{31.3% r L 7‘ .. ' m 1.11:... 1:;‘4 $13521, ,,. DI .1. 1".3 1‘! ”1"““3’fi'51nr‘ . 1': 1131:” ;: 1T3. 1&4}? " J1-111 . ,31 i 5017'» 9;.th “F“. "113» ‘1»;.+fi{§{§%6:21rw ‘ “fwuéhq.§.I 3?! I 1} .1331}? rakfimw-ffmw £2535. Wfiffififi‘i‘gfififi» *‘h'th 3592:? ”131% . * - - 39w? 111%:sz 53“ “5:11:11 . a“ ‘3‘ II Kim I III . 15”“ 5"“‘31fifihIw ”"1 1g". I'Vf. 3312311.“ 111 ”1 km? ".11 11331:“ ~‘11 1-134; I‘EEJ» WE}; éw V 1 111- '1: ma ”Ilijlngym Ii.“ :Tl'iéfi. 11.1. $11.11“ I ’“' ~ 1%-.r“ 111.11% . 111% J. 1% "‘1‘ 14;"??? ":3:— :1" HRH-11x1 fi’tfiut a iflt‘.~‘i_l V u I“ ILI II 7.1. "I. 13.3; :1: ‘15:; 33:19:51.. “EL". "1‘: .w .1. ‘ V 3. 1. "15:."1; 121. ”‘4 .: +131;th M351 1%. n5. 1 - . 137....“ 1. ‘M 51 . , “r . 1,3136 ~ .. .. ~. 51:13.“ first; “.3? " “fi‘tg'i 11:13:... 5-5 ”F113;? - .33.; ”HF m1: 2. .._ "$211.1 y "m "WIZE‘: {111.7% "Una-«.1»! $21 (1 1. ,. I I 1L? ’1: mIIIIAI.) III n? 313.; ‘1' w :«"~ I”: 31.3.3121, :37. "'13:;- W!‘ «I 'L‘ 1 V . ' - firm-«S: ~ flfbwf' ‘ I :Lfi‘ n "L .3?“ 1 1 L3" .5111 1. 4111‘ .9511 i ‘(w ‘ .:1I»Iu JI 3 5.115157%; . I 1:.V‘ujgna-31t ‘13.»! 1 I I. I I. ‘zé‘L 'I‘II “II-IQ; git ...: - #311611; 315111;: ‘3' 1" .32“. L 133,: 13:, 31’1”“; WWI; EE'Lrh-(f: it ‘x - L" In. ‘4 ‘7 ‘39:: 1.; ,.. «1 IIIMI‘I‘E; ”flu-=5:- 1 3.11, :P I I 1-1511“ :3 W315“? L. t: 2; $11,531:? 4:1,. 13;: , :WI, .. $53331 1:; Q1. . fififg 1:1. I ..4,"‘ I '1 11“", 13.“. I I a kin-6.2., _ $1191.13», : 31:1: .21.: “4"‘3512? fig ‘1"ny W1 1 ~ 1:13,“ 131;}? 1 5’3" 3‘1}??? ’x “"1 "Lg-3‘11; 83% V mum “ $37.1 ’- iii: 1 ”kg-{5' “Shrug =11 héggx 3:1 II 9%.}; , .3 .‘3: “$53?" :31?” z? r A 15,35 ‘. ‘ “-3; 6 III II 312 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII III III 619736, 7223 I EKBRAWY __ Michigan State lhnkrersmny This is to certify that the dissertation entitled A CRITIQUE OF THE MARXIST AND NEOCLASSICAL THEORIES OF THE SEXUAL DIVISION OF LABOR presentedby Zohreh Emami-Khoyi has been accepted towards fulfillment of the requirements for .flocmmL degree in _Ecnnnmics. a / Z WWW \I«}"fl//flt/ fl Margy/professor Due August 8, 1985 MSU is an Affirmative Action/Equal Opportunity Institution 0- 12771 RETURNING MATERIALS: Place in book drop to remove this checkout from your record. FINES wiII be charged if book is returned after the date stamped beIow. MSU LIBRARIES V I/ A CRITIQUE OF THE MARXIST AND NEOCLASSICAL THEORIES OF THE SEXUAL DIVISION OF LABOR BY Zohreh Emami—Khoyi A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Economics 1985 ABSTRACT A CRITIQUE OF THE MARXIST AND NEOCLASSICAL THEORIES OF THE SEXUAL DIVISION OF LABOR BY Zohreh Emami-Khoyi The phenomenon of the sexual division of labor, namely, the predominant and exclusive division of tasks between men and women, is the theoretical topic of this dissertation. Its significance as a topic for economic investigation rests with the fact that the sexual division of labor has persisted throughout the history of human society — such that its understanding might begin to contribute to the elimination of sexual inequality, and with the possibility that a focused and coherent understanding of the sexual division of labor might well lead to revision and reconsideration of the economic theory itself. Since a critical approach is particularly appropriate to a topic in which fundamental theoretical questions have not been resolved and definite conclusions have yet to be reached, this work is devoted to the critique of two main economic theories of the sexual division of labor, namely, Marxism and neoclassicism. It argues that both the Marxian and the neoclassical theories suffer from problems of reductionism, circularity, and functionalism, precisely because they attempt to provide strictly economic explanation of the phenomenon of the sexual division of labor. Furthermore, these inadequacies ultimately lead these theories in the direction of naturalistic explanations which ignore the social, cultural, and historical aspects of the process of gender constitution essential to an understanding of the sexual division of labor. Therefore, though making positive contributions to an understanding of the sexual division of labor by recognizing the economic necessity of household production and the economic rationality inherent in the family, these theories remain incomplete without incorporation of some analysis of noneconomic power— relationships. This work concludes that the Marxian theory shows more promise in developing a complete theory of the sexual division of labor, since it is more responsive to considerations of power and self-consciously seeks to develop noneconomic frameworks of analysis. Neoclassical theory, on the other hand, neglects power considerations and does not go beyond strictly economic categories. TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction ...................................... 1 Chapter I: Marx and Engels ........................ 5 Chapter II: The Contemporary Marxists .............. 32 Chapter III: The Chicago School Neoclassicists ..... 57 Chapter IV: The Liberal Neoclassicists ............. 83 Chapter V: Conclusion and Critique.. ............... 102 Bibliography ....................................... 142 INTRODUCTION The theoretical problem of this work is the sexual division of labor, i.e., the predominant and exclusive division of tasks between men and women in society. This problem is significant for several reasons. First, though the sexual division of tasks has varied at different points of time and at any point in time in different societies, the existence of some sexual division of labor has been a persistent phenomenon in human society. Second, one of the most dramatic changes in the contemporary history of capitalist societies has been the increased labor force participation of women of both working-class and middle- class backgrounds. This dramatic change has occurred simultaneously with other profound transformations in the socio—economic structures of the industrialized societies, namely, the ascendancy of monopoly capitalism, the decline of farming and competitive, small, family enterprises; the penetration of capitalism into different facets of the home; and the emergence of new forms of social interaction as implied by changing birth, death, marriage, and divorce rates. However, coincident with all of these changes, reproduction of the sexual division of labor and of sexual inequality has continued. There still is a 40% gap between the earnings of women and men, and women are still occupationally segregated, while experiencing higher rates of unemployment than men. Moreover, the sexual division of labor has not been confined to the sphere of wage work. In non-wage work such as farming, self-employment in manufacturing or trading, and domestic work, e.g., child and house care, the sexual division of labor also has been a continuing phenomenon. Third, an understanding of the sexual division of labor is crucial to any attempt to analyze, understand, and eliminate sexual inequality. Fourth, since sexual division of labor has been a relatively neglected problem in economic theory, a focused historical and theoretical investigation into the issue has the potential of bringing into question not only previous understandings of this phenomenon but also the accepted economic analyses of the division of labor in the economy. The implications of the study of the sexual division of labor therefore go beyond issues concerning women per se and are significant for economic theory and an understanding of the economy as a whole. This work will approach the theoretical problem of the sexual division of labor through a critique of the two traditions in economic theory that have made contributions to an understanding of this issue. The approach here is critical specifically because the topic is one in which fundamental theoretical questions have not been resolved and definite theoretical conclusions have yet to be reached. The questions themselves are in a process of theoretical development. Thus, a critical approach that articulates the problems and questions in the economic theories of the sexual division of labor is particularly appropriate. The two schools of economic thought that are examined here are the Marxist and the neoclassical. Chapter I presents and critiques the analysis of the sexual division of labor and the subordinate position of women developed by Marx and Engels. Chapter II critically traces the development of contemporary Marxist theory through an examination of the reactions of recent Marxist theorists to the limitations of orthodox Marxism discussed in Chapter I. With respect to the neoclassical school, two camps in this tradition can be distinguished according to their views concerning the possibility of economic reform enacted by capitalist government. Chapter III critiques the conservative camp of neoclassicism, namely, the Chicago School, with respect to its treatment of the sexual division of labor and what has more generally been called to as the "new home economics". In Chapter IV the Chicago School's ”new home economics" is contrasted with liberal neoclassicists' analysis of women's labor supply. Chapter IV closes with an evaluation of liberal neoclassicism’s reform orientation and its fundamental assumptions about the nature of power in society. The final Chapter, after a brief summary of the Marxist and neoclassical literature on the sexual division of labor, compares and contrasts these two schools with respect to their theories of the position of women in the economy and the sexual division of labor. The chapter concludes with an assessment of the state of our knowledge on this topic in light of the understanding acquired through the examination of the economic theories of Marxism and neoclassicism. It is argued that an awareness of the limitations of a specifically economic treatment of the sexual division of labor leads us to a greater understanding of what we do know and still need to learn about this phenomenon. CHAPTER I MARX AND ENGELS In the midst of the Industrial Revolution there emerged a social philosopher, Karl Marx, whose influence on socialist thought has survived to the present. Together with Friedrich Engels, Marx expounded the philosophy of historical materialism on which he based his study of capitalism. According to this perspective, although all social institutions and intellectual traditions are related through a complex structure of cause and effect relationships. A society's mode of production and thereby its material economic base is the most important influence in determining. social institutions and the ideological, religious, and intellectual traditions of society. Marx identified his notion of the mode of production by dividing it into two elements, namely, the forces of production and the relations of production. The forces of production were in turn defined as the general level of technology, including production skills and knowledge, and tools, equipment, and factories. The relations of production were for Marx the social relations between the human beings in society in terms of their relationship to the means of production. Marx called the mode of production the foundation or the economic base, while the modes of thought (including ethical, religious, and intellectual ideas) and the social institutions he identified as the society's superstructure. Marx was a methodological collectivist since by referring to the relations of production he was interested in class -— as a collection of human beings defined by their relationship to the means of production -- as his category for analyzing the economic structure of society. Viewing the class structure of society as the most important single aspect of the mode of production, Marx proclaimed the antagonism between classes as the propelling' force in history. In each of the four separate economic systems that Marx identified -- 1) primitive communal, 2) slave, 3) feudal, 4) capitalist -- the contradictions that develop between the forces of production and the relations of production show themselves in the form of class struggle. Within his historical approach Marx employed the dialectical method of identifying the nature of conflicts and contradictions between classes as the dynamic sources of struggle and historical change. Marx believed that, although in all pre-capitalist economic systems the intensification of class struggle had destroyed one class system only to replace it with another based on the exploitation of a large class by a new ruling class, capitalism and thereby the class of capitalists would be overthrown by the proletariat which would eventually establish a classless society. According to Marx capitalism has two features that distinguish it from the systems prior to it. First, there is a class of owners and a class of workers who are separated from the means of 'production. Second, under capitalism the market extends into all human relations. Marx's normative analysis can be clearly identified through his moral condemnations of capitalism which he saw as a system in which people cannot develop their potentialities. Humans, according to Marx, are different from animals because through their work they can shape and control their environment. It is through work that humans refine and develop their senses and intellect and achieve pleasure and self-realization. In pre-capitalist systems, despite the existence of exploitative class structures, humans could achieve this self-realization through their work. Since these exploitative class relations were at the same time personal and paternalistic, the purpose of work was not merely making money. All this changes with the advent of capitalism. Marx and Engels wrote in the Communist Manifesto: . the bourgeoisie, wherever it has got the upper hand, has put an end to all feudal patriarchal, idyllic relations. It has pitilessly torn asunder the motley feudal ties that bound man to his "natural superiors," and has left remaining no other nexus between man and man than naked self-interest, than callous "cash payment." It has drowned the most heavenly ecstasies of religious fervor, of chivalrous enthusiasm, of philistine sentimentalism, in the icy water of egoistical calculation. It has resolved personal worth into exchange value . . .1 Marx condemned in the capitalist system this degradation and dehumanization of the working class, which he termed alienation.2 Marx's analysis and method were both positive and normative. While