PROGRESS ON THE 1/3 − 2/3 CONJECTURE By Emily Jean Olson A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Mathematics — Doctor of Philosophy 2017 ABSTRACT PROGRESS ON THE 1/3 − 2/3 CONJECTURE By Emily Jean Olson Let (P, ≤) be a finite partially ordered set, also called a poset, and let n denote the cardinality of P . Fix a natural labeling on P so that the elements of P correspond to [n] = {1, 2, . . . , n}. A linear extension is an order-preserving total order x1 ≺ x2 ≺ · · · ≺ xn on the elements of P , and more compactly, we can view this as the permutation x1 x2 · · · xn in one-line notation. For distinct elements x, y ∈ P , we define P(x ≺ y) to be the proportion of linear extensions of P in which x comes before y. For 0 ≤ α ≤ 12 , we say (x, y) is an α-balanced pair if α ≤ P(x ≺ y) ≤ 1 − α. The 1/3 − 2/3 Conjecture states that every finite partially ordered set that is not a chain has a 1/3-balanced pair. This dissertation focuses on showing the conjecture is true for certain types of partially ordered sets. We begin by discussing a special case, namely when a partial order is 1/2-balanced. For example, this happens when the poset has an automorphism with a cycle of length 2. We spend the remainder of the text proving the conjecture is true for some lattices, including Boolean, set partition, and subspace lattices; partial orders that arise from a Young diagram; and some partial orders of dimension 2. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would first like to thank my advisor Dr. Bruce Sagan for opening the door to the mathematics community for me. He started by teaching me combinatorics and graph theory, and then advised me as we explored new mathematics together. I would also like to thank Dr. Jonathan Hall, Dr. Peter Magyar, and Dr. Michael Shapiro for serving on my committee. I would additionally like to extend thanks to Dr. Robert Bell for not only serving on my committee, but also for inviting me to be an REU mentor, an experience I will use as I now begin to mentor students of my own. Further, I offer thanks to the SMP community, a network of mathematicians who have given me advice, encouragement, and comfort during my time as a graduate student. Finally, I would like to thank Tim Olson for helping me optimize my code, without which we would still be waiting for the posets of size 7 to run. I am also grateful for his perpetual support, as he is holding the largest sign and cheering the loudest as I finish the last 0.2 miles of this marathon. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS LIST OF FIGURES . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . v Chapter 1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1.1 Poset Basics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1 3 Chapter 2 The 1/3 − 2/3 Conjecture . 2.1 History of the Conjecture . . . . . . . 2.2 Automorphisms of Posets . . . . . . . 2.3 Lattices . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.3.1 Boolean Lattices . . . . . . . 2.3.2 Set Partition Lattices . . . . . 2.3.3 Subspace Lattices . . . . . . . 2.3.4 Distributive Lattices . . . . . 2.3.5 Products of Two Chains . . . 2.4 Other Diagrams . . . . . . . . . . . . 2.5 Posets of Dimension 2 . . . . . . . . 2.6 Posets with Small Balance Constants 2.7 Future Work . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8 8 11 15 16 17 18 19 21 25 30 34 35 APPENDIX . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36 BIBLIOGRAPHY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 iv . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . LIST OF FIGURES Figure 1.1: A poset P with 6 elements and a matrix counting its linear extensions . 2 Figure 1.2: The poset T with three elements and one relation. . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3 Figure 1.3: A diagram of shape (4, 3, 1) and a standard Young tableau of the same shape. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6 Figure 2.1: Two posets with small balance constants. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9 Figure 2.2: The poset P has an automorphism with cycle length 2 and balance constant 1/2, while Q has no nontrivial automorphisms and balance constant 1/2. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 Figure 2.3: P and anti-automorphism σ with 1 fixed point. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15 Figure 2.4: The Boolean lattice B3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 Figure 2.5: The set partition lattice Π3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.6: A 4 element poset P , its corresponding J(P ), and a chart with values e(P + xy). