E r.-«w-s~~.-.~u..-.-. v.-.“ CONCEPTS 0F SAINTHDOD IN T HE NOVELS 0F ALBERT GAMUS AND GRAHAM GREENE Thesis for the Degree of Ph.'D. ’ MICHIGAN STATE UNIVERSITY BARBARA GUSDORF 1963 fl“ 0 THESIS 0-169 LIBRARY f Michigan State University \\\\\\\\\\ \\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\\| “\3 1293 10515 4912 v rrrr A « This is to certify that the thesis entitled ‘ f’ CCwnC‘B'f'tS m. .5"i.1_11‘.:}"1"><3<‘? .111 tho Iinvwls Cf Alhwrt Cmur: find airtimm (ftp-Arum:- presented by has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements. for TR} .TT. . CHTI‘I‘WTJYVW‘Tz'TL ___i__'_degree m I ~ " ' -. I. )l I J'I.‘:€tl-11_"r"-_‘ ‘ . . t P ~_. fimdé K 7’24, Major professor @777] .7, I €43 Date .mm t‘il-fiitiflmlz.. n; . um aflflnMLQA-—H ‘ . l ‘. ABSTRACT CONCEPTS OF SAJNTHOOD IN THE NOVELS OF ALBERT CAMUS AND GRAHAM GREENE by Barbara Gusdorf The purpose of this study is to compare the treatznent of saint- hood by Albert Camus and Graham Greene, two authors of thoroughly divergent views and backgrounds. Camus is, for all practical pur- poses, an atheist, Greene is a Catholic; Camus is a Franco-Algerian of proletarian background, while Greene is a middle-class Englishman. Each is, however, equally concerned with the problem of Justice on both the metaphysical and physical planes. Each knows that on the lat- ter plane the elements which have brought our world to near disaster are cruelty, envy, greed, and what Freud called the death instinct. Additionally, because both authors feel they have a responsibility to mankind, they both serve as a thorn in the side of complacency, believ- ing it is their duty to alert those who accept social custom, or religious and political dogma, blindly. In the section called "Albert Camus: The Temptation Toward Sainthood," Camus seeks to provide men with "styles" for a viable way of life in the face of the absurd. This "absurd" is the tension created between man and a hostile universe. Therefore Camus’ search is for positive ways of living without losing consciousness of "the absurd" and without yielding to any of its negations. In order to arrive at such a style, he presents human types in their careers. The priest, the judge, the anarchist, the Malraux-type hero, the doctor, and the municipal Barbara Gusdorf clerk are considered along with Jean Tarrou, the saint laique of his novel, 1:2} Peste. In the section "Graham Greene: The Journey Toward Sainthood," Greene is shown presenting his hierarchy of values through the human types he depicts. His failures - the maimed and warped, the complacent, the Opportunists, the perverse, and the innocent, are Opposed to his positive characters who include his probable saints. Major Scobie of The Heart o_f t_l_1_e_: Matter and the nameless Mexican priest of The Power and 1113 Glory are considered in this study as pos- sibilities for sainthood in an era whose interest in sanctity is directed toward social commitment rather than individual salvation. Certain values, as well as types, emerge as positive in the views of both authors. Because guilt emerges from the knowledge of evil, it can become a positive factor; innocence, on the other hand, is nearly always suspect. Where innocence is primarily ignorance of evil, guilt, resulting from awareness of another's pain, promotes such val- ues as compassion, responsibility, and solidarity. Because evil exists in both the worlds of Greene and of Camus, sin is present in the view of both the Catholic and the non-believer. In Greene's world, failure to live by what are considered God's wishes for men constitutes sin; in Camus' world, sin is the failure to live within the terms of the lucid- ity and measure demanded by the absurd. In writing on sainthood from two different points of view, the two authors disclose similarities. Their saints are, for instance, absolu- tists in their demands for purity within themselves, a quality which they find impossible to maintain in the world of human affairs. Intheir failure to remain pure, although involved, they long for peace and VI \.1 1' J. " Th“ :5 :0 Barbara Gusdorf passivity. As both peace and purity are impossibilities in life, they long for death. In each case their deaths, whether from suicide, dis- ease, or the bullets of executioners, are seen as self-willed. The greatest dissimilarity among these potential saints is the greater renun- ciation of ego in Greene's saints. Although both Scobie and the Mexican priest have been taught that they must think primarily of their own souls, each willingly sacrifices his eternal peace for another's salva- tion. Tarrou, Camus' aspiring saint, on the other hand, seeks annihi- lation and non-involvement after the cessation of the plague, while Greene's saints remain involved up until the last moment of their lives. Moreover, Major Scobie's suicide is not an act of egotism. He hopes, in dying, to cease hurting God and those he loves. He regards his death not as an escape from frustration but as the beginning of an eter- nity of further pain. Because the problem of justice on the supernatural level will always remain a mystery to Greene, his potential saints are unortho- dox, achieving their ends by sinning against the tenets of their Church. Yet because justice in Camus' view must always remain a question of limits — of lucid awareness of the human condition and of adherence to human possibilities — it is Tarrou who has failed rather than Greene's saints. Tarrou is a failure because in capitulating to death he sins M against the only certainty in his world which is his life. In his asPira- tions for absolutes — those of purity and peace — and in his temptation toward sainthood, which is his desire to surpass the human, he has sinned against lucidity and measure. It is not surprising, then, that Camus rejects his aspiring saint, ‘ (“it Barbara Gusdorf preferring instead his heroes of "the absurd" who are in turn closer to Greene's potential saints in their knowledge that they must live in order to prolong their involvement in the