in his theoretical endeavor he attempted to analyze the "laws of motion" of capitalism, he also claimed that "The philosophers have only interpreted the world, in various ways; the point, however, is to change it."3 Both Marx's historical materialist method and his analysis of capitalism have been criticized as economic determinism.4 More specifically, for having emphasized the economic base and the category of class, Marx has been accused of underestimating the influence of ideological (or what he calls superstructural) factors on the development of society. The dichotomy of base/superstructure, has been considered responsible for his reductionist characterization of the other forms of oppression present in capitalism such as racism and sexism. In this chapter we examine Marx's historical materialist analysis of the position of women and thereby the sexual division of labor in capitalist society. Friedrich Engels referred to The Origins 9f the Family, Private Property, and the State as a "bequest," a "debt I 5 owe to Marx." In the winter of 1880—1881 Marx read Lewis Morgan's Ancient Society, 93 Researches in the Lines 9; Human Progress from Savagery through Barbarism pg Civilization, and was struck by its relevance to his own theory. But ill health prevented his doing more than take ninety-eight pages of notes on the book. In 1884, a year after Marx's death, Engels published the work that his friend apparently had wished to write.6 It was Engels, therefore, who attempted a systematic exposition of the historical materialistic approach to the question of woman's status and the sexual division of labor in modern society, using as his basis the anthropological work of Lewis Morgan. He employed Morgan's three-fold classification of the stages of history -- savagery, marked by gathering and hunting; barbarism, marked by animal breeding and agriculture; civilization, marked by art and industry -- to demonstrate how women's position deteriorates outside the communist structure. In savagery, group marriage or unrestricted sexual freedom prevails, paternity is unknown, and only the female [line or Mother Right is recognized. The childbearing function, and hence woman, is held in high esteem. In this communist structure everyone contributes to the economy, no one is dependent, and there is no distinction between the public and the domestic. With barbarism the pairing family emerges and, to insure paternity, women are held to strict fidelity. The division of labor becomes segregated, since without the need to hunt men turn to flocks and crops. Private property and paternity effect the overthrow of Mother Right, and women are rendered 10 economically dependent. With civilization, monogamy prevails and the patriarchal family solidifies male supremacy. Thus the first class struggle emerges as antagonism among the sexes. Engels believed that wives are essentially slaves, part of men's property just as are land and cattle. Engels predicted that only under socialism, with the abolition of private property, would the relationship between men and women change. Wives would no longer belong to husbands. When marriage is determined by love, not economy, both marriage and divorce will become much simpler. In the Preface to The Origins 9; 3h; Family Engels pointed out that up to 1861, which was the year of the publication of Bachofen's "Mutterrecht" (Maternal Law), there had been no systematic attempt to study the history of the family. Indeed, prior to 1861 the patriarchal form of the family "was not only without further comment considered as the most ancient, but also as identical with the family of our times. No historical development of the family was even recognized."7 Even though historical cases of monogamy, oriental polygamy, and Indo-Tibetan polyandry were known, these forms were never arranged in any historical order and were simply treated as "queer customs" without any connections. According to Engels, Bachofen's work was the first attempt to systematically develop the history of the family. And, although Engels found Bachofen's volume somewhat troublesome and at times frustrating because of its biased 11 nature stemming from Bachofen's mystical conceptions, he nevertheless believed that, "all this does not curtail the 8 value of his fundamental work." According to Engels, Bachofen was the first to question the assumption of a timeless and ahistorical patriarchal form of the family "by the demonstration that ancient classical literature points out a multitude of traces proving the actual existence among Greeks and Asiatics of other sexual relations before 9 monogamy." Engels agrees with Bachofen that with economic development undermining what he calls "the old communism" and with increasing population, "traditional sexual relations lost their innocent character suited to the 10 primitive forest," and the new form of relation that emerged became more debasing and oppressive to women. Engels' normative position was that: [The monogamous family] is founded on male supremacy for the pronounced purpose of breeding children of indisputable paternal lineage. The latter is required, because these children shall later on inherit the fortune of their father. The monogamous family is distinguished from the pairing family by the far greater durability of wedlock, which can no longer be dissolved at the pleasure of either party. As a rule, it is only the man who can still dissolve it and cast off his wife. The privilege of conjugal faithlessness remains sanctioned for men at least by custom (the Code Napoleon concedes it directly to them, as long as they do not bring their concubines into the houses of their wives). This privilege is more and more enjoyed with the increasing development of society. If the woman remembers the ancient sexual practices and attempts to revive them, she is punished more severely than ever. 11 12 The monogamous family, represents the subjugation of one sex by the other as far as Engels was concerned. Indeed, rather than being the highest form of marriage and a reconciliation between the husband and wife, the monogamous family reflects an antagonism between the two sexes that is unprecedented in history. Engels again mixed historical and normative analysis in order to conclude that The first class antagonism appearing in history coincides with the development of the antagonism of man and wife in monogamy, and the first class oppression with that of the female sex by the male sex. Monogamy was a great historical progress. But by the side of slavery and private property it marks at the same time that epoch which, reaching down to our days, takes with all progress also a step backwards, relatively speaking, and develops the welfare and advancement of one by the woe and submission of the other.12 In the monogamous family, this cellular form of civilized society, Engels sought to understand the contrasts and contradictions inherent in this society. Accepting Morgan's analysis in Ancient Society, Engels argued that the victory of the monogamous family by no means implies the complete defeat and disappearance of "the old 13 relative freedom of sexual intercourse". This freedom for both sexes, however, is transformed in civilization into what Engels, following Morgan, called hetaerism by which they meant sexual intercourse of men with unmarried women outside of the monogamous family. This hetaerism, which according to Engels flourishes during the whole period of civilization in many different forms, tends more and more 13 towards open prostitution. To Engels hetaerism is a social institution which continues the old sexual freedom, for the benefit however, of men only. Even when denounced, and it is only nominally denounced, this denunciation strikes by no means the men who indulge in it, but only the women. In fact, it is not only permitted for men, but it is assiduously practiced by the of the ruling class. Women, however, are "ostracized and cast out by society, in order to proclaim once more the fundamental law of unconditional male supremacy over the 14 female sex." Thus, Engels was led to see a second contradiction inherent in the nature of monogamy itself. By the side of the husband, who is making his life pleasant by hetaerism, stands the neglected wife. And you cannot have one side of the contradiction without the other, just as you can not have the whole apple after eating half of it. Nevertheless this seems to have been the idea of the men, until their wives taught them a lesson. Monogamy introduces two permanent social characters that were formerly unknown: the standing lover of the wife and the cuckold. The men had gained the victory over the women but the vanquished magnanimously provided the coronation. In addition to monogamy and hetaerism, adultery became an unavoidable social institution — denounced, severely punished, but irrepressible. 15 Therefore, Engels saw in the monogamous family a clear expression of the conflict between men and women created by the exclusive supremacy of men, a miniature picture of the contrasts and contradiction of society as a whole. Engels 14 quoted Marx to prove that indeed they are in general agreement on this point: The modern family contains the germ not only of slavery (servitus), but also of serfdom, because it has from the start a relation to agriculture service. It comprises in miniature all those contrasts that later on develop more broadly in society and the state.16 In both the advent of the pairing and the transition of this family form to the monogamous patriarchal family, Engels saw the reliability of paternal lineage guaranteed by securing the faithfulness of the wife and delivering women absolutely into the power of men. Indeed, for Engels the monogamous family has the specific character of being monogamy for women alone and not for men. Engels saw the formal and informal inequalities between men and women being caused in the final analysis by the economic dependence and oppression of women. More specifically, in the old communistic societies the administration of the household (which comprised many adults and children) was entrusted to women, and this was as much a social and public function as the job of providing food which was for men. With the advent of the patriarchal, and especially the monogamous, family women lose their equal social—economic footing in public life. Women retain their job of administering the household, while the administration of the household loses its public character, and stops being a concern of society. Indeed, woman's job in the household acquires the character of a private service. In fact, even 15 with the availability of access to social production for some women, "they remain excluded from public production and cannot earn anything, if they fulfill their duties in the private service of the family: or that they are unable to attend their family duties, if they wish to participate in public industries and earn a living independently."17 Modern society is composed of "molecules" in the form of monogamous families, while the foundation of modern family is the overt and covert domestic slavery of women. The man with his public responsibility of earning a living and supporting the family has obtained a superior position. "In the family, he is the bourgeois, the woman represents the proletariat."18 Thus, for Engels, achieving legal equality between the sexes is only the prerequisite for their emancipation. Legal equality simply offers the battleground on which the struggle for the re—introduction of the whole female sex into the public industries can be fought, and this can only be accomplished when the monogamous family ceases to be the industrial unit of society. Engels predicted a social revolution that would abolish the historical basis of the economic foundation of both monogamy and prostitution. This impending revolution, by socializing the means of production and thus abolishing the conditions of accumulation of wealth in only a few hands, would reduce and ultimately eliminate the need for private inheritance which is the foundation upon which monogamy is 16 based. Since for Engels the legal and social oppression of women, as portrayed in the historic monogamous family is ultimately founded on the economic dependency of women in class society, the question that he had to answer is whether monogamy would disappear when the class system of capitalism is abolished. Engels' reply was that not only would monogamy not disappear but it would become perfectly realized. He argued that with the transformation of society and collectivization of the means of production, wage labor and thus the proletariat itself would disappear. With the elimination of wage labor, the necessity for a certain number of women to surrender for money through prostitution will also disappear. With the abolition of prostitution monogamy will not only not go out of existence but it will finally apply to men as well as to women. Engels claimed that after the revolution the monogamous family would cease being the fundamental economic unit of society, thereby, radically changing the situation of both men and women. The functions that were formerly entrusted to the private unit of the family, such as care and basic education of children and private housekeeping, would become matters of public responsibility and a social industry. This would finally be the time when "a new element becomes active, an element which at best existed only in the germ at the time when monogamy developed: individual sexlove.”19 Engels believed that what he calls sexlove is by its very nature exclusive and thus by nature monogamous. Hence, 17 once the economic conditions are removed that have tended to make monogamy apply to women alone by forcing them to submit tothe customary disloyalty of men, women will be placed on an equal footing with men. Thus, it was Engels' belief that rather than giving rise to a gradual increase in unconventional intercourse and making women polyandrous, the realization of individual sexlove would make men truly monogamous. Indeed, society would finally see monogamy with none of the peculiarities and distortions that are stamped upon it because of its rise out of private property relations. More specifically, when male supremacy, which is the result of man's economic independence and superiority, vanishes, there would disappear with it the very basis of male supremacy in monogamy. The direction of causation is from economic change to the establishment of equality and thereby elimination of supremacy, subordination, and dependency. What we may anticipate about the adjustment of sexual relations after the impending downfall of capitalist production is mainly of a negative nature and mostly confined to elements that will disappear. But what will be added? That will be decided after a new generation has come to maturity: a race of men who never in their lives have had any occasion for buying with money or other economic means of power the surrender of women; a race of women who have never had any occasion for surrendering to any man for any other reason but love, or for refusing to surrender to their lover for fear of economic consequences. Once such people are in the world, they will not give a moment's thought to what we today believe should be their course. They will follow their own practice and fashion their own 18 public opinion about the individual practice of every person - only this and nothing more. 20 While Engels was the one who in Th; Origin 2; Egg Family formulated the Marxian theory of the family, there are partial statements on the family and women's exploitation in The Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, The Communig; Manifesto,The German Ideology,and Capital.21 Marx and Engels stated their position on the bourgeois family in The Communist Manifesto, where they saw the family relation as having been reduced to a mere money relation. The bourgeois sees in his wife a mere instrument of production. On what foundation is the present family based? On capital, on private gain . . . . The bourgeois clap-trap about the family and education, about hallowed corelation of parent and child, becomes all the more disgusting the more by the action of modern industry, all family ties among the proletarians .are torn asunder, and than children transformed into simple articles of commerce and instruments of labor. 