm.mml mmH.J Mam-mm» «25.x: ~quwc 1 num.m :m«.o« wok-am aum.mn roe.» mom.mm mmo.mmt mwn.ona HfiHu «Mu.:~l m1“.ama Nm«.rml ckm.c: who-o nuc.m N¢N.m« 12¢.-| «HozH :suomu now.:u mmH.«N mmc.: mma.wl :V:.Unl “~J.“m nu .n: nz<40Q no~.«~l ~0:.n gu:.nn Omu.«o rom.mo «NH.~«| mmm.unc «mn.n« J m« no wwquHcyoou Omauqdu .wHouucmo mummodoo magnum ou kumHmEMHH xwuumz mumafluuooo ummuumom umuMuouaD .mm manmy ma CAN": Hv‘flv‘d «NMJMONOU‘ 181 mm@.¢NMu~« moan; m>thizau ooa.ou«. Has-«an «mm.~n: umm.~3 {we-.2: awaoncu rrm.:\ nuaou omhzzoon; muzhruo a>zku43rau sow-«c Dwain! can. nos. ouk.u om4.m Knew.» Inackuw> anoH>HozH >m you emhzzouoq uozcummn no nonhzwowma mm4.noamt ohcaogumu nmN. Numomsmu mnecmmw .3m.~an: dum.mmmm ncxumhqt mohuu>zuomm no .m_.ocn.: mm34q>2mo~u "34-h hwacm 3.3.! onn.4« ouu...‘ mo:.~« mom...‘ numom eroN.“ Nauol o4~.m onn.«l mm~.mv ”Knish uo~.N~ NMU.MI ms“. -J.«H muc.u«a «usual m:~.- «Mm... nus-«I woo. Nomim nu....m~l enm.: viz.le mmmorl Nau.m.u o u.l «mu.l madam»: :mm.m| Juniwuc $40.“- mum-mun Jamil kao.nn nowoml mn~.ma 23.54 mac-um New-c! neg-I nun.~ .55.?" :~«.r~ aqmfia amm.~ mmooJ mwu.| mamnro Neiuaa .30.¢NI onJJN 09“! a¢u.~v m4“. «:n.t ¢m:.n~ «34.9: ADA.N nu,u.n~v 0,—4.5! "cm. nom.| r«:.o FLO-amt 7.3.11 so:.ml «ow-kw new: rmcuod cqnuc 3%. 44:2: (whion: 54;; ~51: mne.«l mic-Nat «mo.»u~ nrm..u« mN:.mN no... LNM.I :nu.mn nannmfi 3.3.3! 41.".umo «mm-Mal Dido- mom. soc-NM Ncc.ml 2.5... movin 4w:.v macoo mnm. @ro.u«n Jmoomi m::.« mam.o ma ..a n« N." «a 3 m Gang—2mm“ whawuzou wJoqbw o.— ..m»«..wr<~r— Zeupzqom N bum cp¢o mom moanw 4<20~mzurmlo43x UHF—mt a an wwqmaHmn; ma mo mmhdzhoyooo OMJHJqu AwmnaquOUV <:<>:u m« oozou :« «mm: nu momuwu Na mm and o «« 4m~qmn ca Zazxmo 1 m Hawk o «no.2 n .IHJCQ a 44ozpnoa m «m: J omem: m manqqum N «zuzu « .mm waan 182 oom.n~t "doquuom mumwocoo wanmum .xfinumz wumaflvuooo umwuumom n:w.o~ omno:~. 005.40 00¢.ua u:n.ml on .u! mMN.mI «mm.a| ow:.JN www.m«c M1m.«| Nmm.«l an0.m MNacu Mm~.mau c4m.sul ndu.~ MON.¢I mmm.uu mom.“ 59:.nnl «ms.mu 0:m.m Nru.ual «Jo.mNI uc;.u Nod.md Mmc.v ham-an nwm.mw omn.~ cmv.aa| m4m.m .gm. me-n www.4N Nmn.mo sou. $30.¢~| @no.~N 50¢.NN. Nmo.u| nms.l mn«.| O«M.Gul :nm.« Na «a u N wwflrJZ mnDu mu oozno :« ¢mm3 nu momwuo Nu m« tun u «a JHNqum cu :aan0 3 o kum o umcxu s (:440¢ m 4<¢nhwrn m an: : Ouwat n womcoznm N «guru « qu>Du mu 00:00 4« mum: nu woumoo Nu mm and «« JHqum an 23.x u 2 w afium n «HOTH N dzqqna O Jqorwaom m an: 1 Oume: n aoaquzww ~ azuzu « .qN oHAMH \ . . .r 7. N4. 4 I . .,. . 9 . W . Luv .. a? q ..py‘yluliviir. nuts. I v- . ._ . . A _F—m_;__ ( h— _——~__ .__.— __ __ .__ _-_ __ ___._ __ ______ _ ___ .__ _ __ __ ..au. -.‘- ., "IMfifflfiflififlfififlfiiflflyflfifiiiES