never-ending struggle between what is human and what is anti-human. CONCEPTS OF SAINTHOOD IN THE NOVELS OF ALBERT CAMUS AND GRAHAM GREENE by .l I [I‘b’i‘ Barbarai Gusdorf A THESIS Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Comparative Literature June 1968 tr. ‘2" 7 1' C0pyright by Barbara Gusdorf 1968 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I wish to acknowledge a debt of gratitude to the English Depart- ment of the College of General Studies of the University of Puerto Rico and particularly to Mrs. Esther Cressey de Ma’rquez who very patiently typed the first two drafts of this dissertation. I am especially indebted to Dr. Russel B. Nye, the chairman of my committee, and to the two other members of the committee, Dr. Charles D. Blend and Professor A. J. M. Smith. I would also like to thank Mrs. Hally Wood Stephenson, who typed and gave her technical knowledge to the final draft of this dissertation. ii TABLE OF CONTENTS mTRODUCTION O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O O 1 BOOK ONE ALBERT CAMUS: THE TEMPTATION TOWARD SAINTHOOD PART I Désir de Durer, Destin de Mourir . . . . . . . 12 PART StylesdeVie.................20 II PART III LaGénération d'Entre-Deux-Guerres. . . . . . 26 IV V PART The Saint's Progress . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34 PART Sain ou Saint . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 PART VI Creation Corrected . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53 PART VII Oran -— Entre Oui et Non . . . . . . . . . . . 73 PART VIII Tarrou on Trial . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 81 PART D{ Santé ou Sainteté . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 101 BOOK TWO GRAHAM GREENE: THE JOURNEY TOWARD SAINTHOOD PART I The Map: Bits andPieces. . . . . . . . . . . 114 PART II The Greene World . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 120 PART III Some Greenelanders . . . . . . . . . . . . . 139 PART IV Beyond the Greene Baize Door . . . . . . . . . 160 PART V Who Would Be a Father? . . . . . . . . . . . 169 PART VI The Coast . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 180 PART VII Not POppy, nor Mandragora . . . . . . . . . . 186 PART VIII The Pityandthe Terror. . . . . . . . . . . . 198 PART IX ForNaughtDidIinHate . . . . . . . . . . . 209 iii iv PART X The Map: New Pieces Coming into Place I Wonder . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 218 II Faith . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226 CONCLUSION . . .' . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 233 A LIST OF WORKS CITED . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 251 :? ~- INTRODUC TION The purpose of this study, "Concepts of Sainthood in the Novels of Albert Camus and Graham Greene," is to discover the differences and similarities existing in two apparently Opposing views of sainthood. Such a study should consist principally of two factors: the common basis for their interest in sainthood, and how these authors differ and, oddly enough, often coincide, in the area of their chosen subject. There are, first of all, marked contrasts in the backgrounds of Camus and Greene. Camus, for instance, who was born of illiterate parents,1 grew up in Belcourt, an Algerian slum p0pu1ated by EurOpeans and non-EurOpeans of diverse nationalities, races, and religions. Graham Greene, on the other hand, whose father was headmaster of Berkhamsted, a boys’ school near London, comes from an English back- ground which was both middle-class and homogeneous. While the poverty suffered by Camus was greatly offset by the sea, sunlight, and beaches of Algeria, Greene's greater economic security was cancelled by child- hood fears, adolescent boredom, and a dull climate. In respect to their religious backgrounds, Camus, who was born into a predominantly Catholic background, early became a non-believer, or, as Henri Peyre prefers to put it, a pagan.z Greene, however, was 1Although Camus' parents are often referred to as illiterate, the father taught himself to read when he was over twenty; the mother, who was deaf, remained illiterate and spoke with an impediment (see Germaine Bre’e, Camus (New York, 1964) 15). 2"Camus the Pagan," Yale French Studies, xxv (Spring 1960). 20-25. \ . x 4 I x ‘. . < o c a - ( T3133? ,. '05 D‘ out. an fl...” .34.. O. n ET 5 ';.- A "vs a. g“: ‘ '..L.I converted from Anglo- to Roman Catholicism at the age Of twenty-two, and has written from, or even against, this vieWpoint ever since. Yet despite the different social and religious backgrounds of these authors, they share two attitudes in common, their metaphysical and social con- cerns. Although each has been referred to as Pascalian, Jansenist, Cal- vinist, Augustinian, Manichean, Pelagian, and even existentialist,3it is more accurate to claim that both write within a wider trend — the gen- eral background Of terror and anxiety— a trend which, in the present century includes Kafka, Conrad, and James,4along with Melville and Dostoevsky and others from the past century. Although the problem of 3Germaine Brée writes on Camus' doubtful existentialist position: "If we think of a writer whose essential effort is directed toward eluci- dating his Own experience through an effort Of his intelligence as a 'philosOpher' then Camus most certainly is a philosOpher, but nothing could be more erroneous than to consider him an 'existentialist' writer. Camus, himself, was more explicit on this point; his work supports his Opinion; and his controversy with Sartre when L'Homme révolté was published emphasized the difference in the orientation of their thought. 'I have little liking for the too famous existential philOSOphy, and, to speak frankly, I think its conclusions are false,’ he wrote in 1945, a point Of view he never altered" (Camus, 9-10). 