22 The relations of private property become the mode of exchange. The development of these bourgeois priorities transform social relations in the family and, as Marx made clear in The German Ideology, the family, which was seen as the only truly social relationship, becomes a subordinate need.23 The concerns of private property and possession pervade man-woman relations. In "On The Jewish Question," Marx wrote: "The species relation itself between man and woman etc., becgmes an object of commerce. The woman is bought and sold." The mentality of "having" twists species relationships into those of ownership and domination, and 19 marriage into prostitution. Marx saw women's problem as arising from their status as mere instruments of reproduction and the solution in the socialist revolution. In the Manifesto Marx and Engels wrote that "the abolition of the present system of production must bring with it the abolition of the community of women springing from that system, i.e., of prostitution, both 25 public and private." Marx did not propose the abolition of the family. He denounced the incompatibility of the family, such as he observed it, with the woman working outside the home. He deplored the consequences of the hard life of the working woman for rearing her children, for parental authority, and for family morality. And he certainly did not consider the European family as it existed at that time to be the only possible form of conjugal union. However, what is harmful for children and parents alike is the destruction of the family without any new structure being offered to replace it. Even in its most depressing aspects, therefore, capitalism represents an important step toward a new type of family: However terrible and disgusting, therefore, the dissolution, under the capitalist system, of the old family ties may appear, nevertheless, modern industry, by assigning as it does an important part in the process of production outside the domestic sphere to women, to young persons, and to children of both sexes, creates a new economic foundation for a higher form of the family and of the relations between the sexes. 26 20 Apropos of Marx's economic determinism, in the final instance, capitalism not only creates the conditions of existence of the present family with all its problems; but it also creates the conditions under which the nature of this family can be transformed into a "higher form". Marx was far from preaching anarchic sexual freedom; for him that meant making woman even more the mere object of man's pleasure than she is already. He rejected that vulgar communism which contemplates the establishment of a community of women.27 Strengthening woman strengthens man as well, for he who obtains gratification from an object, who has no need to enter into relations with another human being, loses all humanity. Thus, for Marx the genuine liberation of women was part of the more general process of humanization of the entire species. The relationship that exists between man and woman is a good indication of the state of human essence. Since Marx never considered the woman problem as something isolated from society, whatever its structural type, he steadfastly refused to accept simple reformist measures that proposed to protect women or provide sugar coating for their real suffering. It is rather the root 28 causes of the degradation of women which he sought. He sees bourgeois institutions as parasitic to the core: the bourgeoisie make the laws for others to observe. The transgression of the laws is the bourgeoisie's special talent. They violate the laws of marriage, family, and 21 property, yet these institutions remain intact and form the very foundation of class society. Since the only real ties existing within the bourgeois family are those of boredom, money, and adultery, an infraction of its outward juridical form is in fact of no importance. On the contrary, it is maintained as it exists in fact, not as it appears within the juridical superstructure. This is the line Marx took in countering the charge that communists want to introduce a community of women. Since for the bourgeoisie, he explained, woman is a mere instrument of production, and the communists propose to introduce common ownership of the instruments of production, they conclude from this that communists want to introduce a community of women. But for the bourgeoisie such a community already exists. "Our bourgeois, not content with having the wives and daughters of the proletarians at their disposal... takes the greatest pleasure in seducing each other's wives."29 Thus, for Marx the determining factor of woman's social existence derived from a system of produCtion premised upon the oppression of class by class —— a system which alienates and corrupts the body as well the mind. The solution, then, lies in the destruction of this phase of the historical, or rather prehistorical development of humankind. Therefore, Marx believed that women, like men, would only attain true freedom under socialism. 22 Evaluation: Marx saw the bourgeois family as an instrument of capitalist society with no dimension particular unto itself. Woman's oppression is her exploitation in a class society through bourgeois marriage and the- family. Woman is perceived as just another victim, undistinguished from the proletariat in general, of the class division of labor. The sexual division of labor, as the definition of roles, purposes, activities, etc., had no independent existence for Marx. He did not understand, for instance, that the sexual division of labor in society assigns. noncreative and isolative work particularly for women. As a result, Marx perceives the exploitation of men and women as deriving from the same source and assumed that their oppression could be understood in the same structural terms. It has since been argued however that capital and private property are not the cause of the oppression of women qua women, and that in fact women's inferior status predates both private property and capitalism. In this View, the end of capitalism and private property alone will not result in the end of women's oppression. It might very well be that in communist society, where all are to achieve species existence, life would still be structured by a sexual division of labor which would entail different life options for men and women. Sex roles would preassign tasks to women which would necessitate continued alienation 30 and isolation. 23 In The German Ideology, Marx and Engels discussed the division of labor in early pre-capitalist society in familial terms. The first division of labor was the "natural" division of labor in the family through the act of child—breeding. The act of child-breeding, therefore, began the division of labor. It is through this act that the first appearance of property arose within the family. For Marx and Engels, this is when the wife and child became slaves of the husband. This latent slavery in the family, though still very crude, is the first property, but even at this stage it corresponds perfectly to the definition of modern economists who call it the power of disposing of the labor power of others. Division of labor and private property are moreover identical expressions . . .31 Here are the seeds of an early, although crude, insight into the nature of the sexual division of labor, although there is no discussion of it as such. What weakens and finally limits the insight is that for Marx and Engels the division of labor deriving from the act of child—breeding is coincidental and identical with the birth of private property: "division of labor and private property are 32 moreover identical expressions." The division of labor has no specific quality of its own; property arising from a division of labor in the act of procreation is not differentiated from property arising from the relations of capital. Reproduction and production are seen as one, as they come to be analyzed in relation to the capitalist 24 division of labor in society. There is no notion here that inequalities might arise from the act of child-breeding and childrearing. Although reproduction was acknowledged as the first source of the division of labor, it never received specific further examination. The German Ideology presented, then, a skeletal analysis of women's condition as it changes through material conditions. The division of labor is at this stage still very elementary and is confined to a further extension of the natural division of labor imposed by the family.33 The division of labor "imposed by the family" is here spoken of as "naturalh, and whether-this means necessary or good it is a division which was accepted by Marx and Engels. Here, then, the division of labor in the family is not viewed as reflective of the economic society which defines and surrounds it —- as it is in the later Communist Manifesto -- but rather at this early stage Marx and Engels saw the family structuring the society and its division of labor. Marx and Engels' analysis of the family continued: "there develops the division of labor in the sexual act, then that division of labor which develops spontaneously or naturally by virtue of natural predigposition (e.g., physical strength) needs, accidents, etc." In The Origins g; the Family, Engels repeated the theme developed in The German Ideology: that the "first division of labor is that between man and woman for child- 35 breeding." The first class antagonism thus arose with the antagonism between man and woman in monogamous marriage, but 25 . 36 what this antagonism is based on is never made clear. Engels' claim was that the first class antagonism accompanied (arose with) the antagonism between man and woman. One would not think that the antagonism referred to is one of class. Yet he ultimately wrote of the conflict between man and woman as class conflict. The man represents the bourgeoisie within the family, the wife represents the proletariat.37 But the bourgeoisie and the proletariat are respectively positions of power and powerlessness deriving from a relation to the economic means of production, not to the act of reproduction. By categorizing men and women as classes and using the category of class as a metaphor, the relations of reproduction are subsumed under the relations of production. It is contradictory that Engels acknowledged male-female relations within the family as defining the division of labor in society and yet completely subsumed them under the categories of analysis related to production. He offered no explanation that could resolve this dilemma because it stands outside the terms of his analysis. Engels acknowledged that the division of labor emanated from the family to society. Yet his categories of analysis explaining the slavery of women in the family derived entirely from the relations of production. These categories simply take the form of metaphors. The family comes to be defined by the historical economic modes; it does not itself take part in defining the economy as well as the society, and it is no longer spoken of as a source of the division of 26 labor coincident with economic relations. Economic existence comes to determine the family. Hence, Engels forgot his own analysis of the "first division of labor" and assumed that the family will disintegrate and the first division of labor will simply disappear with the elimination of capitalism instead of analyzing how the family itself comes to support an economic mode. Although he acknowledged the problem of women's existence within a private domestic sphere, he saw this reflecting the relations of production rooted in private property. Women's activity in reproduction, which limits her activity in production, is not seen as problematic, as socially derivative. The family has become a microcosm of the political economy for Engels."38 The bourgeoisie- and proletariat became metaphors: the man being the bourgeois and the woman the proletariat. Interestly Engels did not use the metaphoric categories of male as bourgeois and female as proletariat outside of the family. There people were assigned class positions according to their relation to the means of production, not their sex. He used different criteria inside and outside the family to define membership in a class. In the family, economic dependency and subordination distinguish class membership while in the economy it is relationship to the means of production. If these categories were built on like bases of power, the