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20 Figure 2.7: The poset C3 × C4 and its corresponding diagram. . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Figure 2.8: The diagram of shape (4, 4, 2) where each cell is labeled by its hooklength. 23 Figure 2.9: (a) A Young diagram of shape (4, 22 , 1), (b) a shifted diagram of shape (5, 3, 2, 1), (c) a skew left-justified diagram of shape (4, 22 , 1) / (2, 1), and (d) a shifted skew diagram of shape (5, 3, 2, 1) / (3). . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Figure 2.10: The shifted diagram of shape (4, 2, 1) and its corresponding poset. . . . . 26 Figure 2.11: The skew diagram (9, 72 , 54 ) / (6, 5, 32 , 2) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Figure 2.12: Two skew left-justified diagrams and one skew shifted diagram. . . . . . 29 Figure 2.13: The set of linear extensions E(P, ω) of the poset (P, ω) forms the interval [e, 41325] in the weak Bruhat order. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 Figure 2.14: Posets with the smallest balance constants greater than 1/3. . . . . . . . 34 v Chapter 1 Introduction We begin with some background before stating the conjecture. Section 1.1 provides a more complete introduction to partially ordered sets, or posets. Let (P, ≤) be a partially ordered set, and let n be the cardinality of P . Fix a natural labeling on P so that the elements of P correspond to [n] = {1, 2, . . . , n}. A linear extension is a total order x1 ≺ x2 ≺ · · · ≺ xn on the elements of P such that xi ≺ xj if xi

ˆ0, and so the proportion of linear extensions remains the same in P − {ˆ0}. For this reason, we usually insist that posets have at least 2 minimal elements and similarly, at least 2 maximal 10 elements. Also, if we consider the linear sum P + Q of posets P and Q, we can easily see that δ(P + Q) = max{δ(P ), δ(Q)}. For this reason, we need not consider posets that are linear sums. 2.2 Automorphisms of Posets We first provide a proof of an important observation about the linear extensions of a poset with a nontrivial automorphism. Proposition 2.5. A poset P with a nontrivial automorphism α has a nontrivial bijection on its linear extensions. Further, P(x ≺ y) = P(α(x) ≺ α(y)) for all x, y ∈ P . Proof. Let α : P → P be a nontrivial automorphism. This means that for x, y ∈ P , x ≤P y if and only if α(x) ≤P α(y). Now, let π = a1 a2 · · · an be a linear extension of P , and by the definition of linear extensions, we know that if ai ≤P aj , then i ≤ j. As α is an automorphism, then we also have that if α(ai ) ≤P α(aj ), then i ≤ j. This gives us, by definition, that α(π) = α(a1 )α(a2 ) · · · α(an ) is a linear extension of P . Therefore, α induces a bijection on the linear extensions of P . Further, this bijection is nontrivial as α is nontrivial. We can also observe that the linear extensions with x before y map bijectively via α to the linear extensions with α(x) before α(y). Hence, P(x ≺ y) = P(α(x) ≺ α(y)), as desired. In [GHP87], Ganter, Hafner, and Poguntke describe a proof of the fact that a poset with a non-trivial automorphism will satisfy the 1/3 − 2/3 Conjecture. We present their short argument here to illustrate a popular yet insightful approach to the conjecture using proof by contradiction. 11 Theorem 2.6 ([GHP87]). If a poset P has a non-trivial automorphism, then P is 1/3balanced. Proof. Let α : P → P be a nontrivial automorphism of a poset P . Assume there are no x, y ∈ P with 1/3 ≤ P(x ≺ y) ≤ 2/3. We can then create a new relation on P by defining v if P(u ≺ v) > 2/3. u Observe that is transitive. Indeed, for u, v, w ∈ P , assume u v and v w. This means P(u ≺ v) > 2/3 and P(v ≺ w) > 2/3. We can see that since P(u ≺ v ≺ w) + P(v ≺ u ≺ w) + P(v ≺ w ≺ u) = P(v ≺ w) > 2/3 and P(v ≺ u ≺ w) + P(v ≺ w ≺ u) ≤ P(v ≺ u) < 1/3, it must be that P(u ≺ v ≺ w) > 1/3. Therefore, P(u ≺ w) > 1/3, and since we assumed there are no 1/3-balanced pairs in P , then P(u ≺ w) > 2/3. So, u w, and hence is a transitive binary relation. As is transitive, it gives a linear order on P . Now, if u v, then P (u ≺ v) > 2/3, and so by Proposition 2.5, P (α(u) ≺ α(v)) > 2/3. This means that α(u) α respects . But as α(v), and hence is a linear order on P and α respects the linear order, it must be that α is the identity. This contradicts our assumption. Next, we present a result about when a poset has a balance constant of 1/2. Proposition 2.7. If a poset P has an automorphism with a cycle of length 2, then P is 1/2-balanced. Further, if x and y are the elements in the cycle of length 2, then (x, y) is a 1/2-balanced pair. 12 5 4 3 2 6 5 4 3 2 1 1 Q P