4Greene maintains, "with the death of James the religious sense was lost to the English novel, and with the religious sense went the sense of the importance of the human act" (Francois Mauriac," 69). He lauds James's sense of supernatural evil. In "Henry James: The Religious Aspect," he writes: "It is tempting to reinforce this point -- James's belief in supernatural evil — with [he Turn of th_e Screw. Here in the two evil spirits - Peter Quint, the dead valet, with his gin- ger hair and his little whiskers and his air of an actor and 'his white face of damnation,‘ and Miss Jessel 'dark as midnight in her black dress, her haggard beauty and her unutterable woe' - is the explicit breath of hell. They declare themselves. . . with everything but voice, to be suf- fering the torments Of the damned. . ." (37-38). Both citations are from Greene's collection Of essays, The Lost Childhood (New York, 1962). evil is radical in each, Greene, in aligning himself with such men, is showing himself in Opposition to the ”liberal, Optimistic view Of the world nurtured by the Enlightenment which was brought to fruition in the 19th century vision of man'sipredicament as due to economic causes (Marx) or to psychological ones (Freud)."5 Camus, although he has not forgotten his early training in philosoPhy (especially Plotinus, St. Augustine, and their relation to evil), embraces rather than censors the classical or neO-classical heritage. In fact, Camus speaks Often of his "Greek" or "Mediterranean" background. Therefore Camus Opts for the rational approach, Greene for the irrational: Greene that man may not prevail; Camus that in a sense he must prevail. Sharing a sense Of terror and dread, both Greene and Camus adhere to a view of life that many would consider pessimistic. But the critics Kenneth Allott and Miriam Farris assure their readers that ”the pessimistic view Of life is in the long run simply an adult view. Youth, physical well-being, success may temporarily blunt the sharpness Of our perception of its truth, but the optimism dependent on these acci- dents is always precarious. Job, Aeschylus, Dante, Pascal -— the cre- ative artist or thinker —- is not a Cheeryble Brother."6 While both Camus and Greene are in agreement as far as meta- physical anxiety is concerned (although they differ in their answers to the problem), they are even closer in regard to the temporal 5"Introduction," Graham Greene: Some Critical Considerations, ed. Robert 0. Evans (Lexington, Ky., 1963), xiv. 6The Art of Graham Greene (New York, 1963), 17. 4 manifestations of evil in their times. A citation from Greene expresses both views: Errol Flynn, or it may have been Tyrone Power (I don't know how to distinguish them in tights), swung on rOpes and leaped from balconies . . . . rescued a girl and killed his enemy and led a charmed life. It was what they call a film for boys, but the sight of Oedipus emerging with his bleeding eyeballs from the palace at Thebes would surely give better training for life today. 7 In regard to the prevalence Of evil in contemporary life, Morton Dauwven Zabel states "crime has gone beyond Addison's ‘chink in the armor' of civilized society; it has become the symptom Of a radical 1e 8ion in the stamina of humanity,"8 an idea that Greene already devel- Oped in his The Ministry of Fear: "You remember St. Clement's — the bells of St. Clement's. They've smashed that —- St. James', Picadilly, the Burling- ton Arcade, Garland's Hotel, where we stayed for the panto- mime, Maples, and John Lewis. It sounds like a thriller, doesn't it, but the thrillers are like life . . . . You used to laugh at the books Miss Savage read -- about spies and mur- ders, and violence, and wild motor-car chases, but, dear, that‘s real life: it's what we've all made of the world since you died. I'm your little Arthur who wouldn‘t hurt a beetle and I’m a murderer too. The world has been remade by William Le Queux."9 In speaking specifically for Greene, Nathan A. Scott, Jr. writes: He has used violence and melodrama as instruments for awakening his age out of its lethargies, for destroying its specious securities and revealing the underlying nightmare and tragedy. He has wanted to "prohibit sharply the \ 7The Quiet American (New York, 1957), 176. 0. 8"Graham Greene," Forms of Modern Fiction, ed. William Van Canor (Minneapolis, 1948), 289'." 9London, 1943, 71-72. rehearsed response" to resurrect the heart through terror and to exhibit the world itself in all its degradation, as a country wherein man‘s spiritual nature is to be rediscov- ered.l Camus has referred to this century as "1e siecle de la peur," and the critic Nicola Chiaromonte gives the gist of Camus' Columbia Uni- versity speech, in which Camus enumerates the specific problems of the times: We were born at the beginning of the First World War. As adolescents we had the crisis Of 1929; at twenty, Hitler. Then came the EthiOpian War, the Civil War in Spain, and Munich. These were the foundations of our education. Next came the Second World War, the defeat, and Hitler in our homes and cities. Born and bred in such a world, what did we believe in? Nothing. Nothing except the obstinate nega- tion in which we were forced to close ourselves from the beginning. The world in which we were called to exist was an absurd world, and there was no other in which we could take refuge. The world of culture was beautiful but it was not real. And when we found ourselves face to face with Hitler's terror, in what values could we take comfort, what values could we Oppose to negation? In none. If the prob- lem had been the bankruptcy Of a political ideology or a sys- tem Of government, it would have been simple enough. But what had happened came from the very root Of man and society. There was no doubt about this, and it was con— firmed day after day, not so much by the behavior of the criminals but by that of the average man. The facts showed that men deserved what was happening to them. Their way of life had so little value; and the violence of the Hitlerian negation was in itself logical. But it was unbearable and we fought i_t[italics added].11 _ _ _ Starting from nothing and questioning that negation, Camus has realized that "nous portons tous en nous nos bagnes, nos crimes et nos ravages. 