same criterion would be applicable both in and out of the family. And if one wants to say that the family is economic, there 27 are evidently still other considerations involved. If this were not so, then he would not have (1) class divisions in the family as bourgeois-male/proletariat-female, and (2) class divisions in society in terms of ownership of the means of production. Even though, for Engels these ultimately meant the same thing, what do they say about the relations of the family and capitalism? Most of the time Engels worked from the simple equation that oppression equals exploitation. Even though Engels recognized that the family conceals domestic slavery, he believed at the same time that there are no differences, in kind between the domestic slavery of the wife and the wage slavery of the worker under capitalism. They are both derived from capitalism. The real equality of women would come with the end of exploitation by capital and the transference of private housework to public industry. But given his lack of understanding of the sexual division of labor and the hierarchical sexual ordering of society per‘ se, even the public domestic world would, for Engels, most probably remain woman's work. In conclusion, the analysis sketched by Marx and Engels in The German Ideology, and then further developed by Engels in The Origins g: the Family, Private Propertyy and the State, reveals their belief that the family, at some time in the historic past, structured the division of labor in society, and that this division of labor reflected the division of labor in the act of procreation. Initially, the 28 family structure defined the structure of society: According to the material conception, the determining factor in history is, in the final instance, the production and reproduction of immediate life. This, again, is of a two-fold character: on the one side, the production of the means of existence, of food, clothing and shelter and the tools necessary for that production; on the other side, the production of human beings themselves, the propagation of the species. The social organization under which the people of a particular historical epoch and a particular country live is determined by both kinds of production; by the stage of development of labor on the one hand and of the family on the other.39 This perception is lost, however, in the discussion of the family in capitalist society, for here the family comes to be viewed as just another part of the superstructure, totally reflective of class society and relations of production. The point is not that the family does not reflect society, but that through both its patriarchal structure and patriarchal ideology the family and the need for reproduction also structure society. This reciprocal relationship between the family and society, and between production and reproduction, defines the life of women.40 The study of women's situation then, must deal with both sexual and economic material conditions if we are to understand sexual oppression as well as economic exploitation. FOOTNOTES 1. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, "Communist Manifesto," in The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by R. Tucker, (New York: W. W. Norton Company, 1972). p. 337. 2. Bertall Ollman, Alienation: Marx's Conception 9; Man ip Capitalist Society, (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1971). 3. Karl Marx, "Theses on Feuerbach," in The Marx- Engels Reader, edited by R. Tucker, (New York: W. W. Norton Company, 1972), p. 343. 4. M. M. Bober, Karl Marx's Interpretation 9; History, (New York: W. W. Norton and Company, 1965). 5. Friedrich Engels, The Origins g; the Family Private Property and the State, (Chicago: Charles H. Kerr and Company: 1902), p. 10. 6. Martha Osborne, figmgp lg Western Thoughg, (New York: Random House, 1979). 7. Engels, The Origins, pp; gigg, p. 13. 8. gpggy, p. 15. 9. gpggy, p.'16. ‘10. Ibid., p. 54. 11. Ibid., p. 79. 12. Ibid., p. 79. 13. Ibid., p. 80. 14. Ibid , p. 82. 15. Ibid , p 81. 16. Ibid , p 79. 17. Ibid , p 89. 18. Ibid , p 89. 29 30 19. Ibid., p. 84. 20. Ibid., p. 100. 21. Karl Marx, [pg Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts pf 1844, (New York: International Publishers, 1964); Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology, (New York: International Publishers, 1947); Karl Marx, Capital, Vol. I, (New York: International Publisher, 1977). 22. Marx and Engels, "Communist Manifesto," op. cit., p. 349. 23. Marx and Engels, The German Ideology, op. cit., p. 17. “‘_‘ 24. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, "On the Jewish Question," in The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by R. Tucker, (New York: W. W. Norton Company, 1972), p. 109. 25. Marx and Engels, "Communist Manifesto," op. cit., p. 350. 26. Marx, Capital, Vol. I, op. cit., p. 489. 27. Marx, Manuscripts pf 1844, op. cit., pp.133—4. 28. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Holy family, (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1963), p. 224. 29. Marx and Engels, "Communist Manifesto," op. cit., p. 35. 30. See Heidi Hartmann, "The Unhappy Marriage of Marxism and Feminism: Towards a more Progressive Union," in Women and Revolution, edited by L. Sayent, (Boston: South End Press, 1981). 31. Marx and Engels, German Ideology, op. cit., pp. 21-2. 32. Ipigy 33. gpggy, p. 9. 34. gpggg, p. 20. 35. Engels, Tpg Originsy 0p. cit., p. 79. 36. gpigy, p. 79. 37. gpggy, p. 89. 38. Ibid., p. 82. 31 39. Ibid., p. 10. 40. See Lydia Sargent, Women and Revolution, (Boston: South End Press, 1981). CHAPTER II THE CONTEMPORARY MARXISTS Contemporary Marxist analysis of the woman question has taken three main forms. First, contemporary Marxists have incorporated women into an analysis of everyday life in capitalism. From this perspective men and women are both viewed as workers and all aspects of women's lives are seen to reproduce the capitalist system.1 Second, Marxist- Feminists have emphasized the importance of searching for the material base of male domination and have attempted to create a broad theoretical framework which locates sexual inequality directly within the social relations of specific historical social structures.2 Third, Marxists have focused on housework and its relation to capital, some arguing that housework produces surplus value and that houseworkers work directly for capitalists.3 Perhaps the most popular work exemplifying the first Marxist approach is the series of articles by Eli Zaretsky 4 in Socialist Revolution. Recognizing that traditionally Marxist analysis has subsumed the issues of sexism and the sexual division of labor under the specific category of class and the general analysis of capitalism, Zaretsky argues that sexism is not a new phenomenon produced by 32 33 capitalism but that the particular form which sexism now takes has been shaped by capitalism. Zaretsky's analysis focuses on the differential experiences of men and women under capitalism by emphasizing that capitalism has not incorporated women into the labor force on equal terms with men. In fact, Zaretsky who sees a clear separation between the home, family, and personal life, on the one hand and the workplace, on the other, argues that this has been created by capital. According to Zaretsky, it is this separation between housework and wage work that has made sexism so strong and destructive under capitalism by excluding women from wage work and thereby increasing the level of their oppression. Indeed, Zaretsky argues that under capitalism men are oppressed by having to do wage work, while women are oppressed by not being allowed to do wage work. Zaretsky does not define the term oppression explicitly but seems to use it to denote being dominated and subordinated. He sees capitalism as directly and primarily causing the exclusion of women from the labor force, since this system not only creates wage work outside the home but also requires the confinement of women in the home for the purpose of reproducing the labor force and providing psychological nurturing for the workers. Indeed, one could disagree with Zaretsky's starting point by mentioning that women have participated in wage work throughout the history of capitalism and that their labor force participation rates 34 have increased dramatically since 1890's. It is based on the dichotomy of housework and wage work that Zaretsky argues his main point, however, that women work for capital rather than for men per se. More specifically, the privatization of housework which has resulted from the separation of the home from the work place has created the appearance that women work for men privately in the home. This appearance, however, obscures the essence or the reality that women work for capital. Zaretsky sees the difference between the appearance (that women work for men) and the reality (that women work for capital) as having caused a misdirection of the energies of the women's movement. He argues that women should recognize that they too are part of the working class even though they work at home. For Zaretsky, "the housewife emerged, alongside the proletariat [as] the two characteristic laborers of developed capitalist society."5 What is needed, therefore, is a complete reconceptualization of "production". According to Zaretsky, we need a notion of production which includes women's housework if we are to establish a socialist society in which the destructive separation between housework and wage work is overcome. On the more practical level, Zaretsky proposes that men and women struggle both together and _separately to reunite these divided and alienated spheres of their lives. He sees this as the only route to a humane socialism capable of meeting the private and public needs of 35 its people. Thus, for Zaretsky, recognizing capitalism as the root of the problem of both men and women is essential, since this recognition will entice them to fight capital and not each other. Since capitalism is the cause of the separation between our private and public lives, the end of capitalism will end that separation, reunite our lives, and end the oppression of both men and women. Zaretsky accepts the arguments that sexism predates capitalism and that housework is crucial to the reproduction of capital. Moreover, he not only does not belittle housework but considers it hard work. His own analysis rests strongly on his notion of separation and the concept of division between wage work and housework as the crux of the problem, a division that he ultimately attributes to capitalism. It is through his emphasis on the separate but equally important spheres of the home and the market, however, that Zaretsky ultimately denies the existence of inequality between men and women. More specifically, in his analysis of the family, the labor market, the economy, and the society he simply explains the sexual division of labor in capitalism, while in the final analysis failing to tell us why this division places men in a superior, and women in a subordinate position. In other words, even if we accept his theoretical position that capitalism is responsible for the creation of the private sphere as separate and divided from the public sphere, we are still left with the question of how it happened that women work in the private sphere and 36 6 men in the public sphere. Zaretsky sees the creation of the private sphere of the household as the capitalist system's contribution to women's oppression, just as Engels saw private property as the cause of this oppression. Zaretsky's humane socialism, like Engels', will ultimately reunite the family in the image of their romanticized version of the pre-industrial family in which men, women, and children work together. While Zaretsky sees women's work as only appearing to benefit men when ’in reality it is for capital, it has also been argued that women's work in the family really is for men -- though it clearly reproduces capitalism as well. Thus, the struggle between men and women will have to continue along with the struggle against capital.7 It is in light of these weaknesses in Zaretsky's version of contemporary Marxist analysis of women's situation that Marxist-feminists have attempted to locate the material base of male domination similar to the material base Marx found for working class exploitation. One of the first attempts at such an ambitious project was by Juliet Mitchell. In her article, "Women: The Longest Revolution," Mitchell postulates the existence of two separate but interacting spheres of domination, the family versus the organization of production.8 She makes an important contribution by dividing the private sphere of the family into three distinct structures: 1) Reproduction, 2) Sexuality, and 3) Socialization. Women's oppression is 37 located for Mitchell in the organization of all three of these structures as well as in production. She writes: The lesson of these reflections is that the liberation of women can only be achieved if all four structures in which they are .integrated are transformed. A modification of any one of them can be offset by a reinforcement of another, so that mere permutation of the form of exploitation is achieved.9 For Mitchell, the material base of women's oppression is located within and between these three structures and production. She rejects the reduction of the women's problem to their inability to work, which stresses women's simple subordination to the institution of private property and class exploitation. The importance of Mitchell's analysis is in her focus and emphasis on the powerlessness that women experience because they are reproductive beings, sexual beings, working individuals, and socializers of children - in all dimensions of their activities. Thus, power is seen by Mitchell as a complex reality.10 However, upon closer examination, we can see that Mitchell reverts back to the analysis of her socialist predecessors. One is still left with the need to clarify the relationship of the family and the political economy of capitalist society. The question arises: if the structures Mitchell postulates are the source of women's oppression, how do men fit in, i.e., what is the relationship of men and women in creating and maintaining these structures? Mitchell still maintains a form of women/domestic sphere and 38 men/public sphere dichotomy. The material connection of the four structures and relations are not