Figure 2.2: The poset P has an automorphism with cycle length 2 and balance constant 1/2, while Q has no nontrivial automorphisms and balance constant 1/2. Proof. Let α : P → P be an automorphism and x, y ∈ P be such that α(x) = y and α(y) = x. Then we can see that e(P + xy) = e(P + α(x)α(y)) = e(P + yx), where the first equality comes from Proposition 2.5. So we have e(P ) = e(P + xy) + e(P + yx) = 2e(P + xy), and so e(P + xy) = e(P )/2. Hence, (x, y) is a 1/2-balanced pair, as desired. An example of a poset with an automorphism of cycle length 2 is given in Figure 2.2. Poset P has a balance constant of 1/2. A counterexample to the converse of Proposition 2.7 is also provided in Figure 2.2. Poset Q has a balance constant of 1/2, as it has 12 linear extensions and e(P + 34) = 6. However, we can see by inspection it has no nontrivial automorphisms. The following is a corollary to Proposition 2.7. 13 Corollary 2.8. A poset P with a twin pair of elements is 1/2-balanced. Proof. Let P be a poset with x and y a twin pair of elements. We can see that P has a non-trivial automorphism which fixes all elements except for x and y and maps x to y and y to x. So, this poset has an automorphism is a cycle of length 2. By Proposition 2.7, then P is 1/2-balanced and (x, y) is a 1/2-balanced pair. While the above results depend on an automorphism of a poset, it is natural to ask if we can obtain results from other types of maps. Next, we consider an anti-automorphism σ on a poset. Observe that the linear extensions with x before y in P map bijectively via σ to the linear extensions with σ(y) before σ(x). Hence, P(x ≺ y) = P(σ(y) ≺ σ(x)), as desired. Also observe that any even number of iterations of σ give an automorphism of P . Hence, if σ 2 is not the identity, then we know that P has a non-trivial automorphism, and by Theorem 2.6, P is 1/3-balanced. We state this corollary to Theorem 2.6 here for completeness. Corollary 2.9. If σ is an anti-automorphism on P and σ 2 is a non-trivial automorphism, then P is 1/3-balanced. We can also ask when an anti-automorphism guarantees a poset to be 1/2-balanced. Once such case is described in Proposition 2.10. Proposition 2.10. Let σ : P → P be an anti-automorphism. If σ has 2 fixed points, then P is 1/2-balanced. Proof. Let P be a poset and σ : P → P be an anti-automorphism with fixed points x and y. Then, σ(x) = x and σ(y) = y. Since P(x ≺ y) = P(σ(y) ≺ σ(x)) = P(y ≺ x), 14 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 σ 2 3 1 5 6 4 8 9 7 Figure 2.3: P and anti-automorphism σ with 1 fixed point. and P(x ≺ y)+P(y ≺ x) = 1, we can see that P(x ≺ y) = 1/2. Hence, (x, y) is a 1/2-balanced pair in P , and we are done. We cannot weaken the assumption in Proposition 2.10, since a unique fixed point in an anti-automorphism is not enough to guarantee that the poset is 1/2-balanced. For an example, consider the poset P and anti-automorphism σ in Figure 2.3 where for x ∈ P we place σ(x) on the right in the same position as x on the left. Any nontrivial antiautomorphism of P , including σ shown here, will have exactly 1 fixed point, and computer 711 = 1 . calculations give us that δ(P ) = 1431 2 We can also see that the converse of Proposition 2.10 is not true, as evidenced by the counterexample in Figure 2.2. Any anti-automorphism of the poset P will have exactly 1 fixed point, and yet it is 1/2-balanced. 2.3 Lattices One commonly studied type of poset is a lattice. Here, we discuss the general definition of a lattice before considering the conjecture for specific lattices in this section. Definition 2.11. Let S ⊆ P be a nonempty set of elements. A lower bound of S is an element z such that z ≤ u for all u ∈ S. The greatest lower bound, or meet, of S is a lower 15 bound w of S such that if z is another lower bound of S, then z ≤ w. If S = {x, y}, then the meet, if it exists, is denoted by x ∧ y. Similarly, an upper bound of S is an element z such that z ≥ u for all u ∈ S. The least upper bound, or join, of S is an upper bound w of S such that if z is another upper bound of S, then z ≥ w. If S = {x, y}, then the join, if it exists, is denoted by x ∨ y. Note that in general, a set S ⊆ P could have zero, one, or many lower bounds or upper bounds. However, if a meet or join exists, it must be unique. We call a poset a lattice if every nonempty subset S ⊆ P has a meet and a join. One type of lattice we will consider later is a distributive lattice. Definition 2.12. A distributive lattice P is a lattice that obeys the following two equivalent properties for all a, b, c ∈ P : a ∨ (b ∧ c) = (a ∨ b) ∧ (a ∨ c) and a ∧ (b ∨ c) = (a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c). 