10"Graham Greene: Christian Tragedian," Graham Greene: Some Critical Considerations, ed. Robert 0. Evans (Lexington, Ky. , 1963), 26. 11"Albert Camus: In Memoriam," Albert Camus: A Collection c_1_f gitical Essay_s, ed. Germaine Brée (Englewood Cliffs, N.- J.', 1967), 14-15. 6 Mais notre tache n'est pas de les déchatner a travers le monde; elle est Mt de les combattre en nous-marnes et dans les autres."12 r M Because Greene and Camus have dedicated themselves to fighting nihilism wherever it becomes manifest, it is necessary to mention some of the concepts that are to be included under this heading. Nihilism or nothing (112111) was represented in its most radical form, for Camus, in death. Yet generally speaking, and for the purpose of this study, nihil- ism includes any 3 ort of evil -—- that is, any impulse, action, or atti— tude — capable of mutilating men or draining their lives of significance. Nihilism, it can be said, falls into two categories, philosophical and political nihilism. The former is an attitude of despair promoted to a value or a way of life. Such despair, when it leads to an "All is per- mitted" policy, negates such values as love, honor, truth, and the pur— suit Of happiness, and encourages violence and injustice. When nihil- ism becomes political, it embraces totalitarianism and bureaucratic systems which deny the rights of individuals by systematizing disorder, encouraging cant and falsehood, and practicing the inversion of good and evil. By making a principle of the end justifying the means, living men are sacrificed to distant goals or ideals. While Camus is often referred to as a conscience of his time —- he received the Nobel Prize in 1957 in recognition for the "clear-sighted earnestness" with which he had illuminated the problems of the human conscience of our time"— Greene, who has up to this point received less 12L'Homme révolté (Paris, 1951), 361. credit for this aspect of his thinking, will undoubtedly accrue more recognition as time goes by. It is the action of conscience directed towards the problems of one's time which is the source Of the contemporary interest in saint- hood. It is to this end that Mauriac, Bernanos, Silone, Updike, even Simenon, in addition to Camus and Greene, have treated sainthood as a literary theme. The contemporary saint, as well as the absurd hero, offers the secular society of today a reconsideration of values. Of this Henri Peyre writes: . . . the acclaim poured out to Camus, to Dr. Schweitzer or to Gandhi, or to POpe John (for they are comparable) testi- fied to the deep thirst for moral heroism among our con- temporaries and to our readiness to be guided by saints, even by picaresque ones, in an age Of creative discontent. l3 Peyre's reference to the contemporary creative discontent should be understood not so much in terms of the literary artist's dis- satisfaction with matters Of style and expression (although there is the continuous need for new myths and images) but as a discontent which is creative in the sense that it is positive or fructifying, leading us out Of what John Cruickshank refers to as the "breakdown of the settled established intellectual and moral order which the literature Of this century has registered."14 In the Twentieth Century Engclopedia (if Catholicism, Jacques l3Modern Literature / The Literature 9f France (Englewood Cliffs, N. J., 1966), 196. 14"lntrodnction," The Novelist 2L3 Philosopher: Studies in French Fiction 1935-1260 (London, 1962), ix. \l 1" L} -p—. be. at.» m- ’1 8 Douillet asks the question, "What is a saint?” In attempting an answer he writes that in one sense the answer is: "A saint is a person now dead, whom the Church allows to be publicly venerated."15 In Saints £33 Now, edited by Clare Boothe Luce, Mrs. Luce hazards a more extensive defi- nition: What is a Saint? To speak in a dictionary manner, a Saint — with a capital "S" -— is one Of those persons recognized by the Church as having, by holiness of life and heroic virtue, attained a highplace in heaven, and as being therefore entitled to the veneration Of the faithful, fit to serve them as a spiritual model and able to intercede for them in the courts of God. The men and women thus recognized as Saints do not, Of course, include all the holy, or exhaust all the possibilities Of holiness. But of them we are certain.1 Jacques Douillet and Mrs. Luce agree that the saints' recovery Of Christ's virtues is always fractional. Both authors mention aspects of sainthood which apply at times most particularly to either Greene's somewhat unorthodox saints or to Camus' completely unorthodox saint. Jacques DOuillet, for instance, mentions absolutism, a quality which belongs, however, to most saints: "Given their genius," he writes, "they were incapable of evading issues, Of half-measures, of playing at two tables at once" (58); "they did not try to efface what was peculiar, but rather emphasized it" (105). What Jacques Douillet writes concerning the unified love of the 15What i_s_ _a_ Saint? volume XLVI of the Twentieth Century Encyclo- pedia 9f Catholicism, ed. Henry Daniel-R0ps (New York, 1958), 84. All subsequent references to this volume will be given in the text immedi- ately following the quotation. 