presented. For Mitchell, it is production in the last instance which is important. The material base of the family ultimately turns out to be ideological. To put the matter schematically . . . we are . . . dealing with two autonomous areas: the economic mode of capitalism and the ideological mode of patriarchy.11 Mitchell reaches this position because for her not all of women's work counts as production. Only market work is identified as production while the other spheres, which she loosely aggregates as the family, are identified as ideological. Thus, patriarchy which largely organizes reproduction, sexuality, and child-rearing, has no material base for Mitchell. Indeed, she clearly presents patriarchy as the fundamental ideological structure, just as capital is the fundamental economic structure. Thus, the structure of women's oppression becomes a reflection of cultural values and mores, rather than concrete social relations with inherent contradictions and tensions. Credit must be given to Mitchell, however, for giving voice and direction to later Marxist-feminists by beginning the demystification of the family. Her dichotomy of the double spheres -- domestic versus public -- was seized upon and subsequently elaborated in many forms. Two of these further developments, were by Gayle Rubin12 and .Heidi 13 Hartmann and will be examined here. Both of these writers 39 present production as one sphere of domination; on the other side, Rubin postulates a "sex-gender system," and Hartmann, patriarchy. The choice of these two terms is a reflection of what elements each theorist intends to highlight. Rubin's definition of the sex-gender system" - —the set of arrangements by which a society transforms biological 14 sexuality into products of human activity," - - focuses upon the organization of sexuality. She goes on to specify that ". . . at the most general level,. the social organization of sex rests upon gender, obligatory heterosexuality, and the constraint of female sexuality."15 In contrast, patriarchy for Hartmann is " . . . a set of social relations between men, . . . which hierarchically establish or create interdependence and solidarity among men that enable them to dominate women."16 She argues that this focus captures the notion of hierarchy and male domination, which she considers central to the present system, since "Hierarchies work at least in part because they create vested interests in the status quo."17 As a result of these different starting points, each writer offers a different understanding of the material base of sexual inequality. For Rubin, emphasis is placed on sexual coercion; through the exchange of women by men, men ensure that the basic unit of society is one man and one woman with mutual interdependence. The material base for Hartmann, on the other hand, revolves around male hierarchies which enable men to both control women's labor 40 and to claim the valued characteristic of the dominant ideology. However, both of these attempts fall short in their endeavor to connect the dual spheres of production and male domination. Although Hartmann begins her analysis with a thorough critique of past attempts by Marxists and Marxist-feminists, which basically centers around the inadequacies of Marxist categories to explain sexual inequality, and emphasizes the need to create new conceptualizations, her analysis comes full circle. Her analysis concludes with the traditional Marxist starting point of labor. There is no way within this framework to understand either how these male hierarchies came about, since it has been shown male control over female labor varies tremendously from culture to culture,18 or why such hierarchies generate male aggression and violence against women. More importantly, if, as Hartmann states, patriarchal social relations in contemporary capitalism are not confined to the family but also exist in the capitalist workshop and other institutions outside the family, it is hard to see by what principle these patriarchal relations can be separated from the social relations of capitalism. Hartmann concedes that "the same features, such as division of labor, often reinforce both patriarchy and capitalism, and in a thorough patriarchal capitalist society it is hard to isolate the 19 mechanisms of patriarchy." Yet she insists that patriarchy must be separate. It seems reasonable, however, to hold that 41 if patriarchy and capitalism are manifest in identical social and economic structures, they belong to one and not two spheres. More generally, this is the ultimate objection to any dual systems theory.20 However formulated, the dual systems theory allows traditional Marxism to maintain its theories of production relations and historical change and its analysis of the structure of capitalism in a basically unchanged form. That theory, _as pointed out by Hartmann herself, works with gender-blind categories. The dual system theory thus accepts this gender-blind analysis of the relations of production, wishing only to add to it a separate conception of the relations of gender hierarchy. Thus, not unlike traditional Marxism, the dual systems theory tends to see the question of women's oppression as merely an addition to the main question of Marxism. In the case of Rubin's analysis, it should be pointed out that her focus on sexual coercion as the material base of male domination offers a valuable starting point for understanding male violence and aggression against women. Rubin makes the important point that while we are born female and male, biological sexes, we are created woman and man, socially recognized genders. However, in Rubin's presentation there is no discussion of the relation or connection to production and the capitalist system of this social system of sexual coercion. In a sense, Rubin focuses on one side of the duality, Marx on the other, and Hartmann 42 on the point of their intersection. The problem with these frameworks of analysis, however, is representative of a recurring dilemma that emerges in the works of Marxist—feminists, namely, how to find and develop an analysis of two separate motive forces and their points of intersection. Joan Kelly in her article, "The Double Vision of Feminist Theory," discusses this problem in a historical context.21 She suggests that the ". . . bourgeois conception of a private and public domain" has radically affected feminist theory.22 This, according to Kelly, has resulted in the many attempts to create two spheres or systems of domination. Kelly stresses that this opposition stems from and is a reflection of the existing social order. Feminist theories have been caught up in the reified reflection of this false dichotomy. She argues that ". woman's place is not a separate sphere or domain of existence but a position within social existence generally,"23 and that any fruitful analysis must ". treat sexual and reproductive experience in terms of political economy: and treat productive relations of class in connection with sex hierarchy."24 For Kelly it is the systemic connectedness that is important. Kelly's emphasis on a "doubled vision" and her view that a unified theory which "acknowledges the combined power of sexual-familial productive relations in our lives, and the fact that these relations serve male and socio-economic interests at the 25 same time," appear on the surface to reduce the burden of 43 constructing a model of two dynamic and interactive systems, and squarely places at the center of the framework the legitimacy and, in fact, the necessity of studying sexual inequality. But in her next step Kelly generates a different problem. By postulating that ". . . In any of the historical forms that patriarchal society (feudal, capitalist, socialist, etc.) a sex-gender system and a system of productive relations operate simultaneously,"26 we again become entangled in the drudgery of separate spheres. Even if patriarchy is accepted as the generic term for all of human society (with all ensuing problems of universality, trans-historicism, and inevitability that this entails),27 a framework must still be constructed for understanding the interaction of the patriarchy or sex-gender system with the system of production. At the same time, then, when feminists who were also Marxists began to criticize the failure of Marxist theory in coming to terms with the specificity of women's situation, attempts to construct theoretical work in this area tended to draw on existing concepts and to apply them uncritically to the situation of women. More specifically, there is evident a tendency to appropriate existing Marxist theory, first by pointing to its weaknesses where women were concerned, and second by attempting to insert the specific question of women into existing analysis and hence to add to rather than transform Marxist theory. This problem together 44 with that of the apparently transhistorical character of women's oppression have strongly problematized the relationship between such oppression and the mode of production. Any attempt to deal with this fundamental issue has not only necessitated a strong‘reconsideration of the relationship between patriarchy (however formulated) and the economy; it has also made clear that an analysis of the subordination of women cannot be provided by Marxists unless Marxism itself is transformed. This leads to the third form that contemporary Marxist analysis of the woman question has taken. More specifically, this group of Marxist economists has focused specifically on housework, or what has been termed in the literature "domestic labor", and has done so through exploring the economic consequences of patriarchy for production and distribution within the family. The analysis of women's domestic labor has initiated a heated debate.- Maria Dalla Costa28 has claimed that women's domestic labor, since unpaid, has lowered the value of labor power and thereby has served the capitalists by lowering real wages. Christine Delphy, a radical feminist, has asserted, however, that women's unpaid domestic labor not only benefits the class of capitalists but it directly benefits individual men.29 In order to tackle the issue of who actually benefits from women's unpaid house work, the debate has centered around the value of labor power and production of surplus value. Some analysts have suggested 45 that the separate sphere of production in which domestic labor operates contributes to the production of surplus 30 value while not directly producing value. Others have argued that since labor power is a commodity we can analyze 31 its production and reproduction in value terms. However, the latter deny that the reproduction of labor power involves in any way the production of surplus value. There are still other analyses that fall squarely in the realm of traditional Marxist theory by emphasizing that domestic labor not being subject to the law of value is analytically 32 incompatible with wage labor. We will concentrate on the work of Nancy Folbre as representative of the third category of contemporary Marxist analysis on women, characterized by its concentration on domestic labor as the locus of women's oppression and its attempt to transform Marxist theory itself in order to make it compatible with a coherent analysis of the sexual 33 division of labor in capitalist society. With respect to the general debate over domestic labor and the value of labor power briefly summarized above, Folbre writes: Some issues have been clarified along the way. Others have been obscured. The categories of age and gender have been subsumed into the undifferentiated term "domestic labor," and the domestic laborer/wage worker dichotomy has deflected attention from differences between the economic position of husbands and wives, parents and children, differences that often exist independently of the wage-worker status of one or more family member. The distinction between types of domestic labor has been glossed over. Intrahousehold exchange between 46 parents and children clearly have different implications than do exchanges between husbands and wives, but these have not been explored in any detail.34 According to Folbre this debate has failed to generate any attention to "the social organization of human 35 reproduction." Consequently, she claims that, the participants have reinforced the general tendency in Marxism of analyzing the issue of the reproduction of labor power strictly in terms of effects on the relationship between workers and capitalists. Folbre explains that, in Marxian theory, exploitation is explicitly described as the expropriation of surplus value. Surplus value, as applied by Marxists to the capitalist mode of production, is equivalent to the difference between the value of the workers' labor power and the value which they transfer to the product of their labor. The value of labor power is by assumption set equal to the labor embodied in the wage bundle which contains the goods the worker consumes in order to reproduce his capacity to work. In volume I of Capital, Marx briefly mentioned two other factors which might enter into the determination of the value of labor power, "the cost of developing that power" and the "difference between the labor power of men and women, children and adults". "Both these factors," he wrote, "are excluded in the following investigation." With this brief caveat, he dismissed the possibility that household labor might have a significant or even noticeable effect on the reproduction of labor power.36 Folbre goes on to argue that in fact wage workers not 47 only do not consume all their wage bundle, but they share it with the other members of the household. Indeed, other family members, especially women, provide goods and services for the family through their unpaid domestic labor. . If the portion of wage goods transferred to the family were exactly equivalent in value to the portion of family-produced goods and services, the wage bundle would in fact be an accurate reflection of the actual amount of socially-necessary labor time devoted to the reproduction of labor power. But there is absolutely no reason to assume that the exchange between wage workers and family is equivalent in value terms. This assumption merely circumvents a serious problem. If the family labor can not be analyzed in value terms, the condition of equivalent exchange can not even be defined much less satisfied.37 Folbre seems to think that this implicit