2.3.1 Boolean Lattices Consider the set of all subsets of [n], and define an order by S ≤ T when S ⊆ T for S, T ⊆ [n]. This is a lattice as it is closed under joins and meets, specifically, S ∨ T = S ∪ T and S ∧ T = S ∩ T . We call this poset the Boolean lattice of size n, denoted Bn . This poset has the empty set as its ˆ0 and [n] is its ˆ1. An example when n = 3 is given in Figure 2.4. In the case that n = 1, the poset B1 is a chain, and so the 1/3 − 2/3 Conjecture only applies to Bn when n ≥ 2. We present the following as a corollary to Proposition 2.7. Corollary 2.13. For all n ≥ 2, the Boolean lattice Bn has an automorphism with a cycle of length 2, and so the Boolean lattice is 1/2-balanced. 16 {1, 2, 3} {1, 2} {1, 3} {2, 3} {1} {2} {3} ∅ Figure 2.4: The Boolean lattice B3 Proof. Let n ≥ 2. We will first describe a map from Bn to itself that is a poset isomorphism. For S ⊆ [n], consider φ : Bn → Bn defined by φ(S) =     S∆{1, 2}, if S ∩ {1, 2} = {1} or S ∩ {1, 2} = {2}    S, otherwise. We can easily see that φ is a poset automorphism. Let A = {1} and B = {2} in Bn . Then, φ(A) = B and φ(B) = A. Hence, by Proposition 2.7, Bn has a 1/2-balanced pair. 2.3.2 Set Partition Lattices Consider the set Πn of all partitions of [n]. A partition is composed of pairwise disjoint, non-empty subsets B1 , . . . , Bk whose union is [n], and we write B1 / · · · /Bk [n]. Each Bi is called a block of the partition. For π, τ ∈ Πn , we say π is a refinement of τ if every block of π is contained in a block of τ . This produces a partial order on Πn given by π ≤ τ when π is a refinement of τ . This is a lattice as it is closed under joins and meets, specifically π ∨ τ is the minimal partition that refines both π and τ and π ∧ τ is the maximal partition that is a refinement of both π and τ . Hence, Πn is called the set partition lattice. For brevity, we 17 123 1/23 2/13 3/12 1/2/3 Figure 2.5: The set partition lattice Π3 will write 12/3/4 for the set partition {{1, 2}, {3}, {4}} and similarly for other partitions. An example of Π3 can be seen in Figure 2.5. For n = 1, 2, Πn is a chain, and so the 1/3 − 2/3 Conjecture only applies to Πn when n ≥ 3. We present the following as a corollary to Proposition 2.7. Corollary 2.14. For n ≥ 3, the set partition lattice Πn has an automorphism with a cycle of length 2, and so the set partition lattice is 1/2-balanced. Proof. Let n > 2. We consider the map that sends a partition π to the partition π , where π has the same blocks as π with the elements 1 and 2 interchanged. This is an automorphism of the lattice. Indeed, it is a bijection because it is an involution and swapping 1 and 2 preserves ordering by refinement. To see that this automorphism has a 2-cycle, notice that the lattice contains partitions π1 = 13/2/4/ · · · /n and π2 = 1/23/4/ · · · /n as n ≥ 3. Under the automorphism described above, π1 and π2 form a 2-cycle. Hence, by Proposition 2.7, the set partition lattice on n elements is 1/2-balanced when n ≥ 3. 2.3.3 Subspace Lattices Let q = pm be some power of a prime p, and consider the finite vector space V = Fn q , which is the set of n-tuples of elements from the finite field Fq . The subspace lattice Ln (q) consists of the set of all subspaces of Fn q ordered by inclusion. We can see that for two subspaces 18 W, W ⊆ Fn q , their meet W ∧ W is W ∩ W and their join W ∨ W is W + W . As Ln (q) is closed under meets and joins, Ln (q) is a lattice. Further, we can note that Ln (q) is ranked by the dimension of the subspace. If U ⊆ Fn q is a subspace spanned by {v1 , . . . , vk }, then we write U = v1 , . . . , vk . Let ei be the standard basis vector of Fn q that has zeros everywhere except for a 1 in the ith position. We present the following as a corollary to Proposition 2.7. Corollary 2.15. For n ≥ 2, the subspace lattice Ln (q) has an automorphism with a cycle of length 2, and so the subspace lattice is 1/2-balanced. Proof. Let B = {e1 , . . . , en } be the standard basis of Ln (q). Since n ≥ 2, then there are at least 2 distinct elements in B, and e1 and e2 are two 1-dimensional subspaces of Fn q. Consider the linear transformation on Fn q defined by the n × n matrix M that has 1s in the (1, 2), (2, 1), and (i, i), 3 ≤ i ≤ n, positions and zeros elsewhere. We can see that M sends e1 to e2 , e2 to e1 , and fixes all other basis elements of Fn q. We can create an automorphism of Ln (q) as follows: for U ⊆ Fn q , φ(U ) = M · U , where M · U multiplies every element u ∈ U by M . Indeed, this is an automorphism of the lattice, since if U ≤ U in Ln (q), then M · U ≤ M · U as well. Since φ( e1 ) = e2 and φ( e2 ) = e2 , we have that e1 and e2 form a 2-cycle. By Proposition 2.7, Ln (q) is 1/2-balanced. 