16Saints f2; Now (New York, 1952), 1. All subsequent references will be given in the text immediately following the quotation. ”L. 35.. ‘7'“ 9 saints applies particularly to Greene's saints: "The saints' love for God does not prevent them from loving all around them; but it is so intense that these other loves are not only subordinate to it, they are wrapped up and permeated by it. They do in truth love 'in God' " (56). Each writes Of the saints as sinners - an aspect which relates them tO both Greene's and Camus' saints. "The very meaning Of the lives of the Saints for us," Mrs. Luce explains, "lies in the fact that they were sinners like ourselves trying like ourselves to combat sin. The only difference between them and us is that they kept on trying; pre- cisely because they believed that the revision and editing of sinner-into- saint is not done by man's pen but by God’s grace" (3). Although the aspirations of some saints appear remote today (par- ticularly the monasticism of the desert), those monks were fleeing from the abominations of their world no more than is Camus' contem- porary saint. It is the flight that Camus condemns. His saint in fleeing from guilt, enters as they did, a spiritual desert as well, for his saint knows too well, as did Saint Paul, that "guilt makes no more claim on a man who is dead." Heroic virtue is what is usually needed to distinguish the saint from the average man. Writing Of the heroism Of the saints, Jacques Douillet recounts that "the hero is tenacious; he does not count the cost Of attaining his goal; he will wear himself out doing it, and his strength seems more than a man's" (58). But along with heroism goes the renun- ciation Of ego. The martyrs have usually found their strength in the consciousness of their responsibility to their brethren: the idea of 10 failing those for whom they struggle is more abhorrent than suffering or death. Both of Greene's saints are heroic in their actions, but one par- ticularly practices the heroism Of those saints not called to the glory of martyrdom. However, his heroism equals that Of those who give their lives all at once, proving, as did St. The’rése of Lisieux, that the "little way Of the Cross, is not the way of the little cross." Jacques Douillet elaborates this idea Of "pinprick martyrdom" or the "widow's mite" as it has existed among the unknown. For there are millions Of holy men and women, some Of them perhaps greater in the eyes of God than canonized saints, who are unknown because they lived in Obscurity or because their inward holiness was never recognized by their fellows. Their hiddenness serves to enhance their worth before God. . . (118) Camus' potential saint is Jean Tarrou in his novel If Peste. Greene's potential saints are the anonymous Mexican priest in The Power and the Glory, Major Henry Scobie in The Heart if th__e Matter, and Sarah Miles in 'I_‘_h_e End O_f the A__f_f_ai_1;. Only the first two of Greene's aspiring saints will be considered in this study, for the inter- est in sainthood today is predominantly an interest in commitment, involvement, or engagement in the community. Sarah Miles' approach to sanctity is closer to the extreme individual approach Of Camus' absurd hero and stranger, Meursault. The content of this study will reveal the possibilities of a new coherence as they are presented by Graham Greene and Albert Camus in their considerations Of sainthood and will show how, in their searches II 11 for coherence, Camus' saint fails, while Greene's saints are the heroes of the hour . BOOK ONE ALBERT CAMUS: THE TEMPTATION TOWARD SAINTHOOD PART I DESIR DE DURER, DESTIN DE MOURIR Of Albert Camus it has been written: "In a true sense, he was constantly attempting to bring into the clearing of rationality more and more territory, territory which was constantly threatening to step back into the jungles Of chaos and mindlessness. In this he joined the Greeks. What is the Odyssey after all but an attempt to clear out of chaos a territory Of reason where the human community could exist in mutual justice ?1 Camus believes, as do Nietzsche and Tolstoy, that modern man lacks a sense Of direction. For this reason he has dedicated his writ- ings to a study Of positive ways of living in a world which Offers much that is negative. It was to this end that Camus proposed in his re’cit, L’Etranger, the constant confrontation or awareness Of the fact of death as an antidote to the nihilism Of a goalless life. By refusing to accept conventional attitudes toward death or attitudes of unknowing indiffer- ence, man avoids what Camus refers to as self-deception or inauthenti- city. Tolstoy derives a similar premise from his study of the theme of conscious death2 in his nouvelle, The Death of Ivan Ilyich. Ivan Ilyich lAustin Fowler, Albert Camus' The Stranger, The Plague 3&1 Other Works (New York, 1965),*60. 2Frequent acknowledgment is given to the influence Of Kierkegaard, Melville, Dostoevsky, and Nietzsche, among others, on Camus' thought; 12 13 had always hidden his authentic self and the knowledge that he will some day die amidst the trivializing details Of his social, Official, and famil- ial routine. With the imminence Of death and with the questions he asks himself in the face of it, the futility of his unexamined life becomes apparent. As Tolstoy prescribed the constant reminder of death as an antidote to meaninglessness, so does Camus. According to Louis R. Rossi in his study "Albert Camus: The Plague of Absurdity,"3 Camus' protagonist, Meursault. is an embodi- ment of Heidegger's Being-toward-Death (Sein zum Tode), that is, one WhO. having lived his life with a minimum of hypocrisy and self-decep- tion, had been aware, even if unconsciously, that "du fond de mon avenir, pendant toute cette vie absurde que j'avais mene’e, un souffle obscur remontait vers moi é travers des anne’es que n'étaient pas enc Ore venues et ce souffle e’galisait sur son passage tout ce qu'on me Proposait alors dans les années pas plus réelles que je vivais." Meursault's life is neither empty nor joyless. He knows that he \ 2 C(cont.)yet it is Walter Kaufmann who, in Religion from Tolstoy t_9 Ca\111118_ (New York, 1961), brought out the close relationship between isamus and Tolstoy, declaring: "What is so remarkable about Camus of, as much as anything, that he had the courage to accept the heritage he.Tolstoy, when no one else could stand before the world as Tolstoy's Bel-1'" (39). He further points out: "The persistent preoccupation with 1i 1frdeception and an appeal to the reader to abandon his inauthenticity Cults Anna Kare’nina with The Death 9f Ivan Ilyich" (3). In by-passing elf-Inn“ L'Etranger, Kaufmann noted, "The Plague is the posthumous 11d of The Death 2f Ivan Ilyich" (40). 