assumption in Marxism is the source of much of the confusion in the contemporary debate over the value of labor power and its relationship to domestic labor. Folbre argues that though Marxists tend to deny that families pursue any economic goals (i.e., follow an objective function), there is in fact, an implicit objective function embedded in the Marxian notion of the working class, namely, that working class families are primarily 38 concerned with survival and subsistence. She goes on to assert that the notion that household behavior is dictated purely by the survival motive only works if wages are set at a subsistence level. She sees this as inconsistent with Marx's insistence that the value of labor power has a "moral 48 and historical" element. "It seems logical, then, that a 'moral and historical' element may also govern the amount of household labor that is devoted to the reproduction of labor power . . . The full cost of the reproduction of labor power, specific to a given cultural and class context, may be affected by traditions and social norms."39 Folbre thus intends to effect a fundamental theoretical reorientation of Marxism by insisting that households pursue some specific objective-function that both varies across classes and changes over time. She claims that this theoretical reorientation makes it possible, first, to analyze transfers of goods and labor time between family members and, second, to redefine the value of labor power by suggesting that both surplus and value may be generated within the household. Folbre builds an economic model based on the assumption that family members pool the product of their labor to reproduce the family and its members. Her intention is to show that the claim that family members cooperate when making decisions regarding production does not imply that the product of family labor is distributed equally. Indeed, according to Folbre, this claim provides "a framework for asking whether they are distributed equally."4O Having limited her model to the case where the family has at most one wage earner who is exploited as a wage worker, her model accommodates the role of the family non- wage laborer and lends itself to three distinct 49 possibilities. First, the exchange of labor products is on an equal basis among family members; thus the wage worker alone is exploited. Second, the wage worker recoups the loss of surplus value to the capitalist through unequal exchange within the family, in which case only the non-wage worker is exploited. And finally, the burden of exploitation is shared between wage and non-wage workers in the family. This is the case in which the total number of hours worked by family members is greater than the total hours embodied in their total consumption bundle. Therefore, in both the second and third case exploitation comes home in the sense that the woman domestic worker is exploited. Which of these possibilities, or combination of possibilities, actually holds in reality cannot be determined unless hours worked in household labor are commensurable with wage work in terms of abstract labor. I have argued that this commensurability is made possible by the socially-necessary character of household production. Despite the fact that household workers do not produce for the market they choose the most efficient means to perform their task. Their work may differ in skill and intensity, their fixed capital may differ in cost and depreciation, and they may engage in joint production, but none of these factors significantly distinguishes their work from that of wage workers.41 Folbre next elaborates her notion of exploitation. She points out that a simple transfer of surplus value is not itself necessarily an expropriation of surplus value, and therefore, unequal exchange does not in and of itself imply exploitation. At the same time, one of the most important lessons of Marxism, according to Folbre, is that 50 exploitation is often disguised by appearing to be equal exchange. Thus, the question of exploitation can be resolved only by reference to the political dimension of Marxian distribution theory and by very close scrutiny of the notion 42 of free choice. More specifically, the worker who receives a wage which is less than the value of the product of his labor may voluntarily exchange his labor for this wage and even benefit from this exchange, but if he has no independent access to the means of production the worker's choice to sell his product is essentially predetermined. Folbre criticizes the Marxists for not being fully aware of the differences in access to the means of production due to age and sex (and here it should be mentioned that she herself misses race). . . . Yet a large body of scholarship describes peasant and petty commodity modes of production, both outside and within capitalist formations, in which legal and practical control over the family's land and capital resides in the hands of older males. Even where a part of the labor force has been proletarianized, control over home and hearth often rests with men. Furthermore, social sanctions and laws which prohibit contraception and abortion sometimes give men substantial control over women's own biological means of production.43 Folbre argues that women in fact rarely face an either- or situation. Since they often lack access to an independent means of survival, they voluntarily marry and thus continue to cooperate within a patriarchal family, despite its 51 inequalities. Therefore, in a society in which men qua men have relatively more access to the means of production; participate in forming and enforcing laws, institutions, and social norms and practices that weaken women's economic independence; enjoy a substantially greater bargaining power; and have lower rates of exploitation, Folbre believes that "one can make a strong case that they are indeed, exploiters."44 According to Folbre, the possibility of this type of exploitation has serious implications not only for the patriarchal family structure, but also for any understanding of capitalism. One important implication is that it is now possible for one to argue that women indeed compensate the male wage earner for his exploitation in the market. Moreover, exploitation of women by men suggests "that class lines between families are likely to be cross-cut and weakened by non-class forms of conflict."45 While admitting that her analysis requires further elaboration, Folbre concludes that, in order to comprehend women's subordination, Marxists have to be more concerned with the economics of the family. Folbre's conception of the family as a locus of conflict and struggle rather than an active agent with unified interests, plus her identification of the family as a location where production and distribution take place rather than a unit shaped by affect and kinship, goes a long way in identifying and exploring the material aspects of 52 gender relations within family units in particular and capitalist society in general. She also is at least partially successful in transforming Marxist theory and making it consistent with a more adequate analysis of the sexual division of labor. Her work proceeds, however, within certain limits. She does not, for instance, address in her work the many real differences in the ways people of different periods, regions, or ethnic groups structure and experience family life. She focuses mainly on the capitalist mode of production. Second, she concentrates almost exclusively on domestic labor and women's oppression in the working class. Third, she restricts her analysis to the economic level. All these limit the scope of Folbre's analysis. More specifically, her emphasis on domestic labor and the economics of the family sheds little light on the problem of whether housework is analytically the ‘same in different classes within capitalism and even less on the theoretical status of domestic labor in noncapitalist societies. Also, by essentially identifying domestic labor with housework and child-care, and by leaving the status of child-bearing undefined, Folbre does not explain why domestic labor falls generally to women: Moreover, since women's oppression is not specific to capitalist societies, one is left to wonder how to reconcile its particular contemporary character with the fact that women have been subordinated for thousands of years. Similarly, one is left 53 wondering whether women are or will be liberated in socialist societies. Finally, the relationship between the material processes of domestic labor and the range of phenomena which make up women's oppression, especially those of an ideological and psychological nature, is a key issue with which she does not consider. FOOTNOTES 1. Eli Zaretsky, "Capitalism, the Family and Personal Life," Socialist Revolution, No. 13-14, (1973). 2. See for example Juliet Mitchell. "Women: The Longest Revolution." New Left Review, No. 14. (1966). 3. Jean Gardiner, "Women's Domestic Labour," New Left Review, No. 89, (1975). 4. Zaretsky, "Capitalism," op. cit.; Eli Zaretsky, "Socialist Politics and the Family," Socialist Review, No. 19, (1974). 5. Zaretsky, "Capitalism," op. cit., p. 114. 6. Hartmann, op. cit. 7. Ibid. 8. Mitchell, "Longest Revolution", op. cit., pp. 11— 37. 9. Ibid., p. 20. 10. Ibid., pp. 11-37. 11. Juliet Mitchell, Psychoanalysis and Feminism, (New York: Pantheon Books, 1974), p. 412. 12. Gayle Rubin, "The Traffic in Women: Notes on the 'Political Economy' of Sex," in Towards pp Anthropolpgy 9; Women, edited by R. Reiter, (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1975). 13. Hartmann, op. cit. 14. Rubin, op. cit., p. 182. 15. Ibid., p. 182. 16. Hartmann, op. cit., p. 13. 17. Ibid., p. 15. 54 55 18. Rayna R. Reiter, Towards pp Anthropology pf Women, (New York: Monthly Reviw Press, 1975). 19. Iris Young, "Beyond the Unhappy Marriage: A Critique of the Dual Systems Theory," in Women and Revolution, edited by L. Sargent, (Boston: South End Press, 1981). 20. Ibid. 21. Joan Kelly, "The Doubled Vision of Feminist Theory," Feminist Studies, Vol. 5, No. 7, (1979). 22. Ibid., 220. 24. Ibid., P 23. gpigy, p. 221. p 221. P 25. Ibid., 220. 26. Ibid., p. 224. 27. See Mitchell Barrett, Women's Oppression Today, (London: Verso, 1980). 28. Mariarosa Dalla Costa, "Women and the Subversion of the Community." The Power 9; Women and the Subversion pg the Community, (Bristol: Falling Wall Press, 1972). 29. Christine Delphy, The Main Enemy, (London: Women's Research Center, 1976). 30. John Harrison, "The Political Economy of Housework," Bulletin 9; the Conference pp Socialist Economists, Vol. IV, (1973). 31. Wally Seccombe, "The Housewife and her Labor under Capitalism," New Left Review, No. 83, (1974). 32. Susan Himmelweit and Simon Mohun, "Domestic Labor and Capital," Cambridge Journal 9; Economics, Vol. 1, (1977). 33. Nancy Folbre, "Exploitation comes home: a critique of Marxian Theory of family labor," Cambridge Journal 9; Economics, No. 6, (1982). 34. Ibid., p. 319. 35. Ibid., p. 319. 36. Ibid., p. 318. H pl H U‘ 5.4. D. H 0" p. Q. H U‘ P. Q; H U‘ 5... Q. H D‘ p. Q. H 0‘ 5.... Q. H 0' HO O. H 0‘ £1, 'U'U'U'U'U'U'G'U'U 56 CHAPTER III THE CHICAGO SCHOOL NEOCLASSICISTS There is a split in the neoclassical school regarding the appropriate economic role of government. The conservative neoclassical tradition, or the Chicago school. defends a policy of laissez-faire. The liberal neoclassical tradition, on the- other hand, advocates a substantial economic role for the government. These two camps, however, have three characteristics in common which are important enough to classify them both as neoclassicists. Both camps adhere to the principle of methodological individualism, viewing socio-economic theories as -being grounded in the attitudes and behavior of individual economic agents. Consequently, both camps utilize the concept of the economic man to postulate rationality, an assumption of self-interested and maximizing behavior under constraints. For both camps methodological key to correct economic analysis is to distinguish positive versus normative investigation. Both camps view the prediction of human behavior as giving theories of economic life their scientific character. The consequence of the emphasis on predictiOn and the separation of normative and positive analysis for neoclassical economists is that they can be 57 58 characterized as "methodological monists". More specifically, "methodological monism" is defined as the view that accepts a common methodology for both the natural and the social sciences, as opposed to "methodological dualism" which distinguishes between the correct methodological principles of the natural and social sciences.1 In addition to their adherence to the same methodological principles, both camps defend the private property system of capitalism. Finally, .they both defend some version of the three basic tenets characteristic of neoclassical economic theory. The first is the argument that a market economy harmonizes all interests and leads to an efficient allocation of resources. The second is the automaticity of market clearing leading to full—employment equilibrium. The third is the belief in the marginal productivity theory of income distribution which equates each individual's income and the value that he or she creates at the margin.2 This chapter investigates the Chicago School tradition. Chapter IV will be devoted to the liberal wing. It should be mentioned at the outset that the Chicago School has an extensive analysis of the sexual division of labor within the family; a similar discussion of the familial division of labor is lacking in the liberal tradition. Thus, the discussion of the Chicago tradition is by necessity more extensive. The liberal tradition does have analyses of women's labor supply and therefore the sexual division of labor in the economy as a whole. 