2.3.4 Distributive Lattices For a given poset P , consider the lower order ideals of P . Recall the definition of order ideals is given in Definition 1.3. The lower order ideals are partially ordered by I ≤ I if I ⊆ I . This gives us the distributive lattice J(P ) created from P . It is a lattice as meets and joins are given by intersections and unions, respectively. An example of P and J(P ) is 19 {1, 2, 3, 4} {2, 3, 4} {1, 2, 3} 4 3 1 {2, 3} {1, 2} 2 P {2} J(P ) y {2} {2, 3} {2, 3, 4} {1} 5 10 13 4 10 {1, 2} 5 {1, 2, 3} x {1} ∅ Figure 2.6: A 4 element poset P , its corresponding J(P ), and a chart with values e(P + xy). given in Figure 2.6. In fact, by the Fundamental Theorem on Distributive Lattices, every distributive lattice is isomorphic to the lattice of lower order ideals of some poset P . As a result, we were motivated to find results about J(P ) that depend on properties of P . Unfortunately, it is not true that if P is 1/2-balanced, then J(P ) is 1/2-balanced as well. An example can be seen in Figure 2.6. While P is 1/2-balanced by the pair (1, 3), J(P ) is not 1/2-balanced, as evidenced in the chart in Figure 2.6 whose entries are e(P + xy) for every x and y not comparable in J(P ). Since J(P ) has 14 linear extensions, we can see no pair is 1/2−balanced. Adding an extra condition, namely that P has an automorphism with a 2-cycle, allows us to prove that J(P ) is 1/2-balanced. Proposition 2.16. If P has an automorphism with cycle of length 2, then J(P ) is 1/2balanced. Proof. Let α : P → P be an automorphism with α(x) = y and α(y) = x for some x, y ∈ P . This induces an automorphism α ¯ of J(P ), given by α ¯ (I) = {α(w) : w ∈ I} for I ∈ J(P ). We claim that α ¯ has a cycle of length 2, namely that α ¯ (Lx ) = Ly and α ¯ (Ly ) = Lx . We will show α ¯ (Lx ) = Ly , as the proof of the other equality is similar. Let z ∈ α ¯ (Lx ), 20 so z = α(w) for some w ∈ Lx . This means that w ≤ x, and so α(w) ≤ α(x) = y. Therefore, z ≤ y and we have z ∈ Ly . Hence, α ¯ (Lx ) ⊆ Ly . The proof of the other set containment is similar. Thus, we have proven the claim. Since α ¯ has a cycle of length 2, by Proposition 2.7, J(P ) is 1/2-balanced. This leads to another proof that Boolean lattices are 1/2-balanced. Corollary 2.17. For n ≥ 2, the Boolean lattice Bn is 1/2-balanced. Proof. Let n ≥ 2. The Boolean lattice Bn is the distributive lattice corresponding to the poset P with n elements and no relations. There is an automorphism on P that swaps elements 1 and 2 and is the identity on the remaining elements. Since P has an automorphism with a cycle of length 2, then by Proposition 2.16, Bn is 1/2-balanced. 2.3.5 Products of Two Chains Let Cn be the chain with n elements. This section will be concerned with the product of two chains Cm and Cn , with m, n ≥ 2. The poset Cm × Cn is a lattice with grid structure, as in Figure 2.7. Recall Young diagrams from Definition 1.4 and notation from Section 1.1. Figure 2.7 depicts the rectangular Young diagram of shape λ = (43 ) corresponding to C3 ×C4 . We can see the correspondence as m gives us the number of rows of the Young diagram, while n gives us the length of each row. The number of linear extensions of Cm × Cn is the same as the number of standard Young tableaux (SYT) of the Young diagram of shape (nm ). Unlike many other demonstrations that a poset is 1/3-balanced, our proof for Cm × Cn finds the exact value of P(a ≺ b) for a pair of elements (a, b). Let a be the atom from the chain Cm × ˆ0 and b the atom from the chain ˆ0 × Cn , as labeled in Figure 2.7. In order to 21 a b b a Figure 2.7: The poset C3 × C4 and its corresponding diagram. compute how many linear extensions of Cm × Cn have a ≺ b, we will compute how many SYT have (1, 2) filled with a smaller number than (2, 1). Since the entry 2 must go in one of these two cells, this assumption forces the SYT to have the (1, 1) cell filled with a 1 and the (1, 2) cell filled with a 2. Flipping and rotating by 180 degrees, one sees that this is equivalent to counting the SYT of shape (nm−1 , n − 2). To prove Lemma 2.18, we will need the hooklength formula for f λ , the number of SYT of a diagram of shape λ. For a given cell (i, j) in a diagram of shape λ, its hook is the set of all the cells weakly to its right together with all cells weakly below it, and its hooklength hλ (i, j) is the number of cells in its hook. The hooklength formula for a diagram with n cells is fλ = n! , hλ (i, j) where the product is over all cells (i, j) in λ. A diagram of shape (4, 4, 2) is given in Figure 2.8, and each cell is labeled by its hooklength. Using the formula, we can see that f (4,4,2) = 6 · 52 10! = 252, · 4 · 3 · 23 · 12 and so the diagram has 252 SYT. Lemma 2.18. Let m ≥ 1 and n ≥ 3. We can relate the number of standard Young tableaux 22 6 5 3 2 5 4 2 1 2 1 Figure 2.8: The diagram of shape (4, 4, 2) where each cell is labeled by its hooklength. of shape (nm ) and of shape (nm−1 , n − 2) by the following equality: f (n m−1 ,n−2) = (n − 1)(m + 1) (nm ) f . 