3The Kenyon Review, XX, 3(Summer 1958), 399-422. an 4Albert Camus, W (Paris, 1957), 176-177. Subsequent otations from L'Etranger are taken from this edition. . l s , V ~ ~ fl ‘ l t. ,. . v o , t . .. . I t . ' C ’ i - l I - ‘ . , . ‘- O ‘ O s A ~ ' T’ ' v - i t _ . ' . . . .1 , s ‘ ‘ I so -_ V n ‘ ‘ . ~ _ . . - . o a ‘ . . s a ' I * fl ' _ Q ' I a - , J - ' ' ‘ ‘ 1‘ f (' I . ‘ ' 'I o '. ~ \ I ' I n T I ' i ‘ .. I . t " 4 A b o ‘ . . T I l \ v ,y, , r . I o .. o r .o ' ' . ’s s ’ I V. . v I n Y. . r - s I I ,~ ‘ u . i a. ’ 14 has been happy, that he will continue to be happy, and he anticipates the moment of his death with equanirnity, as the rounding out Of his life, that his life may become an entity, that all may be consummated. Rossi points out that Camus, "like the existentialists and Nietzsche (and their predecessor Hegel) proceeds by negation, "for death defines liberty and gives meaning to life; the acceptance of evil leads to inno- cence (414-415). In Camus’ use Of death5 as a means of fighting nihil- ism, he has learned that the confrontation of death can be a cure for "de ad souls," forcing them whenever they face death as a fact, to arrive at an hone st and even positive evaluation of life. In ad0pting the method of Bazarov — the protagonist of Turgenev's Fathers 3.2? Sons and literature’s first nihilist recognized as such --which was to accept n(”filling (nihil) as valid without first submitting it to critical testing, \ 50n the predominance of death as a theme in contemporary and deern EurOpean literature, R. W. B. Lewis wrote in The Picaresque m Representative Figures i_r_l Contemporay Fiction (Philadelphia and New York, 1959): "It is not easy for the majority Of American read- ers_ to understand, much less to sympathize with Camus' deep preoccu- $313,011 with death. . . . The public impulse in America, when faced c 1th a work Of Camus, is to inquire into the causes for the psychologi- eal abnormality allegedly there depicted: to ask how Meursault, for sxafilple, or even Camus himself got so maladjusted in a generally Siltlsfying world. The EurOpean reader, remembering that both 'I_‘l_1_<_e W and 'I_'_l_l_e Myth ch Sisyphus were written during the Second - Orld War and the occupation of France, for the most part, finds their tigolvement with death almost inevitable. For death, cruelty, humilia- di 11,. violent aberrations of justice, and a searing contempt for human Eugnlty have been the norms of contemporary experience for many Europeans." Lewis, at the same time that he points out that recent de 1‘Opean literature would be inexplicable without death also points out to :th's traditional importance, "that it is more than a natural reaction Philhe atrocious events Of the twentieth century. It has the status Of a . OsOphical position, " relating Camus particularly to Dostoevsky and tune teenth century Russian literature (72)- 15 Camus proceeds to reexamine all values in the harsh light of man's mortality. Testing them for viability, only such values or attitudes which do not threaten life or endanger man's happiness are reinstated; in this way many Of mankind's cherished self-deceptions are discarded. Furthermore, in employing the nineteenth-century nihilists' meth- ods which advocated, in some instances, the destruction of a world in order to build it anew, Camus paradoxically applies their method to the restoration Of order over chaos and to the instatement of sounder values and attitudes. Working through the denial of much that humanity vener- ate 3, Camus inaugurates in hilnself and in his protagonists the nihilistic approach of the anti-nihilist! Camus' knowledge that new values are Obviously needed derives from his early and late encounters with death and dissolution. With the Poverty of his childhood, there is "the dead father, the dying grand- IIIOther, the paralyzed uncle, the deaf and silent mother," but Opposed to 1ihis there is the sun Of Algeria. It is in the "dark night" of EurOpe that Camus learns that death was not only part Of his personal life but is al so the rule Of the day. In fighting death and the nihilistic reaction to death, Camus seeks "1a, gue’rison au bout de la maladie." He has one clue. He knows that death often results from excesses and that nihilism is a form Of excess and that excesses are, by their very nature, abnormalities or diseases. For that reason Camus uses the plague or 1_a \ 6Fowler, 5. l6 Eeste7 as one of the symbols or controlling metaphors in his writings to depict such excesses as nihilism, wars, death --- whatever is life- denying or destructive tO human happiness. In his novel 1.3 Peste, on one level Of meaning BEE? signifies war in general, for Camus points out that not only has the bubonic plague been one Of the most dreaded threats to human life, but that there have been as many plagues as wars in history. The term also stands more specifically for the French defeat in 1940 (in the German occupation which followed, the occupying troops were actually referred to as 1_a peste brune). Camus expands the sense of the word pea—to so that it appears to include all that he has also implied in his uses of the term "nihilism." Of this symbolism Rachel BeSpaloff wrote in her study of Camus, n'I‘he World Of the Man Condemned to Death": Perhaps the use of the term cryptic to define a style which is at times sententious and whose transparency appears without mystery, will seem debatable. The multiplicity of meanings and interpretations it suggests, the decipher- ing it necessitates, certainly seem to remove it from alle- gory, which always conceals some precise Object. Nothing Of the sort in 'I_‘_h_e Plague, where the scourge sometimes designates the event, sometimes the human condition, sometimes misfortune. 3 Germaine Brée also implies that the word plague or peste covers many forms of nihilism as she describes the syndrome of the twentieth- \ V 7The image of plague or peste appears for the first time in W— the first version of which was written as early as 1938, and 1:13am in 1947 and 1948 in La Bests and the play yEtat gig siege respec- (lgely’ and it also appears from time to time in the Carnets I and II 354942) and (1942-51). The remaining Carnets have not yet been publishecl. (E 89111138; A C_o_1_le_c_t_i_9£ Of Critical Essays, ed. Germaine Brée 11glewood Cliffs, N. J., 1967.), 98. 