59 Chicago Analysis 9; Women's Labor Supply The rising labor force participation of women, especially married women, since the 1890's was the first issue that attracted economists to the questions concerning women in the economy. The orthodox theory of labor supply held that the rational worker would allocate time to the labor market so as to balance the benefits gained from income and leisure. According to the standard approach, the effect of a wage change could not be predicted a priori. The substitution effect of a wage increase makes leisure relatively more expensive and therefore tends to elicit more work. However, the extra income resulting from the higher wage“also induces additional purchases of all normal goods, including. leisure. Thus, the income effect predicts a decrease in the hours of week offered to the market. A backward—bending labor supply curve would result if, over a certain income range, the income effect outweighs the substitution effect. As women's increasing entry into the paid labor force became impossible to ignore after World War II, economists set out to explain the female labor supply. Jacob Mincer opened the discussion in 1962 with an article in which he pointed out that cross—section data for women and time— series data for men were consistent with the- backward— bending supply curve hypothesis.3 However, the continuing secular increase in women's labor force participation meant that the time—series data for women were inconsistent with 60 the backward-bending supply curve for women. Cross—section studies concluded that there was an inverse relationship between wives' labor force participation and husbands' income. On the other hand, time-series studies showed a positive relation between these two variables. Mincer's main goal was to resolve the contradiction that had developed in these two sets of data for the labor force participation rates of married women. Mincer, logically enough, introduced the wife's own wage rate as a relevant variable and explicitly designated the family as the decision—making unit. For the women the choice between market work and leisure was expanded into a more realistic one also involving work at home. Mincer's resolution concentrated on the double impact of income and prices on married women's behavior. He argued that a woman's Choice depends not only on her husband's income but is also influenced by her own wage rate, i.e., the price of her labor. According to Mincer, the opportunity cost of time spent consuming leisure and doing housework has risen because of the higher take-home pay of married women in the twentieth century. Therefore, at the same time that the husbands' income has pulled women out of the labor force and into the home, women's higher wages have pushed them into the labor force and out of the home. The observed increase in married women's labor force participation Mincer concluded, implies that the substitution effect has triumphed over the income 61 effect. Beginning most visibly with the work of Kelvin Lancaster in 1966, the notion that households only consume was dramatically challenged.4 In essence, the traditional view treats the household as a black box; market goods enter one side and somehow utility exit the other. The activities of household members by whom market goods are made to yield utility are totally neglected and real work is assumed to occur only in the market. In contrast, the new framework acknowledges the existence and legitimacy of household production in which time and market goods are combined to produce household commodities that in turn are the immediate sources of utility. Mincer's work inspired a rapid expansion of the boundaries of neoclassical economic analysis. Since in neoclassical theory a problem qualifies as economic if scarcity is involved, the discovery of time as a scarce resource with competing uses has made analyses of nonmarket activities involving time quite respectable. In Gary Becker's hands the theory has become more general.5 Time is designated as an input along with market goods in the family's utility function. Moreover time is necessary to produce as well as consume household goods and both uses compete with time allocated to the labor market. According to Becker the household would allocate the time of all its members according to their relative efficiencies and also has the choice to switch to less time—intensive 62 commodities such as frozen dinners. As in the 'previous model, the effect on women's labor force participation of an increase in the market wage cannot be predicted. The research that followed in the 1960's was directed toward empirical estimation of the model. Several variables hypothesized as influencing women's labor supply were tested which were expected to influence participation through either the income or the substitution effect. The two definitive works of this type were Glen Cain's Married Women in the Labor Force6 and The Economics 9: Labor Force Participation by William Bowen and T. Aldrich Finegan.7 Bowen and Finegan include as major factors for increasing women's labor force participation the development and diffusion of labor saving devices and the increasing wages of domestic servants.8 In fact, however, other studies have shown that domestic work in hours has not decreased with the proliferation of the so-called labor- saving devices.9 Also, domestic servants' wages, at relevant rates, seem unlikely to affect the labor market decision of the average working women unless she is considering it for an occupation. Economists have also invoked psychological explanations to analyze a woman's decision to work. For example, Glen Cain suggests that black women's high labor force participation rates relative to white women might be due to a fear of losing their husbands because of the greater 10 marital instability of the black community. 63 In the more recent literature on women's labor supply, the framework of analysis is relatively unchanged. Married women are the focus of both the theoretical and the empirical studies.11 The wage rates of the woman and her husband, her level of education, and the number and ages of children are the primary determinants of labor supply of women. The most important theoretical development has been the extension to an explicit life-cycle model. This model bases all time allocation, human capital investment, fertility, and consumption decisions of the individual on a desired level of expected permanent income. This concept was developed by Milton Friedman in 1975.12 With respect to labor supply decisions the life-cycle approach predicts that individuals, or family units plan a level of life-time commitment to the labor force but time their periods of participation according to fluctuations in economic conditions and corresponding fluctuations in wage rates. Evaluation 9; Chicago School Labor Supply Literature: Alice H. Amsden has remarked that by explaining a woman's behavior as the result of two opposing forces, the neoclassical model explains at the same time everything and nothing. Since either the income or the price effect must dominate any result is admissible and the theory is irrefutable. As to why one effect or another might dominate at any particular time, an historical analysis becomes relevant. This view does not rule out the influence of price 64 and income changes, but it argues that the relation between these changes must be explored for a more complete picture.13 The rebuttal to this objection might be that if the results of the orthodox analysis are useful and the predictions correct, then economists need not concern themselves with social variables. Therefore, the question is whether the results are indeed convincing. One example that suggests a negative answer, is that the behavior of black women has persistently not conformed to the hypothesis. It might be that an analysis which integrates theories of class, race, and sex would lead to a more realistic understanding of the differentials between white and minority women than explanations such as the greater marital instability in the black community. Another example of the shortcomings of the Chicago analysis in the area of women's labor supply can be seen in a recent work by Heckman and Macurdy.14 They exclude non— white women from their empirical work. In addition, they confine their study to middle-age women, though it is young women who show the most dramatic increase in labor force participation. Finally, they restrict their sample to families with a male head and stable family composition. It must be questioned if this is a valid test of "female labor supply" as the title of the article suggests. It should be mentioned that besides the empirical 15 anomalies, some of which were mentioned above, the Chicago 65 theory of sexual division of labor in the economy, i.e., women's labor supply, suffers from the shortcoming of being highly selective. Becker's analysis selectively includes non-material commodities that he believes contribute to utility. However, he fails to include the utility of education for its own sake, or the utility of change and diversity. The Chicago Theory 9; the Family Gary Becker's general theory of the allocation of time among alternative uses has laid the analytical ground-work for what Tullock and McKenzie have called the "new world of economics",16 in which economic analyses of education, crime, dishonesty, death, suicide, politics, and bureaucracy, have become very common. Given the importance of the family outside the monetary sector, there was also born the "new home economics", the Chicago School's analyses of marriage, divorce, fertility, and even sexual behavior.17 The Chicago School's theory of marriage starts with two basic assumptions. The first is the rationality assumption, that people marry because in doing so they increase their utility. The second assumption is that there is a marriage market in which men and women compete in their search for mates. The marriage market is assumed to be in equilibrium when the men and women are each in a Pareto optimal 66 position. Each person is seen to be involved in increasing his/her utility and finding the best mate in the market for marriage, subject to the restrictions imposed by market conditions. According to Becker, these two principles explain why the institution of the family exists. Becker finds that the gain from marriage compared to remaining single for a man and a woman is positively related to their income, the relative difference in their wage rates, and the traits that affect nonmarket productivity, such as beauty and intelligence. The gain from marriage is also greater the more complementary the inputs of the husband and wife in the household. The gain from marriage is also positively related to the importance of children. From all this Becker provides a justification for assuming that each family acts as if it maximizes a single utility function. According to the "new home economics" the division of labor within the family derives from the nature of the marriage market equilibrium. The determinant of the division of labor in this market, as in every other market, is the marginal productivities of the husband and wife which in turn are determined by their human and physical capital. Marriage in this framework is conceptualized as "a two person firm with either member being the 'entrepreneur' who hires the other at . . . (a) 'salary' . . . and receives residual 'profits'."18 Women hire men as bread winners since men earn more than women in the market, women's market 67 earning powers having been diminished by their childrearing activities. Men hire women as nurse-maids since women bear children and are superior at rearing them, men's child- rearing powers having been diminished by their market earning activities. Thus, the division of labor within the family is concluded to be consistent with economic maximizing principles. Becker's work consists essentially of extensions and application of the concept of maximizing production under constraints. Specifically, for the household production function, time and goods are inputs and time and income are constraints in the production of commodities including but not limited to "children, prestige and esteem, health, altruism, envy, and pleasure."19 With respect to labor supply decisions, in accordance with earlier theories it is the relative efficiencies of household members that determines their allocation of time to the home or the market or both. This approach is patterned on the theory of comparative advantage which was developed to explain gains from specialization and trade between countries.20 In this context, one's comparative advantage is the ratio of his or her productivity in the market to productivity in the home. Productivity in the market is measured by the wage that one can obtain. Productivity at home cannot be directly observed. Leaving aside for the moment the question of why these productivities vary systematically between men and women, the discussion turns to the implication of this 68 theory. As might be expected, the theory shows that a household can profit from specialization when the relatively more market-efficient members allocate time there, and household— efficient members allocate time to the domestic sphere.21 Becker goes further to demonstrate that even if household members have identical productivities and training an efficient household would specialize: "Theorem 2.3: At most one member of an efficient household would invest in ’both market and household capital and would allocate time to both sectors." If a certain not implausible assumption is made, then "all members of efficient households would specialize completely in the market or household sectors . . ."22 The explanation for this conclusion, though presented in a rigorous mathematical manner, is quite simple and intuitive. The gains from specialization derive from the savings in training costs which Chicago School economists call the costs of human capital. From the perspective of society as a whole, this analysis is quite clear and sensible. If there are to be plumbers and accountants, and if there are significant training costs of time and money to learn those trades, then it is certainly not reasonable to expect everyone to develop those skills extensively. On the other hand, as an explanation and justification for the sexual division of labor in all societies at all times, the specialization principle is inadequate by itself. If it is granted that 69 specialization makes sense, then the question remains as to why the split between market and home has developed along gender lines. Realizing that he has to answer the question of why it is women who bake the bread and men who make the laws, Becker steps outside of his field to give biology its due. He asserts that "intrinsic differences between the sexes" are also responsible for the sexual division of labor thus combining economic and socio-biological analysis. For example, he finds that women care and nurture for