2(mn − 1) Proof. Let λ = (nm ) and µ = (nm−1 , n − 2) be diagrams and f λ be the number of SYT of shape λ. We will proceed by first describing which factors differ between f λ and f µ . We can observe that the hooklengths only disagree between λ and µ in those cells in the last two columns and those in the last row. The last two columns of λ have hooklengths of m + 1, m, . . . , 2 and m, m − 1, . . . , 1, while in µ the last two columns have hooklengths m, m − 1, . . . , 2 and m − 1, m − 2, . . . , 1. Overall, f µ is missing a factor of (m + 1)m which appears in the denominator of f λ . Similarly, the hooklength values of the last row of λ, excluding the ones in the last two columns which have already been accounted for, are n, n − 1, . . . , 3, while those in µ are n − 2, n − 3, . . . , 1. So our formula for f µ is missing a factor of n(n − 1) from the denominator and a factor of 2 from the numerator. Finally f λ has a numerator of (mn)! while µ has a numerator of (mn − 2)!, so there is a factor of (mn)(mn−1) we need to remove from the numerator of f λ . Overall, our hooklength formula for µ derived from f λ is fµ = n(n − 1)(m + 1)m λ f 2(mn)(mn − 1) as desired. 23 = (n − 1)(m + 1) λ f , 2(mn − 1) Theorem 2.19. Let Cm and Cn be chains of lengths m ≥ 2 and n ≥ 2, respectively. Then their product Cm × Cn has a 1/3-balanced pair. Proof. Without loss of generality, we can let n ≥ m. Let P = Cm × Cn . If m = 2, then P has width 2, and so by Theorem 2.1, we know that δ(P ) ≥ 1/3. If m = n = 3, then P has a non-trivial automorphism, and so by Theorem 2.6, P has a 1/3-balanced pair. Next, let m ≥ 3 and n ≥ 4. We can see that P has exactly two atoms. Let the atoms be labeled a and b, as in Figure 2.7. We claim that a, b are a 1/3-balanced pair. Notice that the linear extensions of P begin with either ˆ0a . . . or ˆ0b . . ., and the number that begin with ˆ0a . . . is the same as e(P + ab). We can also see that e(P + ab) is the same as the number of standard Young tableaux of shape (nm−1 , n − 2). Hence, by Lemma 2.18, we know that e(P + ab) = (n − 1)(m + 1) e(P ). 2(mn − 1) It remains to be shown that 1 (n − 1)(m + 1) 2 ≤ ≤ 3 2(mn − 1) 3 (2.1) for all m ≥ 3, n ≥ 4. For the first inequality, cross multiply and bring everything to one side to get the equivalent inequality (mn − 1) + 3(n − m) ≥ 0. This inequality is true since n ≥ m and mn ≥ 1. For the second inequality, proceed in the same manner to get mn + 3(m − n) − 1 ≥ 0. By the lower bounds for m, n we have (m − 3)(n − 4) ≥ 0. So it suffices to prove mn + 3m − 3n − 1 ≥ (m − 3)(n − 4). Moving everything to one side yet again gives the equivalent inequality 7m − 13 ≥ 0 which is true since m ≥ 3. Therefore, we have shown that (2.1) holds, and so (a, b) is a 1/3-balanced pair in P . 24 (a) (b) (c) (d) Figure 2.9: (a) A Young diagram of shape (4, 22 , 1), (b) a shifted diagram of shape (5, 3, 2, 1), (c) a skew left-justified diagram of shape (4, 22 , 1) / (2, 1), and (d) a shifted skew diagram of shape (5, 3, 2, 1) / (3). 2.4 Other Diagrams In Section 2.3.5, we considered the product of two chains as a rectangular Young diagram, and the linear extensions of the poset corresponded to the standard Young tableaux of that Young diagram. Given Theorem 2.19, it is natural to consider other posets that come from other diagrams. Recall the definition of Young diagram given in Definition 1.4, and let λ = (λ1 , . . . , λk ) be a weakly decreasing partition of n. An example of the Young diagram of shape (4, 22 , 1) is given in Figure 2.9(a). To generalize the notion of Young diagram, next let λ1 > λ2 > · · · > λk , in which case λ is called a strict partition. The shifted diagram corresponding to a strict partition λ indents row i so that it begins on the diagonal cell (i, i). An example is given in Figure 2.9(b). A third type of diagram is a skew diagram, λ/µ, which is the set-theoretic difference between diagrams λ = (λ1 , . . . , λk ) and µ = (µ1 , . . . , µl ) such that µ ⊆ λ, that is, l ≤ k and µi ≤ λi for each 1 ≤ i ≤ l. A skew diagram can be either left-justified, as seen in Figure 2.9(c), or shifted, as seen in Figure 2.9(d). We would like to point out that if we allow µ to be an empty partition, then λ/µ could refer to a Young, shifted, or skew diagram. To avoid ambiguity, we will always specify the type of diagram we intend, and to be clear, when referring to Young diagrams, we exclusively mean left-justified and non-skew diagrams. 