17 century mal d_u siecle and the implications of such a syndrome for humanity: the plague, she writes, in whatever context we consider it, symbolizes any force which systematically cuts humanity Off from the breath of life, the physical joy of love, the freedom to plan our tomorrows. In a very general way it is death and, in human terms, al_1 that enters into complicity with death: metaphysical or political systems, bureaucratic abstrac— t____ions and even Tarrou' s and Paneloux's efforts t_(_) trans- cend their humanity [italics added]. 9 To Germaine Bre’e’s elucidations other concepts may be added which still remain within the categories of peste or nihilism. They are: fanaticism, tyranny, self-deception, or bad faith, le___s ombres inutiles (Cant or residues Of false reasoning), crimes, lawlessness, disorder, a'liibsolutism, and surprisingly enough, the temptation toward sainthood! In Camus' consideration of whatever constitutes a threat to the moral health of his times, he has, first of all, in determining the Ila-tlare Of the ailment, to study its symptoms, to isolate the microbe befOre he can inaugurate its cure. To this end he refers to the illness PIOVisionally as 1_e mal, 1_e malheur, 1_a maladie, 1_a malaise, 1_e fléau, and 13. peste, or in English the plague, the pest, or the pestilence. To the list of maux which Camus sees afflicting contemporary man, he also added 1e malentendu,lo as it poses, more than a mere annoyance, a real \ G 9Camus (New York, 1964), 128. Subsequent quotations from erIllatine Bre: e's Camus are taken from this edition. th 10Whether in Le Malentendu, Camus' play Of that name, or in his - e1- treatments Of the same theme, Camus Obviously wishes, accord- W§r ‘30 S. Beynon John, to create another myth of man's existence in the 111a 1d. "the world without signs or sense, the absurd world in which 11. is never at home" (89). Rachel Bespaloff sees the world that Camus l 18 threat to the human community. Of 1_e malentendu or the misunderstand- ing as a current theme, John Cruickshank has written that Camus' writ- ings on the absurd "belong to a wider world in which the sense Of incoher- ence has grown rapidly more acute, and for which he bears witness to an age marked by increasing division, conflict, violence, and the failure to communicate adequately."11 On this subject Camus himself writes in L’Homme re’volte’, written in 1951 as an attempt to understand the times, "chaque équivoque, chaque malentendu suscite la mort. Le sommet de toutes les tragedies est dans la surdité de heros."12 Camus‘ intuition in including l_e malentendu as yet another mal or evil besetting mankind is productive, for it proves to be an important factor in the complex recognized as nihilism or pest . It is apparent that in the very heart of Camus' nihilistic world View -—- the absurd -- he finds values which, while constituting "la guéri son an bout de la maladie," instigate a movement from the negative \ ¥0(C0nt.)describes as one where "everyone is betrayed by everyone, w eluding himself. . . .there is almost no sentence in the second act hiCh does not have a different meaning for the one who speaks it and tor 1ihe one who hears it. The entire play is built on ambiguity; one has 0 choose in the dark, without being recognized, without being able to zlake oneself known. . . . Camus saw the heart Of the matter: our mod- sin tragedy is the tragedy of ambiguity touching all mankind" (105). His G 01": story "L'HOte" treats another facet of ambiguity, for according to fraeton Picon, it treats Of a misunderstanding in which the "gestures Of (1 ggernity turn against us leaving only the solitude Of incomprehension. . .” )- A11 quotations are from Camus: A Collection if Critical EssaLs, a 1 rea.dy cited. 11Albert Camus a_n_c_l tile Literature O_f Revolt (New York, 1960), 22. 12L'Homme révolté (Paris, 1951), 340. Subsequent quotations fr 0111 L'Homme re’volté are taken from this edition. if? ‘I v s i o n I . . n \ . D . . l r \ s . v . I . I U u e . I o t t . . 4\ l . .II t 9 . n . t n .n. u/ .. e n a r T _ I . .p u . s I ‘ t l o \ . . Ii . I f. I z . . . o\ . . . a \ . . t . . . a I a J . l . u c . ‘ . I e v c A . . 4 a i \ 4 . . n r . . . . . .4 . . I . x . . K r. r . . . I y 4 ’ o I .e u I ‘ o a t n a a o . a t a b . n . ; t I l I \ I , A o I o . \ .:\ . ¢ “ p ,t . o l o 4 A Q . e \ st \ l r .. . u I I) '\ t a a a a I u I l J r t u t n \r . s “I no I ‘ v r a a o c a s. I a f \ Q . w . ,. . I a u . x o I \I . A A ‘ n ' I J . , s . . \ § . t . . I V r o ' u . t t u h a n v o C n 1 9| 1 a ' . . . 6 a .\ r O O . .A n I f t \. . . . 1 . s 1 O '- o ' n . O . o . 9 . . . t n . u A. . v o o s 4 . [I I n . 9 l l . . s . l . t. . . t o \ D I o n n I \ . b s _ O. . I i ‘- . . o .u . \ a o . l . 7 . s . N . \ o o C I .t, . . s s Q I t. 19 to the positive, from incoherence to coherence, from negation itself to a solution for living. In Rachel Bespaloff's recognition that Camus has tried to restore meaning and the sense of joy for all the Ivan Ilyiches — who far outnumber the Meursaults of this world— and who remain strangers to life, she writes: Reduced to its simplest expression, Camus's thought is con- tained in a single question: What value abides in the eyes of the man condemned to death who refuses the consolation of the supernatural? Camus cannot take his mind Off this ques- tion. All his characters bring an answer; one has only to listen to them. 13 13Bespaloff, 9 2. PART II STYLES DE VIE In his Nobel Prize Acceptance Speech, Camus Speaks of the neces- sity of fighting nihilism and the death instinct at work in Our society. It is necessary, he claims, "8e forger un art de vivre par temps de catastroPhe, pour nai‘tre une seconde fois, et lutter ensuite, a visage