children because "they want their heavy biological burden in 23 reproduction to be worthwhile." Further, according to Becker, biological differences explain not only the sexual division of labor but also heterosexuality and child rearing practices which support traditional roles. If only a small fraction of girls are biologically oriented to the market rather than household activities, then in the face of no initial information to the contrary, the optimum strategy would be to invest mainly household capital in all girls and mainly market capital in all boys until any deviation from the norm is established. In this manner investments in children with "normal" orientation reinforce their biology, and they become specialized to the sexual division of labor. Investment in "deviant" children, on the other hand conflict with their biology, and the net outcome for them is uncertain.24 Tullock and Mckenzie by building on Becker's theory, elaborate on the division of labor within the family. Since it is more costly to make decisions when more than one 70 person is involved, the husband and wife often voluntarily agree to have different decisions made administratively by one or the other.25 In general, marriage is viewed as an elaborate contract between a man and a woman, with each party explicitly or implicitly agreeing to bear certain responsibilities and commitments and to abide by a set of rules that divide and assign decision making to each party.26 This process is compared to the process of the development of the constitution and by-laws of a firm. It is also claimed that the "central purpose of dating and engagement is to set the provisions of the marriage contract."27 It is in fact emphasized that without the development of a set of marriage provisions, the future of the marriage will be uncertain and filled with disagreements, eventually resulting in divorce.28 The long-range and more fundamental explanation for the division of labor, including the sexual division of labor, in the Chicago tradition is provided by the human capital theory.29 Since individuals enjoy freedom of choice, it follows that what exists in the market is the result of the choices that individuals have made. Therefore, most Chicago theorists consider women's lower earnings to be the result of their voluntary investment in human capital smaller than men's. Women choose to make smaller investment in human capital and thus have lower earnings. Human capital theorists give two reasons for women's 71 smaller investment in human capital and their consequent lower earnings. First, they argue that women's labor force participation is more uneven and unstable than men's due to the time spent bearing and rearing children. Secondly, when they are in the labor market, women choose jobs that offer fewer opportunities for increasing their productivity. Mincer and Polachek, for instance, argue that since acquiring experience and on-the-job training, and therefore skills, is costly in terms of foregone earnings, women usually choose jobs that do not require much skills. In other words, women maximize their earnings over their life cycle by avoiding jobs that requires skills and training.30 The same maximization principle leads the profit maximizing employer to fill the jobs that require high skills with men, since they too know that men's labor force participation is more stable. In this process, employers may inadvertently discriminate against women who do have a stable labor force attachment. But because of the high cost of obtaining accurate information about the traits of individual workers, such stereotypical judgment on the part of employers is rational.31 In addition to earning less than men, women on average also experience higher rates of unemployment. The higher tendency of women to move in and out of the labor force is also the explanation given for the difference in the rates of unemployment between men and women. The Chicagoans argue that the income maximizing process of search that precedes 72 reentry into the labor force necessarily involves a period of frictional unemployment for women. Thus, women's higher unemployment also is considered as voluntary by the Chicago 32 School economists. Evaluation 2; the New Home Economics: One may be impressed by the beauty of such a symmetri- cal modeling of market and nonmarket activities by Chicago theorists or one may be struck by its absurdity. The rest of this section, however, attempts a critical appraisal of the Chicago doctrine not on the basis of the beauty, symme-try, or absurdity of this theory. More specifically, the aim is to provide what Warren J. Samuels calls a "constructive critique": "the attempt to bring into focus the meaning of the nature, strengths, and limits of a body of ideas. . . to understand what is being said, what is not being said, and the bases and limits thereof."33 A general circularity has been pointed out by the opponents of the Chicago School in their theoretical treatment of the division of labor within the family.34 More specifically, in order to explain the division of labor within the home, the female-male wage differential is taken as given. Thus, we are told that since women earn less than men because of their lower investment in human capital and lower productivity, the division of labor within the household in which the woman is the nursemaid and the man the bread-winner is logical. 73 At another stage in the analysis, however, in order to explain the female-male wage differential, the division of labor within the home is taken as given. We are told that this wage differential is the result of women choosing to invest less in human capital because of their commitment to the household. It logically follows then, that women have lower productivity and thus lower wages. In Isabel Sawhill's words, ". . . we have come full circle . . . and it is time to ask whether economists have done anything more than describe the status quo in a society where sex roles are given — defined by culture, biology, or other factors not specified in the economic model."35 Such theoretical circularity affects the explanation provided by the "new home economics" for the origins of the family. The gains from marriage are said to be greater, the greater the difference in wage rates between the wife and the husband. It follows logically then, that women marry because they earn less than men. But they earn less than men because they enter into marriages in which sex roles are given and in which it is simply assumed that they have a comparative advantage in doing housework rather than market work. Thus, it can be argued that unless sexist social relations based on gender-differentiated values, roles, and functions, are introduced, Chicago style economics is unable to give an explanation for either the division of labor within the family or the existence and origins of the family 74 itself. Let us examine the consequence of the circularity and the subsequent assumption of sexist social relations for the Chicago analysis, an analysis that is methodologically based on atomistic individualism. Chicago's primary methodological and analytical category is the individual, who is seen not as an integral part of an integrated socio—economic whole, but as an isolated, independent, atomistic unit with essentially two characteristics. First, the individual derives utility from the consumption of different goods produced in the market or the home. Second, the individual is a rational, calculating maximizer. The individual maximizes utility, however, subject to constraints. The market variables of income and prices are the major constraints, and thus the major determinants of individual behavior. Since it is believed that the essence of individual behavior can be captured by a model that uses a limited number of universal economic variables, namely, income and prices, it is also believed that this model can be projected over time, across social strata, and across cultures. Therefore, Chicago analysis is ahistorical and asocial, and it abstracts economics from power. The human subject of the Chicago investigation is a timeless, classless, raceless creature, although male unless otherwise specified. Changes in income and prices, however, do not necessarily give rise to structural changes. In other words, 75 quantitative changes do not give rise to qualitative changes. Rather, income and prices are conceptualized as changing in small imperceptible amounts. Thus, human behavior, which is responsive primarily to anonymous variations in income and prices, changes very slowly over time. The techniques of the calculus, therefore, are easily applied in research. Behavioral influences which are social, cultural, or ideological are lumped together as tastes and are generally assumed to be stable. Recently it has been argued that even differences in tastes may be subsumed under income and prices a view which conveys the absolute centrality of market prices and income in the Chicago approach. In the words of two of the School's most prominent and influential proponents, George Stigler and Gary Becker, . one does not argue over tastes for the same reason that one does not argue over the Rocky Mountains - both are there, and will be there next year, too, and are the same to all men. On the traditional view, an explanation of economic phenomena that reaches a difference in tastes between peoples or times is the terminus of the argument: the problem is abandoned at this point to whoever studies and explains tastes (psychologists? anthropologists? phrenologists? sociologists). In our' preferred interpretation, one never reaches this impasse: the economist continues to search for differences in prices or incomes to explain any differences or changes in behavior.36 Thus, individuals are free atoms, free from any influences other than the market variables of income and prices. The 76 society itself is simply the sum of these atomistic individuals, with voluntary market transactions being the only social interaction between them. In effect, the market is the society. The independence of individuals from any social forces that might influence them and thereby, erode their freedom of choice, is of fundamental importance for neoclassical theory in general and Chicago School analysis, including the "new home economics" in particular. Voluntary decisions have significance in and of themselves if and only if they have not been influenced by social forces outside the market, forces over and above the individual's sphere of influence. In summary, with atomistic individualism as the important feature of the methodology of the Chicago School, these theorists reduce everything to the sphere of the market and thereby to exchange relations. They abstract from any other social relation that destroys the unanimity that exists in the market. The consistency of .their whole approach depends on this. By smuggling in unequal and thus sexist social relations through their circular explanation of the sexual division of labor, however, the Chicago theorists of the family do exactly what their methodology prohibits them from doing. They effectively assume sexist social relations involving power and predetermined results at the outset and then build their theory on this assumption. They thereby implicitly reject atomistic individualism and the notion that individuals are free from 77 forces that influence their actions and choices. Moreover, the assumption of sexual inequality which drives their model also points to the ideological and thus normative nature of their theory. The circularity in the Chicago argument and the consequent assumption of sexist social relations, implies that in a world in which men and women have unequal wealth and power, their abilities to exercise freedom of choice differ. . The ideological nature of the Chicago approach to the family and the sexual division of labor becomes apparent when one looks at human capital theory critically. The human capital metaphor reduces all economically relevant skills to a single measure. But economically relevant skills are not unidimensional and cannot simply be aggregated across individuals into a single formal measure of which some individuals have more or less. Moreover, families, schools, and training institutions teach different things to different individuals, and differing learning contexts are closely associated with the racial, sexual, and class characteristics of the student body.37 The justification by human capital theorists for using the metaphor of human capital is that skills like other assets offer a claim on future income. While most Chicago theorists argue that normative, ethical, and ideological positions are completely foreign to their science of economics, other theorists claim that this definition and characterization of capital —- i.e., claim on future income 78 --stems directly from the normative and ideological position 38 of the Chicago theorists. In fact, for classical economists, the concept of capital encompassed two distinct but necessary notions. One was the claim on future income and the other was the ownership and control of the means of production. Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis argue that education and skill cannot be called capital in the classical sense, since except for rare exceptions, educated workers do not control, much less own, the means of production. The problem of measuring and identifying capital not- withstanding, the ideological impact of the human capital metaphor becomes even more clear when it is realized that with this metaphor labor disappears as a fundamental category in economic analysis. In fact, Bowles and Gintis emphasize that human capital theory is the ultimate step in the elimination of classes as central economic concepts, with every worker now having become a capitalist.39 The ahistorical, highly general and highly abstract framework of the Chicago 'new home economics' has been purchased at the high price of obliterating most of the trees from the forest. Indeed, the black box of the family and household production through which the sexual division of labor emerges is ultimately retained. In Chicago theory, production in general and household production in particular is a kind of alchemy. The entrepreneur and the household have a complex mathematical recipe, called a production 79 f11r1ction. Many of the variables found in the sociological ar1