25 g a b c f d d e f c g e b a Figure 2.10: The shifted diagram of shape (4, 2, 1) and its corresponding poset. For each diagram, there is a corresponding poset formed by letting each cell be an element of P . For x, y ∈ P , x ≤ y exactly when the cell for y is weakly to the right and/or weakly below the cell for x. See Figure 2.10 for an example of the poset corresponding to the shifted diagram (4, 2, 1). We will use the notation λ/µ to refer to a diagram and Pλ/µ for the corresponding poset. As we have already seen, the cells of a Young diagram can be filled with integers from 1 to n using each number exactly once and increasing in the rows and columns to form a standard Young tableau. In a similar manner, we define shifted standard Young tableaux and skew standard Young tableaux. The standard (shifted) (skew) Young tableaux for a given diagram are in bijective correspondence with linear extensions of the poset. Therefore, when we want to discuss linear extensions, we can discuss standard (shifted) (skew) Young tableaux instead. We next present a generalized version of Theorem 2.19. For any type of diagram, we use the notation (i, j) to refer to the cell in the ith row and jth column. For instance, the (2, 2) cell in the shifted diagram in Figure 2.10 is labeled with an e. Theorem 2.20. Let Pλ/µ be the poset corresponding to the diagram λ/µ, where µ could be an empty partition, and assume Pλ/µ is not a linear order. If λ/µ is a Young diagram, shifted diagram, or skew diagram, Pλ/µ is a 1/3-balanced poset. 26 Proof. Let λ = (λ1 , . . . , λk ) and µ = (µ1 , . . . , µl ) be partitions such that µ ⊆ λ. Assume the diagram λ/µ does not correspond to a linear order. Assume first that µ is empty; we will show that when Pλ corresponds to a Young diagram or shifted non-skew diagram, it has an almost twin pair of elements. Hence, by Theorem 2.4, Pλ is 1/3-balanced. When λ is a Young diagram, let x correspond to the (1, 2) cell and y correspond to the (2, 1) cell of λ. So, (x, y) is an almost twin pair of elements in Pλ . When λ is a shifted diagram which is not skew, then λ1 ≥ 3, as Pλ is not a linear order. Let x correspond to the (1, 3) cell and y correspond to the (2, 2) cell. So, (x, y) is an almost twin pair of elements in Pλ . Next, we consider skew diagrams. If λ/µ is a disconnected diagram, observe that an almost twin pair in a connected component of Pλ/µ remains an almost twin pair in the entire poset. Therefore, we can assume λ/µ is a connected skew diagram that does not correspond to a poset that is a chain. First consider left-justified skew diagrams. By removing any empty columns on the left of the diagram, we can assume without loss of generality that k ≥ l + 1. For ease in discussing the first and last rows of µ, define µ0 = λ1 and µl+1 = 0. We have the following cases: (i) If there exists i ∈ [l] such that µi−1 − 1 ≥ µi = µi+1 + 1 then (i, µi + 1) and (i + 1, µi+1 + 1) is an almost twin pair. For an example of this case, see the pair (a, b) in Figure 2.11. 27 a b c d e f Figure 2.11: The skew diagram (9, 72 , 54 ) / (6, 5, 32 , 2) (ii) If there exists i ∈ [l − 1] such that µi−1 − 2 ≥ µi = µi+1 then (i, µi + 2) and (i + 1, µi+1 + 1) is an almost twin pair. Note that (i, µi + 2) exists in the diagram since λ/µ is connected. For an example of this, see the pair (c, d) in Figure 2.11. (iii) If k = l + 1 and µl−1 − 1 ≥ µl , then (l, µl + 1) and (l + 1, 1) are an almost twin pair. For an example of this, see the pair (e, f ) in Figure 2.11. (iv) If k ≥ l + 2 and µl ≥ 2, then (l + 1, 2) and (l + 2, 1) are an almost twin pair. Notice this is similar to case (ii), only it occurs at the bottom of the skew diagram. We can now decide what types of diagrams do not fall into cases (i)-(iv) above. We claim that any remaining diagram has µ of the form (sm1 , (s − 1)m2 , . . . , (s − p + 1)mp ) where mi ≥ 2 for all i ∈ [p] and s ∈ N\{0}. We call this case (v). 