déc ouvert, contre l'instinct de mort a 1'oeuvre dans notre histoire."l4 Germaine Bre’e writes that in countering a nihilism he refuses to accept, Camus realizes that what is needed is a ”style of life" worthy of a man (209 ). In seeking these "styles Of life" worthy of men, Camus has pro- Posed in all his writings, but particularly in his novel If M, a hier- archy of attitudes Opposed to nihilism. Such attitudes are studied and c°n8idered for acceptance or rejection on the basis of viability in a wol‘ld where death has become the order of the day. These attitudes are symbolized in certain "careers." Some Of the "careers" which Camus has tested are those Of the anarchist, the revolutionist, the bureaucrat, the tYrant, the Malraux-type hero, the police Official, the priest, and the judge (le__s robes rouges). Against these, he juxtaposes the absurd man in whatever role he is given, whether that of the engineer, the s choolteacher, the municipal clerk, the commercial salesman, l_e_ J:&e&rier délicat, the poet, or the physician. It is those who, in adOpt- 111g a scornful image of man, side with nihilism by bringing about the \ thi 14% (E giggle (Paris, 1958), 17. Subsequent quotations from 8 Work are taken from this edition. 20 ‘9 , ~ . t ' t r i . ‘ r H n 'x ._ I. t" ’ I . o 'i . . J ‘- J r, . ‘ 1‘ Q ' .5 . 1 y . ‘ fl ' f - S I . . \ I ‘ I ) I.'. p o ' I. t , - v T‘ I O ‘ \ ~ . I I .' I ' '1 ‘ \. O .. “ U, K. I . . . v i .l . - , \ ‘ ~ ’ ‘ . l . . , k ' ' . \_ ‘ -‘ . ‘ I t . '- ‘ t ( 1 ‘- . I ‘ ‘ t‘ .. ’ ‘ n t s I ("A t ,,. x o \ o \ n r n h ‘41 , s. t . . ' r v " ,I 1‘ V f I v. .‘ " I . .. g ’ O l ' ‘ . 1 . . . u U s 21 destruction of others and the annihilation of self. Am0ng these is the saint. In his consideration of sainthood as an approach to living, Camus presents his protagonist Jean Tarrou in the novel 1_a Peste. Tarrou's temptation toward sainthood is part of a peculiar manifestation of this century; the desire for sanctity without God. Camus' aspiring saint is governed largely by nostalgia -- by forms 0f nostalgia determined by what might be described as his "life cycle." This "life cycle" which prOpagates nostalgia consists of four stages: ( 1) an initial innocence; (2) an awakening to the knowledge that the world is not madeto his order; (3) resulting in an exhausting struggle to try to make the world fit a preferred pattern; and (4) a weariness with life and the by now acquired consciousness that he has been aspiring to Sainthood. The accompanying nostalgias are: a longing for an absolute of good or purity in a world made up of both good and evil; and the long- ing for, or concentration on an abstraction, goal, or ideal projected t:oVVard future realization; and finally, the nostalgia for peace or com- Plete annihilation in death. It is then evident that his weariness with life: his concern with an ideal not realizable within his own lifetime, and his yearning for self-annihilation all add up to a complete rejection of 1ife by the saint. In his treatment of Jean Tarrou as an aspiring saint, Camus indi- cates that Tarrou's yearning for saintliness, his nostalgia for purity and peace, incorporates attitudes which, although positive, become aspects of nihilism when excessively manifested. For in Camus' view L‘. C l a; luv U6. h‘fi ‘ VKA ‘ a 68 .F. FIV 22 any ideal or temptation which leads the individual on the path of absolutes makes him a stranger to life and a friend of death. This is apparent in the term itself, for ”absolute" is synonymous with "complete," "perfect," ”total," "unconditional," "ultimate"; to aSpire to purity or peace in their mo st concentrated, complete, or perfect forms is to Opt for excesses, such excesses that, because they can only be attained in death, are inim- ic al to life. The aspiring saint by-passes life. He seeks escape in his annihilation rather than in continued rebellion against 1_a condition Efi-ll'l'ilaine. All of Camus' works become studies of true or false rebels and it is in regard to the would-be saint that Camus shows his reservations as early as the spring or summer of 1942 as his Carnets reveal: Qu'est-ce qui fait 1a supe’riorité d’exemple (1a seule) du christianisme? Le Christ et ses saints — la recherche d'un style d_e y_i_e_. Cette oeuvre comptera [as his work progresses toward a definition of the atheistic saint] autant de formes que d'étapes sur 1e chemin d'une per- fection sans recompense. L'Etran er est 1e point zéro. 1_._§ Peste est un progrés, non de zero vers l'infini, mais vers une complexite’ plus profonde qui reste a definir. Le dernier point sera le saint, mais i1 aura sa valeur arithmé- tique -—- me surable comme l'homme. 15 The would-be saint's cooPeration with nihilism, through his nos- gla for qualities or a state unattainable 1n life, induces 1n Tarrou, El. hd occasionally in Camus, a death instinct.16 \ Q 15Carnets, II (Paris, 1964), 31. Subsequent quotations from M, II, are taken from this edition. Such a longing for 16In the early 1920's Freud began to consider the possibility of a a‘th instinct as an integral part of the human personality. In his study titled "Beyond the Pleasure Principle," he considered the fact that § §h 23 absolutes is referred to by Tarrou as his Beste intérieure. Undermin- ing both will and intellect, it constitutes a threat to both the personality and the life of the individual. Indications of the threat of such dissolution in Camus himself can be noted in his writings. In L'Eté, which contains "Le Minotaure ou la ha]. te d’Oran" written as early as 1939, Camus equates such a temptation With the desire to achieve in death the peace of stones: "Quelle tentation de passer a l’ennemi! Quelle tentation de s'indentifier a ces pierres, de se confondre avec cet univers brfllant et impossible qui de’fie l'his- toire et ses agitations."17 Emily Zants has made a study of the symbolism involved in such elel'rnents as sea, sky, and deserts in Camus' writing. In her "Camus' De Berts and Their Allies, Kingdoms of the Stranger" she observes that I.<)<=1