28 a b c d e f (8, 6, 5, 3, 2) / (6, 3) (53 , 43 , 3) / (42 , 32 , 22 ) (34 , 22 , 1) / (22 , 13 ) Figure 2.12: Two skew left-justified diagrams and one skew shifted diagram. Indeed, all consecutive µi values differ by 1 or 0 since if there is some r with µr−1 −2 ≥ µr , then to avoid cases (i) and (ii) above, it must be that µs−1 − 2 ≥ µs for all s ∈ [r, l + 1]. In particular, this means µl ≥ 2, and this diagram will fall into case (iii) or (iv). So, any consecutive µi values differ by 1 or 0. Further, if mi = 1 for any i ∈ [p], the diagram would fall into case (i). Hence, µ must have the form above. It also must be true that λ/µ has λ1 = µ1 + 1, in order to avoid case (ii) above. Two examples of diagrams λ/µ that do not fall into cases (i)-(iv) are given in Figure 2.12. In these remaining diagrams, (1, µ1 + 1) and (m1 + 1, µ(m +1) + 1) is an almost twin pair. Examples 1 of this pair are (a, b) and (c, d) in Figure 2.12. Hence every skew left-justified diagram λ/µ satisfies one of these five cases, and so Pλ/µ not a chain has an almost twin pair. Finally, we consider the skew shifted diagrams. Notice that that the first l rows of the diagram can be viewed as a skew left-justified diagram. Therefore, if any of the first l − 1 rows are of the forms found in cases (i) or (ii), or if the first rows correspond to case (v), then the almost twin pairs in those cases remain almost twin in this poset, and we are done. If none of cases (i), (ii), or (v) apply, then consider µl . In particular, it must be the µl > 1, else case (ii) or (v) applies. If µl > 3, then the last k − l rows of the diagram 29 are a shifted diagram, and so we have the same almost twin pair as in the shifted case. If µl ∈ {2, 3}, then (l, µl + l) and (l + 1, l + 1) are an almost twin pair, as seen by the pair (e, f ) in Figure 2.12. Hence, for skew diagrams λ/µ, if Pλ/µ is not a chain, it has an almost twin pair of elements, as claimed. 2.5 Posets of Dimension 2 The set of linear extensions E(P ) of a labeled poset P with n elements can be considered a subset of Sn , where permutations are written in one-line notation. The full set Sn is a poset under the weak Bruhat ordering. For background on the weak Bruhat order, see [BB05, Chapter 3]. Since we use natural numbers to discuss the elements of a labeled poset P , we will use πj . Definition 2.22. For π and σ permutations, π is said to contain σ as a pattern if some subsequence of π has the same relative order as σ. Otherwise we say that π avoids σ. We can also consider a subsequence S = πi1 πi2 · · · πim of elements from π = π1 · · · πn . We say that S is contained in the pattern σ if some instance of σ in π contains S. Otherwise, we say that S avoids σ. An example of Definition 2.22 can be seen with π = 23154. We can see that π contains the pattern 123 in the subsequence 235, while it avoids 321. If S = 14, then S is contained in the pattern 132 in the instance 154 and avoids 123. 30 For the remainder of this section, we will consider E(P ) for any poset P to be a subposet of Sn . We might ask what can be said about E(P ) as a poset, and Bj¨orner and Wachs [BW91] showed that E(P ) has especially nice structure when P has dimension 2. The dimension of a poset is the least k such that there is some U ⊆ E(P ) of size k such that ∩U = (P, ≤). An equivalent definition is that the dimension of P is the least k such that P can be embedded as a subset into the product Nk . For our purposes, we discuss posets with dimension 2, which Bj¨orner and Wachs [BW91] characterize in the following proposition. Proposition 2.23 ([BW91]). A poset P has dimension 2 if and only if it has a labeling ω such that E(P, ω) forms an interval in the weak Bruhat ordering of Sn . If the labeling ω for a poset P of dimension 2 is natural, then E(P, ω) forms a lower order interval. Since the characterization by Bj¨orner and Wachs is necessary and sufficient, we know there is a correspondence between naturally labeled posets and lower-order intervals in Sn . The interval contains permutations between the identity permutation e and some maximal permutation π. When E(P, ω) forms the interval [e, π], the two linear extensions required to describe P as a poset of dimension 2 are exactly e and π. For the reverse correspondence, we can start with a permutation π and create the naturally labeled poset (Pπ , ω) with the property that E(Pπ , ω) is the set of permutations in the interval [e, π]. Here, the subscript emphasizes that Pπ was created from π. To create Pπ , add labeled elements by reading π left to right. A relation is added between two elements a and b exactly when a is to the left of b in π and a N x. Now, since yx avoids 312 and 231, there are no elements between x and y in π that are larger than y or smaller than x. Also, no elements to the right of x or left of y have values between x and y. To put this description another way, if yx avoids 312 and 231 in π, the elements between y and x in π are exactly those in the set {a | x